Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T02:26:19.616Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part I - The Object and Purpose of Corporations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 May 2023

Marco Corradi
Affiliation:
ESSEC Business School Paris and Singapore
Julian Nowag
Affiliation:
Lunds Universitet, Sweden

Summary

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

1 Corporate Law, Antitrust, and the History of Democratic Control of the Balance of Power

Michelle Meagher

Grown to tremendous proportions, there may be said to have evolved a “corporate system”—as there was once a feudal system—which has attracted to itself a combination of attributes and powers, and has attained a degree of prominence entitling it to be dealt with as a major social institution.Footnote 1

Adolf A. Berle and Gardiner C. Means, The Modern Corporation & Private Property (1932)
1.1 Introduction

Since their creation, corporations have proven to be vehicles for incredible aggregate wealth creation. Indeed, this was part of the intended design: the resource-strapped state sought a catalyst for public investment and so constituted the legal entity of the company, attaching to this artificial construct the rights and privileges that would allow it to successfully corral private capital.Footnote 2 From the creation of the Bank of England to the empire-building of the East India Company, the company form was harnessed as a tool for the expansion of public life.

It was, however, recognised at the outset that in creating a unique set of legal features that would make the company so attractive for private investment – in particular the later ability to own property, via the company, with limited liability – the state was not only creating its own co-investor in public wealth but there was also the possibility that the company would pose a threat to the state itself through its ability to channel and multiply the accumulation of private power.Footnote 3 The public’s salvation, therefore, came with an inherent threat of its undoing.

As such, since its inception, the corporation has been involved in a delicate dance with the state both to route its productive capacity towards socially desirable ends and to control the corporation’s power.Footnote 4 Today, as technological development and the mobilisation of international financial capital allow the power of the corporation to transcend that of the democratic state in both scale and scope, the tools of the past that were used with varying degrees of vigour to constrain the corporation are increasingly relevant. Corporate law and antitrust were once used to maintain the balance between the power of the corporation and the power of the state. Today, this vital role has been all but forgotten.

We have many regulatory tools that are used to proscribe the bounds of operation of the company, corporate law, and antitrust being two of them. Both disciplines are currently engaged in an active debate as to their core purpose in the modern context. Within antitrust, this has involved revisiting the ‘consumer welfare standard’ as the accepted litmus test of permitted competitive conduct; within corporate law, it manifests as a collective reflection on the shareholder primacy principle of corporate governance and the stakeholder capitalist model proposed as its alternative. Each debate would benefit from a more nuanced understanding of the origins of antitrust in corporate law (and vice versa) and the historical attempts to constrain the corporation as an entity with the built-in capability of challenging the state’s governmental power.

What we see from looking at the history of corporate law and antitrust is that each discipline historically played a complementary role in maintaining the balance of power between private, economic concentrations and the demos. The now-separate conversations about corporate responsibility in the corporate governance sphere and about corporate power within competition policy circles have always, in fact, been fundamentally connected and targeted at the same set of risks.

This chapter will start in Section 1.2 by exploring the concept of the balance of power, which will then form the framework for our historical exploration of corporate and antitrust law. We will then consider two manifestations of private power that the state must regulate: its own public grants of monopoly power, considered in Section 1.3, and what we will designate as ‘constructed monopolies’, discussed in Section 1.4. Constructed monopolies differ from publicly granted monopolies in that they are generated within the market, and it is in reaction to the development of such monopoly market positions that modern antitrust law comes into being. It is tempting to consider such monopolies to be ‘self-generating’ and as such the mirror-image of the public grant of monopoly. But as we shall see the state is continually involved in co-creating the market and the conditions for monopoly – or competition – and thus ‘constructed’ is a more accurate framing for the modern monopoly than ‘self-generating’.

Whereas modern antitrust forged its path in the regulation of constructed monopolies, corporate law marched into the territory of corporate responsibility, in particular, a responsibility towards investors. Corporate responsibility will be the focus of Section 1.5. Although at face value corporate responsibility seems to operate according to a different logic to the control of corporate and market power – focused instead on investor protections – we shall see that this is, or at least could have been, an aspect of the balance of power. Finally, this chapter will conclude in Section 1.6 by considering the relevance today of the concept of the balance of power to the operation of antitrust and corporate law.

1.2 Balance of Power

The challenge of maintaining the balance of power between the demos and industry stems from the phenomenon of economies of scale. As Ellis Hawley observes:

One of the central problems of twentieth-century America has revolved about the difficulty of reconciling a modern industrial order, necessarily based upon a high degree of collective organization, with democratic postulates, competitive ideals, and liberal individualistic traditions inherited from the nineteenth century. This industrial order has created in America a vision of material abundance, a dream of abolishing poverty and achieving economic security for all; and the great majority of Americans have not been willing to destroy it lest that dream be lost. Yet at the same time it has involved, probably necessarily, a concentration of economic power, a development of monopolistic arrangements, and a loss of individual freedom and initiative, all of which run counter to inherited traditions and ideals.Footnote 5

As Hawley describes, the industrial economy is prone to the agglomeration of production capacity, and with that concentration of economic resources comes a threat to individual freedom. Whether the industry is centralised within the state or centralised within private entities, the balance between the autonomy of society and the power of whoever commands the industry must be maintained. The allocation of property rights is thus central to society’s response to economies of scale. After identifying the ‘corporate system’ in the quote with which this chapter began, Berle and Means emphasise that the ‘Organization of property has played a constant part in the balance of powers which go to make up the life of any era’.Footnote 6 For Berle and Means, the ‘corporate system’ not only channels resources towards corporations but the impact of the overall system is so great that ‘it may even determine a large part ofthe behaviour of most men living under it’.Footnote 7 The corporation, as a tool for infrastructural and economic development, became the vessel into which increasing returns have been channelled, giving rise to an entity with equivalent powers to the state.

