Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-hvd4g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-13T10:45:10.608Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Towards a Moral Division of Labour between IHL and IHRL during the Conduct of Hostilities

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 January 2020

Ziv Bohrer
Affiliation:
Bar-Ilan University, Israel
Janina Dill
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Helen Duffy
Affiliation:
Universiteit Leiden

Summary

When should international humanitarian law (IHL) apply? When should it prevail over, and when should it give way to international human rights law (IHRL) in regulating the conduct of hostilities during international and non-international armed conflicts? IHL and IHRL give diverging answers to the crucial question of when it is legally permissible to kill another person. Following the customary IHL principles of distinction, proportionality and necessity systematically leads to breaches of the legal provisions safeguarding the human right to life. Some legal scholars, notably Helen Duffy in this volume, do not acknowledge this norm conflict, but aver that the two bodies of law can be reconciled through interpretation. Those that reject a substantive convergence between IHL and IHRL tend to take one of three broad positions: many argue that the norm conflict can be resolved by reference to lex specialis; others suggest that, in each instance, the rule should prevail that affords greater protection; yet others cast the matter as depending on which rules states intended to apply in a given context.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

I. Introduction

When should international humanitarian law (IHL) apply? When should it prevail over, and when should it give way to international human rights law (IHRL) in regulating the conduct of hostilities during international and non-international armed conflicts?Footnote 1 IHL and IHRL give diverging answers to the crucial question of when it is legally permissible to kill another person. Following the customary IHL principles of distinction, proportionality and necessity systematically leads to breaches of the legal provisions safeguarding the human right to life.Footnote 2 Some legal scholars, notably Helen Duffy in this volume, do not acknowledge this norm conflict, but aver that the two bodies of law can be reconciled through interpretation.Footnote 3 Those that reject a substantive convergence between IHL and IHRL tend to take one of three broad positions: many argue that the norm conflict can be resolved by reference to lex specialis;Footnote 4 others suggest that, in each instance, the rule should prevail that affords greater protection;Footnote 5 yet others cast the matter as depending on which rules States intended to apply in a given context.Footnote 6

This chapter, in contrast, treats the question of when IHL should prevail over IHRL as a moral question. That means a moral standard, based on a general theory of the moral purpose of law explained in Section III.A, should determine the applicability scope of a body of law. Specifically, I will argue that when two bodies of law make diverging substantive demands – as IHRL and IHL do – that which better discharges the law’s moral tasks should displace the other. The law’s two moral tasks, according to this theory, are to guide its subjects’ conduct, as often as possible, towards the course of action that conforms to their moral obligations (task one) and to secure the fullest feasible protection of rights in the outcome of conduct (task two). IHL and IHRL’s scope of application should be determined by their respective ability to guide individuals towards the fulfilment of their moral obligations and to secure morally desirable outcomes in war.

Both, our moral obligations on the battlefield and the morally desirable outcomes of warfare, centre on fighting without violating the rights of the persons against whom we fight.Footnote 7 There are two scenarios in which it can be morally justified to infringe an individual’s right to life without violating it. First, if an individual A threatens an individual B with morally unjustified harm and B can only defend himself by harming A, then A has forfeited her moral right not to be intentionally harmed through non-performance of her duty not to harm B.Footnote 8 A has made herself morally liable to B’s defensive harming. Individuals hence forfeit their moral right to life when they responsibly contribute to an unjustified threat and killing them is a necessary and proportionate defensive response. Secondly, besides killing individuals who have forfeited their right to life through their own conduct, it can sometimes be morally justified to override innocent bystanders’ moral right to life in order to prevent a greater moral evil, namely, a greater number of unjustified rights violations.Footnote 9

During the conduct of hostilities, law then has the following two moral tasks: its first moral task is to guide soldiers towards directing fire only against individuals who have forfeited their individual moral right to life.Footnote 10 If innocent bystanders are expected to be harmed in an attack, law must only permit the attack if overriding their moral right to life is a necessary and proportionate side-effect of the attack’s contribution to achieving a morally just war aim.Footnote 11 The law’s second moral task is to avoid and reduce as much as possible all morally unjustified infringements (i.e., violations) of individual rights in war. I will show that, if we compare IHL and IHRL, IHL’s provisions governing the conduct of hostilities further diverge from the principles setting out when it can be morally justified to infringe individual rights.Footnote 12 IHL permits a wider range of conduct that amounts to individual rights violations than IHRL. This makes IHRL the prima facie morally better law for governing hostilities.

However, even though IHRL more faithfully reflects fundamental moral principles, it is not necessarily better at discharging the law’s two moral tasks during armed conflict. In situations in which the morally right course of action is systematically difficult to discern (epistemic barriers), a legal rule that diverges from moral prescriptions may be better than one that mirrors these prescriptions at guiding the individual towards what is typically the morally right course of action (task one). In such situations, a rule that does not simply repeat moral principles may also secure a better protection of individual rights in the outcome of conduct (task two). Epistemic barriers to discerning the morally right conduct affect a rule’s ability to discharge both of law’s moral tasks. In addition, if in certain situations individuals cannot be moved to fully conform to their moral obligations (incurable volitional defects), a legal rule that asks for conduct other than the morally right course of action may generate better moral outcomes (task two). Incurable volitional defects affect a rule’s ability to discharge the law’s second moral task.

Whether IHRL or IHL should prevail depends on the epistemic and volitional context of decision-making during the conduct of hostilities. In other words, the empirical reality of armed conflict shapes the morally ideal scope of application of IHL and IHRL. I raise the question of whether IHL or IHRL should govern the conduct of hostilities for six types of non-international and international armed conflicts (NIACs and IACs). One of two characteristics distinguishes them from confrontations that do not count as armed conflicts: either the intensity of hostilities or a State’s (non-authorised) use of armed force outside its own territory. Armed confrontations count as law enforcement operations rather than armed conflicts if they are neither protracted, meaning hostilities remain below a threshold of intensity discussed in Section V.B, nor involve a State’s use of unauthorised force outside its own territory.Footnote 13 If hostilities become protracted, but do not involve the unauthorised extraterritorial use of force by a State, they count as NIACs (types 1, 3 and 5a). If hostilities involve a State’s armed forces crossing international borders without the authorisation of the territorial State, they currently count as IACs, whether they are protracted or not (types 2, 4, 5b and 6).

I will argue that when hostilities become protracted or cross international borders, IHRL needs to be applied ‘symmetrically’. By this I mean that both sides should interpret their obligations under IHRL as if they faced unlawful threats and uses of violence from soldiers on the other side and as if they themselves had lawful aims, regardless of the legal status of their respective resorts to force. I will show in Section V.C that international law on the resort to force does not track moral principles. As a result, if we relied on general international law on the resort to force to determine the lawfulness of soldiers’ aims during organised armed violence that crosses international borders, the ius contra bellum would often empower the side without a morally just war aim and hamstring the side fighting for a just cause. A State’s armed forces crossing borders without the territorial State’s consent does not otherwise affect ‘symmetrical IHRL’s’ better ability to discharge the law’s two moral tasks. An increase in the intensity of hostilities, in contrast, raises the epistemic barriers to identifying the morally right course of action and it renders more acute incurable volitional defects in soldiers’ decision-making. Compared with IHL, ‘symmetrical IHRL’ nonetheless remains the better law for discharging the law’s first moral task. Its ability to discharge the law’s second moral task, however, declines as hostilities become protracted.

This analysis leads to the following proposal for a moral division of labour between IHRL and IHL: as the morally prima facie better law IHRL should govern the conduct of hostilities in law enforcement operations. In non-protracted IACs, ‘symmetrical IHRL’ should govern the permissibility of killing. Above the threshold of intensity at which hostilities count as protracted, hence during NIACs and protracted IACs we face a choice between affording individuals a guide towards what is typically the course of action that conforms to their moral obligations (task one) and reducing individual rights violations in the outcome of warfare (task two). ‘Symmetrical IHRL’ better discharges task one; IHL better discharges task two. It depends on the relative moral costs of prioritising one task over the other as to which body of law should prevail. I will argue that IHL currently offers a better, but far from morally ideal, law for governing the permissibility of killing during the conduct of hostilities, once these hostilities reach the crucial threshold of being protracted. IHL should therefore displace IHRL and govern, on its own, the conduct of hostilities during NIACs and protracted IACs.

An alternative way of thinking about the implications of this argument would be to assert that only protracted armed confrontations should count as armed conflicts in the first place. This would allow us to uphold the traditional understanding that all armed conflicts should be governed by IHL and all law enforcement operations by IHRL, but it would mean redefining IACs as only confrontations among States that are protracted. Instead, I accept the dominant classification of armed confrontations as IACs if they involve the non-consensual crossing of borders by a State’s armed forces even if hostilities are not protracted. The implication of the argument for a moral division of labour between IHL and IHRL is then that not all armed confrontations that count as IACs should be governed by IHL. Only those that are protracted should fall under its purview; non-protracted IACs should be governed by ‘symmetrical IHRL’. In turn, IACs that are protracted and all NIACs (which per definitionem are protracted) should be governed only by IHL. This chapter hence presents a moral argument for the displacement of IHRL during certain types of armed confrontations, rejecting the intellectual coherence of a convergence between IHRL and IHL and the moral desirability of a parallel application of both bodies of law.

The argument proceeds as follows. Section II outlines the substantive conflict between the two bodies of law regarding the conditions of permissible killing. Section III defines the law’s two moral tasks and thereby sets the moral standard that later determines which body of law should prevail. It then explores the extent to which IHRL and IHL, respectively, track moral principles about the permissibility of killing. Section IV offers a typology of armed conflicts, highlighting what characterises six different types of confrontations as armed conflicts. Section V systematises how these characteristics affect IHRL and IHL’s respective ability to discharge the law’s two moral tasks. Based on this, I propose a division of labour between the two bodies of law. The concluding section takes stock of the divergence between the current applicability scope of IHL and this morally better division of labour with IHRL.

II. The Human Right to Life and the Permissibility of Killing according to IHL

A. IHL and the Rights of Individuals in War

As argued by Helen Duffy in this volume, it is largely uncontroversial now that IHRL does not simply cease to apply during armed conflict, even if the conflict extends beyond the territory of a State.Footnote 14 Indeed, the co-applicability of IHRL and IHL during armed conflict has become the ‘new orthodoxy’.Footnote 15 Co-applicability raises two logically distinct questions.Footnote 16 The first is whether the two bodies of law create a substantive conflict, in the sense that following one would systematically lead to or imply a breach of the other. Only if we answer this first question with yes, does the second question even arise: which body of law, or more specifically, which legal rule prevails?Footnote 17 One of the most frequently quoted authoritative statements on the relationship between IHL and IHRL conflates these two questions. The ICJ holds that ‘[i]n principle, the right not arbitrarily to be deprived of one’s life applies also in hostilities. The test of what is an arbitrary deprivation of life, however, falls to be determined by the applicable lex specialis, namely the law applicable in armed conflict …’Footnote 18

The ICJ’s statement suggests that IHL elucidates the meaning of IHRL in times of war, which would imply that following IHL does not lead to conduct that amounts to a breach of IHRL. At the same time, the statement refers to IHL as lex specialis, a tool for resolving a conflict between laws.Footnote 19 In this section, I reject the ICJ’s position that IHL elucidates what it means to protect human rights in war.Footnote 20 I argue instead that IHL and IHRL give diverging answers to the crucial question of when and whom it is permissible to kill during the conduct of hostilities. Complying with IHL, namely, with its customary principles of distinction, necessity and proportionality, leads to conduct that will often violate IHRL. Attacks that are lawful under IHL will regularly deprive individuals of the legal right to life that they hold under IHRL.

Before we compare the substance of the protections afforded to the individual under IHL and IHRL respectively, we need to address the formal question of whether, like IHRL, IHL bestows rights directly onto the individual at all. This remains controversial because IHL, unlike IHRL, does not afford individuals standing before an international court or tribunal tasked with adjudicating violations of IHL.Footnote 21 Crucially, the rise to prominence of international criminal law has largely settled any dispute over whether individuals incur duties directly by virtue of IHL. IHL imposes obligations on both the belligerent and the individual combatant.Footnote 22 A body of law that looks past the State long enough to bestow duties on the individual certainly recognises the latter as a subject for its purposes and by implication an agent capable, in principle, of bearing rights as well.

A textual interpretation of the Geneva Conventions supports the position that IHL indeed bestows some rights directly onto the individual. The four Geneva Conventions feature a common provision that prohibits special agreements among belligerents that would ‘restrict the rights which [the Conventions] confer … upon’ protected persons.Footnote 23 All Conventions enjoin protected persons from renouncing ‘the rights secured to them’.Footnote 24 GCIII and GCIV, which are dedicated to the protection of prisoners and civilians, respectively, use the term ‘right’ pervasively and contain a long list of proceduralFootnote 25 and substantive entitlements.Footnote 26 This leaves no room for doubt that, once in the power of an enemy belligerent, an individual, whether a civilian or combatant, bears legal rights. At the same time, it is arguably on the battlefield that individuals’ fundamental legal rights are most directly threatened.

The First Additional Protocol, the most elaborate and recent legal regime for the conduct of hostilities, recognises a right of combatants to participate in hostilities.Footnote 27 However, this cannot be understood as a claim right in the Hohfeldian sense because no other subject – a combatant’s own State, the enemy belligerent or other individuals – has a duty to not impede a combatant’s participation in war. Most recently, Adil Haque has convincingly argued that this ‘right’ is therefore best thought of as being an immunity from being prosecuted for engaging in hostile actions.Footnote 28 Otherwise, the chapters concerned with battlefield conduct are silent on the matter of individual rights either with reference to combatants or civilians. Juxtaposed with several references to the rights of individuals who are under the control of an adverse party to the conflict in the Protocol,Footnote 29 this omission of individual claim rights in the chapters on the conduct of hostilities has an air of purposefulness.

Of course, many of IHL’s restrictions on the conduct of hostilities evidently benefit individuals. If the substantive protections IHL affords soldiers and civilians were equivalent to those that individuals can claim as rights under IHRL, the formal question of whether or not IHL conceives of these protections as individual claim rights would be less important.Footnote 30 However, the observed disjuncture between provisions that regulate behaviour beyond the battlefield and the prescriptions concerned with the conduct of hostilities re-emerges when we inquire into the substance of IHL’s principles. The Protocol reiterates many of the substantive protections that the Conventions confer on individuals who are in the hands of the enemy. In contrast, the next two sub-sections will show that, during hostilities, neither civilians nor soldiers enjoy protections by virtue of IHL that safeguard the human right to life that they hold under IHRL.

B. IHL and Civilians’ Human Right to Life during Hostilities

During the conduct of hostilities civilians are generally immune from deliberate harming.Footnote 31 They are legitimate targets of intentional attack only for such time as they directly participate in hostilities.Footnote 32 This might suggest that civilians retain their right to life at least until they decide to directly contribute to overcoming the enemy. However, according to the principle of proportionality, it is permissible under IHL to injure or kill civilians as a foreseeable side-effect of an attack against a military objective, if the expected ‘incidental harm’ is not excessive in relation to the military advantage that is anticipated to arise from the attack.Footnote 33 Can killing civilians in accordance with the principle of proportionality amount to an unlawful deprivation of the right to life that they hold under IHRL? The following paragraphs show that IHL-compliant proportionate incidental civilian harm is not systematically covered by any of the exceptions to the right to life that IHRL recognises.

One exception to the prohibition on depriving individuals of their human right to life, contained in Article 2(2)(c) ECHR, permits the killing of individuals who threaten others with ‘unlawful violence’ or who resist or flee from ‘a lawful arrest’. The use of lethal force for the purposes of law enforcement is also widely recognised to give rise to an exception to Article 6 ICCPR. Depriving someone of their right to life is non-arbitrary, if it is necessary for the purposes of ‘self-defence or the defence of others against the imminent threat of death or serious injury; to prevent a particularly serious crime involving grave threat to life; to arrest a person presenting such danger and resisting their authority; or to prevent his or her escape’.Footnote 34 Crucially, these exceptions permit killing individuals who through their own unlawful conduct pose a threat to others. Civilians in war cannot be assumed to have broken the law, whether it is IHL, IHRL or domestic law. These exceptions cannot therefore explain why IHL-compliant incidental civilian harm would systematically be permissible under IHRL.

That civilians have not necessarily broken any laws also means that capital punishment, another recognised exception to the prohibition on depriving individuals of their right to life, cannot explain why incidental civilian harm would comply with IHRL.Footnote 35 Of course, it would be ludicrous to bring killing in war in connection with capital punishment, but a closer look at this exception is useful to elucidate what it means that a deprivation of the right to life is ‘non-arbitrary’ for the purposes of the ICCPR, in particular. The conditions that make a death sentence non-arbitrary are all oriented towards the goal of giving the defendant his or her individual legal due.Footnote 36 The Commentary to the ICCPR demands that ‘the personal circumstances of the offender and the particular circumstances of the offence, including its specific attenuating elements must be considered’.Footnote 37 Incidental civilian harm in war, in contrast, is not individuated to the circumstances of the civilian that is killed.Footnote 38

Killing civilians as a foreseen side-effect of an attack against a carefully selected and vetted military target may not seem arbitrary in the sense of being random, senseless or purposeless. Moreover, killing civilians in accordance with the principle of proportionality obviously has a basis in IHL and thus in law. However, the most recent UN Human Rights Committee’s Commentary on Article 6 ICCPR emphasises that the lawfulness of a rights deprivation is not the sole determinant of whether it is arbitrary. Rather arbitrariness ‘must be interpreted … to include elements of inappropriateness, injustice, lack of predictability, and due process of law’.Footnote 39 Appropriateness is often in the eye of the beholder. The next section will argue in detail that IHL does not systematically take account of the moral status of civilians and thus of whether or not their incidental killing is morally justified. Here it warrants reiterating that vetting a target for compliance with IHL does not amount to a process aimed at giving the individual his or her legal due.

Indeed, what makes IHL-compliant incidental civilian harm irrevocably arbitrary for the purposes of IHRL is its unpredictability. Besides the intention of the attacker, the following factors account for the legality of a civilian being deprived of her or his life under IHL: his or her physical proximity to a military target; the military value that the target has at that moment in the attacker’s campaign; the blast radius of the weapon the attacker happens to have at their disposal; and the absence of other civilians, who could render the expected incidental harm excessive. With the exception of the civilian’s physical proximity to the target, these factors are entirely beyond his or her control.Footnote 40 From the point of view of the individual that is deprived of his or her life, IHL’s permission to kill him or her incidentally is arbitrary in that the individual’s legally sanctioned fate is entirely disconnected from – and it cannot be influenced by – his or her legally required conduct.

In addition to these exceptions to the human right to life that are rooted in the individual’s own conduct, the ECHR also recognises an exceptional permission to kill individuals who are not themselves legally liable to harming, if this is ‘absolutely necessary … for the purpose of quelling a riot or insurrection’.Footnote 41 A legal permission to override rights that is unrelated to the conduct of the affected individual, but instead hinges on necessity is the most likely point of convergence between IHRL and IHL.Footnote 42 After all, the First Additional Protocol likewise stipulates that incidental civilian harm has to be necessary. Does the necessity to override an individual right to life in accordance with Article 2(2)(c) ECHR align with the necessity to kill civilians in order to pursue an anticipated military advantage under Article 57(2)(ii) API? No, two differences between necessity in IHL and necessity in IHRL account for why this exception to the human right to life does not systematically cover incidental civilian harm that complies with IHL.

The first difference between IHL and IHRL’s necessity exceptions concerns the aim with regard to which necessity has to obtain. Under IHRL necessity confers an exceptional empowerment to override a human right in order to achieve a legitimate aim such as the protection of human life or the protection of public order.Footnote 43 In contrast, under IHL killing civilians has to be necessary for the pursuit of a military advantage. This is not an emergency measure, but part and parcel of waging war. Notably, IHL does not require that a given military advantage is necessary to win a war. In turn, killing civilians under IHL does not have to be necessary for victory. Even if IHL did demand that incidental civilian harm was necessary also for victory, civilian harm would not automatically be necessary for the achievement of a legally recognised aim as required by the ECHR. To the contrary, at least on one side in each IAC, incidental civilian harm would be permissible because it was necessary for the furtherance of an aim that defies general international law.Footnote 44

The second difference between the meaning of necessity in IHL and the ECHR concerns the epistemic threshold at which we may consider a course of action necessary. In situations in which a reasonable observer perceives an imminent threat to human life, both IHRL and IHL deem overriding a right ‘necessary’. Where no such threat exists, the ECHR comes closer than IHL to still taking necessity literally to mean ‘lastness’. Under the ECHR, the course of action that overrides an individual right to life has to be the only, in the sense of the mildest, available path to the achievement of the recognised aim.Footnote 45 Establishing necessity in this sense means taking steps to ascertain the infeasibility of milder measures and the absence of alternative courses of action.Footnote 46 Crucially, if these steps cannot with reasonable certainty determine that overriding individual rights is necessary, the State would not be permitted to proceed.Footnote 47 Necessity under the ECHR implies an absolute standard of minimum reasonable knowledge about the alternatives to and consequences of conduct that overrides human rights.

Under IHL, the epistemic threshold at which a commander may assert that an attack is without alternative is much lower. Article 57(3) API demands that ‘[w]hen a choice is possible between several military objectives for obtaining a similar military advantage’ the attacker shall select the objective that can be attacked with the least expected incidental harm. This is not usually interpreted to mean that an attacker has to actively search as far and wide as reasonably possible for alternative targets with better expected incidental harm prognoses.Footnote 48 An attacker’s required knowledge about the consequences of an attack hinges on the feasibility of acquiring this knowledge. An attacker has to ‘take all feasible precautions in the choice of means and methods of attack with a view to avoiding, and in any event to minimizing, incidental loss of civilian life’.Footnote 49 That may often mean that an attacker explores the possibility of further reducing expected civilian casualties. However, equally as often, few or no measures to explore civilian harm mitigation may be feasible.

Crucially, an attacker is permitted to launch an attack even if all feasible verification measures were insufficient to establish with reasonable certainty that the expected incidental civilian harm could not have been further reduced while still achieving the military advantage at stake.Footnote 50 Although doing ‘everything feasible’ appears to be a demanding legal standard, it makes the level of knowledge required under IHL contingent on the circumstances of an attack.Footnote 51 It follows that complying with IHL does not vouchsafe that a reasonable observer (with reasonably sufficient knowledge about the alternatives and consequences of an attack) deems the expected incidental civilian deaths the only possible path to the achievement of a given military advantage. This, however, is the connection between expected casualties and a military advantage that IHRL would require if achieving a military advantage was equivalent to a lawful aim recognised under IHRL.Footnote 52

The jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) corroborates the argument that incidental civilian harm permitted under IHL is not systematically covered by the ECHR’s permission to exceptionally override an innocent bystander’s right to life.Footnote 53 The Court has ostensibly drawn on IHL’s requirement to take precautions in attack when elucidating the meaning of a necessary deprivation of the right to life in contexts of large-scale organised violence.Footnote 54 At the same time, the Court has mostly stayed faithful to the strict necessity standard of IHRL.Footnote 55 It has regularly enquired into the legitimacy of the aim behind the State’s use of violence.Footnote 56 Moreover, judgments feature not only questions about the availability of milder means, but also about the care devoted to exploring the latter.Footnote 57 A close reading of Article 57 API leaves little room for doubt that the Court has thereby asked for more care towards persons not directly participating in hostilities than would be required under IHL.

C. IHL and Soldiers’ Human Right to Life during HostilitiesFootnote 58

IHL permits intentional lethal attacks against combatants and members of organised armed groups who have a continuous combat function,Footnote 59 hence against persons who regularly participate in hostilities.Footnote 60 Could their participation in hostilities, even if it conformed to the principles of IHL, be considered unlawful so that their threat or use of violence might trigger an exception to their human right to life? Individuals fighting for an organised armed group against their own State are indeed likely in breach of their domestic legal obligations.Footnote 61 In an internal NIAC, when the State attacks enemy fighters, it thus deprives individuals of their right to life who engage in violence that is unlawful under domestic law. If an intervening State is authorised by the territorial State to use force against members of an organised armed group, it may also often be true that the latter’s fighters have defied the territorial State’s laws by taking up arms against a third State. We cannot assume this to be the case if an intervening State wages war against an organised armed group without the territorial State’s consent.Footnote 62 Furthermore, we have no reason to believe that combatants fighting for a State party to a conflict have broken the domestic law applicable to them.

When it comes to the lawfulness of the use of force by combatants, rather than relying on domestic law, we could draw on general international law (namely, the ius contra bellum) to establish whether and when IHL-conforming participation in hostilities amounts to an unlawful threat or use of violence for the purposes of IHRL. Namely, we could argue that combatants who contribute to a State’s use of force in contravention of Article 2(4) UN Charter and corresponding customary law are using violence unlawfully, even if it accords with IHL. In this reading, participation in a legal (defensive or mandated) IAC would prima facie leave intact combatants’ right to life under IHRL. At the same time, none of the violence threatened or used by combatants on the side of the aggressor State would be lawful for the purposes of IHRL, even if it complied with the principles of IHL. Participation in hostilities on the side of an aggressor State would thus open a combatant to the permissible deprivation of their human right to life.

Of course, IHL permits attacks against combatants on all sides in an IAC, regardless of the status of a belligerent’s resort to force. More importantly, it is highly problematic to suggest that general international law could trigger an exception to the prohibition on depriving individuals of their human right to life. This would amount to anchoring an individual’s legal status under IHRL in the conduct of her or his State, over which she or he has likely little or no control.Footnote 63 Nonetheless, the United Nations Committee on Human Rights, in its recent commentary on Article 6, has endorsed a view that links the lawfulness of States’ use of violence on the battlefield to the status of the resort to force under general international law. Though not addressing the implications of this stipulation for the status of individual combatants, the Committee has argued that ‘[s]tates parties engaged in acts of aggression as defined in international law […] violate ipso facto Article 6 of the Covenant’.Footnote 64

Even if a State’s breach of the ius contra bellum could in principle trigger a permission to deprive an individual of his or her right to life under IHRL, even combatants whose IHL-compliant participation in hostilities contributed to waging an aggressive war would not necessarily have lost their human right to life. Depriving an individual who threatens another with unlawful violence of their right to life has to be necessary under IHRL.Footnote 65 Lethal attack has to be the last resort. IHL’s permission to intentionally kill combatants at all times, except when they are hors de combat, on the other hand, is not tied to combatants’ in fact using violence or posing a threat. The same is widely deemed to be true for members of organised armed groups with a continuous combat function.Footnote 66 Lethal attack against them can be the intended and planned first resort. Recent scholarly claims that IHL requires that killing soldiers is necessaryFootnote 67 have been roundly rejected.Footnote 68

IHRL’s exceptional permission to override an individual’s human right to life for the purposes of ‘quelling an insurrection or emergency’ or ‘establishing public order’ does not cover IHL’s permission to intentionally kill soldiers either. IHRL again requires necessity, as discussed in the previous sub-section. Although combatants can through their conduct gain immunity from attack, namely, by surrendering,Footnote 69 no particular conduct on their part is required for IHL to endorse their killing in the first place.Footnote 70 IHL’s provision that is most directly geared towards benefiting combatants who are not already hors de combat is the prohibition on employing ‘weapons, projectiles and material and methods of warfare of a nature to cause superfluous injury or unnecessary suffering’.Footnote 71 This provision shines a glaring light on IHL’s endorsement of virtually all intentional attacks against soldiers; its endorsement of conduct that will often amount to a deprivation of the soldiers’ right to life in contravention of IHRL.

D. IHL’s Authorisation of Conduct that Amounts to a Human Rights Violation

Some scholars argue that we can avoid the problematic conclusion that IHL authorises violations of IHRL by claiming that IHL is only ‘prohibitory’ and does not confer any authorisations at all. In this reading, the principle of proportionality is merely the absence of a prohibition on proportionate incidental civilian harm, not a legal liberty to cause foreseen non-excessive harm to civilians. Moreover, in this view, rather than a legally privileged course of action, killing combatants is conduct that IHL has simply omitted to outlaw. This interpretation is surprising because the Geneva Conventions as well as the Protocols contain a number of demands for positive causal interventions into the world, for instance, taking all feasible measures to minimise incidental harm or issuing a warning before an attack. Conduct meant to meet these requirements is surely, by logical implication, imbued with the authority of a legal permission. Nonetheless, this interpretation of the principles of distinction, proportionality and necessity as mere prohibitions is frequently stated rather than defended.Footnote 72 The two most convincing explanations ultimately both fall short.

Adil Haque maintains that IHL affords combatants immunity from prosecution for participation in hostilities. However, it cannot grant combatants an authorisation to participate in hostilities because it does not ‘authorize organized armed groups to kill State armed forces or to harm civilians’.Footnote 73 He holds that this lack of authorisation for organised armed groups is evident because members of organised armed groups are subject to domestic criminal prosecution for participation in hostilities. IHL cannot then authorise combatants fighting for States, lest the principle of equal applicability is in jeopardy.Footnote 74 This reasoning rests on four claims which are unlikely to be simultaneously true: first, members of (non-State) organised armed groups are not authorised to use force because they are not immune from prosecution for participation in hostilities; secondly, combatants are not authorised to use force because a divergence in formal authorisations between combatants and members of non-State armed groups would challenge belligerent equality; thirdly, even though they are not authorised to participate in hostilities, combatants are immune from prosecution for participation in hostilities; fourthly, this divergence in immunities between combatants and members of non-State armed groups does not challenge belligerent equality.

Let us assume that members of non-State organised armed groups are indeed neither immune from prosecution nor authorised to use force (claim one), but combatants are both. Only in NIACs would this asymmetry in authorisations create an inequality among belligerents (claim two). In IACs, claim two would not hold. IHL allows States to incorporate or recognise paramilitaries or irregular armed groups.Footnote 75 This, in turn, confers the immunities and authorisations associated with combatant status on their members.Footnote 76 Individuals who fight in an IAC as members of an organised armed group without the backing of a State party share their lack of immunity from prosecution, and, in Haque’s view, the attending lack of authorisation to use force, with civilians who temporarily directly participate in hostilities, spies and mercenaries. As this fate befalls these groups of individuals on any side of an IAC, it does not affect the equal applicability of IHL.Footnote 77

In NIACs, on the other hand, if members of the State’s armed forces were authorised to use force and a lack of immunity from prosecution meant that members of (non-State) organised armed groups were not authorised to use force, an inequality among belligerents would indeed follow. However, the equality IHL affords belligerents in wars that pit a State against a non-State actor has arguably always been, and necessarily remains, qualified.Footnote 78 This qualification is evidenced not least in the asymmetry in immunities that Haque affirms in claim three: he holds that IHL affords immunity for combatants’ participation in hostilities (claim three), but his claim that IHL does not authorise participation in hostilities rests on the observation that IHL does not afford such immunity for participation to members of non-State organised armed groups. If in NIACs an asymmetry in immunities does not undermine belligerent equality (claim four), why should an asymmetry in formal authorisations to use force have this effect?

Even if we insisted on full belligerent equality also in NIACs, it would still not follow that IHL does not authorise killing in NIACs or indeed in IACs. In NIACs it is plausible to contest that IHL provides immunity from prosecution even for combatants fighting on behalf of the State. Article 6(5) APII urges the authorities in power at the end of hostilities to grant amnesty to persons who have participated in hostilities. Note that the provision refers to the ‘authorities in power’ at the end of hostilities, not the High Contracting Party. The Protocol evidently envisages the possibility that the regime challenger prevails and prosecutes soldiers who started out as combatants fighting on behalf of the State. The treaty hence acknowledges that in NIACs, IHL can afford immunity from prosecution to neither side. This is consistent with the absence in APII of a provision spelling out a ‘right’ of the State’s combatants to participate in hostilities. If we think of lack of immunity from prosecution as indicative of a lack of authorisation to use force, we could hence conclude that APII indeed does not authorise either side to use violence. Alternatively, the Protocols’ plea for immunity from prosecution under domestic law may simply not be indicative of whether IHL authorises participation in hostilities at all. In either case, nothing much follows for our interpretation of API and IHL’s permissions in IACs. The difference between the two treaties – APII lacks most of the provisions on the conduct of hostilities that I argue authorise attacks – means that something that is true for APII does not by logical implication hold for API.Footnote 79

Derek Jinks offers a different argument, unrelated to belligerents’ power to prosecute individual soldiers, for why IHL does not authorise the attacks that do not defy it. He maintains that the Geneva Conventions cannot be ‘read like domestic statutes’ because they do not ‘authorize states to engage in practices otherwise forbidden in law’.Footnote 80 It is not at all obvious, however, why international law should only be able to authorise conduct as an exception to its own prior prohibition. This evokes a bilateralist international system, in which States start out as utterly unfettered sovereigns whose actions are deemed acceptable unless expressly prohibited by international law. This view radically challenges dominant understandings of the contemporary international legal order.Footnote 81 Crucially, even if we subscribed to the view that all State conduct not prohibited by international law is permissible, we would not necessarily have to endorse the position that international law is only prohibitory. As a matter of logic, nothing would prevent international law from endowing with the legitimacy of a legal permission conduct that a State could otherwise have engaged in without either violating or actualising a legal rule.

Jinks’ contention that IHL does not concern practices otherwise forbidden under international law is all the more astonishing because he is a proponent of the co-applicability of IHL and IHRL, but denies their convergence.Footnote 82 Jinks endorses the view that before conflicts of laws are resolved or a State derogates, during war, IHRL prohibits any and all deprivations of the right to life that do not meet any of its own recognised exceptions (for co-applicability). He also correctly deems ‘perverse’ the ICJ’s view that IHL elucidates the meaning of such exceptions and that all killing in war permitted, or in his view not prohibited, by IHL does not violate IHRL (against convergence). Logically, IHL’s principles for the conduct of hostilities then govern practices that are already heavily regulated by international law, namely, by IHRL. The conduct of hostilities is rife with ‘prior prohibitions’,Footnote 83 to which IHL could be deemed to afford exceptions.

Even if the argument that killing in compliance with IHL is not formally authorised by IHL were compelling, we would still face a legal situation in which IHRL prohibits conduct that IHL does not prohibit. A denial of IHL’s authorisation of violence does not at all answer the question as to which body of law an individual on the battlefield ought to turn to for guidance. Moreover, regardless of whether IHL formally authorises the conduct that it does not prohibit, we have to grapple with the considerable expressive force of the uncontested legal situation that IHL does not prohibit intentional killings of soldiers and foreseen side-effect deaths of civilians.Footnote 84 The traditional reference to ‘belligerent privilege’ suggests that, scholarly debate notwithstanding, military practitioners widely assume that IHL endorses the attacks that do not defy it; attacks that will often breach IHRL, depriving civilians and sometimes soldiers of the right to life they enjoy under IHRL.

III. The Moral Right to Life and the Legal Permissibility of Killing in War

A. The Law’s Moral Tasks in War

When two simultaneously applicable bodies of law make diverging demands, the morally better law should prevail. How do we decide which one is the morally better law? Largely side-stepping the extraordinarily complex question of how law conceptually relates to morality, I make two assumptions: first, the content of law can be determined without reference to morality. It is hence possible that law makes demands on its subjects that diverge from their moral duties. Secondly, individuals have a moral interest in the rule of law ‘because human life goes better when subjected to governance by a (conscientious) authority’.Footnote 85 Legality therefore provides a moral reason for action. This reason is not decisive. It may sometimes be morally impermissible to obey a wicked law. At the same time, a morally wrongful act can be less wrongful because it is required by law.Footnote 86 With these assumptions, I rely on Raz’ conceptualisation of law as ‘a kind of complex social practice [that] can be put to moral use, and that, where it exists … has moral tasks to discharge’.Footnote 87

What are the law’s tasks through the performance of which it can morally improve human life? In Raz’ view, a law exercises legitimate authority over its subjects if the latter better conform to the moral reasons that apply to them when they act according to the guidance of the law.Footnote 88 Law can provide a moral service to the individual by assisting him or her in adopting the morally right conduct. This is the law’s first moral task. Crucially, this ability to guide the individual towards fulfilment of her or his moral obligations does not exhaust the law’s ability to morally improve human life. Law can also serve the individual as a guarantor of her or his moral rights. Law can be of moral use to each individual by ensuring that the conduct of legal subjects overall better conforms to the moral goal of preserving individual rights. Guiding behaviour towards the fullest possible protection of individual rights is the law’s second moral task.Footnote 89

When there is a conflict between simultaneously applicable legal rules, we should allow those rules to prevail that better accomplish these two moral tasks. The first step in determining whether IHL or IHRL ought to govern the conduct of hostilities is then to establish what moral obligations apply to the individual on the battlefield and what battlefield conduct leads to the best possible outcome in terms of protecting individual rights.Footnote 90 Ordinarily we forfeit our moral right to life only when we responsibly contribute to an unjustified threat against another person.Footnote 91 The defensive harm we make ourselves liable to by virtue of this conduct has to be proportionate and necessary to avert the unjustified threat. Moreover, it can sometimes be morally justified to override innocent bystanders’ moral right to life in order to prevent a greater moral evil.Footnote 92 Crucially, the only moral evil that warrants overriding an innocent bystander’s right to life is a great number of unjustified individual rights infringements.Footnote 93 Unintended, but foreseen harm against non-liable individuals has to be necessary for and proportionate to the moral aim of preventing a greater number of individual rights violations.

During the conduct of hostilities, law fulfils its first moral task if it guides soldiers towards directing fire against individuals who are morally liable to defensive harm or against targets that harm only individuals whose killing can be justified as a necessary and proportionate side-effect of the achievement of a morally just war aim. The law’s second moral task is to reduce as much as possible unjustified infringements (i.e., violations) of individual rights in a war. Guiding agents towards the course of action that fulfils their moral duties and that thus avoids individual rights violations in each instance is normally the best way to avoid such violations overall. Both moral tasks therefore prima facie point towards the same morally ideal legal rules: international law that discharges its two moral tasks in war prohibits all killing that amounts to, or results in, morally unjustified infringements of the individual right to life.

Is the law that better discharges these moral tasks in war, then, the law that more closely restates these fundamental moral prescriptions about the permissibility of killing? No, if there are genuine epistemic barriers to establishing which course of action avoids unjustified infringements of individual rights on the battlefield, a law that simply mirrors the moral demand will fail to discharge the law’s first moral task. By comparison, a law that accommodates systematic epistemic constraints on decision-making and that is clear, accessible and action-guiding in the context in which it actually addresses individuals is more effective in helping them conform to their moral obligations.Footnote 94 In general, a law that guides its addressees through the choice they typically encounter is better at discharging its first moral task than a law that addresses the individual as if he or she were omniscient. The epistemic context of decision-making on the battlefield is hence relevant to the question of whether IHL or IHRL better discharges the law’s first moral task.

Epistemic constraints account for why even the best possible law for discharging its first moral task may not always point towards the morally right course of action. The harder it is to morally parse the situations in which a law typically addresses the individual – due to time pressure on action, moral complexity or uncertain consequences – the more we should expect the morally best law for discharging its first task to diverge from underlying moral principles.Footnote 95 The more we should also expect that law may have to stipulate what is usually the morally right course of action, but not necessarily the right course of action in all situations. Law discharges its first moral task if an individual guided by law generally better conforms to her or his moral obligations than an individual not guided by law. The closer and more often law-directed conduct fulfils the guided individuals’ moral obligations, the better the law is at discharging its first moral task. However, compliance with law may not vouchsafe that conduct in all situations is morally right.

That law is action-guiding and sensitive to the epistemic context in which its subjects actually operate is also crucial for law’s ability to discharge its second moral task of securing the fullest feasible protection for individual moral rights. In addition, there is another reason why a law might better discharge its second moral task if it diverges from fundamental moral precepts: volitional defects, which are incentive structures, emotional or cognitive biases that account for why agents systematically fail to follow their moral obligations.Footnote 96 Law can cure some volitional defects by attaching sanctions to certain courses of action that subjects are tempted to take instead of the morally right course of action. Alternatively, law can counter some volitional defects by making detailed demands on how to act that ‘would be unintelligible as elements in moral rules or principles’.Footnote 97 Both sanctions and detailed action guidance can improve a law’s ability to secure a better moral outcome in terms of protecting individual rights in the face of volitional defects.

However, law cannot cure all volitional defects. Sometimes, outlawing morally wrongful actions creates incentives for further wrongdoing and thus morally worse results.Footnote 98 At other times, a law that prescribes the morally right conduct would be highly costly to obey, all while non-compliance is hard to sanction.Footnote 99 Such a law would likely be ignored and miss altogether the opportunity to morally improve the effects of conduct for the protection of individual rights.Footnote 100 By comparison, a law that accommodates the volitional defects that it cannot cure, by demanding less or other than the morally required course of action, may be able to secure better moral outcomes for rights. The volitional context of decision-making during armed conflict hence matters for the question of whether IHL or IHRL better discharges the law’s second moral task.

Incurable volitional defects can create a tension between the morally better law for discharging the law’s first task and the morally better law for discharging the law’s second task. If law demanded conduct that typically points individuals towards the conduct that fulfils their moral obligations, considering epistemic uncertainty and the need for law to guide action across a range of situations (task one), but this demand would, due to incurable volitional defects, be ignored or create worse moral results, law would fall short in its second task. On the other hand, if law demanded less than the morally right conduct in order to accommodate an incurable volitional defect and thereby morally improve the results of conduct (task two), it would fall short in discharging its first moral task. Both moral tasks are equally important. When they imply divergent rules, what is the solution?

If the demands associated with discharging the law’s two tasks diverge, a law that satisfices rather than maximises its ability to discharge either of its moral tasks may be morally preferable. Specifically, what such a law ought to look like depends on answers to two questions: first, how great a divergence from the morally right conduct would law have to prescribe in order to produce the fullest feasible protection of individual rights; and, secondly, how far from the morally best possible outcomes for the protection of individual rights would the results of conduct be, if law did not accommodate incurable volitional defects, but insisted on prescribing the typically morally right course of action? The law should strike the least morally costly compromise possible between its two tasks. In such a situation, the morally best possible law is then neither the law that, as often as possible, prescribes the typically morally right course of action (task one), nor the law that as much as possible protects rights in the outcome of conduct (task two).

There are two reasons then why even a law that discharges both its moral tasks (i.e., first, individuals guided by law, compared with those not guided by law, more often meet their moral obligations and, second, individual rights are better protected than in the absence of guidance by law) might permit or even ask for conduct that is morally wrongful in a particular situation: first, epistemic constraints mean law prescribes the course of action that is typically, but not always, the morally right course of action; and, second, law prescribes conduct other than the morally right course of action in order to accommodate incurable volitional defects. In situations in which law, as a result, demands conduct other than the morally right conduct, should an individual obey the law?

It can indeed be permissible or morally required to disobey a law that discharges its two moral tasks. However, such cases should be rare. As mentioned, law that discharges its moral tasks, but diverges from fundamental moral prescriptions, does so primarily because there are epistemic obstacles to determining the morally right course of action or volitional barriers to individuals’ conforming to their obligations. Knowing this, individuals would need to have particularly compelling reasons to trust their own judgement over the law’s guidance. Moreover, when deciding whether to obey a legal rule, besides the question of whether (non-)compliance would instantiate their moral obligations, individuals ought to consider how (non-)compliance would affect the rule of law. As alluded to above, that conduct is demanded by law adds a moral reason to the balance of reasons. This is not indefeasible, but it is a weighty reason, particularly if the law generally discharges its moral tasks of guiding individuals towards the fulfilment of their duties and of protecting their rights.