Although economies of scale may be part and parcel of technological development, it is important to note that the dominance of the corporation as an institution was not an inevitable consequence;Footnote 8 the corporation is a creature of the state.Footnote 9 Alternative modes of an economic organisation include partnerships, associations, municipal corporations, charities, and cooperatives. But it is the corporation that has really thrived, and it has done so with the explicit endorsement of the state. Historically, as we shall see in Section 1.3, the corporation was a positive creation of the state.Footnote 10 Today, the corporation exists at the pleasure of the state – anyone can start a corporation for any legal purpose and hardly any effort or bureaucracy is involved in the process. Yet still, the corporation relies on the passive acceptance of the state; the privilege of incorporation could be removed at any time.

The balance of power with which this chapter is concerned refers to the relationship between the power of the corporation and the power of the state. Given the mode of creation of corporate power, the balance of power is inherently reflexive. In a literal sense, the corporation’s power does not – cannot – exist independent of the state that creates it,Footnote 11 and at the same time, the capacity of the state has become dependent on the economic contributions of corporations as the chosen vehicle for harnessing economies of scale. Being creatures of the state, corporations are tied up in conference with the state, continually negotiating their very existence. This allows the state to push the corporation in directions that benefit society but also gives rise to the opportunity, and leverage, for the corporation to push back.

The balance of power does not start with the desirability or otherwise of increasing returns to scale in economic terms. Concentrated centres of power can be corrosive to public life and are automatically suspect as such. As K. Sabeel Rahman reminds us:

the biggest moral threats in a democratic society are those practices and arrangements that undermine the capacities and powers of citizens to be active political agents: the concentrated private power of firms that can dominate individuals in the economy; the diffused system of the market that can narrow one’s life opportunities and prospects; the spectre of an unresponsive and unaccountable state itself.Footnote 12

We can relate this notion of balance of power to Polanyi’s concept of the ‘double movement’.Footnote 13 As Polanyi explores in his seminal book The Great Transformation, the market is propelled to continuous expansion as it attempts to pull away from society and render the demos subservient to its logic. But this movement is met by a countermovement of society as society seeks to protect itself from the market’s destructive capacity. This manifests as a concerted effort to protect society from the market.Footnote 14 Touching on the reflexive nature of the relationship between Berle and Means’ ‘corporate system’ and the state, Polanyi developed the concept of ‘embeddedness’ which proposes that the market is embedded within society and the state.Footnote 15 This embeddedness ensures that the market’s attempts to pull away from society will always be met by a corresponding countermovement, tethered as the market is to the society that generates it.

This indeed is just what happened in relation to the corporation. As Naomi Lamoureaux and William Novak describe, as the’ persistent growth in the scale and scope of the largest business corporations frequently challenged extant regulatory rubrics – most famously with the development of interstate trusts and holding companies’ society has proven to be ‘surprisingly creative and versatile in generating new legal, administrative, and regulatory tools to bring even the most powerful corporations under a modicum of democratic control’.Footnote 16

Corporate law and antitrust have both played a role in this democratic countermovement. Corporate law constrains the scope of action of the entity that is the corporation. It thus can act as a check on the power of the corporation on the market and in society, not dissimilar to the remit of antitrust law. Meanwhile, antitrust looks to the external business arrangements of corporations, as well as other business organisations, and determines which configurations of capital are to be permitted the licence to wield collective power and which are to be forced to compete.Footnote 17 Antitrust was also once used to govern the corporation at an existential level, as a type of corporate law. Understanding the reactive, contingent, and ever-evolving nature of developments in each of these legal disciplines sheds light on the present-day efforts to respond to corporate domination.

1.3 Grant of Monopoly

The original model of the corporate ‘licence to operate’ was the corporate charter. In order to come into existence, a corporation required an affirmative act of the state – a decree of the sovereign or, later, an act of Parliament (in the United Kingdom), state legislatures, or Congress (in the United States).Footnote 18 Some of the first corporate charters were granted in England by a state eager to take advantage of private investment for the completion of public projects. By granting these artificial legal entities protection from liability and by guaranteeing a financial return, the corporate form was utilised as an engine for economic growth.Footnote 19

Corporate charters were a rare privilege. Very few were granted before the turn of the nineteenth century.Footnote 20 Before the rise of manufacturing, charters were generally granted to provide transportation infrastructure, water utilities, to create banks and insurance companies.Footnote 21 Many of these early corporations, including the East India Company in EnglandFootnote 22 and the Bank of New York in the United States,Footnote 23 were, as Eric Hilt describes, ‘the largest business enterprises that had ever been created …, and were endowed with valuable legal priveleges that were not accessible to other firms’.Footnote 24

A corporation was a way for private citizens to pool together their resources, and although public benefit was initially a feature of charter grants, private gain was also part of the bargain. The presence of economies of scale and the public interest in seeing the relevant project completed were the justifications of a monopoly grant: it was felt that the underlying enterprise – the construction of a bridge or canal or road – would be unremunerative without some exclusive licence providing a barrier to entry.Footnote 25 Not all charters related to industries with substantial economies of scale, but the balance of power was most imperilled in relation to enterprises either with a tendency to grow in size or influence or where the monopoly related to some critical infrastructure or bottleneck in the economy.