To recapitulate, when two bodies of law make diverging demands – as IHRL and IHL do regarding the permissibility of killing – that which better discharges the law’s two moral tasks should prevail. The law’s moral tasks are to guide individuals’ actions as often as possible towards meeting their moral obligations of not violating individual rights (task one), and to secure the morally best possible outcomes for rights, meaning minimising unjustified infringements of individual rights overall (task two). Which rules better accomplish these two tasks depends on the epistemic and volitional context of decision-making on the battlefield.Footnote 101 If there is a tension between the demands of the law’s two moral tasks due to incurable volitional defects, the morally better law strikes the morally less costly compromise between its two tasks. The next two sub-sections explore to what extent IHL and IHRL, respectively, diverge from fundamental moral prescriptions about the permissibility of killing. Sections IV and V then systematically map which body of law better performs the law’s moral tasks in the epistemic and volitional context of real-world armed conflicts.

B. IHRL and the Moral Right to Life

Both moral justifications for infringing individuals’ moral right to life, that is, forfeiture and avoidance of a greater evil, have echoes in IHRL. A person who threatens another with unlawful violence, and who may hence be deprived of their human right to life under Article 2(2)(a) ECHR, may also be morally liable to necessary and proportionate defensive harm due to the forfeiture of her or his moral right. If a person poses a threat by evading lawful detention or arrest, just as they may have forfeited their legal right to life in accordance with Article 2(2)(b) ECHR, they may have forfeited their moral right to life. In addition, Article 2(2)(c) ECHR permits overriding individual rights with a view to allowing a State to avert an insurrection or riot, something that may well be a greater moral evil.Footnote 102

Although these exceptions to the prohibition on depriving individuals of their legal right to life under IHRL have similar structures to moral justifications for killing, the scope of the moral and legal permissions does not necessarily always align. Not every evasion even of a lawful arrest or detention warrants a lethal attack from a moral point of view, even if such an attack is ‘absolutely necessary’ and proportionate to the threat as demanded by the ECHR.Footnote 103 After all, the threat posed by the fleeing individual may be morally justified.Footnote 104 By the same token, we cannot be sure that in every instance in which State agents kill individuals for the purpose of quelling a riot or insurrection in accordance with IHRL, individual rights are really sacrificed for the avoidance of a greater moral evil.Footnote 105 Whether an insurrection or riots amount to a greater moral evil depends on the harm to innocent bystanders that quashing the insurrection likely necessitates as well as on the likely implications of the insurrection for citizens’ fundamental moral rights.Footnote 106

By hinging its permissions on the lawfulness of the threat or the use of violence rather than on its moral justification, IHRL opens the door to a possible lack of congruence between morally and legally permissible killing. At the same time, the more legitimate the authority of a State is and the more a State’s laws in general fulfil their moral tasks, the more likely it is that there will nonetheless often be an alignment between legally permissible human rights deprivations and morally justified killing. The reason is that overriding individual rights for the sake of establishing public order is more likely to be morally justified if the State institutions are morally legitimate, protecting individual rights in the first place. In turn, a riot or insurrection is more likely to be morally unjustified if the State exercises legitimate authority. Similarly, the morally better a State’s laws are at discharging their two moral tasks, in general, the more likely it is that an unlawful threat of violence or the evasion of a lawful arrest is also morally unjustified.

Moreover, as IHRL hinges the permissibility of individual rights infringements on the lawfulness of the arrest, the unlawfulness of the threatened violence and the preservation of the State’s legal authority, it generally permits the deprivation of individual rights in furtherance of the rule of law. As mentioned above, the latter is itself a morally important goal in as much as law performs its dual service to the individual of guiding him or her towards his or her moral duties and protecting a person’s moral rights. Some infringements of individual rights that IHRL authorises, which would on the balance of reasons be morally unjustified, might end up being morally permissible, or at least less morally wrongful, if we account for the moral importance of upholding the rule of law. Nonetheless IHRL’s focus on unlawful rather than on unjustified threats means that divergences between legally and morally permissible killing cannot be ruled out.

This very focus on unlawful rather than on unjustified threats, however, may improve IHRL’s ability to discharge its first moral task. When making what is potentially a split-second decision about whether it is necessary to shoot a fleeing individual, a law-enforcement officer may have neither the requisite information nor the cognitive capacity to make a judgement about whether the fugitive’s threat is morally justified. That lawfulness, not moral justification, is the reference point for the legal permissibility of rights deprivations according to IHRL is one way in which this law lightens the individual agent’s ‘burden of judgement’.Footnote 107 Similarly, by replacing ‘avoiding a greater moral evil in terms of individual rights violations’ with the morally potentially over- and under-inclusive, but much more concrete goal of ‘establishing public order in an emergency’, the ECHR better discharges its moral task of guiding action towards what is, in a State that exercises legitimate authority, typically the course of action that conforms to an individual’s moral obligations.

Of course, not all divergences between moral principles and IHRL’s rules on the protection of the individual right to life will necessarily serve the law’s ability to discharge its first moral task and guide its subjects towards the morally right course of action all while accommodating epistemic constraints. After all, drafting a treaty, such as the ICCPR or the ECHR, is a political process, which gives expression to the interests of the drafters. IHRL, for instance, allows deprivations of the right to life in the execution of a lawful death sentence. A convicted criminal in custody rarely poses an imminent threat. Whether killing a person because of their past culpable wrongdoing, hence for reasons of retribution and possibly in the uncertain hope of deterrence, can ever be morally justified is much more contestable than the justifiability of necessary lethal harm to avoid a future wrong.Footnote 108 Nonetheless, both mentioned treaties permit it.Footnote 109

At the same time, the permissibility of capital punishment may serve the law’s ability to discharge its second moral task. As mentioned above, considering the incentive structure of its addressees is one condition for law’s ability to morally improve the outcome of conduct. This not only means managing volitional defects of the individual whose conduct law seeks to guide, for instance, law-enforcement officers or soldiers. International law, unlike most domestic laws, also needs to accommodate the incentives of the agents who decide whether a treaty is ratified. It bears noting, however, that a treaty’s divergence from underlying moral prescriptions that are necessary to ensure ratification ultimately only helps law discharge its second moral task if, the pragmatic divergence from moral precepts notwithstanding, guidance of law still results in morally better outcomes for the protection of individual rights than conduct not guided by law.

From a moral point of view there is a limit then to how far international law should accommodate incurable volitional defects in order to secure treaty ratification and hence the law’s applicability. If law prescribes conduct that is not the morally right conduct in order to avoid being ignored, this has costs in terms of the law’s ability to discharge its first moral task. If the course of conduct that law prescribes in order to be deemed applicable also leads to outcomes that are overall morally worse or no better than those of conduct unguided by law, then accommodating incurable volitional defects also undermines law’s discharging of its second moral task. In this case, law should prioritise its first moral task and risk being ignored or not ratified, thereby failing to discharge its second task.

C. IHL and the Moral Right to Life

Both moral justifications for infringing the individual moral right to life, forfeiture and avoidance of a greater evil, have echoes also in IHL. IHL’s rules governing the conduct of hostilities, however, diverge significantly further than IHRL’s from the moral principles that determine the moral permissibility of killing. The general lack of congruence between IHL’s rules and moral principles centred on the protection of individual rights is well appreciated among just war theorists.Footnote 110 This section briefly discusses the three main features of IHL that account for this further divergence: first, the legal permission to intentionally kill all soldiers, regardless of necessity and proportionality; secondly, IHL’s failure to demand actual necessity when permitting the deaths of innocent bystanders/civilians; and, thirdly, IHL’s equal empowerment of all parties to a war, regardless of the moral or legal status of their aims.

First, according to IHL, all combatants are always legally permissible targets of attack; civilians are prima facie immune from intentional harm. There may be a systematic coincidence between having combatant status and having the skills and intention to pose a threat to the enemy.Footnote 111 Ultimately, however, being a combatant is an assigned status, which first and foremost results from membership in a belligerent State’s organised armed forces. Military cooks, mechanics and logistics personnel are all permissible targets of lethal attack.Footnote 112 In fact, neither the ability nor the inclination to inflict harm on the enemy is a condition for combatant status under IHL. Even combatants actually trained for combat may lack the skills, courage or motivation to pose a threat. Finally, combatants retain their status as legal targets of intentional attack when their location or occupation makes them decidedly non-threatening. The latter is also true for members of non-State armed groups with a continuous combat function. They remain permissible targets of intentional attack regardless of their actual conduct, intention or location until they opt out of their combat function.

Moreover, even if all soldiers indeed posed a threat to the enemy, they would not all be morally liable to being killed. To be morally responsible for a threat they pose, individuals either have to be aware or reasonably should be aware of the moral status of this threat. In reality, soldiers often systematically lack the information necessary to make the determination of whether their aim in war is just.Footnote 113 Moreover, some soldiers may have been coerced into fighting either by a State, an organised armed group or by circumstances. Soldiers who are coerced or who act in the reasonable, but mistaken, belief that their use of violence is justified may therefore be excused, in which case their moral liability to defensive harm is in question.Footnote 114 Finally, even soldiers who are fully morally responsible for an unjustified threat they pose, are not necessarily morally liable to lethal attack if it is possible to avert the threat they pose by milder means.Footnote 115 Just as many soldiers, who are permissible targets of lethal attack under IHL, retain their legal right to life under IHRL, many will not have forfeited their moral right to life.Footnote 116

It is not hard to find reasons for why IHL should not attempt to restate the conditions of moral liability to harm in lieu of the principle of distinction. If it did, rather than a blanket permission to kill all soldiers and an obligation to spare all civilians, IHL would have to dictate that attackers direct harm towards individuals who responsibly contribute to the threat posed by a belligerent, but only if lethal attack is a necessary and proportionate response to that contribution. Such a law might fail in its first moral task of guiding soldiers who generally lack the information necessary to determine the moral status of the person they face on the battlefield.Footnote 117 Indeed, such a law might fail to fulfil its second moral task as well. In the supremely stressful environment of battle, combatants who are subject to dehumanising narratives about and physical threats from the enemy may well perceive any individual ‘on the other side’ as morally liable to harm. A law that explicitly endorsed killing individuals based on their moral status, might exacerbate rather than cure this volitional defect, leading to more rather than less unjustified killing.

The second divergence of IHL’s prescriptions from moral principles concerns unintentional but foreseeable harm to innocent bystanders. When moral principles demand that such incidental harm has to be necessary, much like IHRL, that means harm ought to be the only and the mildest available course of action for the achievement of an aim. As outlined in the previous section, IHL in contrast only requires that an attacker does not eschew a target with a more favourable ‘collateral damage’ prognosis ‘when a choice is possible’ between similar targets. IHL further demands that the attacker takes all ‘feasible’ steps to reduce expected incidental civilian harm. Even if an attacker caused incidental civilian harm in order to achieve a morally just aim, IHL’s epistemic standard for when an attacker may deem necessary an attack that kills civilians is too low to vouchsafe that killing civilians is morally permissible.Footnote 118

Thirdly, as already indicated, both moral permissions – intentionally killing an individual in defence against a threat and foreseeably killing an innocent bystander on grounds of necessity – depend on the attacker’s pursuing a morally just aim. In war that means that even if all soldiers responsibly contributed to the threat posed by their belligerent State, from a moral point of view only those on the unjust side would prima facie be liable to defensive harm. In contrast, the equal applicability of IHL, specifically the ‘right to participate in hostilities’ of combatants on both sides in an IAC without regard to ‘the causes espoused by … or attributed to the parties to the conflict’,Footnote 119 means that IHL also endorses killing in defence against a morally justified threat. It is also due to the equal applicability of IHL that IHL’s principle of proportionality regularly permits killing civilians, hence potentially innocent bystanders, in pursuit of an aim that is morally unjust.Footnote 120

Again, it is not difficult to find epistemic constraints that account for why IHL needs to bracket the moral status of the resort to force when prescribing conduct in war if it is to fulfil its first moral task. Determining whether or not a belligerent’s resort to force is morally justified, and hence whether an attack contributes to the pursuit of a morally just aim, is a complex, future-oriented judgement. It involves estimating whether waging war is the lesser moral evil in terms of unjustified individual rights infringements compared with not resorting to force. I have argued elsewhere in detail that this question in reality regularly amounts to an ‘epistemically cloaked forced choice’.Footnote 121 Even if we could overcome the inherent difficulty of judging whether the resort to force will be a moral lesser evil, this judgement is unlikely to be sound without precise information about what is at stake when a State resorts to force and how a war is meant to unfold from a military point of view. This is information that States typically do not share with their soldiers.Footnote 122

Tying the permissibility of conduct in war to the moral status of a war’s aim, would not only mean that compliance with law would require that combatants answer a question to which they almost certainly do not know the answer, undermining the law’s ability to discharge its first moral task. A law that tied the legal permissibility of killing to whether or not an attack was launched in pursuit of a just aim would also be undermined in the fulfilment of its second moral task of reducing individual rights violations as much as possible. In an international system of sovereign and formally equal States, who would hold to account a State that resorted to force for an unjust aim, but allowed combatants to avail themselves of the legal empowerments that IHL reserves for just combatants? An alternative IHL which differentiated between belligerents depending on the justice of their aim would, at best, secure both sides’ compliance with the law for the just side. Worse even, such an ‘asymmetrical IHL’ might simply miss the opportunity to better protect individual rights on at least one side in each war.

If we compare all three codes of conduct – IHRL’s prescriptions, IHL’s demands and moral obligations – side by side, it becomes evident that IHL diverges further from moral precepts than IHRL along the three lines mentioned: first, individuals are morally liable to lethal attack only if they pose or contribute to an unjustified threat for which they are responsible, and the threat means a lethal attack is necessary and proportionate. IHRL demands that intentional lethal attacks are directed against individuals who use or threaten unlawful violence which makes the use of defensive lethal force necessary and proportionate. In opposition, IHL permits targeting soldiers based on their status as combatants or because they assume a continuous combat function, regardless of the necessity or proportionality of the attack.

Secondly, it may be morally permissible to unintentionally kill an innocent bystander if this is necessary for and proportionate to preventing a greater number of individual rights violations. IHRL likewise demands that unintentional killing of innocent bystanders is strictly necessary for and proportionate to the achievement of a legally recognised aim, generally involving the protection of human life. In contrast, IHL only demands that attackers do everything feasible to minimise expected incidental civilian harm. And if two attacks are expected to yield the same military advantage and a choice is possible, they should attack the target that is expected to cause less incidental civilian harm. Civilian harm needs to be proportionate only to the achievement of a military advantage, not the achievement of a war’s aim.

Thirdly, from a moral point of view, individuals only forfeit their right to life if they contribute to an unjust threat. Similarly, it is only ever morally permissible to kill innocent bystanders in pursuit of a just aim – only then can their deaths potentially be justified as the lesser moral evil. Under IHRL, law enforcement officials may use violence only during a lawful arrest and in defence against unlawful violence. By the same token, the State needs a legally recognised aim to override the right to life of innocent bystanders, for instance, quelling an insurrection or averting ‘danger to life or limb’.Footnote 123 IHL, in contrast, is symmetrical. That means IHL affords the same permissions to both sides in a war, regardless of the legal or moral status of the resort to force or the aims that belligerents pursue in a war.

The first section of this chapter established that IHRL and IHL give diverging answers to the question of when it is permissible to use lethal force. This section showed that IHL’s answer diverges further than IHRL’s from the answer that moral principles give to the question of whether and when it is permissible to kill a person. This makes IHRL prima facie better suited to discharging the law’s two moral tasks. However, whether IHRL is actually better at guiding the individual soldier towards the course of action on the battlefield that typically conforms to her or his moral obligations (task one) and whether it really is better at securing the protection of individual rights in war (task two) depends on the epistemic constraints and the volitional defects of decision-making during the actual conduct of hostilities. The next section will delineate the empirical phenomenon IHL is meant to govern, identifying the characteristics of armed conflicts that could affect epistemic barriers to and volitional defects in soldiers’ decision-making.

IV. Six Types of Armed Conflict

A. When is a Violent Confrontation an Armed Conflict?

The preceding section showed that IHRL more closely than IHL tracks moral principles regarding the permissibility of killing. Although this makes IHRL the prima facie morally better law, which body of law should prevail in a given context depends on which law better discharges the law’s moral tasks in that context. Traditionally, we think of the division of labour between IHRL and IHL as the former governing the use of force during law enforcement operations and the latter governing armed conflicts.Footnote 124 This section brackets the question of whether IHRL should indeed govern law enforcement operations. Given its status as the prima facie morally better law for governing permissible killing, I assume the answer to this question is yes. Instead, I seek to establish whether IHL should govern the conduct of hostilities during violent confrontations that are currently deemed to constitute armed conflicts.Footnote 125 In order to establish this, we need to analyse what characterises an armed conflict. Or, put differently, what distinguishes a confrontation that counts as an armed conflict from one that does not?

Historically wars were declared. In order for a confrontation to be considered a war, it had to be recognised as such by the warring States. This recognition, in turn, triggered the applicability of IHL.Footnote 126 The Hague and the Geneva Conventions of 1929, as a result, did not define war or armed conflict. The Geneva Conventions of 1949 radically break with this understanding of war as depending on recognition. According to Common Article 2, the Geneva Conventions shall ‘apply to all cases of declared war or of any other armed conflict which may arise between two or more of the High Contracting Parties’.Footnote 127 The Commentary stresses that ‘the determination of the existence of an armed conflict … must be based solely on the prevailing facts demonstrating the de facto existence of hostilities between the belligerents’.Footnote 128 But what are those prevailing facts?Footnote 129 What we can infer from the wording of the provision is no more and no less than that an armed conflict is any situation that involves the use of force between States.Footnote 130

Are any and all uses of force by States against States armed conflicts? In 1949, State-on-State violence not governed by IHL would have been beyond the purview of international law. Drafters therefore deemed it appropriate to conceive of the applicability of the Geneva Conventions in the widest possible terms. The Commentary describes it as ‘in conformity with the humanitarian purpose of the Conventions that there be no requirement of a specific level of intensity of violence to trigger an international armed conflict’.Footnote 131 Scholarly opinion is in almost total agreement that ‘[i]t makes no difference how long the conflict lasts, how much slaughter takes place, or how numerous are the participating forces’.Footnote 132 Neither is the existence of an armed conflict between States contingent on the purpose for which they use force.Footnote 133 The phenomenon that IHL is meant to govern then includes all situations in which one State uses armed force against another.

The identification of armed conflicts between a State and a non-State actor is by comparison more complicated. Even in 1949, the use of force by a State on its own territory would have been regulated by domestic law. An intensity threshold for the applicability of IHL to internal armed conflicts did therefore not create a legal black hole.Footnote 134 NIACs, first mentioned in Common Article 3 of the Geneva Conventions, are correspondingly widely deemed to be defined by a threshold of minimum intensity.Footnote 135 For the Second Additional Protocol of 1977 to apply to an armed confrontation the organised armed group has to be ‘under responsible command, exercise such control over a part of its territory as to enable them to carry out sustained and concerted military operations and to implement this Protocol’. Crucially, these criteria trigger the applicability of the treaty. They are not constitutive of an armed conflict because Common Article 3 is applicable to ‘armed conflict[s] not of an international character’, but it makes no such demands.

Where then is the threshold of minimum intensity for a NIAC more generally? One of the most widely reproduced concretisations of the required threshold of minimum intensity was articulated by the Appeals Chamber of the ICTY. It defines a NIAC as ‘protracted armed violence between governmental authorities and organised armed groups or between such groups within a State’.Footnote 136 Though widely accepted, this definition does not necessarily provide a definitive and incontestable test for each empirical case. Specifically, what criteria make armed violence ‘protracted’ is far from obvious.Footnote 137 Indicators drawn on in international jurisprudence include the frequency of hostile confrontations, the type and range of weapons and the calibre of munitions used, the number of persons participating in combat, wounded or killed as a result of hostilities, the severity and extent of the physical destruction and the number of displaced persons.Footnote 138

Assuming we can tell when these indicators of intensity point towards the existence of an armed conflict, is killing in all such situations really meant to be governed by IHL’s principles of distinction, proportionality and necessity? Common Article 3 does not itself concern the conduct of hostilities and not all NIACs also trigger the applicability of APII. The most recent authoritative commentary to Common Article 3, however, states that ‘when common Article 3 is applicable, other rules, especially those on the conduct of hostilities, with different restraints on the way force may be used compared to peacetime law, may also apply’.Footnote 139 This statement does not rule out that IHRL is simultaneously applicable during NIACs, but the contrast to ‘peacetime law’ is a gesture towards the traditional view that IHL’s rules for the conduct of hostilities displace otherwise applicable more stringent rules when armed violence meets the threshold of a NIAC.Footnote 140

In sum, IHL’s principles for the conduct of hostilities are meant to govern the permissibility of killing in all situations of armed force used between States and in all situations of ‘protracted armed violence between governmental authorities and organised armed groups or between such groups within a State’.Footnote 141 It is, hence, either a particular configuration of belligerents, namely States on both sides, or the intensity of a confrontation between a State and non-State challenger on the former’s territory that defines the real-world armed confrontations that count as armed conflicts under the purview of IHL. The former characterises and differentiates an IAC, the latter a NIAC from armed confrontations presumed to be governed by IHRL.

B. When does Intensity Matter?

In recent years instances of armed violence that seem to fit neither the definition of IACs as violence purely between States, nor that of NIACs as protracted violence on the territory of one High Contracting Party have become more frequent. Instead, these conflicts cross international borders while also involving non-State organised armed groups. As we have already established the applicability of the rules for the conduct of hostilities to all NIACs and IACs, we might be tempted to bracket the contested question of how to classify armed confrontations that appear to have elements of both types. However, to delineate the universe of real-world confrontations that IHL is meant to govern, and to understand the epistemic and volitional context of decision-making in these situations, we have to know whether we need to enquire into the intensity of a particular armed confrontation to assert the applicability of IHL (NIAC) or not (IAC).

Beyond classic NIACs (1) and IACs (2), we can distinguish four types of armed confrontation that cross international borders while also involving non-State organised armed groups:Footnote 142 (3) internal confrontations in which the territorial State is supported by a third State; (4) internal confrontations in which the non-State actor is supported by a third State; (5) internal confrontations that involve only one State, but spill over onto the territory of a neighbouring State; and (6) transnational confrontations between a State and a non-State actor entirely conducted on a third State’s territory, but without the consent of that territorial State. Which of these four types of armed confrontations are NIACs and which IACs? Or, put differently, which of these confrontations only fall under the purview of IHL if hostilities are ‘protracted’?

When another State or coalition of States intervenes in an internal confrontation on the side of the territorial State, we have an ‘internationally-supported internal confrontation’ (3). While the intervention lends the confrontation an international element, hostilities remain confined to one territory and there is no violence of one State against another, so that such internationally supported internal confrontations should be deemed NIACs. They fall under the purview of IHL only if they cross the threshold of being protracted.Footnote 143 The outside intervention on the side of the territorial State will often intensify hostilities that were previously below that threshold. Outside intervention can thus turn a situation from a law enforcement operation into a NIAC by intensifying hostilities, but this is not automatically the case and has to be separately established.

In contrast, if a State or coalition of States intervenes on the side of the non-State actor in an internal confrontation (4), the use of force between States ensues. Such an ‘internationalised internal confrontation’ is hence an IAC.Footnote 144 Even an internal confrontation that did not rise to the intensity of a NIAC before the intervention becomes an IAC once internationalised. Internationalised internal confrontations are therefore not subject to a requirement of minimum intensity in order to come under the purview of IHL. The difference between an ‘internationally supported internal confrontation’ and an ‘internationalised internal confrontation’ shows that it is not the involvement of more than one State in an armed confrontation per se that constitutes it as an IAC, but the crossing of borders by a State’s armed forces into another State’s territory without the latter’s consent or authorisation.

What about the use of force by a State on another State’s territory without the latter’s consent, but against a non-State actor rather than against the territorial State? Both ‘spill-over internal confrontations’ (5) and ‘transnational confrontations’ (6) raise this question. Dapo Akande has convincingly argued that in such situations, two armed conflicts exist in parallel: a NIAC between the State and the non-State actor; and an IAC between the intervening and the territorial State.Footnote 145 He has further stressed that it is practically impossible to establish whether an attack by the intervening State, meant to weaken the non-State actor but carried out on the territory of another State, is part of the NIAC or the IAC. Whether or not their intensity means that they meet the threshold of a NIAC, all attacks by a State against a non-State actor on another State’s territory are hence also part of an IAC.Footnote 146

In the case of a transnational confrontation (6), the cross-border scope of hostilities in effect moots the intensity requirement for the applicability of IHL. In the case of spill-over internal confrontations (5), attacks outside the State’s territory are likewise inevitably part of an IAC. However, this is not true for attacks carried out on the State’s own territory. We will have to separately establish that these internal hostilities cross the required threshold of intensity of being protracted to count as a NIAC. Spill-over internal confrontations might hence present the odd situation in which hostilities between the State and the organised armed group on the State’s own territory remain below the threshold of a NIAC, but their hostilities on another State’s territory are inextricably intertwined with and therefore part of an IAC, even if they are no more intense.Footnote 147

In sum, IHL is meant to govern the permissibility of killing in purely internal confrontations or classic NIACs with the involvement of no more than one State on that same State’s territory (1), internationally supported internal confrontations (3), and the internal part of a spill-over confrontation (5a), but only if hostilities cross a threshold of minimum intensity at which they count as ‘protracted’. In addition, IHL is meant to govern any armed force used by a State on the territory of another State, without the consent and not on behalf of the territorial State, regardless of its intensity. This category includes classic State-on-State IACs (2), internationalised internal confrontations (4), the part of an internal confrontation that spills-over into another State’s territory (5b), and transnational confrontations (6). It is thus one of two features that distinguish an armed confrontation that counts as an armed conflict under the purview of IHL from a law enforcement operation governed by IHRL: either the intensity of hostilities, that is, their protracted nature, or a State’s (non-authorised) use of armed force outside its own territory.

V. Discharging the Law’s Moral Tasks in Armed Conflicts

Section III showed that IHRL is prima facie better than IHL at guiding soldiers towards the conduct that conforms to their moral obligations (task one) and better at securing the protection of individual rights in the outcome of conduct (task two). However, epistemic constraints and volitional defects might make a law that further diverges from underlying moral principles, such as IHL, better at discharging one or both of the law’s moral tasks. Section IV suggested that an armed confrontation qualifies as an IAC that comes under the purview of IHL when a State is using force outside its own borders on the territory of another State without the territorial State’s authorisation or consent, regardless of the intensity of hostilities.Footnote 148 Moreover, armed confrontations count as NIACs that are governed by IHL when they do not involve a State’s using unauthorised force outside its own borders, but hostilities reach a threshold of intensity at which they count as ‘protracted’. In this section, we seek to answer the question as to whether either of these two features should trigger the applicability of IHL because they create epistemic barriers or volitional defects that undercut IHRL’s ability to better discharge the law’s two moral tasks.

Section A will show that the use of force beyond a State’s own territory does not per se create epistemic barriers that could affect IHRL’s ability to guide soldiers towards the fulfilment of their moral obligations (task one). Section B asserts that hostilities becoming more intense, in contrast, does create such epistemic barriers. Still, IHRL remains the better law for discharging its first moral task compared with IHL. Section C shows that it is not only the reality of armed conflict, but also the legal context that structures the epistemic environment in which law addresses the soldier on the battlefield. Due to the open-endedness of the ius contra bellum and its divergence from moral principles, IHRL only retains its ability to better discharge the law’s first moral task as hostilities become protracted or cross international borders if it is applied ‘symmetrically’, meaning as if both parties to an armed confrontation had a lawful aim. Finally, Section D turns towards the law’s second moral task and the implications of extraterritoriality and the intensity of hostilities for the volitional context of decision-making on the battlefield. It again finds that extraterritoriality does not per se create volitional defects. When hostilities reach the threshold of becoming protracted, however, IHL is better than ‘symmetrical IHRL’ at discharging the law’s second moral task.

A. The Use of Force across International Borders and the Law’s First Moral Task

Does the unauthorised use of force by a State outside its own borders create epistemic constraints that could interfere with IHRL’s ability to discharge the law’s first moral task? Let us imagine an internal confrontation between State A and an organised armed group, which spills-over into neighbouring State B’s territory (type 5). In A’s territory hostilities are not protracted and therefore governed by IHRL alone. However, on B’s territory, hostilities are part of an IAC and thus under the purview of IHL. It is important to stress that the question at hand is not whether State A would be able to guarantee the full panoply of human rights just as easily on State B’s territory as it would be able to do so on its own territory. Instead, the question is whether soldiers on the battlefield are less able to discern the implications of the more complex demands of IHRL regarding the permissibility of killing when they operate in neighbouring State B compared with when they use armed force on their own territory. Traditionally, State A would have been less familiar with the terrain across the border, which could reduce the situational awareness of its soldiers operating in B’s territory compared to those fighting at home. In the twenty-first century, however, satellite imagery mostly makes up for any such shortfall.

In other than spill-over confrontations, a State may face a less familiar enemy when fighting beyond its own borders. For instance, a State opposing a non-State armed group in a transnational IAC (type 6) or another State in a traditional IAC (type 2), might have less insight into the opponent’s organisation and conduct, compared with a State fighting an organised armed group that operates on its territory. However, ultimately the level of intelligence that belligerent C has about belligerent D has much more to do with the sophistication and length of C’s intelligence-gathering than with where D operates. Moreover, in internationalised internal confrontations (type 4), which involve the use of extraterritorial unauthorised force, just like in internationally supported internal confrontations (type 3), which do not, the intervening State can benefit from the intelligence of the belligerent it supports about the belligerent it opposes. These examples suggest that a State’s unauthorised crossing of international borders does not necessarily change the epistemic context of battlefield decision-making, though sometimes it can.

Familiarity with the terrain and with the enemy, which are contingently linked to where a belligerent is conducting hostilities, may speak to what human rights jurisprudence conceives of as a State’s ‘effective control’. Although the ECHR and the ICCPR both define their jurisdictional reach primarily with reference to a State’s own territory,Footnote 149 domestic as well as international case law has over the last decades converged on the interpretation that IHRL applies extraterritorially if a State exercises effective control.Footnote 150 Effective control, like familiarity with an enemy and terrain, is systematically linked to, but not necessarily only a function of whether the State operates on its own territory. The ECtHR and the Human Rights Committee indicate that just as a State does not necessarily lack control outside its borders, it does not always have control over all individuals on its own territory. Organised armed violence on a State’s territory is one possible reason for why a State might lack internal control.Footnote 151 At the same time, a State can have extra-territorial control ‘as a consequence of … military action’.Footnote 152 It follows that crossing international borders normally reverses the presumption from a State having effective control to a State not having effective control. On a State’s own territory, armed violence may signal the absence of control. Beyond a State’s territories it may be an indicator of the opposite.

Does IHRL require that a State has effective control in order to discharge the law’s first moral task? Or, put differently, is the loss of effective control associated with the emergence of epistemic barriers to discerning the morally right course of action which would undercut IHRL’s ability to guide soldiers’ actions? If this were true, then the morally right point for IHL to displace IHRL would be the (now widely accepted) de iure limit of IHRL’s extraterritorial applicability: where the State lacks effective control. This raises the question of what it looks like when a State exercises extraterritorial effective control in the context of the use of force. The ECtHR’s jurisprudence asserts that a belligerent can exercise ‘temporarily, effective overall control of a particular portion’ of another State’s territory,Footnote 153 in which case IHL’s rules for occupation, enshrined in GCIV, will likely apply. Alternatively, a belligerent State can exercise authority and control over persons without controlling territory.Footnote 154 Although this latter type of extraterritorial control over a person has mostly been found to obtain in the context of detention,Footnote 155 the Court has also asserted that a State can have control over an individual passing through a checkpointFootnote 156 and even one affected by the use of force.Footnote 157

When it comes to defining the factual indicators of such extraterritorial effective control over persons during the conduct of hostilities, the literature unfortunately often verges on tautology. Murray, for instance, mentions ‘factors such as, troop density, effective command and control, control of the skies, control of the sea lines of communication, a robust intelligence picture, suitable military hardware, control of cyberspace, or control of infrastructure and logistic support’.Footnote 158 The case law meanwhile overwhelmingly focuses on the parameters of a State exercising effective control over individuals in detention.Footnote 159 ‘What is decisive in such cases is the exercise of physical power and control over the person in question’.Footnote 160 This leaves unclear what it looks like when a State has effective control over persons affected by the use of force, that is, during the conduct of hostilities. Actual physical control, the literal power to handle a person’s body and command them to be in one place rather than another, is a feature of detention. The use of force against a person during the conduct of hostilities, however, will often signal the absence of this power.

Indeed, if we home in on the ordinary meaning of the word ‘control’ as ‘the power to influence or direct people’s behaviour or the course of events’,Footnote 161 it becomes evident that the use of violence is either itself an exercise of such control or it is a sign of its absence. If an attacker subdues a challenger through the use of armed force, this is an expression and indeed conclusive evidence of their effective control over the challenger. Exchanges of armed force that go on, in contrast, suggest that neither side has the power to subdue, that is, to control, the other. During an ongoing violent confrontation neither side then has effective control. It follows that it is the intensity of hostilities, particularly their quality of being ‘protracted’ that determines whether a party to an armed confrontation has effective control and whether IHRL can discharge the law’s first moral task. We can thus conclude that crossing international borders does not itself undercut the ability of IHRL to discharge the law’s first moral task. In peacetime, extraterritoriality may reverse the presumption of a State’s effective control, but whether the use of force is an exercise of effective control or the expression of its absence, depends on the intensity of hostilities not on where the confrontation takes place.

B. The Intensity of Hostilities and the Law’s First Moral Task

How does an increase in the intensity of hostilities affect IHRL’s ability to guide soldiers towards fulfilling their moral obligations? The more intense hostilities are, the more difficult it is to determine whether, at any given moment, IHRL indeed exceptionally permits the use of intentional lethal force. If IHRL governed hostilities, it would address the soldier on the battlefield with the prescription to kill combatants or enemy fighters only if they in fact used or threatened violence, and a lethal attack was necessary to defend themselves or a third party against this threat.Footnote 162 Soldiers would not be allowed to plan on using force as a first resort against enemy fighters as soon as they present themselves. Capture would have to be impossible.Footnote 163 Implementation of this provision requires a judgement about an individual’s likely conduct and about their intention. Two recognised indicators for the intensity of hostilities, in particular, diminish the attacker’s capacity to divine a potentially hostile individual’s state of mind and predict their behaviour: the type of weapons, namely, their range, and the number of persons involved in hostilities. The latter accounts for how many different individuals’ conduct and state of mind a soldier likely has to evaluate at the same time, potentially straining her or his cognitive capacity beyond the humanly possible.

An intensification in hostilities similarly increases the epistemic barriers to discerning when IHRL exceptionally permits overriding an innocent bystander’s right to life on grounds of necessity. IHRL either requires an immediate threat to human life or it imposes on the attacker a duty of care. A duty of care means an attacker is only authorised to launch the attack if a reasonable observer would with reasonable certainty affirm that this attack was the last and mildest means of achieving the aim which is legally recognised to unlock this exception. It may not be possible to establish true ‘lastness’ even in an environment in which the attacker has relatively solid knowledge about how reality will likely unfold in the near future. As the adversary gets a vote in the consequences of an attack, and success in war partly depends on not being predictable to the enemy, achieving reasonable certainty about the consequences of one’s conduct during an armed confrontation is likely rare. The more numerous, complex and fast-paced exchanges of violence are, the rarer will be moments in which the attacker can fulfil a duty of care towards innocent bystanders.Footnote 164

That it becomes harder to discern when IHRL exceptionally permits an attack on the battlefield does not mean IHRL ceases to have implications for action. Both Conventions discussed in Section II start out with a blanket prohibition on deprivations of the right to life. The use of lethal force is an exceptional empowerment. If the conditions of an exception cannot be established with reasonable certainty, the obligation not to deprive individuals of their human right to life remains intact. In the midst of hostilities, if it is impossible to establish who is threatening human life by using the kind of unlawful violence that can only be neutralised through lethal attack, then not carrying out a lethal attack is the reaction IHRL demands. Similarly, if it is impossible to establish with reasonable certainty the necessity of overriding a bystander’s right to life, IHRL does not grant such a permission.

As hostilities intensify, IHL’s rules of distinction, proportionality and necessity do not become harder to apply in the same measure as do IHRL’s rules. Neither does IHL revert to a default of no permission to use lethal force as does IHRL. Combatants do not necessarily become harder to distinguish from the civilian population in all-out war. Members of organised armed groups with a continuous combat function may even be easier to tell apart from the general population the less sporadic and more protracted hostilities are. Moreover, the implications of IHL’s principles of proportionality and necessity depend on an attacker’s expectations. The care in formulating these expectations that is owed to civilians under Article 57 API diminishes with intensifying hostilities, as the range of verification measures that are ‘feasible’ shrinks. As hostilities intensify it may also be less often true that ‘a choice is possible’ among several targets, which are anticipated to yield the same military advantage.Footnote 165 As its permissions do not hinge on an absolute threshold of minimum knowledge about the status of a target or the consequences of an attack, IHL is no less likely to permit attacks as intensifying hostilities decrease the knowability of an attack’s alternatives and consequences.Footnote 166

Which body of law then guides the soldier towards what is typically the morally right course of action as hostilities intensify? Moral principles, like IHRL, start with a presumption against killing and only allow infringing or overriding an individual’s moral right to life in exceptional circumstances. If these circumstances cannot be established with reasonable certainty, the morally right course of action is typically not to kill another person or launch an attack that is expected to kill an innocent bystander. Past a certain point of doubt, I would not be permitted to defend myself by killing an individual that may or may not threaten me. Similarly, past a certain point of doubt, rescuing innocent bystanders by killing an individual who I thought was attacking them would not be the morally right course of action. Inaction, as demanded by IHRL, is prima facie the morally appropriate reaction to uncertainty. That IHRL, on epistemic grounds, permits fewer attacks as hostilities intensify hence means it continues to guide the individual towards what is typically the course of action that conforms to his or her moral obligations.

One may reasonably interject here that compliance with IHRL would surely hamstring a belligerent in prosecuting a war. Not winning or not even fighting a war, in turn, can carry a moral cost if the war has a just aim, such as repelling a brutal aggressor or preventing a genocide and thereby protecting individual rights overall. Here we need to note what we have so far bracketed: IHRL requires a lawful aim for the exceptional deprivation of an individual right to life. Of course, moral principles also only permit the use of lethal force in pursuit of a just aim and in defence against an unjustified threat. If having a lawful aim for the purposes of IHRL was the same as having a morally just aim, IHRL would guide soldiers on both sides of an armed conflict towards what is typically the morally right course of action in their respective situations: inaction on the side in want of a lawful/just aim and exceptional permissions to infringe individual rights on the side pursuing a lawful/just aim. This would make the belligerent with the just/lawful aim likely to win, the constraining effect of IHRL notwithstanding.

We can conclude that intensifying hostilities change the epistemic context of decision-making on the battlefield, making it more difficult to discern the implications of IHRL’s demands and reducing the instances in which IHRL affords an exceptional permission to deprive an individual of their right to life. In contrast, it does not become more difficult to follow the prescriptions of IHL as hostilities become protracted. IHRL nonetheless continues to be a better guide to soldiers meeting their moral obligations on the battlefield. An intensification of hostilities does not undermine its better ability to discharge the law’s first moral task.

C. The Legal Context and the Law’s First Moral Task

The above assertion that IHRL better discharges the law’s first moral task even in the context of protracted armed hostilities and when States cross borders to use unauthorised force on other States’ territory rests on the assumption that having a lawful aim for the purposes of IHRL coincides with having a morally just aim. If this were not the case, IHRL would risk guiding soldiers with an unjust aim towards the perpetration of individual rights violations. It would also systematically prohibit soldiers with a morally just aim from committing infringements of individual rights that are necessary and justified in order achieve this aim. The above assertion further rests on the second assumption that soldiers are generally able to determine whether they have a lawful aim. Otherwise they would not be able to establish the implications of IHRL for their actions and IHRL would in fact fail to guide them towards meeting their moral obligations. Let us focus on the first assumption for now: is it systematically the case that in each armed conflict, the side that uses force lawfully also has a morally just aim and the side that has broken the law uses morally unjustified violence?

Section II.C touched on the difficult question of what it means to use or threaten unlawful violence for the purposes of IHRL during an organised armed confrontation that counts either as a NIAC or an IAC. For armed conflicts that pit non-State organised armed groups against State belligerents, we can sometimes rely on domestic law to establish that members of the organised armed group, specifically if they challenge their territorial State, use force unlawfully.Footnote 167 For conflicts among States, we could draw on general international law, namely, the ius contra bellum, to determine which side has a lawful aim.Footnote 168 We need to establish then whether the domestic law-based differentiation between State and non-State belligerents and the ius contra bellum track the moral principles that determine when it is morally justified to resort to armed force.

According to the moral standard outlined in Section III.A, the sole locus of moral value is the individual and resorting to force is justified only in defence of individual rights. States’ and other political communities’ rights are derivative of the rights of the individuals that constitute them. A community’s moral right to resort to force in self-defence is contingent on its being a vehicle for the protection of individual rights.Footnote 169 Crucially, this justification for resorting to force is the same for non-State organised armed groups as it is for States. There is no reason to assume that a non-State actor that challenges the territorial State has necessarily resorted to force unjustifiably and that the territorial State is always morally justified in fighting back. In contrast, as mentioned above, if we rely on domestic law to determine the lawfulness of a soldier’s use of violence during a NIAC, we will often find that the belligerent State’s soldiers have a lawful aim, whereas members of non-State organised armed groups threaten and use unlawful violence. This domestic law-based differentiation between State and non-State belligerents’ use of force does not track moral principles.

Having a morally just war aim means fighting to preserve individual rights or to prevent their violation. Past a certain level of intensity, armed confrontations inevitably involve the killing of innocent bystanders. As warfare thus always leads to infringements of individual rights, establishing a just cause means determining whether a resort to force is the lesser moral evil. When facing an outside aggressor or when deciding whether to intervene to halt a genocide, the State or non-State actor resorting to force has to ask: what is the lesser evil in terms of morally unjustified infringements of individual rights, resorting to war or refraining from using force? If the individual rights infringements that a resort to force will inevitably cause are the lesser evil, are they also proportionate to the aim of avoiding the greater number of rights violations?Footnote 170 If, but only if, the answers to both questions are yes, is a resort to force morally justified?Footnote 171

Calculating whether a resort to force would entail fewer or more unjustified infringements of individual rights than would not responding militarily to an aggression or a humanitarian catastrophe, is an extraordinarily difficult, future-oriented judgement. It not merely requires divining the intended and unintended consequences of one’s own actions. The extent to which a defensive war jeopardises individual rights – which rights, for how many individuals and how severely – also depends on the reactions of the adversary.Footnote 172 From a moral point of view, the decision as to whether or not to resort to armed force therefore often takes the form of what I have termed an ‘epistemically cloaked forced choice’Footnote 173 between allowing individual rights violations to occur and committing potentially unjustified individual rights infringements by resorting to force. Given this high epistemic barrier to determining whether and when resort to armed force is morally justified, it is not surprising that general international law diverges from moral principles. Just restating that a resort to armed force is lawful if it is a lesser evil in terms of individual rights infringements would be rather unhelpful. At the same time, if general international law on the resort to force discharges the law’s first moral task, it will typically both permit morally justified resorts to force and prohibit those that are not. Does it?