Today, we think of monopoly in a narrow sense as the market position that allows a firm to raise price above cost and restrict output. Under the model of corporate chartering though, the grant of a monopoly licence – understood to be an exclusive right to engage in a particular enterprise – was one of several kinds of inducements that could be negotiated as part of a charter grant, all giving some kind of monopolistic privilege. For example, the Society for Establishing Useful Manufactures, which was a textile company chartered in New Jersey in 1791, secured permission to raise funds through a public lottery as well as obtaining exemptions for the company’s employees from taxes and military service.Footnote 26 There was an inevitable reciprocity that simultaneously reinforced and delimited the role of the state as grantor of the privileges and the corporation as grantee: charters were granted at the behest of the state but a business would not seek a charter for an enterprise that did not require public support – for this, there was no need to incorporate.

With the grant of monopoly came corresponding power. Such power was not granted without protections. The countermovement to constrain the power of corporations to keep them embedded within society took several forms, which will be explored in this section: (a) restrictions on the ability to grant special privileges; (b) restrictions on the scope of the grant; (c) reservations of the power to revoke the charter; and (d) the introduction of general incorporation.

1.3.1 Restrictions on the Ability to Grant Special Privileges

The scope for nepotistic favouritism within the power of the state to grant special privileges has always been keenly felt. In the Tudor Royal Court, privileges – in the form of ‘letters patent’ – were dispensed liberally as quid pro quo for supporting the sovereign either politically or financially, or even simply given as favours to the sovereign’s servants and courtiers.Footnote 27 The case of Darcy v. Allen,Footnote 28 known commonly as the Case of Monopolies, demonstrates both the profligacy of the grants and the public intolerance for sovereign power to be so abused. In that case, Queen Elizabeth I had granted an exclusive licence for the production of playing cards to her groom, which the court rendered invalid on the basis that it created a monopoly contrary to common law restraint of trade. In terms of the balance of power, we can understand the perversity of this particular special privilege – the grant of an exclusive licence to produce playing cards is not in fulfilment of some public need and yet it interferes with the right of others to earn their daily bread through an otherwise legally permitted enterprise and does so through the co-option of the state. The focus of the court was on the economic costs of monopoly but also, as Barry Hawk has described, on ‘political constitutional objections to royal authority’.Footnote 29

Eventually, Parliament enacted the Statute of Monopolies in 1624 which prohibited the sovereign from making outright grants of monopoly except as a temporary reward for technological innovation – from which the modern patent is derived. Corporate charters, as opposed to other grants of monopoly privilege, which came with various restrictions attached, did however continue.

In the United States, the distaste for the abuse of public power for private gain found expression in the East India Company tea thrown into Boston harbour in 1773, and this sentiment continued after independence. Several states had antimonopoly provisions in their constitutions,Footnote 30 and there was even a proposal to include an antimonopoly provision in the US Constitution or Bill of Rights.Footnote 31 Although states retained the ability to grant corporate charters, courts were reticent to embellish the grant of a charter with implied privileges. In Charles River Bridge,Footnote 32 when a new bridge was chartered to be built right next to the already-existing Charles River Bridge, the courts refused to interpret the grant of the earlier corporate charter as an implicit grant of monopoly to collect bridge tolls. Interpretation of corporate privileges was to err on the side of limitation, not expansion.

The US context before and after independence usefully illustrates the dual role of the corporation as a threat to the balance of power but also as a safeguard against the state. At the same time that the American colonists rejected English corporations like the East India Company as vehicles of oppression, they also embraced their own corporate organisations as protection against the British monarch.Footnote 33 Many of the early colonies had been formed as chartered companies and they governed themselves according to those charters as a way to ensure due process as between the colonists, with the governance provisions of the corporate charter serving as a model for the governance of public life.Footnote 34 Adhering strictly to the terms of the charter also served as a shield against interference by the granting power – the King in England. Individual state constitutions were eventually modelled on these charters.Footnote 35

It also emerged as a legal principle that benefits conveyed by the state should not be capriciously withdrawn. The Contracts Clause in the US Constitution was instituted to protect contracts with the state from arbitrary abuse of state power. In the watershed Dartmouth College case,Footnote 36 the Supreme Court held that the state of New Hampshire could not unilaterally amend a previously granted charter. In that case, the charter for Dartmouth College had been granted by King George III, before the state of New Hampshire had even been formed. The court found that since the corporate charter constitutes a contract, it could not be unilaterally altered. It could only be changed through mutual consent.