The resort to force is prohibited according to Article 2(4) of the UN Charter and under customary international law.Footnote 174 Article 51 of the UN Charter recognises individual and collective self-defence as an exception to this prohibition. It is the only such exception where the unilateral resort to force by States is concerned. The continued lack of a legal permission to resort to force for the purposes of humanitarian intervention means that a class of cases of potentially morally justified resort to force – necessary intervention to rescue individuals from their own State’s egregious individual rights violations – does not qualify as lawful.Footnote 175 There may be good moral reasons for the continued legal prohibition on humanitarian intervention,Footnote 176 but the absence of a clearly delineated international legal empowerment to use force as a means of rescue is one source of a likely divergence between a morally justified and a legally permissible resort to armed force.

International law empowers the Security Council to authorise the use of force. However, Article 39 UNC does not ask the Security Council to authorise specifically measures that are necessary to protect individual rights or even measures that are necessary to defend a State’s right to territorial integrity, which could be a vehicle for protecting individual rights. Rather, it empowers the Security Council to authorise measures that are necessary ‘to maintain or restore international peace and security’. Some scholars argue that the Security Council’s mandate of maintaining peace and security coincides with the broader goal of enforcing international law.Footnote 177 Individual rights are protected under international law, but is the protection of individual rights therefore co-extensive with the preservation of international peace and security? That may sometimes be the case. However, that a resort to force can be in defence of both international peace and security and individual rights does not mean that these goals never conflict and that measures necessary for the achievement of the former are also necessary (or sufficient) for securing the latter. Whether or not Security Council-mandated resorts to force have a morally just cause is therefore entirely contingent.

Does Article 51 UNC at least permit, more often than not, resorts to force that are also morally justified while excluding those that are not? The right to use force in self-defence is triggered ‘if an armed attack occurs against a Member of the United Nations’. Scholarly opinion broadly coalesces around the understanding that not just any use of force on another State’s territory amounts to an armed attack,Footnote 178 and that a mere threat of force is not enough to warrant forcible self-defence.Footnote 179 A State that is subject to the use of force below the threshold of an armed attack ‘is bound, if not exactly to endure the violation, at least to respond only by means falling short of the use of cross-border force’.Footnote 180 Any threat or use of force clearly jeopardises the State’s right to territorial integrity, but from a moral point of view, this is not a sufficient just cause for war. If a ‘bloodless invasion’ only violated individuals’ political rights, but an armed response would also endanger their right to life, not resorting to war in self-defence could be the lesser moral evil.

For us to understand whether armed attacks in the meaning of international law usually create a cause for morally justified resort to force, we need to know whether a use of force that rises to this threshold typically threatens individual rights, while a use of force below this threshold typically does not. The first obstacle to answering this question is the contestability of the minimum threshold that the use of force has to meet in order to fall in the category of an armed attack.Footnote 181 As the ICJ in the Nicaragua case assumed there was a ‘general agreement on the nature of the acts which can be treated as constituting armed attacks’,Footnote 182 the Court expended little ink on discussing the minimum intensity or scale of violence required to meet the threshold.Footnote 183 Every time the Court has returned to the concept of an armed attack, its application has been highly context-specific. Scholars have correspondingly found the concept ‘too vague to be useful’Footnote 184 in adjudicating real-world cases.

An alternative way of gauging whether the kind of war that responds to an armed attack is typically a morally justified resort to force is to delineate the goals that Article 51 UNC envisages as a lawful purpose of self-defence. However, like the minimum threshold of intensity that defines an armed attack, the horizon towards which defensive force has to be directed is subject to uncertainty.Footnote 185 Some scholars argue that it is ‘halting and repelling’ the armed attack.Footnote 186 Other scholars maintain ‘that the legitimate ends of using force in self-defence may differ, depending, inter alia, on the nature and scale of the armed attack, the identity of those who carried it out, and the preceding relationship between the aggressors and the victim state’.Footnote 187 Crucially, even scholars who agree on the interpretation that a State must seek to halt and repel the attack admit that what that means is controvertible. Many argue that it must be more than an empowerment to end an ongoing aggression.Footnote 188 As it is not clear what counts as a lawful aim for the resort to force in self-defence, there is no reason to assume that it is necessarily a morally just aim.

In sum, we cannot assume that soldiers using unlawful violence for the purposes of IHRL necessarily lack a just aim while those who use lawful violence fight in pursuit of a morally just aim. International law does not regulate the resort to force by non-State armed groups. If we rely on domestic law, a non-State actor that rises up against the territorial State in order to prevent the latter’s individual rights violations, likely uses violence unlawfully even if it is in pursuit of a morally just aim. In addition, we uncovered three major sources of divergence between moral principles and the ius contra bellum. First, the absence of a humanitarian intervention exception accounts for why international law may prohibit morally justified resorts to force. Second, the Security Council’s focus on international peace and security rather than on individual rights means mandated resorts to force may or may not be morally justified.Footnote 189 Third, it is very likely that international law systematically authorises the use of force by States in self-defence when this is not morally justified in cases in which the territorial integrity of a State is threatened by an armed attack, but resorting to force would be a greater evil in terms of individual rights infringements.

Moreover, the ius contra bellum does not afford a straightforward guide for soldiers according to which they can easily determine the lawfulness of their cause. Specifically, the threshold for and permissible aims of self-defence are contestable. Our second assumption made above – soldiers on the battlefield are generally able to determine the lawfulness of their aims – is therefore not warranted either. The combination of a significant substantive divergence from moral principles and a high degree of contestability means that general international law on the resort to force poorly discharges its first moral task. As it partly determines what individuals on the battlefield know about the lawfulness of their aims, its limitations affect the epistemic context of soldiers’ decision-making. The law that determines the permissibility of resort to armed force, when force is protracted or crosses international borders, thereby undermines IHRL’s ability to discharge its first moral task during hostilities. Even if individuals knew whether their aims were (un)lawful, and they acted accordingly, IHRL might fail to guide them towards the course of action that fulfils their moral obligations because the ius contra bellum sometimes empowers and hamstrings the wrong sides, respectively.

Given these limitations of general international law on the resort to force, IHRL may better discharge the law’s first moral task if it is applied ‘symmetrically’, meaning as if both sides in a war had a lawful aim and as if the threats and uses of violence that soldiers on both sides encountered from their opponents on the other side were unlawful. As mentioned, IHRL will regularly empower what is from a moral point of view ‘the wrong side’ and undermine the pursuit of a just aim on ‘the right side’. ‘Symmetrical IHRL’ would still empower rights violations on the part of soldiers who lack a morally just war aim. It would, however, avoid undercutting soldiers’ pursuit of morally just war aims not recognised as lawful under international law. Whereas regular IHRL might vouchsafe that the side with the morally unjust aim secures victory, ‘symmetrical IHRL’ would merely fail to prejudge which side prevails.

Would IHRL that is applied as if both sides had a lawful aim still better discharge the law’s first moral task than IHL? The answer is certainly yes. If soldiers on both sides in a war ended up applying IHRL as if their war aim was lawful and the violence they encountered from soldiers on the other side amounted to a threat or use of unlawful violence, IHRL would still guide soldiers on the just side towards the typically morally right course of action. IHL, in contrast, would not. Its status-based distinction and laxer standard of care towards civilians would license additional unnecessary (and therefore unjustified) infringements of individual rights. On the unjust side, even if soldiers were permitted to act as if their aim was lawful, IHRL would guide soldiers towards courses of action that are less morally wrongful than IHL. A ‘symmetrical IHRL’, one in which soldiers on both sides act as if the threat or use of violence on the other side was unlawful, still better discharges the law’s first moral task than IHL.

In sum, given that the ius contra bellum diverges from moral principles, lacks determinacy and leaves questions unanswered where non-State actors are concerned, ‘symmetrical IHRL’ will more often guide individuals towards the conduct that conforms to their moral obligation than asymmetrical, that is, regular IHRL. ‘Symmetrical IHRL’ will typically guide soldiers fighting for a just aim towards the course of action that conforms to their moral obligations, and soldiers fighting for an unjust aim towards conduct that is less morally wrongful than the conduct allowed by IHL, given the latter’s greater divergence from moral principles. Before the next section turns to the moral implications of compliance with law for the protection of individual rights (task two); it is worth emphasising that, if general international law on the resort to force were clarified or changed, if it were to systematically regulate the resort to force by and against non-State actors across international borders, we would have to revisit the question of whether IHRL should be symmetrical or not with a view to fulfilling the law’s first moral task.

D. The Use of Force across International Borders, the Intensity of Hostilities and the Law’s Second Moral Task

We have assumed that in typical law enforcement contexts, in which hostilities are neither protracted nor do they cross international borders, IHRL discharges both of the law’s moral tasks better than IHL. The analysis in the preceding sections then revealed that neither a state using unauthorised force beyond its own borders nor an increase in the intensity of hostilities undercuts IHRL’s better ability to discharge the law’s first moral task. However, given the shortcomings of the international legal regulation of the resort to force, ‘symmetrical IHRL’ discharges the law’s first moral task better than regular IHRL when hostilities cross borders or become protracted. A law that better discharges the law’s first moral task also prima facie better discharges its second moral task of securing the fullest feasible protection of individual rights. That is unless incurable volitional defects mean that a law that reminds soldiers of their moral obligations and guides them towards the course of action that typically fulfils these obligations fails to attract compliance or leads to morally worse outcomes.

In this final sub-section, we turn to the law’s second moral task. We have to answer two questions. First, does a State’s use of unauthorised force beyond its own territory create volitional defects that would undermine ‘symmetrical IHRL’s’ ability to discharge its second moral task in IACs that are not protracted?Footnote 190 Secondly, does an increase in the intensity of hostilities mark the emergence of such defects in NIACs and protracted IACs? I will discuss these two questions in turn.

Our assumption that in regular law enforcement contexts IHRL better than IHL fulfils both of the law’s moral tasks implies that States and their law enforcement officials are by and large willing to obey IHRL in such situations. Again, a spill-over armed confrontation (type 5) that remains below the threshold of being protracted in a neighbouring State’s territory proves instructive in showing that extraterritoriality does not on its own undercut this ability of IHRL to attract compliance. If hostilities are not protracted, the State has the capacity to subdue a non-State challenger. There is no reason then why soldiers should be less willing to follow the guidance of IHRL simply because they operate in a neighbouring State’s territory. But what if the opponent is not a non-State actor on another State’s territory, but really another State, such as in a classic IAC (type 2) or an internationalised internal confrontation (type 4)? If hostilities are not protracted, a State has effective control as a result of the extraterritorial use of force and is, by logical implication, able to subdue the opposing State’s soldiers. In other words, if the use of force is itself an exercise of control rather than a struggle signalling the absence of such control, the volitional context is conducive to compliance with IHRL.Footnote 191 Extraterritoriality alone does not create volitional defects.

Here it becomes obvious that, when States use force beyond their own borders, IHRL needs to be applied as if both sides had a lawful aim not only for the purpose of discharging its first moral task, as discussed above, but also in order to fulfil its second moral task. Let us again imagine a non-protracted classic IAC (type 2). It is highly unlikely that combatants on the side that lacks a lawful aim would comply with regular IHRL. Assuming that State A’s combatants knew their State’s resort to force violated the ius contra bellum, the only guidance IHRL would have to offer them would be to hold still, to cease threatening or using violence like a criminal in a domestic law enforcement context. Section III.C has already highlighted that this could violate the spirit of IHRL if A’s combatants were conscripted or had little choice but to participate in hostilities. Even if A’s combatants fought voluntarily in a war which they knew to lack a lawful aim, it would not necessarily be reasonable to expect them to hold still while according the authority to enforce international law to State B’s combatants. Even if this were a reasonable expectation, the international legal order, in which soldiers are primarily and much more directly subject to the authority of their own State rather than any international institution, provides soldiers with few incentives to follow the demand of IHRL to hold still over their State’s command to participate in hostilities. Regular IHRL would likely miss the chance to guide the actions of soldiers on one side in each war, forgoing the opportunity to morally improve the outcome of warfare and to discharge the law’s second moral task.

If ‘symmetrical IHRL’ is meant to attract compliance from both sides in non-protracted IACs, is there not a more fundamental challenge to its discharging its second moral task? Contrary to IHL, IHRL does not bind non-State armed groups.Footnote 192 IHRL is addressed to the State; it concerns the State’s obligations vis-à-vis its subjects. The horizontal implications of IHRL are traditionally fairly weak.Footnote 193 However, three out of the four types of IACs discussed here involve non-State actors (all except type 2). How can a body of law hope to better secure the protection of individual rights in the outcome of warfare if it does not even address all belligerents in each of these confrontations? For an analysis that sought to establish lex lata, this would be a crucial limitation. However, this section provides an answer to the question of when and to whom IHRL should apply from a moral point of view. Nothing prevents us from stipulating that in instances of organised armed violence in which ‘symmetrical IHRL’ ought to govern the permissibility of killing by a State, that is, in non-protracted IACs (types 2, 4, 5b and 6), it ought to also govern the permissibility of killing by a non-State organised armed group. After all, the applicability of IHL to non-State actors is also stipulative. Non-State armed groups are not parties to the pertinent IHL treaties. ‘Symmetrical IHRL’ is hence no less procedurally legitimate than IHL as a framework for non-State actors’ conduct, nor is ‘symmetrical IHRL’ less likely than IHL to in fact attract compliance by non-State armed groups.Footnote 194

What about armed confrontations that are protracted, either NIACs or protracted IACs? Does crossing this threshold of intensity create volitional defects that could undermine the ability of ‘symmetrical IHRL’ to secure the protection of individual rights in the outcome of warfare? Could IHL potentially better discharge the law’s second moral task? Volitional defects are in the first instance created by compliance costs, that is, incentives to ignore the demands of moral principles. Moral principles that demand that soldiers fight wars without violating the rights of the individuals against whom they fight have two major compliance costs: first, diminished military effectiveness, that is, a reduced likelihood of prevailing in the armed confrontation; and, secondly, diminished survival chances, that is, a reduced likelihood of escaping the confrontation unharmed and alive. These compliance costs increase radically as hostilities become more intense and they account for why individuals left to their own devices often fail to meet their moral obligations in protracted armed confrontations.

Compliance with IHL and ‘symmetrical IHRL’ likewise bears a cost of reduced military effectiveness. Crucially, ‘symmetrical IHRL’s’ compliance costs rise much faster than IHL’s as hostilities intensify. As previously noted, under IHRL, during protracted hostilities, a soldier will often have to forgo attacks because it is unclear whether the targeted individual really does present a threat that makes force necessary. Under IHL, in contrast, an attacker may kill opposing soldiers to further military progress, even if it is not strictly necessary. The duty of care towards innocent bystanders, imposed by IHRL, likewise means that an attacker who cannot establish with reasonable certainty the consequences of their attack on a military objective – and the strict necessity of the expected incidental deaths – would be enjoined not to attack. IHL’s verification demands, in opposition, shrink with the increasing intensity of hostilities, as described above.

The other type of compliance costs, diminished survival chances, likewise expand more quickly for ‘symmetrical IHRL’ than for IHL as hostilities intensify. The faster-paced, more numerous and more violent confrontations are, the more likely it is that any additional effort devoted to establishing that killing a prima facie hostile person is indeed strictly necessary, reduces the attacker’s own chances of survival. IHRL would not demand that a soldier sacrifice him- or herself on the battlefield, but if he or she was averse to taking the increased risk involved in establishing the strict necessity of infringing the human rights of innocent bystanders, this would diminish the soldier’s ability to launch attacks. Resisting the rise in one type of IHRL’s compliance costs (diminished survival chances) could thus further accelerate the rise in the other type of compliance costs (diminished military effectiveness). Under IHL, in contrast, a soldier may attack all other soldiers even before they pose a threat to him or her. Although contestation persists about exactly what makes a verification measure ‘infeasible’ for the purpose of Article 57 API, many militaries limit the extent to which they put their own forces at risk in order to verify the necessity of expected incidental civilian harm.Footnote 195

Compliance costs incentivise non-compliance, a volitional defect that law would normally cure by making non-compliance costly. This can be achieved by making visible unreasonable interpretations or outright violations of law, by opening them up to social opprobrium, or by attaching sanctions to compliance failures. However, there is a general lack of oversight over the conduct of hostilities that may allow soldiers to obscure an unreasonable prioritisation of the attacker’s safety over that of civilians. Although lack of oversight is a challenge in all armed confrontations, it is exacerbated as the fog of war thickens during more protracted hostilities. Indeed, the more intense hostilities are, the less likely it becomes that an investigation and assessment after the fact would even uncover intentional attacks against non-threatening individuals or incidental harm that was not strictly speaking necessary. As hostilities become protracted, law cannot easily cure the volitional defects associated with IHRL’s higher compliance costs. These compliance costs hence create the kind of volitional defect that means law risks being ignored.

A different type of volitional defect – affective and cognitive bias – risks that law is systematically misinterpreted leading to morally worse rather than better outcomes. In an armed confrontation in which one side is strong enough to subdue the other before hostilities become protracted, we may be able to count on soldiers’ being no more biased than most of us are in our day-to-day lives. That means soldiers likely have an affective preference for their compatriots and fellow soldiers over members of the ‘outgroup’. And they likely display varying degrees of outgroup hostility.Footnote 196 In all-out war, in contrast, the exhaustion of battle, the stress of being under lethal threat and seeing comrades die likely amplify these biases against individuals ‘on the other side’.Footnote 197 Protracted hostilities breed bias which, in turn, creates biased interpretations of the law.

The more uncertain a law’s implications are in the situation in which it typically addresses the individual, the more room there is for the individual’s bias to distort these implications. As previously indicated, the implications for actions of ‘symmetrical IHRL’ become harder to discern the more intense hostilities become. Under an IHRL paradigm, all individuals ‘on the other side’, including civilians, are potentially lawful targets of intentional attack, depending on their conduct. For a soldier during protracted hostilities, every person ‘on the other side’, whether they wear a uniform or not, may appear threatening. Neutralising that threat may appear of paramount necessity the more often a soldier has seen a comrade die or the further out of reach military victory appears. If a soldier in that situation draws on ‘symmetrical IHRL’, the law risks empowering morally unjustified individual rights infringements that the soldier would not have committed if they had been left to their own devices. ‘Symmetrical IHRL’ might not merely miss the opportunity to secure a better protection of individual rights in the outcome of warfare, it might make these outcomes worse compared with soldiers’ following their own judgement.

Bias against individuals on the other side, like high compliance costs, creates volitional defects during protracted hostilities that law cannot easily cure. IHL, however, accommodates these volitional defects. It forestalls, as much as possible, the effect of bias against individuals ‘on the other side’ by reducing the individual soldier’s burden of moral judgement. Indeed, IHL demands that soldiers suspend their moral judgement: civilians are immune from attack and combatants are legitimate targets of lethal attack regardless of necessity, regardless of their conduct,Footnote 198 their mental state or their cause, hence irrespective of any parameter that requires a moral judgement or that is open to biased interpretation. IHL severs the rules for the conduct of war as much as possible from moral judgements. In circumstances in which bias is pervasive, this means IHL can secure better outcomes for individual rights. Of course, it is exactly this disconnect from underlying moral principles that enhances IHL’s ability to discharge the law’s second moral task that also makes IHL so bad at guiding soldiers towards the fulfilment of their moral duties.

If we focus on the law’s second moral task of securing the fullest feasible protection of individual rights in the outcome of warfare – that is, minimise as much as possible unjustified infringements of individual rights – IHL’s principles for the conduct of hostilities perform better than IHRL even if IHRL is applied as if both sides had lawful aims. IHL accommodates the volitional defects that it cannot cure; volitional defects that stem from higher costs of compliance and soldiers’ more acute bias during protracted hostilities. That does not mean IHL is the morally ideal law for the performance of law’s second moral task during the conduct of protracted hostilities. It may well be possible that law could demand the necessity of lethal attacks against enemy soldiers and still attract reciprocal and good faith compliance even during highly intense hostilities. Such a law would reduce the number of unjustified infringements of individual moral rights compared with IHL as it currently stands. However, if the choice is between IHL as it stands and ‘symmetrical IHRL’, then from the point of view of the law’s second moral task, IHL should govern the conduct of hostilities above the threshold of intensity at which the discussed incurable volitional defects kick in, meaning when hostilities become protracted.

VI. Conclusion

When should IHL apply? When should it prevail over, when give way to IHRL in regulating the conduct of hostilities during IACs and NIACs? The argument presented in this chapter leads to the following proposal for a moral division of labour between IHL and IHRL. IHRL better discharges both of the law’s moral tasks during law enforcement operations, when organised armed violence neither involves the use of unauthorised force by a State beyond its own borders nor rises to the threshold of being protracted. When a State uses unauthorised extraterritorial violence, IHRL needs to be applied as if both sides were facing unlawful threats and uses of violence from the other side. Applying IHRL ‘symmetrically’ is necessary due to the failure of general international law to discharge its first moral task. It also helps IHRL attract compliance from soldiers on both sides of a non-protracted IAC. As long as hostilities do not become protracted, ‘symmetrical IHRL’ discharges the law’s two moral tasks better than IHL. A moral division of labour between IHRL and IHL, then clearly requires that non-protracted hostilities during armed conflicts are governed by ‘symmetrical IHRL’ rather than by IHL.

Among the six types of armed conflicts we distinguished, currently only NIACs – that is, purely internal NIACs (type 1), internationally supported NIACs (type 3) and the internal part of spill-over confrontations (type 5a) – are subject to an intensity requirement. That means that if conflicts with these belligerent configurations are not protracted, they do not count as armed conflicts at all and they are governed by regular IHRL. Classic IACs (type 1), internationalised internal conflicts (type 4), the extraterritorial part of a spill-over confrontation (type 5b) and transnational confrontations (type 6), in contrast, fall under the purview of IHL regardless of their intensity. From a moral point of view, if conflict types 1, 4, 5b and 6 are not protracted, they should instead be governed by ‘symmetrical IHRL’. Conflicts with States on both sides may not seem amenable to governance by IHRL. However, this intuition is likely rooted in the association of these conflicts with intense hostilities. In reality, extraterritorial spill-over conflicts and transnational conflicts, in particular, are often characterised by sporadic rather than protracted hostilities.Footnote 199 ‘Symmetrical IHRL’ should prevail over IHL during such non-protracted IACs.

Above the threshold of intensity at which hostilities count as protracted, meaning during protracted IACs and during NIACs, ‘symmetrical IHRL’ remains the better law for guiding individuals towards conformity with the moral reasons that apply to their conduct (task one). However, IHL generates morally better outcomes for individual rights (task two). Insisting that ‘symmetrical IHRL’ should prevail over IHL would have moral costs. ‘Symmetrical IHRL’ has compliance costs that are almost as high as those of moral principles. It thus risks being ignored. Moreover, due to the acute bias associated with intense hostilities, those soldiers who do recur to the guidance of ‘symmetrical IHRL’ might mistakenly feel empowered to commit more individual rights violations than if they had been left to their own judgement. Allowing IHL to displace ‘symmetrical IHRL’ during protracted hostilities would, however, also have moral costs. IHL operates as if soldiers on the battlefield inevitably ceased to be active centres of moral intelligence. It effectively asks soldiers to suspend their moral judgement. In reality, soldiers might be better served by law reminding them of the morally right course of action even if taking this course of action is costly and recognising it requires that soldiers transcend their bias against the enemy.

This chapter nonetheless makes a moral case for the displacement of ‘symmetrical IHRL’ and for IHL alone to govern the conduct of hostilities during protracted IACs and during NIACs. This is not because securing individual rights in the outcome of war (task two) is more important than guiding the individual towards the typically morally right course of action (task one). Both of the law’s moral tasks are equally important. Rather, it is because IHL falls short of discharging the law’s first task by a metre, whereas IHRL falls short of discharging its second moral task by a mile. IHL still guides soldiers towards a course of action that is less morally wrongful than the course of action they would likely take if left to their own devices. IHRL, even if applied symmetrically, in contrast, either fails to improve outcomes altogether or risks making them worse. As a result, the moral costs of ‘symmetrical IHRL’s’ failing to fulfil task two are higher than the moral costs of IHL’s not fully discharging task one. Put differently, allowing IHL to prevail for the sake of securing individual rights in the outcome of warfare is less morally costly than risking that protracted hostilities are unguided by law. The staggering moral catastrophe presented by armed conflicts waged beyond the international community’s gaze and thus seemingly out of reach of international law serve as a reminder of how important it is for international law to stand a chance at attracting the good faith compliance of individuals on the battlefield.

It warrants restating though that allowing IHL to prevail in governing the conduct of protracted hostilities during NIACs and intense IACs means failing the soldier as a moral agent. We have a legitimate expectation that law, at least to some extent, helps us to meet our moral obligations. That IHL fails in this crucial task makes the ICJ’s claim that compliance with IHL actualises what it means to uphold human rights in war not only false as a matter of legal exegesis, but morally problematic. The least societies can do when sending soldiers into protracted battle with the demand that they obey IHL, is not pretend that this is the be-all and end-all of a moral conversation about battlefield conduct.

Footnotes

1 This chapter focuses on the conduct of hostilities and specifically the rules concerning the permissibility of killing. I say very little about rules on such issues as humanitarian access, detention, internment or belligerent occupation.

2 When referring to legal rights, I use the terms ‘individual rights’ and ‘human rights’ interchangeably. Even though these two categories are not congruent, it is uncontroversial that the right to life, which is at the centre of this investigation, is both an individual and a human legal right (see Joseph Raz, ‘Human Rights Without Foundations’, in Samantha Besson and John Tasioulas (eds.), The Philosophy of International Law (Oxford University Press, 2010), 321–38). When talking about moral rights, I will only use the term ‘individual rights’ and usually preface it with the designation ‘moral’ to avoid confusion.

3 For instance, Louise Doswald-Beck, ‘The Right to Life in Armed Conflict: Does International Humanitarian Law Provide all the Answers?’, International Review of the Red Cross 88 (2006), 881904; Alexander Orakhelashvili, ‘The Interaction between Human Rights and Humanitarian Law: Fragmentation, Conflict, Parallelism or Convergence?’, European Journal of International Law 19 (2008), 161–82. In a variation of this argument, Hakimi maintains that the two bodies of law can be applied simultaneously, but in instances in which their implications diverge, we should take a functional approach to reconciling them. Monica Hakimi, ‘A Functional Approach to Targeting and Detention’, Michigan Law Review 110 (2012), 1365–420.

4 See, among others, Christopher Greenwood, ‘Rights at the Frontier: Protecting the Individual in Time of War’, in Barry Rider (ed.), Law at the Centre: The Institute of Advanced Legal Studies at Fifty (The Hague: Kluwer Law International, 1999), 277–93; Hans Joachim Heintze, ‘On the Relationship between Human Rights Law Protection and International Humanitarian Law’, International Review of the Red Cross 86 (2004), 789814; Marco Sassòli, ‘The Role of Human Rights and International Humanitarian Law in New Types of Armed Conflicts’, in Orna Ben-Naftali (ed.), International Humanitarian Law and International Human Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2011), 3494.

5 Cordula Droege, ‘The Interplay between IHL and IHRL in Situations of Armed Conflict’, Israel Law Review 40 (2007), 310–55. In a variation of this argument, Watkin holds that States should by default rely on IHRL when facing non-State belligerents, unless this is operationally infeasible (Kenneth Watkin, Fighting at the Legal Boundaries (Oxford University Press, 2016), 606). Ohlin argues that it should depend on whether a State acts in its capacity as sovereign or as belligerent whether IHRL or IHL prevails. Jens David Ohlin, ‘Acting as a Sovereign versus Acting as a Belligerent’, in Jens David Ohlin (ed.), Theoretical Boundaries of Armed Conflict and Human Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016), 118–54 (129).

6 For instance, Marco Milanovic, ‘Norm Conflicts, International Humanitarian Law and Human Rights Law’, Journal of Conflict & Security Law 14 (2009), 459–83; Daragh Murray, Practitioners’ Guide to Human Rights Law in Armed Conflict, eds. Elizabeth Wilmshurst, Françoise Hampson, Charles Garraway, Noam Lubell and Dapo Akande (Oxford University Press, 2016), paras. 4.26, 4.31 and 4.37.

7 A violation of a right is a morally unjustified failure to respect that right. As explained in this paragraph, infringing a right can be morally justified. Rights violations are hence a sub-set of rights infringements. See Judith Jarvis Thomson, ‘Some Ruminations on Rights’, in William Parent (ed.), Rights, Restitution, and Risk (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), 4965 (51).

8 I am referring to forfeiture as a basis for liability to defensive harm rather than as a basis for liability to punishment. For the difference, see Massimo Renzo, ‘Rights Forfeiture and Liability to Harm’, Journal of Political Philosophy 25 (2017), 324–42.

9 For detailed outlines of this account of the morality of defensive harming, see, among others, Cécile Fabre, Cosmopolitan War (Oxford University Press, 2012), 6; Jeff McMahan, ‘The Ethics of Killing in War’, Ethics 114 (2004), 693732; Seth Lazar, ‘The Morality and the Law of War’, in Andrei Marmor (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law (London: Routledge, 2012), 364–80.

10 I use the term ‘soldier’ to refer to persons in two legal categories: (1) combatants, i.e., all members (other than medical and religious personnel) of armed forces, organised armed groups and units under a command responsible to a State party to a conflict; and (2) individuals with a continuous combat function in an organised armed group not connected to a State party to a conflict, whether in an international or non-international armed conflict. I sometimes refer to persons in the latter category as fighters or as members of non-State armed groups.

11 As will be discussed further below, a war has a morally just aim if resorting to force is overall the lesser evil in terms of unjustified individual rights infringements.

12 This divergence is well appreciated among just war theorists. See, among others, Jeff McMahan, ‘The Morality of War and the Law of War’, in David Rodin and Henry Shue (eds.), Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers (Oxford University Press, 2010), 1943; Adam Roberts, ‘The Principle of Equal Applicability of the Laws of War’, in Rodin and Shue (eds.), Just and Unjust Warriors, 226–54; Henry Shue, ‘Do We Need a “Morality of War”?’ in Rodin and Shue (eds.), Just and Unjust Warriors, 87–111.

13 In this chapter, I mostly bracket the question whether, from a moral point of view, IHRL should indeed govern those armed confrontations currently deemed to fall in the category of law enforcement operations rather than armed conflict. Given that IHRL is the morally prima facie better law for the regulation of permissible killing, I assume that the answer to this question is yes.

14 For an affirmation of the extraterritorial applicability of IHRL, see UN Human Rights Committee, General Comment No. 31, Nature of the General Legal Obligation on States Parties to the Covenant, CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.13 (2004), para. 10. For an affirmation of the applicability of IHRL during armed conflict, see, among others, ICJ, Legal Consequences of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory, Advisory Opinion of 9 July 2004, ICJ Reports 2004, 136, para. 106. For a thorough discussion of the international jurisprudence supporting both claims, see Noam Lubell, ‘Challenges in Applying Human Rights Law to Armed Conflict’, International Review of the Red Cross 87 (2005), 737–54. For a dissenting voice against the extraterritorial application of the ICCPR, see Second and Third Periodic Report of the United States of America to the UN Committee on Human Rights Concerning the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Annex I, Territorial Scope of Application of the ICCPR (21 October 2005). For the scholarly position against the applicability of IHRL in armed conflict, see Wolf Heintschel von Heinegg, ‘The Rule of Law in Conflict and Post-Conflict Situations: Factors in War to Peace Transitions’, Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 27 (2004), 868964.

15 Orna Ben-Naftali, ‘Introduction: International Humanitarian Law and International Human Rights Law – Pas de Deux’, in Orna Ben-Naftali (ed.), International Humanitarian Law and International Human Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2011), 312 (5). For an extensive defence of this position, see also Helen Duffy in this volume, Chapter 1.

16 The term co-applicability is used in a variety of ways. I will take it to imply merely that IHL and IHRL both apply during the conduct of hostilities in NIACs and IACs. It does not prejudge whether the two bodies of law have diverging implications for action or which prevails over the other.

17 It is not the purpose of this section to provide another overview of the diverse positions in the legal literature on how IHL and IHRL formally relate to each other – several excellent discussions exist. See, among others, Droege, ‘The Interplay between IHL and IHRL’ 2007 (Footnote n. 5); Duffy in this volume, Chapter 1; Marco Milanovic, ‘The Lost Origins of Lex Specialis: Rethinking the Relationship between HR and IHL’, in Ohlin (ed.), Theoretical Boundaries of Armed Conflict 2016 (Footnote n. 5), 78–117; Christian Tomuschat, ‘Human Rights and International Humanitarian Law’, European Journal of International Law 21 (2010), 1523.

18 ICJ, Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion of 8 July 1996, ICJ Reports 1996, 240, para. 25. For the position that IHL elucidates the meaning of IHRL in armed conflict, see also Magdalena Forowicz, The Reception of International Law in the European Court of Human Rights (Oxford University Press, 2010), 314; Tomuschat, ‘Human Rights and International Humanitarian Law’ 2010 (Footnote n. 17).

19 A more charitable reading of the statement is that the ICJ, unlike much of legal doctrine, considers the rule of lex specialis a tool for the avoidance rather than the resolution of conflicts of laws. The ICJ reaffirmed its position in a later Advisory Opinion (ICJ, Legal Consequences of the Wall (Footnote n. 14), para. 106), but did not mention lex specialis in the case of Congo v. Uganda. ICJ, Case Concerning Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo (Democratic Republic of the Congo v. Uganda), Judgment of 9 December 2005, ICJ Reports 2005, 168, para. 216.

20 The most recent Human Rights Committee’s Commentary on Art. 6 affirms the ICJ’s assertion, stating that the use of ‘lethal force authorised and regulated by and complying with international humanitarian law [is], in general, not arbitrary’ (UN Human Rights Committee, General Comment No. 36, Art. 6 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, ‘On the Right to Life’, para. 64). At the same time, the Commentary suggests that all killing in an aggressive war amounts to a violation of Art. 6 (Footnote ibid., para. 70), and it defines arbitrariness in such a way as to make it highly implausible that incidental civilian harm in conformity with IHL is not arbitrary. I return to this issue in the next sub-section.

21 Of course, an inability to exercise a right is not itself a bar to bearing it. For the obiter dictum establishing this position as part of international law, see PCIJ, The Peter Pázmány University (Czechoslovakia v. Hungary), Appeal from a Judgment of the Hungaro/Czechoslovak Mixed Arbitral Tribunal, Merits, Judgment of 5 December 1933, PCIJ Series A/B 1933, 61, para. 231. For the view that individuals hold rights directly in virtue of IHL, see Christopher J. Greenwood, ‘Historical Development and Legal Basis’, in Dieter Fleck (ed.), The Handbook of International Humanitarian Law, 2nd edn. (Oxford University Press, 2009), 101–50 (134); Jean S. Pictet, IV Geneva Convention: Commentary (Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross, 1958), 79; Theodor Meron, The Humanization of International Law (Oxford University Press, 2000), 240; Rüdiger Wolfrum, ‘Enforcement of International Humanitarian Law’, in Dieter Fleck (ed.), The Handbook of International Humanitarian Law, 2nd edn. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009), paras. 1401–43 (para. 1434). For contestations of this position, see Françoise Hampson, ‘Human Rights Law and Humanitarian Law: Two Coins or Two Sides of the Same Coin?’, Bulletin of Human Rights 1 (1991), 4654 (49); Kate Parlett, The Individual in the International Legal System: Continuity and Change in International Law (Cambridge University Press, 2011).

22 Greenwood, ‘Historical Development’ 2009 (Footnote n. 21), para. 134.

23 Articles 6 Convention (I) for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and Sick in Armed Forces in the Field, Geneva, 12 August 1949, 75 UNTS 31 (hereinafter: GCI); Convention (II) for the Amelioration of the Condition of Wounded, Sick and Shipwrecked Members of Armed Forces at Sea, Geneva, 12 August 1949, 75 UNTS 85 (hereinafter: GCII) and Convention (III) relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War, Geneva, 12 August 1949, 75 UNTS 135 (hereinafter: GCIII), and Art. 7 Convention (IV) relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War, Geneva, 12 August 1949, 75 UNTS 287 (hereinafter: GCIV).

24 Arts. 7 GCI, GCII and GCIII, and Art. 8 GCIV.

25 They include rights of defence (Arts. 84, 105 GCIII, Art. 72f GCIV), appeal or petition (Art. 106 GCIII), a fair and regular trial (Art. 174 GCIV), and the right to complain to a protecting power about the conditions under which an individual is being held (Arts. 50, 78 GCIII, Arts. 30, 52, 101 GCIV).

26 For instance, Arts. 28, 57, 73 GCIII, Arts. 27, 35 GCIV. To the contrary, GCI and GCII, which are concerned with the protection of armed forces in the field and at sea, only mention the right of medical and religious personnel to ‘wear the armlet’ as a sign that they are immune from attack in Art. 40 GCI and Art. 42 GCIII, respectively.

27 Article 43(2) Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and relating to the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts (Protocol I), 8 June 1977, 1125 UNTS 3 (hereinafter: API).

28 Adil A. Haque, Law and Morality at War (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017), 28. Sub-section D of this section argues that this right can also be considered an authorisation or liberty right in the Hohfeldian sense.

29 Among others, Arts. 6(2)(a) and (e), 11(5), 32, 44(2), 45(2) and (3), 75(4), 85(4) API.

30 If we deny that individual combatants or civilians hold rights during the conduct of hostilities, attackers’ duties of protection which benefit civilians and, to a lesser extent, combatants could be anchored in rights held by the opposing belligerent. In contrast, some scholars maintain that IHL’s duties are not mirrored in rights at all (see Bohrer in this volume, 59). The argument presented here does not hinge on which view is correct.

31 Article 51(1) API.

32 Article 51(3) API.

33 Article 51(5)(b) API.

34 UN Economic and Social Council, United Nations Principles on the Effective Prevention and Investigation of Extra-legal, Arbitrary and Summary Executions, GA Res. 1989/65 of 24 May 1989, UN Doc. E/1989/89, 9, para. 52; similar Eighth United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders, Basic Principles on the Use of Force and Firearms by Law Enforcement Officials, GA Res. 45/166 of 18 December 1990, para. 9; UN Human Rights Committee, ‘On the Right to Life’ 2017 (Footnote n. 20), para. 13.

35 See Art. 5 (sentence 2) Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, Rome, 4 November 1950, 213 UNTS 221 (hereinafter: ECHR); Art. 6(2) International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, adopted and opened for signature, ratification and accession by General Assembly Resolution 2200 A (XXI) of 16 December 1966, 999 UNTS 171 (hereinafter: ICCPR).

36 See Art. 6(2)(4) and (5) ICCPR.

37 UN Human Rights Committee, ‘On the Right to Life’ 2017 (Footnote n. 20), para. 37.

38 Furthermore, the Commentary cautions that persons with ‘limited moral culpability’ must never be subjected to the death penalty (Footnote ibid., para. 49). The next section will argue in detail that IHL does not take account of civilians’ moral status when determining whether their harming is permissible.

39 Footnote Ibid., para. 12.

40 Even a civilian’s physical proximity to a military target does not affect her or his legal status. IHL does not impose on civilians an obligation to move away from military targets. I have made this argument in more detail with regard to the status of civilians who are deemed to physically shield military objectives in Janina Dill, ‘The DoD Law of War Manual and the False Appeal of Differentiating Types of Civilians’, blog post on Just Security, December 2016 and Janina Dill, ‘Israel’s Use of Law and Warnings in Gaza’, blog post on Opinio Juris, July 2014.

41 Article 2(2)(c) ECHR. The ICCPR does not recognise an equivalent exception.

42 Derogations in ‘time[s] of public emergency which threatens the life of the nation’ follow a similar logic of overriding individual rights in order to avoid what is recognised as a greater legal evil. However, neither the ICCPR nor the ECHR allow derogations from Art. 6 ICCPR and Art. 2 ECHR, respectively (see Art. 4(1) ICCPR and Art. 15 ECHR). Crucially, derogation would be a way to avoid rather than resolve a substantive conflict between IHRL and IHL. When Art. 15(2) ECHR allows deprivations of the right to life ‘in respect of deaths resulting from lawful acts of war’, it hence implies that IHL authorises deaths that do fall foul of Art. 2. Rather than bringing lawful deaths in war under one of the exceptions to the prohibition on depriving individuals of their right to life in Art. 2, the Convention refers to killing in war in accordance with IHL as a type of derogation from a State’s obligations under the ECHR. The conflict between IHRL and IHL outlined here, as far as the ECHR is concerned, could be avoided by derogation. This is not the case for the conflict between the ICCPR and IHL.

43 UN Human Rights Committee, ‘On the Right to Life’ 2017 (Footnote n. 20), paras. 10, 12; similar UN Human Rights Committee, General Comment No. 35, on Art. 9 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, ‘Liberty and Security of Person’, UN Doc. CCPR/C/GC/35, 14 December 2014, para. 10. ECtHR, McCann and Others v. United Kingdom, Judgment of 27 September 1995, Application No. 18984/9, para. 194.

44 Under IHL, expected incidental harm has to be not only necessary, but also proportionate/not excessive to the anticipated military advantage. At first glance, this principle of proportionality has no equivalent in IHRL treaty law. The ECtHR has held, however, that the use of lethal force must be proportionate to the aim of protecting human life (ECtHR, Finogenov and Others v. Russia, Judgment of 20 December 2011, Application Nos. 18299/03 and 27311/03, para. 210; ECtHR, McCann and Others v. United Kingdom (Footnote n. 43), para. 194). As in the case of necessity, the aim with regard to which proportionality has to obtain hence differs between IHRL (the protection of human life) and IHL (the pursuit of a military advantage).

45 The UN Basic principles emphasise that the use of lethal force has to be ‘strictly unavoidable’ and ‘less extreme means’ have to be ‘insufficient’. See Eighth United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders, Basic Principles on Use of Force and Firearms by Law Enforcement Officials, GA Res. 45/166 of 18 December 1990, para. 9. See also, ECtHR, Finogenov and Others v. Russia (Footnote n. 44), para. 208.

46 See ECtHR, Isayeva, Yusupova and Bazayeva v. Russia, Judgment of 24 February 2005, Application No. 57947/00, para. 189; ECtHR, McCann and Others v. United Kingdom (Footnote n. 43), paras. 148, 150. Any potential violation of the right to life, moreover, triggers a duty on the part of the State to investigate whether it was indeed necessary. Footnote Ibid., para. 161.

47 ECtHR, Finogenov and Others v. Russia (Footnote n. 44), para. 208.

48 Noam Neuman, ‘Applying the Rule of Proportionality: Force Protection and Cumulative Assessment in International Law and Morality’, Yearbook of International Humanitarian Law 7 (2004), 79112 (98).

49 Article 57(2)(ii) API.

50 I have argued elsewhere in more detail that under IHL an attacker does not incur a robust duty of care to ensure that incidental civilian harm is truly necessary for the pursuit of a given military advantage. See Janina Dill, ‘Do Attackers have a Legal Duty of Care? Limits to the “Individualization of War”’, International Theory 11 (2019), 1–25.