Dartmouth College had the potential to permanently alter the balance of power in favour of corporations, and indeed the decision was hotly contested on these grounds by those who saw it as paving the way for arbitrary private power. As one commentator remarked: ‘Sure I am that, if the American people acquiesce in the principles laid down in this case, the Supreme Court will have affected what the whole power of the British Empire, after eight years of bloody conflict, failed to achieveagainst our fathers’.Footnote 37 States responded by enacting legislation that allowed them to insert ‘reservation clauses’ into corporate charters, maintaining the ability to alter and revoke grants going forward. Nevertheless, the principle of protection against state power, alongside the protections against corporate power built-in to the corporate charters themselves, continued as a theme in the regulation of the corporation.

1.3.2 Restrictions on the Scope of the Grant

Beyond limiting the ability of the sovereign or the state to grant monopolies, individual corporate charters tended to contain a whole host of provisions designed to constrain the size of the corporation and the extent of its power.Footnote 38 Charters would limit the industries and sectors in which a company could engage. They might contain limits on the amount of capital a corporation could accumulate and limits on the amount of debt. And, they would generally fix the lifespan of the corporation at the outset – sometimes to just a couple of decades or less.Footnote 39 Common law also restricted the right of corporations to own stock in other firms.Footnote 40 Each of these provisions was intended to circumscribe the corporation and thus limit its ability to expand beyond the granted scope and beyond the balance of power.

1.3.3 Charter Revocation

A crisis of the balance of power occurred when corporations outgrew the states that granted them the possibility of existence. The privilege of incorporation, which initially required an act of the state to create, came with not just restrictions in scope but also obligations to perform certain public duties, often including a commitment to complete the public venture for which the company was incorporated. For this reason, the sovereign or the state also retained the right to revoke the charter for either non-use or abuse.Footnote 41 This was a meaningful mechanism of public accountability and an existential threat to any company that abused its privilege or reneged on its commitment. But if the corporation no longer relied upon any individual state for its licence, then the balance of power would shift in favour of the corporation.

The procedure by which the corporate charter was initially challenged was known as a quo warranto proceeding. A quo warranto action is a demand made by the state on some individual or corporation to show ‘by what warrant’ or right they may exercise a particular franchise or privilege. The burden of proof was on the respondent to show that they had the adequate right to enjoy the privilege in question. The procedure stemmed from an ancient legal writ in use in England since the twelfth or thirteenth century.Footnote 42 On Edward I’s return to England in 1274, he ordered a general inquiry to be held throughout the land into the reported misconduct of the feudal lords in his absence.Footnote 43 The quo warranto writs were issued to challenge the privileges that the lords had taken the liberty of enjoying. The basis for adjudication was merely whether it could be factually established that the privilege had been validly granted by the King or his predecessors. If there was no valid basis for the grant, or no proof of the grant, then an ad hoc court convened for this purpose could order the privilege to be revoked.Footnote 44 In later cases against corporations, this would mean that the courts had the power to revoke the corporate charter.

Abuse of the charter usually meant a breach of one of the terms of the charter itself, – for example, the restrictions on scope.Footnote 45 But with the rise of the infamous ‘trusts’ in the second half of the nineteenth century, quo warranto proceedings and charter revocation were also used by state attorneys general as what Daniel Crane has described as a ‘form of crude antitrust law’.Footnote 46 This was how states, with limited tools available at the time, sought to return the balance of power in face of the epochal challenge of the new conglomerate business organisations.

Towards the end of the nineteenth century, quo warranto proceedings were brought frequently to challenge what we would now construe as anticompetitive conduct, first against vertical integration, and then against horizontal combinations.Footnote 47 These cases were not primarily about competition though, certainly not about the protection of ‘consumer welfare’. They were instead motivated by a desire to protect society from the threat of economic concentrations – or in other words to correct the balance of power. Nevertheless, as a matter of form, state attorneys general often found it easier to rely on the argument that the corporation had strayed ultra vires from its charter rather than argue the public policy point of public detriment or economic harm, and they were quite successful as a result of this technical focus on the bounds of the charter – which the courts were accustomed to adjudicating and which the state had clear power to enforce via the courts.Footnote 48

The question at the heart of these quo warranto cases was whether the trusts, comprised of trustees representing multiple individual enterprises, would be permitted the privilege of coordinating their economic assets in an analogous manner to the grant of licence given to all monolithic corporations and whether such a privilege would be read into the individual charter grants of the constituent companies. The trust mechanism was used to circumvent the restrictions in corporate charters that prevented companies from vertically integrating or owning stock in other corporations.Footnote 49 The term ‘robber baron’ which came to be synonymous with the tycoons of the Gilded Age such as John D. Rockefeller and Andrew Carnegie was perfectly apt: the trusts were attempting to assert baronial privileges akin to those of feudal times, and the state, just as Edward I in the thirteenth century sought to challenge the warrant by which those privileges were being asserted.