51 What the obligation to take precautions in attack requires in practice is subject to considerable controversy. The United Kingdom Law of War Manual acknowledges the legal uncertainty: ‘The Law is not clear as to the degree of risk that the attacker must accept’ (UK Ministry of Defence, Manual of the Law of Armed Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2004), 25, para. 2.7.1). For the range of views on this matter, see, among others, Eyal Benvenisti, ‘Human Dignity in Combat: the Duty to Spare Enemy Civilians’, Israel Law Review 39 (2006), 81109; Yoram Dinstein, The Conduct of Hostilities under the Law of International Armed Conflict (Cambridge University Press, 2016), 168; Adil A. Haque, ‘Killing in the Fog of War’, Southern California Law Review 86 (2012), 63116; David Luban, ‘Risk Taking and Force Protection’, in Yitzhak Benbaji and Naomi Sussman (eds.), Reading Walzer (London: Routledge (online edn.), 2011), 277301 (277).

52 I have argued above that these aims are not equivalent.

53 For the general claim that necessity is stricter in IHRL than in IHL, see also Lawrence Hill-Cawthorne, ‘The Role of Necessity in International Humanitarian and Human Rights Law’, Israel Law Review 47 (2014), 225–51; Niels Melzer, Targeted Killing in International Law (Oxford University Press, 2008), 228; Jens David Ohlin, ‘The Duty to Capture’, Minnesota Law Review 97 (2013), 1268–315 (1298 et seq.); Jens David Ohlin and Larry May, Necessity in International Law (Oxford University Press, 2016), 273.

54 Most notably in ECtHR, Isayeva, Yusupova and Bazayeva v. Russia (Footnote n. 46), paras. 168, 743. See also ECtHR, Ergi v. Turkey, Judgment of 28 July 2008, Application No. 23818/94, para. 79 et seq.; ECtHR, Ozkan v. Turkey, Judgment of 6 April 2004, Application No. 21689/93, paras. 305–6. Note that in Isayeva the Court explicitly casts the operation as a law enforcement operation ‘outside of armed conflict’. Footnote Ibid., Isayeva, Yusupova and Bazayeva v. Russia (Footnote n. 46), para. 191.

55 For the argument that the standard of necessity that the Court employs across these cases is not uniform, but relaxed in situations of more intense hostilities to resemble an IHL standard, see Cordula Droege, ‘Elective Affinities? Human Rights and Humanitarian Law’, International Review of the Red Cross 90 (2008), 501 (532).

56 ECtHR, Isayeva, Yusupova and Bazayeva v. Russia (Footnote n. 46), para. 200; ECtHR, Finogenov and Others v. Russia (Footnote n. 44), para. 219; ECtHR, Case of Kerimova and Others v. Russia, Judgment of 15 September 2011, Application Nos. 17170/04, 20792/04, 22448/04, para. 248. For the interesting point that this insistence on a legitimate aim is akin to regulating the resort to force by a State within its own territory, see Eliav Lieblich, ‘“Internal” Jus Ad Bellum’, Hastings Law Journal 67 (2016), 687748.

57 For instance, ECtHR, Isayeva, Yusupova and Bazayeva v. Russia (Footnote n. 46), para. 200; ECtHR, Kerimova and Others v. Russia (Footnote n. 56), para. 253; similar David Kretzmer, ‘Rethinking the Application of IHL in Non-International Armed Conflict’, Israel Law Review 42 (2009), 2331 (30); Noëlle Quénivet, ‘The Right to Life in International Humanitarian Law and Human Rights Law’, in Roberta Arnold and Noëlle Quénivet (eds.), International Humanitarian Law and Human Rights Law: Towards a New Merger (Leiden: Brill/Martinus Nijhoff, 2008), 331–53 (341). For an example of the application of this strict necessity standard outside the Court’s case law, see First Public Commission to Examine the Maritime Incident of 31 May 2010, para. 232.

58 To recall, as discussed in Section I, the term ‘soldiers’ refers to combatants and to individuals with a continuous combat function who are members of organised armed groups not connected to a State party to a conflict.

59 An individual who is a member of an organised armed group assumes a ‘continuous combat function’ if his or her role ‘involves the preparation, execution, or command of acts or operations amounting to direct participation in hostilities’ (Niels Melzer, Interpretive Guidance on the Notion of Direct Participation in Hostilities under IHL (Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross, 2010), 34). Even though the term was originally meant to designate individuals fighting for a non-State party in a NIAC, I use it to include individuals with similar roles in organised armed groups not belonging to any State party to an IAC.

60 I exclude from the discussion in this sub-section civilians who directly, but temporarily, participate in hostilities, including members of organised armed groups without a continuous combat function.

61 Similar Marco Sassòli, ‘Jus ad Bellum and Jus in Bello – The Separation between the Legality of the Use of Force and Humanitarian Rules to be Respected in Warfare: Crucial or Outdated?’, in Michael N. Schmitt and Jelena Pejic (eds.), International Law and Armed Conflict: Exploring the Faultlines (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff, 2007), 242–64 (248). Members of organised armed groups, not recognised or associated with any State belligerent in an IAC, are likewise likely in breach of the domestic law of the State on whose territory they fight when they threaten or use violence.

62 It is an unsatisfying legal situation that it may well depend on the political relationship between the territorial State and an organised armed group that threatens another State, whether or not the IHL-conforming attacks by the latter against members of the organised armed group violate these members’ right to life under IHRL because the organised armed group is considered in violation of domestic law.

63 It is noteworthy that IHL is agnostic as to whether individuals consent to assuming combatant status or whether they are conscripted, coerced or forced by circumstances. We might think that individuals who assume a continuous combat function in an organised armed group have made a free choice to do so. For the argument that this is not universally true either, see Center for Civilians in Conflict, The People’s Perspectives: Civilian Involvement in Armed Conflict (New York: CIVIC, 2015), 50.

64 Human Rights Committee, ‘On the Right to Life’ 2017 (Footnote n. 20), para. 70.

65 Even though the principle of proportionality is not mentioned in the ECHR or the ICCPR, it is well established that in a law enforcement context, the use of force ought to be not only necessary, but also proportionate to the threat and the gravity of the offence (Lubell, ‘Challenges in Applying Human Rights Law’ 2005 (Footnote n. 14), 745). IHL, in contrast, does not recognise a proportionality restriction on the use of force against combatants or members of organised armed groups with a continuous combat function.

66 For a critique of the continuous combat function as extending status-based targeting to individuals who are not combatants, see Philip Alston, Report of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions, A/HRC/14/24/Add.6 (28 May 2010), para. 65.

67 For this claim, see Melzer, Interpretive Guidance 2010 (Footnote n. 59), part I, recommendations VII and IX; Quénivet, ‘The Right to Life’ 2008 (Footnote n. 57), 340.

68 Michael N. Schmitt, ‘Military Necessity and Humanity in International Humanitarian Law: Preserving the Delicate Balance’, Virginia Journal of International Law 50 (2010), 795839; Michael N. Schmitt, ‘The Interpretive Guidance on the Notion of Direct Participation in Hostilities: a Critical Analysis’, Harvard National Security Journal 1 (2010), 544. For the argument that IHL ought to contain such a demand, see Gabriella Blum, ‘The Dispensable Lives of Soldiers’, Journal of Legal Analysis 2 (2010), 69124; Janina Dill, ‘Forcible Alternatives to War’, in Ohlin (ed.), Theoretical Boundaries of Armed Conflict 2016 (Footnote n. 5), 289–314 (301).

69 Individuals with a continuous combat function can more easily gain immunity from attack by opting out of this function or renouncing membership in the organised armed group.

70 Even if an individual’s prior consent could render his or her killing human rights-conforming, IHL would not vouchsafe that individuals who are permissible targets of intentional attack have forfeited their right to life. As adumbrated, IHL does not regulate the conditions under which States assign individuals the status of combatant. Predictably, IHL does not require that an attacker enquires into an individual’s motives or potential consent in the course of establishing their continuous combat function either.

71 Article 35(2) API.

72 By way of explanation, many scholars do not point to the history, text, practice or structure of IHL, but to the observation that such an authorisation of force would challenge principles of justice, because IHL would authorise conduct that may well further an illegal or unjust aim. This is an interpretive path to the elucidation of what the law is that many of these scholars would otherwise eschew. For instance, John Westlake, International Law: Part II War (Cambridge University Press, 1907), 52.

73 Adil A. Haque, ‘International Law in Armed Conflict’, blog post on Just Security, 23 November 2016.

75 Article 43 API.

76 Article 43(1) API.

77 Organised armed groups fighting in their own right in an IAC, without the backing of a State party to the conflict are a recent phenomenon. Nothing indicates that API would deem such an organised armed group a party to the conflict to which it seeks to extend the equal applicability of IHL enshrined in the preamble of the treaty.

78 For the argument that the principle of equality among belligerents does not apply in NIACs, see Doswald-Beck, ‘The Right to Life in Armed Conflict’ 2006 (n. 3), 881904 (903). For the argument that belligerent equality is much weaker in NIACs, see Jonathan Somer, ‘Jungle Justice: Passing Sentence on the Equality of Belligerents in Non-International Armed Conflict’, International Review of the Red Cross 89 (2007), 655–90 (659 et seq.).

79 The regimes for IACs and NIACs are now widely argued to converge as a matter of custom. This conclusion would therefore raise the question of whether the principles for the conduct of hostilities now deemed applicable in NIACs are indeed ‘only prohibitory’ there, even though they authorise the corresponding acts in IACs.

80 See Derek Jinks, ‘International Human Rights Law in Time of Armed Conflict’, in Andrew Clapham and Paola Gaeta (eds.), Oxford Handbook of International Law in Armed Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2014), 656–74 (666).

81 See, for instance, Jean Cohen, ‘Sovereignty in the Context of Globalization: A Constitutional Pluralist Perspective’, in Besson and Tasioulas (eds.), The Philosophy of International Law 2010 (Footnote n. 2), 261–82 (262).

82 Jinks, ‘International Human Rights in Time of Armed Conflict’ 2014 (Footnote n. 80), 688.

83 Even if we demanded that those prior prohibitions were anchored in IHL, in the case of the principle of proportionality, IHL creates what is in effect an exception to its own prohibition on targeting civilians intentionally. That this exception is likewise formulated as a prohibition on overstepping the limits of the exception does nothing to lessen the endorsement that, by logical implication, IHL affords conduct that does not fall foul of the prohibition.

84 For the concept of the law’s expressive force and the argument that law does not only govern by means of formal authorisation and sanction, but also by ‘shap[ing] individual preferences by changing one’s taste for specific outcomes’, see Elizabeth Anderson and Richard Pildes, ‘Expressive Theories of Law: a General Restatement’, University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148 (2000), 1503–75.

85 Joseph Raz, Between Authority and Interpretation: On the Theory of Law and Practical Reason (Oxford University Press, 2009), 173.

86 Buchanan speaks of a ‘content-independent’ reason to obey rules that emanate from legitimate institutions. This reason has to be considered alongside content-dependent reasons for or against compliance (Allen Buchanan, ‘The Legitimacy of International Law’, in Besson and Tasioulas (eds.), The Philosophy of International Law 2010 (Footnote n. 2), 79–98 (82)). Some scholars hold that the content-independent reason to obey legitimate rules is decisive (for instance, John Tasioulas, ‘The Legitimacy of International Law’, in Besson and Tasioulas (eds.), The Philosophy of International Law 2010 (Footnote n. 2), 97–118 (98)). Not least because the procedural legitimacy of international legal rules cannot universally be assumed, and I do not discuss it here, I maintain that the content-independent reason to obey a law is not decisive and can be defeated by stronger moral reasons.

87 Raz cautions that ‘we cannot say that in its historical manifestations through the ages [law] has always, or generally, been a morally valuable institution, and we can certainly not say that it has necessarily been so’. Raz, Between Authority and Interpretation 2009 (n. 85), 179.

88 Joseph Raz, ‘The Problem of Authority: Revisiting the Service Conception’, Minnesota Law Review 90 (2006), 1003–44.

89 In his recent account of how IHL relates to the morality of war, Haque rejects the relevance of the second moral task for our moral assessment of IHL. He equates a Razian ‘service view’ of law with the task of guiding the individual towards the fulfilment of his or her moral duties in war and offers a detailed critique of IHL in the light of this moral goal (Haque, Law and Morality at War 2017 (Footnote n. 28)). Dill and Shue’s account of the moral justification of IHL, in contrast, only focuses on IHL’s second task of producing the best possible outcome for rights, i.e., a minimisation of unjustified infringements of individual rights in war overall (Janina Dill and Henry Shue, ‘Limiting Killing in War: Necessity and the St. Petersburg Assumption’, Ethics and International Affairs 26 (2012), 311–34). Building on both works, I show exactly how and where these two tasks make divergent demands on the rules of warfare. If we treat both tasks as prima facie equally important, the morally best possible rules for conduct in war offer a compromise, as discussed in the last section of this chapter.

90 Both conventional just war theory and the now dominant revisionist critique recognise the preservation of individual moral rights as the touchstone for justified conduct in war. For a comprehensive account of conventional just war theory, see Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: a Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations (London: Basic Books, 1977), 135, 137. For the most influential example of the revisionist critique, which challenges the conventional account on reductive individualist grounds, see Jeff McMahan, Killing in War (Oxford University Press, 2009); McMahan, ‘The Ethics of Killing in War’ 2004 (n. 9), 693732.

91 Fabre, Cosmopolitan War 2012 (Footnote n. 9), 6; Lazar, ‘The Morality and the Law of War’ 2012 (Footnote n. 9).

92 This proposition is derived from the moral doctrine of double effect, which permits causing unintentional, but foreseeable harm (the bad effect) in pursuit of a good effect, if the latter is proportional to the former. It is widely credited to St. Thomas Aquinas. See Judith Lichtenberg, ‘War, Innocence and the Doctrine of Double Effect’, Philosophical Studies 74 (1994), 347–68.

93 No other considerations, such as individual welfare or the rights of communities, ‘count’ towards the proportionality of the infringement of an individual right to life. The rule of law, as discussed below, is morally relevant also only to the extent that it serves the protection of fundamental individual rights.

94 In order to fulfil the law’s first moral task, a legal ‘ought’ should therefore presuppose ‘can’. That is also a matter of fairness as law often claims the authority to impose a cost on those subjects that fail to meet its demands. In the context of the laws of war, this point is most forcefully articulated by Shue, ‘Do We Need a “Morality of War”?’ 2010 (Footnote n. 12).

95 In contrast, the more straightforward it is how to follow one’s moral obligations in any given situation, the more likely it is that the morally best law looks quite like the underlying moral principle.

96 Tasioulas, ‘The Legitimacy of International Law’ 2010 (Footnote n. 86), 101.

97 H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law, 2nd edn. (Oxford University Press, 1997), 237.

98 For instance, enforcing a law against pre-natal behaviour that seriously harms the child would reflect the moral wrongfulness of such an action. At the same time, it would not only require a morally problematic interference into a women’s physical autonomy, it would also create incentives to terminate pregnancies. This example is developed in McMahan, ‘The Morality of War and the Law of War’ 2010 (Footnote n. 12), 33.

99 In this context, law might still serve its first moral task of affording the individual a guide towards meeting her moral obligations, even if the individual is likely to forgo this service.

100 For instance, if a law demanded that soldiers accept so much risk that they are highly unlikely to survive, but this law could not be monitored or enforced, it would be unable to fulfil its second moral task as it would very likely be ignored.

101 As we will see, it also depends on the legal rules that govern the resort to force because they manage the incentives and shape the epistemic context in which the law addresses soldiers.

102 Derogation clauses likewise echo the logic of a moral lesser evil justification. They grant an exceptional permission to override individual legal rights if this is unavoidable in the pursuit of safeguarding an important legally recognised aim.

103 Neither the ECHR nor the ICCPR actually mention proportionality as a condition for permissible killing. However, as discussed in the previous section, the UN Human Rights Committee suggests that the use of lethal force in law enforcement operations has to be proportionate to the gravity of the offence/threat.

104 Imagine a case in which the fleeing individual is evading arrest in order to save a great number of innocent bystanders and he or she poses a threat only to one innocent bystander. Infringing that person’s right to life may be proportionate to the threat she or he poses to the one individual, but if the latter is justified on lesser evil grounds, then killing her or him may not be morally justified.

105 Neither is it universally true from a moral point of view that in any given public emergency, a State should always be permitted to derogate from some of its legal obligations and override individual moral rights in the process.

106 On the other hand, there may well be contexts in which it could be exceptionally morally justified for the State to override individual rights for the protection of an even greater number of individual rights, but such conduct would not be condoned by IHRL because it would not fit the recognised context of an insurrection, riot or organised violence, for instance, the use of force to prevent the spread of a deadly disease or to prevent an environmental catastrophe.

107 John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 54.

108 Reviewing the insufficiency of moral reasons for capital punishment is beyond the scope of this chapter. For a succinct overview of moral arguments for and against capital punishment, see Theodore L. Dorpat, Crime of Punishment: America’s Culture of Violence (New York: Algora, 2007), ch. 9.

109 The ICCPR only reluctantly permits the death penalty, calling for its abolition in the same provision.

110 In their influential exchange on this issue, McMahan and Shue agree that the laws of war diverge from fundamental moral principles on the permissibility of killing and that moral reasons account for some of this divergence. However, they disagree on the question of whether IHL should therefore be considered morally less than ideal. McMahan, ‘The Morality of War and the Law of War’ 2010 (Footnote n. 12); Shue, ‘Do We Need a “Morality of War”?’ 2010 (Footnote n. 12). See also Lazar, ‘The Morality and the Law of War’ 2012 (Footnote n. 9).

111 For an exploration of factors that make soldiers more likely to be morally liable to attack than civilians, see Seth Lazar, ‘The Responsibility Dilemma for Killing in War: a Review Essay’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 38 (2010), 180213.

112 Only religious and medical personnel are exempt.

113 On this account a war has a just aim if resorting to force is the lesser moral evil in terms of unjustified rights infringements, as outlined in detail in Section V.C.

114 For a discussion of potential excuses for participating in an unjust war and their moral implications, see Judith Lichtenberg, ‘How to Judge Soldiers Whose Cause is Unjust’, in Rodin and Shue (eds.), Just and Unjust Warriors 2010 (Footnote n. 12), 112–31 (118).

115 IHL does not only permit unnecessary attacks against soldiers, it also allows disproportionate harm against them. From a moral point of view, in contrast, intentional defensive harm has to be proportionate to the gravity of an unjustified threat.

116 In turn, IHL likely shields some civilians from attack who are morally liable to harm in virtue of a significant, but indirect, contribution to an unjust war.

117 This argument is elaborated further in Dill and Shue, ‘Limiting Killing in War’ 2012 (Footnote n. 89). For the view that a more fine-grained differentiation among individuals than IHL demands would be possible, see Bradley Jay Strawser, ‘Revisionist Just War Theory and the Real World: a Cautiously Optimistic Proposal’, in Fritz Allhoff, Adam Henschke and Nick Evans (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Ethics and War: Just War in the Twenty-First Century (London: Routledge, 2013), 7690. Section IV.B returns to this issue in more detail.

118 See Section II.B for a detailed analysis of the epistemic threshold at which IHL permits deeming civilian harm necessary.

119 Preamble to API.

120 For a similar critique, see Thomas Hurka, ‘Proportionality in the Morality of War’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 33 (2005), 3466.

121 Janina Dill, ‘Should International Law Ensure the Moral Acceptability of War?’, Leiden Journal of International Law 26 (2012), 253–70.

122 Judging the moral permissibility of a resort to force is in principle equally difficult if the belligerent is a non-State organised armed group rather than a State. Whether in reality fighters in non-State organised armed groups have more or less information than combatants in States’ armed forces about the true aims and likely consequences of a resort to force may vary depending on the hierarchy and organisation of an armed group.

123 ECtHR, Nachova and Others v. Bulgaria, Judgment of 6 July 2005, Application Nos. 43577/98 and 43579/98, para. 107.

124 An alternative approach distinguishes between ‘active hostilities’, guided by IHL, and ‘security operations’, guided primarily by IHRL. The latter include the use of force in the context of an IAC, but without nexus to the conflict and ‘low-intensity military operations’ against a non-State belligerent in a NIAC. See Murray, Practitioners’ Guide to Human Rights Law in Armed Conflict 2016 (Footnote n. 6), paras. 5.05, 5.08.

125 As mentioned, the general claim that, for moral reasons, IHL has to diverge from underlying moral principles is widely accepted among analytical just war theorists. Some international lawyers similarly argue that IHRL is ill-suited for governing the conduct of hostilities, even though it may be relevant for the regulation of armed conflict more generally. These claims are, however, rarely rooted in a systematic analysis of the features of armed conflict that account for these intuitions.

126 ICRC, ‘Article 2: Application of the Convention’, Commentary on the First Geneva Convention: Convention (I) for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and Sick Armed Forces in the Field of 12 August 1949 (Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross, 2016), para. 192.

127 Common Art. 2 GCI–GCIV.

128 ICRC, ‘Article 2: Application of the Convention’ 2016 (Footnote n. 126), paras. 209, 211. This understanding of war as a matter of fact has been reaffirmed in the case law of international criminal tribunals. See, among others, ICTY, Prosecutor v. Boškoski and Tarčulovski, Case No. IT-04-82-T, Trial Chamber Judgment of 10 July 2008, para. 174; ICTR, Prosecutor v. Akayesu, Case No. ICTR-96-4-T, Trial Chamber Judgment of 2 October 1998, para. 603.

129 The prohibition on the use of force at roughly the same time as the adoption of the Geneva Conventions accounts for this change. As war morphed from a legitimate expression of sovereign statecraft into a deviation from the recognised rules of inter-State relations, it became unlikely that States would declare war and acknowledge a presumptive breach of international law.

130 Similar ICRC, ‘How is the Term “Armed Conflict” Defined in International Humanitarian Law?’ Opinion Paper of 17 March 2008, 1.

131 ICRC, ‘Article 2: Application of the Convention’ 2016 (Footnote n. 126), para. 243.

132 Pictet, IV Geneva Convention: Commentary 1958 (Footnote n. 21), 20–1; similar Dapo Akande, ‘Classification of Armed Conflicts: Relevant Legal Concepts’, in Elizabeth Wilmshurst (ed.), International Law and the Classification of Conflicts (Oxford University Press, 2015), 3279 (41); Richard Baxter, ‘The Duties of Combatants and the Conduct of Hostilities (Law of The Hague)’, in International Dimensions of Humanitarian Law (Henry Dunant Institute/UNESCO, 1988), 98; Christopher J. Greenwood, ‘Scope of Application of International Humanitarian Law’, in Fleck (ed.), Handbook of International Humanitarian Law 2009 (Footnote n. 21), 46, paras. 201–63 (para. 202); Jean Pictet, Commentary on the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, vol. III (Geneva, 1960), para. 23; Sylvain Vité, ‘Typology of Armed Conflicts in International Humanitarian Law: Legal Concepts and Actual Situations’, International Review of the Red Cross 69 (2009), 6994 (72). For the minority view that there is a threshold of intensity for the applicability of IHL in IACs, see International Law Association, Committee on the Use of Force, Final Report on the Meaning of Armed Conflict in International Law (The Hague Conference, 2010), 32–3.

133 The First Additional Protocol demands that it ‘must be fully applied in all circumstances … without any adverse distinction based on the … causes espoused by or attributed to the Parties to the conflict’ (preamble of the First Additional Protocol). See also ICTY, Prosecutor v. Duško Tadić, Case No. IT-94-1-A, 66, Decision on the Defence Motion for Interlocutory Appeal on Jurisdiction of 2 October 1995, para. 218.

134 Akande, ‘Classification of Armed Conflicts’ 2015 (Footnote n. 132), 42.

135 The Commentary to Common Art. 3 argues that an ‘armed conflict not of an international character’ is a situation ‘in which organised Parties confront one another with violence of a certain degree of intensity.’ ICRC, ‘Article 3: Conflicts not of an International Character’, Commentary on the First Geneva Convention: Convention (I) for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and Sick Armed Forces in the Field of 12 August 1949 (Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross, 2016), para. 387.

136 ICTY, Tadić, Decision on Jurisdiction (Footnote n. 133), para. 70. It is noteworthy that this definition dispenses with State participation as a necessary element of an armed conflict and extends the applicability of IHL to the use of armed force solely by and against non-State actors. The threshold of minimum intensity is thus crucial also for the differentiation of armed conflicts from private violence. The ICC Statute further excludes ‘situations of internal disturbances and tensions, such as riots, isolated and sporadic acts of violence or other acts of a similar nature’ as falling below this threshold. Art. 8(2)(d) and 8(2)(f) ICC Statute, following Art. 1 APII; similar ICRC, ‘Article 3: Conflicts not of an International Character’ 2016 (Footnote n. 135), para. 386.

137 Although the term clearly suggests that there is a minimum length of hostilities, the Abella case affords a counter-example of an armed conflict taking the guise of one intense, but discrete and relatively short attack. Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, Juan Carlos Abella v. Argentina, Case No. 11.137, Report No. 55/97 of 18 November 1997, OEA/Ser L/V/II.98.

138 For an overview, see Akande, ‘Classification of Armed Conflicts’ 2015 (Footnote n. 132), 53, referencing, ICTY, Prosecutor v. Haradinaj et al., Case No. IT-04-84-T, Trial Chamber Judgment of 3 April 2008, para. 49; similar Watkin, Fighting at the Legal Boundaries 2016 (Footnote n. 5), 583.

139 ICRC, ‘Article 3: Conflicts not of an International Character’ 2016 (Footnote n. 135), para. 386.

140 The ICRC Customary Law study identified 148 out of 161 rules applicable in IACs as also applicable in NIACs, without differentiating between NIACs under the purview of APII and those only under the purview of Common Art. 3. Jean-Marie Henckaerts and Louise Doswald-Beck (eds.), Customary International Humanitarian Law, Vol. I: Rules (Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross, 2005).

141 ICTY, Tadić, Decision on Jurisdiction (Footnote n. 133), para. 70 (emphasis added).

142 For a slightly different typology, see Jelena Pejic, ‘Conflict Classification and the Law Applicable to Detention and the Use of Force’, in Wilmshurst (ed.), Classification of Conflicts 2015 (Footnote n. 132), 80–116 (84).

143 For the view that intervention with the consent of or on behalf of the territorial State does not turn a conflict into an IAC, see also Dieter Fleck, ‘The Law of Non-International Armed Conflict’, in Dieter Fleck (ed.), The Handbook of International Humanitarian Law, 3rd edn. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013), 589–610 (605); ICC, Prosecutor v. Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo, Case No. ICC-01/05-01/08, Confirmation of Charges Decision (Pre-Trial Chamber), 15 June 2009, para. 246.

144 Watkin, Fighting at the Legal Boundaries 2016 (Footnote n. 5), 336.

145 Akande, ‘Classification of Armed Conflicts’ 2015 (Footnote n. 132), 73.

146 Similar Human Rights Council, ‘Report of the Commission of Inquiry on Lebanon Pursuant to Human Rights Council Resolution S-2/1’, A/HRC/3/2 (23 November 2006), paras. 50–62.

147 To recall, ‘[t]he requirement for a degree of intensity indicates that the threshold of violence that is required for the application of international humanitarian law in non-international armed conflicts is higher than in the case of international armed conflicts’. Akande, ‘Classification of Armed Conflicts’ 2015 (Footnote n. 132), 53–4.

148 This does not mean that there is currently scholarly consensus that the conduct of hostilities in such a situation is exclusively governed by IHL. Watkin, for instance, argues that a State should be guided by IHRL when facing a non-State opponent – so in IAC types (4), (5b) and (6) – for as long as this is ‘operationally feasible’. Watkin, Fighting at the Legal Boundaries 2016 (Footnote n. 5), 550.

149 Article 2(1) ICCPR. See also Sarah Joseph and Melissa Castan, The International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights Cases, Materials, and Commentary (Oxford University Press, 2013), para. 4.11. For a discussion of the jurisdictional reach of the ECHR, see ECtHR, Banković and Others v. Belgium and Others, Decision of 12 December 2001, Application No. 52207/99, para. 59; ECtHR, Khan v. United Kingdom, Decision of 28 January 2014, Application No. 11987/11, para. 25.

150 For a review of the relevant jurisprudence, see Oona Hathaway, Philip Levitz, Elizabeth Nielsen, Aileen Nowlan, William Perdue, Chelsea Purvis, Sara Solow and Julia Spiegel, ‘Human Rights Abroad: When Do Human Rights Treaty Obligations Apply Extraterritorially?’, Arizona State Law Journal 43 (2011), 138.

151 For limits on the intra-territorial applicability of the ICCPR, see Joseph and Castan, The International Covenant 2013 (Footnote n. 149), para. 4.21. ECtHR case law suggests that such limits can be due to a secessionist party’s operating on a State’s territory (ECtHR, Ilaşcu and Others v. Moldova and Russia, Grand Chamber Judgment of 8 July 2004, Application No. 48787/99, para. 312) or because the State hosts an international court or tribunal. ECtHR, Djokaba Lambi Longa v. the Netherlands, Decision of 9 October 2012, Application No. 33917/12, para. 80; ECtHR, Galić v. the Netherlands, Decision of 9 June 2009, Application No. 22617/07, para. 44; ECtHR, Blagojević v. the Netherlands, Decision of 9 June 2009, Application No. 49032/07, para. 44.

152 The Court has concluded that the ECHR applies ‘when, as a consequence of lawful or unlawful military action, a Contracting State exercises effective control’. ECtHR, Al-Skeini v. United Kingdom, Decision of 7 July 2011, Application Nos. 55721/07 and 27021/08, para. 138. See also ECtHR, Loizidou, Decision of 8 December 1996, Application No. 15318/89, para. 62.

153 ECtHR, Issa and Others v. Turkey, Judgment of 16 November 2004, Application No. 31821/96, para. 74.

154 As indicated, once a belligerent State has effective control over an enemy State’s territory, IHL’s rules on occupation rather than those governing hostilities may apply. In the following, in order to elucidate the epistemic implications of a State having effective control during the conduct of hostilities, I therefore focus on the parameters of effective control over persons rather than the parameters of effective control over territory.

155 For an overview of the case law, see Sarah H. Cleveland, ‘Embedded International Law and the Constitution Abroad’, Columbia Law Review 110 (2010), 225–51.

156 ECtHR, Jaloud v. the Netherlands, Judgment of 20 November 2014, Application No. 47708/08, para. 125.

157 See, for instance, ECtHR, Pad and Others v. Turkey, Judgment of 28 June 2007, Application No. 60167/00, para. 54.

158 Murray, Practitioners’ Guide to Human Rights Law in Armed Conflict 2016 (Footnote n. 6), para. 3.4. The commentary lists ‘the extent to which the military, economic, and political support for the local subordinate administration provides it with influence and control over the region’. William Schabas, The European Convention on Human Rights: a Commentary (Oxford University Press, 2015), 103.

159 The ECtHR uses ‘effective control’ in three different ways: first, to designate the attributability of an agent’s conduct to a State; second, to refer to a State’s legal competence to exercise public powers; and, third, as a description of the factual conditions that mean a State is presumed to be able to discharge its obligations under the ECHR (for this point, see Marco Milanovic, ‘From Compromise to Principle: Clarifying the Concept of State Jurisdiction in Human Rights Treaties’, Human Rights Law Review 8 (2008), 411–49 (423)). It is only this third use of the term effective control that is relevant for the moral question of whether or not IHRL or IHL are the better law for guiding an individual towards the fulfilment of his or her moral obligations.

160 ECtHR, Al-Skeini v. United Kingdom (Footnote n. 152), para. 137.

161 ‘Control’, see Oxford English Dictionary, available at: https://en.oxforddictionaries.com/definition/control.

162 We assume for now that the use of violence ‘on the other side’ is unlawful. I return below to the implications of IHRL demanding a lawful aim for the deprivation of the right to life to be permissible.

163 Intentionally killing civilians would be equally permissible, subject to the same conditions.

164 Whereas an intensification of hostilities reduces instances in which an attacker can fulfil a duty of care, it may increase the number of instances in which soldiers have to counter an obvious and immediate danger to their own life or that of civilians. Under IHRL, soldiers would be permitted to defend themselves or third parties in such situations by using lethal force if necessary.

165 I bracket the substantive implications of IHL’s principle of proportionality here because it fails to be action-guiding regardless of the care invested in formulating expectations about the consequences of an attack. It is hence not only the degree of action guidance, but also the substantive implications for action of the principle that remain unaffected by an intensification of hostilities. For this argument, see Dill, ‘Do Attackers have a Legal Duty of Care?’ (Footnote n. 50).

166 The exception is that an intensification in hostilities may make attacks against persons less likely to be permissible. This is due to Art. 50(1) API, which stipulates that ‘in case of doubt whether a person is a civilian, they shall be considered to be a civilian’.

167 Section III.C also emphasised the legal uncertainty surrounding the resort to force by and against non-State actors across international borders. Relying on domestic law does not, for instance, afford a definitive answer to the question of which side uses force unlawfully during a transnational armed confrontation (type 6).

168 Section III.C also highlighted that it would be highly problematic to tie individuals’ loss of their human right to life to the conduct of their State over which they likely have little control.

169 These rights may include individually held political rights to collective self-determination alongside the basic moral right to life.

170 I assume that lesser evil and proportionality calculations require a consideration of both the likelihood and the gravity/number of necessary individual rights infringements compared to the individual rights violations to be prevented. It follows that the resort to force is not subject to a separate criterion of ‘reasonable chance of success’.

171 Whether the individual rights infringements inflicted to avoid a greater evil are proportionate to the rights violations prevented is an even more difficult question to answer than whether a war will be a lesser evil, in the first place. I mostly bracket the proportionality question in the following discussion.

172 Whether the agent resorting to force for a morally just aim bears any moral responsibility for the individual rights violations the other side commits in reaction to their resort to force is subject to contestation. For a discussion of this issue, see Henry Shue, ‘Last Resort and Proportionality’, in Seth Lazar and Helen Frowe (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War (Oxford University Press, 2018), 260–76.

173 Dill, ‘Should International Law Ensure the Moral Acceptability of War?’ 2012 (Footnote n. 121).

174 Olivier Corten, The Law Against War: the Prohibition on the Use of Force in Contemporary International Law (Oxford: Hart, 2010), 200; Yoram Dinstein, War, Aggression, and Self-Defence, 5th edn. (Cambridge University Press, 2012), 8698; Jochen A. Frowein, ‘Jus Cogens’, in Rüdiger Wolfrum (ed.), Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law (online edn.), March 2013.

175 For the continued contestability of a right to unilateral humanitarian intervention, see, among others, Sir Nigel Rodley, ‘Humanitarian Intervention’, in Marc Weller (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Use of Force in International Law (Oxford University Press, 2015), 775–96.

176 For moral critiques of humanitarian intervention, see Beate Jahn, ‘Humanitarian Intervention: What’s in a Name?’, International Politics 49 (2012), 3658; Jennifer Welsh, ‘Taking Consequences Seriously: Objections to Humanitarian Intervention’, in Jennifer Walsh (ed.), Humanitarian Intervention and International Relations (Oxford University Press, 2004), 5270.

177 Daniel Joyner, International Law and the Proliferation of Weapons of Mass Destruction (Oxford University Press, 2009), 178; Louis Cavaré, ‘Les sanctions dans le cadre de l’ONU’, Recueil des Cours de l’académie de droit international (1951), 191291 (221); Jean Combacau, Le pouvoir de sanction de l’ONU. Étude théorique de la coercition non militaire (Paris: Pedone, 1974), 916; Marco Roscini, ‘The United Nations Security Council and the Enforcement of International Humanitarian Law’, Israel Law Review 43 (2010), 330–59 (334).

178 Corten, The Law Against War 2010 (Footnote n. 174), 403; Dinstein, War, Aggression and Self-Defence 2012 (Footnote n. 174), 174; Eritrea–Ethiopia Claims Commission, Partial Award of 19 December 2005, Jus Ad Bellum Ethiopia’s Claims 1-8, para. 11; ICJ, Case Concerning the Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. United States of America), Merits, Judgment of 27 June 1986, ICJ Reports 1986, 14, para. 195; ICJ, Oil Platforms case (Iran v. United States of America), Merits, Judgment of 6 November 2003, ICJ Reports 2003, 161, para. 51. For the minority position that an armed attack does not have to cross a particular threshold of gravity, but includes all cross-border uses of force by States, see Chatham House, ‘The Chatham House Principles of International Law on the Use of Force in Self-Defence’, International and Comparative Law Quarterly 55 (2006), 963–72 (966); Adam Sofaer, ‘Terrorism, the Law, and the National Defense’, Military Law Review 126 (1989), 8393 (89).

179 Michael Bothe, ‘Terrorism and the Legality of Pre-emptive Force’, European Journal of International Law 14 (2003), 227–40 (230); Michael Bothe, ‘Das Gewaltverbot im Allgemeinen’, in Wilfried Schaumann (ed.), Völkerrechtliches Gewaltverbot und Friedenssicherung (Baden-Baden: Nomos, 1971), 1130 (16 et seq.); Mary Ellen O’Connell, ‘The Myth of Pre-emptive Self-Defence’, American Society of International Law Task Force on Terrorism (2002), 8; Corten, The Law Against War 2010 (Footnote n. 174), 403; Dinstein, War, Aggression, and Self-Defence 2012 (Footnote n. 174), 184, 207; Christine Gray, International Law and the Use of Force, 3rd edn. (Oxford University Press, 2008), 118; Malcom N. Shaw, International Law, 6th edn. (Cambridge University Press, 2008), 1133.

180 Georg Nolte and Albrecht Randelzhofer, ‘Ch. VII Action with Respect to Threats to the Peace, Breaches of the Peace and Acts of Aggression, Article 51’, in Bruno Simma, Daniel-Erasmus Khan, Georg Nolte, Andreas Paulus and Nikolai Wessendorf (eds.), The Charter of the United Nations: a Commentary, 3rd edn. (Oxford University Press, 2012), 1397–428 (para. 6). For the minority view that customary law permits forcible self-defence against military violence below the threshold of an armed attack, see Shaw, International Law 2008 (Footnote n. 179), 1131; ICJ, Military and Paramilitary Activities (Footnote n. 178), para. 12.

181 Dapo Akande and Thomas Liefländer, ‘Clarifying Necessity, Imminence, and Proportionality in the Law of Self-Defense’, American Journal of International Law 107 (2013), 563–70 (569); Daniel Bethlehem, ‘Self-Defense Against an Imminent or Actual Armed Attack by Nonstate Actors’, American Journal of International Law 106 (2012), 769–77 (774); David Kretzmer, ‘The Inherent Right to Self-Defence and Proportionality in Jus ad Bellum’, European Journal of International Law 24 (2013), 235–82 (235).

182 ICJ, Military and Paramilitary Activities (Footnote n. 178), para. 195.

183 I bracket a discussion of the legal necessity and proportionality of the resort to force in self-defence. Akande and Liefländer argue convincingly that, at the ‘ad bellum level’, these criteria are mostly deemed fulfilled when the initial use of force reaches the threshold of an armed attack. Akande and Liefländer, ‘Clarifying Necessity, Imminence, and Proportionality’ 2013 (Footnote n. 181).

184 Dinstein, War, Aggression and Self-Defence 2012 (Footnote n. 174), 195; Abdulqawi A. Yusuf, ‘The Notion of “Armed Attack” in the Nicaragua Judgment and its Influence on Subsequent Case Law’, Leiden Journal of International Law 25 (2012), 461–70 (463).

185 Nolte and Randelzhofer, ‘Ch. VII Action with Respect to Threats to the Peace’ 2012 (Footnote n. 180).

186 Roberto Ago, Special Rapporteur to the International Law Commission, ‘Eighth Report on State Responsibility’, International Law Commission Yearbook I (1980), UN Doc. A/CN.4/318/ ADD.5-7121, 13, para. 120.

187 Kretzmer, ‘The Inherent Right to Self-Defence’ 2013 (Footnote n. 181), 240. Christian Tams has noted that defensive operations often follow purposes of deterrence, prevention and even retaliation. Christian Tams, ‘The Use of Force against Terrorists’, European Journal of International Law 20 (2009), 359–97 (391).

188 See, among others, Christopher Greenwood, ‘Self-Defence’, in Rüdiger Wolfrum (ed.), Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law (online edn.), April 2011, para. 28; Judith Gardam, Necessity, Proportionality and the Use of Force by States (Cambridge University Press, 2004), 160 et seq.; Tarcisio Gazzini, The Changing Rules on the Use of Force in International Law (Manchester University Press, 2005), 148; Gray, International Law and the Use of Force 2008 (Footnote n. 179), 150; Rosalyn Higgins, Problems and Process (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), 232; Georg Nolte, ‘Multipurpose Self-Defence, Proportionality Disoriented: a Response to David Kretzmer’, European Journal of International Law 24 (2013), 283–90 (286) (more references).

189 Furthermore, the Security Council is, of course, a political, rather than an adjudicative body.

190 Armed confrontations that according to their belligerent configurations would count as NIACs (i.e., types 1, 3, and 5a), but which are not protracted, count as law enforcement operations under the purview of IHRL for the purposes of this discussion.

191 What happens when the opposing State’s soldiers put up enough resistance to render hostilities protracted is addressed below.

192 ICTY, Prosecutor v. Kunarac et al., Case No. IT-96-23-T&1-T, Trial Chamber Judgment of 22 February 2001, para. 470.

193 Pejic, ‘Conflict Classification’ 2015 (Footnote n. 142), 6. For the argument that IHRL is increasingly deemed applicable and applied horizontally, see Phillip Alston (ed.), Human Rights and Non-State Actors (New York: Oxford University Press, 2005); Andrew Clapham, Human Rights in the Private Sphere (Oxford University Press, 1993); Andrew Clapham, Human Rights Obligations of Non-State Actors (Oxford University Press, 2006).

194 Unfortunately, we can be confident about this because IHL attracts very little compliance among non-State armed groups. For a discussion of measures that could be taken to assist non-State armed groups in applying IHRL during the conduct of hostilities, see Sandesh Sivakumaran, ‘Re-envisaging the International Law of Internal Armed Conflict’, European Journal of International Law 22 (2011), 219–64.

195 Thomas W. Smith, ‘Protection of Civilians or Soldiers? Humanitarian Law and the Economy of Risk in Iraq’, International Studies Perspectives 9 (2008), 144–64.

196 Joshua D. Kertzer, Kathleen E. Powers, Brian C. Rathbun and Ravi Iyer, ‘Moral Support: How Moral Values Shape Foreign Policy Attitudes’, Journal of Politics 76 (2014), 825–40.

197 If an outgroup is ‘morality based’, as enemies in war tend to be, outgroup hatred often intensifies. See Ori Weisel and Robert Boehm, ‘“Ingroup Love” and “Outgroup Hate” in Intergroup Conflict between Natural Groups’, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 60 (2015), 110–20.

198 The exception for civilians is direct participation in hostilities and for combatants surrender.

199 The guidelines for targeted killings outside areas of active hostilities of the previous US administration come indeed somewhat closer to a human rights standard in terms of the threat that the target has to pose and the requirement of zero expected incidental harm. Executive Order, Procedures for Approving Direct Action Against Terrorist Targets Located Outside the United States and Areas of Active Hostilities of 22 May 2013, available at: https://fas.org/irp/offdocs/ppd/ppg-procedures.pdf.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×