One of the key features of the second industrial revolution of the 1860s and 1870s, during which time the phenomenon of increasing returns to scale really comes to the fore in America, is the development for the first time of a national market across the United States.Footnote 50 Prior to that time, companies would typically seek a charter in the state in which their business was going to be predominantly operating because they would tend to need some state support, such as permission to print bank notes or the power to annex land, in order to operate the business at all – otherwise, there would be no need to incorporate.Footnote 51 When the trusts thrust themselves across state lines this co-dependence between corporation and state shifted and states founds themselves wooing these national conglomerates to incorporate in their jurisdiction. Unsurprisingly, quo warranto cases suing companies for bold expansion were hardly brought at all.Footnote 52

1.3.4 General Incorporation

The original process of granting incorporation through an act of Parliament or Congress was bureaucratically burdensome. It was also open to lobbying and rife with exactly the nepotism that the Statute of Monopolies had attempted to remove from the Royal Courts.Footnote 53 The idea of allowing for general incorporation, through laws that would permit anybody to form a company for any legal purpose, was to democratise the corporate vehicle and remove elitism from incorporation.Footnote 54 It was a move to restore the balance of power, but it contained within it a destabilising force that would again act to untether the corporation from society: with anybody able to form a company, the public perception shifted from incorporation as a privilege, granted at the sufferance of the state, to incorporation as a right.Footnote 55 The authority of the state to constrain the theoretically democratised corporation was thus compromised.

It was still recognised that the corporation was a vehicle through which private wealth would naturally multiply and thus general incorporation laws alone would not be sufficient to level the playing field across prospective incorporators. Hence, individual general incorporation statutes across the US states initially contained many of the same restrictions as had characterised individual corporate charters.Footnote 56

This defence against corporate expansion was not to last. The pressure on states to accommodate the needs of the burgeoning corporations mounted at the end of the nineteenth century and a few states led the way in relaxing their corporate laws. Their target was the boon of registration fees and tax revenues that came with incorporation.Footnote 57 This phenomenon, as it played out across a few key states, has been termed the ‘race to the bottom’ – as states competed to attract corporations into their jurisdictions.Footnote 58 Today, Delaware is the preferred state of incorporation for publicly traded companies, but initially it was New Jersey that was victorious after loosening its law with successive amendments from the 1870s onwards, by which time the legacy restrictions of scope, limited cross-ownership and size of the corporation, had been replaced with a regime amenable to the now-common holding company structure.Footnote 59 This transformed the power of the corporation to control economic resources at an increasing scale and represented a fundamental shift in the balance of power.

As will be discussed in Section 1.4, contemporaneous to this relaxation of state incorporation laws, the ‘democratic counterreaction’ of state and federal antitrust law, in its modern and less ‘crude’ form, was just taking shape.Footnote 60 The net effect was mixed and, as some commentators remarked at the time, somewhat confused: states were weakening corporate law, which had served as a powerful brake on corporate power, just as federal antitrust laws were being strengthened, in part to achieve the same aim.Footnote 61

This context is critical to understanding the evolution of the trusts and the origins of modern corporate and antitrust law. It is clear that the balance of power has not been static; it is in constant, reactive flux. Initially, companies like Standard Oil opted to adopt the trust structure to implement their conglomerate concentrations precisely in order to avoid the corporate law prohibitions against cross-ownership in state incorporation laws.Footnote 62 Standard Oil and others rolled-up whole industries and granted what was essentially corporate control to a board of trustees, thus achieving by contract and trust deed what was prohibited by a merger under the terms of the charters.Footnote 63 Undeterred, state attorneys general used the quo warranto procedure to successfully challenge the trust arrangements as ultra vires the charters of the constituent corporations of the trusts.Footnote 64 It was by such a procedure that Standard Oil was forced to exit its initial trust.Footnote 65 The trusts then used their growing economic might and strategic leverage to lobby for the weakening of corporate law, and the states eventually obliged.Footnote 66 This then paved the way for the formation of giant single corporations, which tended still to be referred to as ‘trusts’, without the need to disguise their intentions behind the trust arrangement.Footnote 67 Corporate law thus granted, by default, greater ability to coordinate, and a relief from the necessity of competition (or the risks and instability of cartelisation of the constituent companies), to the expanded, conglomerate corporation – immunising, from antitrust scrutiny, to a certain extent, the underlying economic cooperation within the corporation. State and federal antitrust law was then used to attempt to reign in those newly emboldened corporations, but without the same powers to challenge monopoly power at an existential level or to act against abuse of corporate privilege per se.

1.4 Constructed Monopoly

With general incorporation and the loosening of incorporation laws, the ability of the state to control the corporation through existential challenge was much diminished. The state was no longer the grantor of monopoly privilege, and yet monopolistic companies were arising anyway, taking advantage of technological advances, the growing national market, and the benefits of the corporate form itself – all of which, in different ways, gave rise to economies of scale.Footnote 68 The immediate need was therefore to identify other tools to constrain the increasingly problematic concentrations of power or, in other words, to address the tilting balance of power in favour of monopolies. This is where the joint origins of antitrust and corporate law rupture, spawning a fragmented approach to corporate regulation.Footnote 69 Within antitrust, there were two overlapping streams: (a) the use of common law to challenge coercive practices and (b) the passage of the Sherman Act in 1890. We shall consider the separate path of corporate law in Section 1.5.

1.4.1 Common Law Restraint of Trade and Monopolisation

The common law notions of ‘restraint of trade’ and ‘monopoly’, which had developed under English law and were transported across to the United States with colonisation, were both focused on conduct that sought to prevent others from entering a market and/or attempts to control prices and supply.Footnote 70 The concern was with coercion or the limitation of another party’s freedom to trade.Footnote 71 It was a protection against abuse of imbalance of power but did not prevent or prohibit imbalance itself. Monopolisation, at common law, was effectively a special case of unlawful restraint of trade concerned again with exclusion from the market.

There was one sense in which the common law did act to promote balance of power. Common law restraint of trade applied not to corporations but also to other organisations. Unlike modern statutory antitrust, this common law tradition was permissive of coordination between a wide range of actors which may have served as a countervailing force to balance private corporate power with collective action on the part of workers, farmers, and others.Footnote 72 It has also been argued that the tolerance in the common law restraint of trade doctrine for cooperation between business competitors was in part due to the phenomenon of worker unionisation, creating both a model for cooperation among firms and a counterweight to cartels of producers.Footnote 73 Although economic power as such was not the primary focus of common law restraint of trade, there was at least this aspect of maintaining the balance and protecting not just competition but a person’s right to earn their daily bread.Footnote 74 Cooperation and coordination of economic resources were not unlawful per se under the restraint of trade doctrine.Footnote 75

The common law did not however have experience responding to the nature of the conglomerate corporation that emerged at the turn of the twentieth century. The focus of the law had been relatively small-scale restraints of trade: interferences with the market, non-competes, and questionable business practices. The perspective was somewhat different from today: what we might deem to be anticompetitive conduct was often categorised as the essence of vigorous competition. As one example, in the seminal Mogul Steamship case, a cartel of shipowners engaged in trading tea in China responded to a new entrant by declaring that they would refuse cargo from any exporter who used the competitor’s vessels and also put on extra sailings to match those of the entrant at below cost.Footnote 76 When the case reached the House of Lords, Lord Halsbury articulated the prevailing view that the very essence of competition was to ‘compete for a time as to render trade unprofitable to your rival in order that when you have got rid of him you may appropriate the profits of the entire trade to yourself’.Footnote 77

Other than as observed above, common law restraint of trade did not concern itself in any meaningful way with the relative power of private firms and the state. After an earlier decision in the Mogul Steamship case, at the Court of Appeal, The Times newspaper commented that the case ‘forces us to realise that we are left with no defence against the monopoly or “trust” except such as the Legislature chooses to give us’.Footnote 78 As we have seen, ‘defence against monopoly’ was the purview of the statutes on monopoly and incorporation, but the focus there was on public grants of monopoly not on private power.

The remedies at common law for a successful claim of restraint of trade or monopolisation were to render the contract or conduct void. An unlawful restraint of trade was unenforceable. This was a private action. There was no scope for enforcement by the state.Footnote 79 Hence the reliance by state attorneys general on the less targeted quo warranto proceedings as ‘crude antitrust’. State antitrust laws and the federal Sherman Act were enacted to allow for governmental enforcement, but the overlap with corporate law continued: some state antitrust laws contained provisions familiar from incorporation laws, making participation in trusts ultra vires or instituting a remedy of charter forfeiture for breach of the antitrust law.Footnote 80 Meanwhile, some interest groups continued to argue that the federal Sherman Act should contain or be complemented by a federal incorporation framework.Footnote 81

1.4.2 Sherman Act

The Sherman Act was historic in giving the federal government, not just state governments, the power to address the balance of power. As William Novak explains, the progressive movement at the end of the nineteenth century explicitly identified the risks of concentrated power.Footnote 82 There were known risks in terms of political influence and potential corruption of government. But it was also understood that there was a risk to the ‘balance of power’ itself; not just an economic or political problem but also a constitutional one.

As it played out, the Sherman Act built on the restraint of trade model at common law, and not the more powerful tool of federal chartering which was a live alternative at the time and immediately after the law’s passage.Footnote 83 Herbert Hovenkamp has noted that by preserving the common law position, with its tolerance for ‘reasonable’ monopoly power, the potential of the Sherman Act was considerably emasculated.Footnote 84 Meanwhile, David Millon argues that the reliance on the supposedly equalising force of competition to maintain the balance of power turned the Sherman Act into ‘the dying words of a tradition that aimed to control political power through decentralization of economic power, which in turn was to be achieved through protection of competitive opportunity’.Footnote 85 The theory was that disparate economic interests, dispersed through competition, would not be able to co-opt the state for private political gain. According to Millon,’ The Senate’s conservative approach to the concentration crisis failed to appreciate the magnitude and complexity of the problem. The Sherman Act thus had little impact on the rapidly accelerating consolidation of big business’.Footnote 86

Instead, coordination among labour and small producers, often permitted at common law, became the occupying focus of antitrust enforcers, with the previously central concern with corporate power fading into the background.Footnote 87 Today, the influence of the Chicago School since the mid-twentieth century on antitrust law can be seen in the inconsistent treatment of cartels – treated as an ultimate evil with no redeeming ‘efficiencies’ – and mergers, which are often construed as presumptively ‘efficient’,Footnote 88 as well as the preoccupation with specific economic concepts of ‘efficiency’ and ‘consumer welfare’ as opposed to the broader concepts of democracy, both economic and political, and the balance of power.

1.5 Corporate Responsibility

While the aspects of corporate regulation that we today recognise as antitrust forked away from corporate chartering in the direction of restraint of trade and monopoly, corporate law was forged in the model of the reciprocal obligations and commitments embodied by the original charters. Under this model, the balance of power would be maintained not primarily by the state but by empowering corporate stakeholders. This section will explore these mechanisms, in particular: a) shareholder protections and b) shareholder democracy.

1.5.1 Shareholder Protections

Alongside the restrictions to the scope of grant of any privilege which served to constrain corporate power,Footnote 89 corporate charters contained provisions expressly designed to protect investors. These rules have changed little to the present day: requirements to publish annual financial statements, rules on dividend payments, rules on electing directors – including protections for minority shareholders.Footnote 90 Equally, after the passage of the general incorporation laws, most corporate laws contained some mechanisms to protect shareholders: rules prescribing the number of directors – sometimes requiring them to be shareholders and/or citizens of the incorporating state; rules stipulating one share, one vote; limits on the total proportion of votes to be exercised by a single shareholder.Footnote 91 Underlying these provisions was the democratic concern that the special privilege of incorporation would be abused to the detriment of weaker shareholders and the public at large, a parallel line of thinking to that which precipitated the Sherman Act. Part of the purpose of these rules in corporate law was to maintain the balance of power.

There was also a direct way in which shareholder protections reinforced antitrust enforcement. As state attorneys general found their ability to bring quo warranto proceedings hampered by weakened corporate law, some minority shareholders challenged the anticompetitive use of the trust structure in state court through derivative suits.Footnote 92 This would generally involve the minority shareholders of an acquired entity, that was about to be rolled-up into a trust and shut down, bringing a suit to challenge the effective merger. In these cases, the complaining shareholders would launch derivative suits against the majority shareholders, reinforcing their case with allegations of illegal conduct under the antitrust laws, claims to which the state courts were on the whole sympathetic.Footnote 93 Shareholder protections thus had a role in challenging the power of the corporate entity.

1.5.2 Shareholder Democracy

Although the principle of shareholder primacy is widely accepted today,Footnote 94 the legacy of corporate chartering was initially the notion of public responsibility that came with the early charters. This assumption – that corporations were meant to act to the public benefit, continued, at least in the public imagination, into the early twentieth century.Footnote 95 Then in 1919, the Michigan Supreme Court decided the landmark case prioritising the primacy of the shareholders within the corporate structure, Dodge v. Ford, holding that ‘A business corporation is organized and carried on primarily for the profit of the stockholders’.Footnote 96 Dodge heralded a new era of corporate governance, equating corporate responsibility not with the public interest but with shareholder interests.

Among corporate legal scholars, it is often thought that Adolf Berle and Gardiner Means’ seminal book The Modern Corporation cemented the shareholder primacy principle by demonstrating that the separation of ownership and control alienated shareholders from their property and left managers free to pursue their own interests. This then was the justification for giving shareholders primacy in corporate decision-making. But the context of the time lends a different reading. Despite Dodge, it was not business practice of the day to only consider the interests of shareholders in corporate governance.Footnote 97 The debate on the role of the corporation was between more or less managerial discretion, with the goal of public benefit taken as a given.Footnote 98 The animating purpose of The Modern Corporation was to explore the troubling phenomenon of rising corporate concentration in the US economy in the Gilded Age of the 1920s, which left a few ‘princes of property’ – the corporate managers – with unprecedented power over the whole economy and society. Thus, Berle and Means’ prescription of shareholder empowerment was intended as a democratising, counterbalancing force, rendering management, and therefore the corporation, accountable to the shareholding public and thereby society at large.Footnote 99 This was not to be an active democratic participation on the part of the masses, but rather a mechanism to collectivise capital interests and recreate reciprocal public responsibility on the part of the corporation. In terms of balance of power, this democratisation would constrain the power of the corporate entity in a more flexible way than a corporate charter – instead of fixing a list of public responsibilities at the outset, the corporation would be liable for meeting evolving shareholder – and therefore public – needs, on an ongoing basis.

What Berle and Means did not give sufficient weight to in their analysis was that it was not shareholders per se that had been alienated by the separation of ownership and control. Rather, particular segments of financial capital were able to push aside the needs of the general stockholding public, and with the development of the holding company, by then permitted under corporate and antitrust law, they were able to do so with even relatively small shareholdings.Footnote 100 This situation was made worse by the move towards further shareholder empowerment within corporate law. Certain shareholder classes were able to maintain control of corporate resources and thus effectively recreate the elitist special privileges of the chartering era.Footnote 101

As a matter of theory, corporate law in the latter half of the twentieth century departed from the ‘concession theory’ of the corporation as a creature of the state. Building on Ronald Coase’s Theory of the Firm, the ‘nexus of contracts’ theory framed the corporation as existing not in relation to the state but in relation to those involved in its creation – labour, input suppliers and capital, with the last having primacy within the nexus.Footnote 102 In harmony with neoclassical price theory and the transaction cost economics of the Chicago School, the nexus of contracts replaces the balance of power as the organising principle of corporate regulation, just as the Chicago School interpretation of ‘consumer welfare’ and ‘efficiency’ have come to displace the concept of ‘corporate power’ within antitrust. The shareholders’ ‘contract’ is construed as one that guarantees the maximum possible return on investment – and any resulting imbalance of power is therefore irrelevant as all stakeholders must refer to the terms of their contracts at the nexus.

The democratising thrust of Berle and Means’ prescriptions are all but forgotten to history, with Milton Friedman’s succinct edict in 1970 operating in its place: ‘The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase Its Profits’.Footnote 103 Although over the decades debates have still raged in legal scholarly circles over whether shareholder primacy is cogent, whether it is feasible, whether it is the law, and whether it exists as a concept, as of 2001, Henry Hansmann and Rainier Kraakman had declared ‘The End of History for Corporate Law’, with a resounding victory for shareholder primacy.Footnote 104 The emphasis in corporate law has narrowed considerably towards a focus on investor protection as such and not as part of the counterbalancing of corporate power within society. The power of the modern corporation of the twenty-first century must be viewed in this context.

1.6 The Balance of Power Today

Where does the balance of power stand today? The forking paths of antitrust and corporate law away from the charter model and towards restraint of trade and shareholder primacy do not leave the state well-equipped to implement any countermovement against concentrations of economic power. Meanwhile, such concentrations are ascendant yet again, as the contributions to this book show: the evidence, again, of rising industrial concentration almost 100 years after Berle and Means’ investigation; the inequality of share ownership, skewed towards the wealthy; the web of corporate ownership, enabled by the holding company structure, concentrating power among a few entities; the incidence of common ownership, particularly through asset managers. The dual concentrating impacts of financialisation and digitalisation, explored in more detail in the contribution from Ioannis Lianos and Andrew P. McLean, Financialisation of the digital value chains and competition law, in Chapter 16, leave us with a sense that the technologically and financially constructed monopoly will not bend to the balancing force of competition alone, nor to any imposition of corporate responsibility. Again, economies of scale, to the extent that they are an economic and technological reality, need not be a corporate inevitability – the power that comes with scale must be actively managed. When the economy, and society, is shaped by ‘platform power’ – the power to control the infrastructure of digital capitalism, the power to self-preference, the power to predict and influence consumer behaviour, the power to instrumentalise the generation and harvesting of personal data – the balance of power is gravely threatened. It may be argued that this is not the remit of antitrust or corporate law. But without antitrust to constrain the exercise of corporate power on the market and corporate law to constrain the power of the corporate entity as a corporation, other efforts by the state to regulate corporate conduct face unenviable hurdles to success.Footnote 105 The political, economic, and constitutional power of the corporation must be addressed at a foundational level, and it is the role of antitrust law and corporate law to do so.Footnote 106

We will need to go further than the early, crude attempts at creating and simultaneously constraining the corporation if we are to meet this challenge. In this vein, Elizabeth Warren’s Accountable Capitalism ActFootnote 107 revives the notion of federal chartering. States continue to have the power to revoke charters – the quo warranto procedure was codified into statute in most US states – although the power is little used. The procedure was actually abolished under English law in 1938,Footnote 108 but an equivalent power exists under section 124A of the Insolvency Act 1986 which allows the Secretary of State for Business to petition the courts for the winding up of a company ‘in the public interest’. Ewan McGaughey has argued for the application of this provision against oil and gas companies in an attempt to combat climate changeFootnote 109 – perhaps the ultimate example of the consequences of a persistent imbalance of power between the demos and corporations.

Again and again, however, the courts emphasise that winding up a company is a serious step,Footnote 110 as compared to the ease with which a company can be formed under a general incorporation framework. Without some longstop beyond which the corporation’s existence will no longer be tolerated, the threat to corporate power posed by the state cannot be fully credible. Modern antitrust, hamstrung by the concepts of ‘efficiency’ and ‘consumer welfare’, can be no match for corporate domination and does not, as it stands, provide a sufficient counterweight. So too with corporate law that empowers insider groups of shareholders. The balance of power will continue to swing in favour of the corporation unless there is a mechanism for counterbalance. The roles of antitrust law and corporate law in embedding the corporation in society must be re-established.

2 ESG Policies at the Intersection between Competition and Corporate Law

Marco Corradi and Julian Nowag
2.1 Introduction

The last decade has witnessed a radical shift in both the corporate governance and competition law debate: while profit maximisation was core and centre, its interaction with other objectives has come into focus.

Starting from the end of the 1970s,Footnote 1 and until just after the ENRON scandal, corporate governance was heavily focused on agency costs.Footnote 2 Nowadays, the leitmotiv inspiring the academic debate and catalysing the attention of the policy-makers is ‘environmental, social and corporate governance’ (ESG).Footnote 3 Obviously, this does not mean that the ESG debate was previously absent in the corporate law and governance debate.Footnote 4 The debate was simply not mainstream and had developed at the margin, as fuelled especially by management literature.Footnote 5 Beyond academia, the legal practice had already started adopting corporate social responsibility (CSR) codes in the early 1990s.Footnote 6 ‘By the beginning of the twenty-first century, most large companies in the U.S. and Western Europe [had] formed their own policies CSR’.Footnote 7 As a matter of fact, the main tenets of CSR may be as ancient as civilisation.Footnote 8 And this is due to the fact that any human action is likely to produce externalities both on other human beings and on the environment. Nonetheless, the novelty that the recent preponderance of the ESG debate may bring is the degree to which logics not based on profit maximisation need to coordinate from a practical perspective and in day-to-day corporate strategy with the profit maximisation rationale, which has become mainstream in corporate finance.

In competition law, a similar shift in focus can be observed. The last decade(s) were marked by a focus on economics and competition law.Footnote 9 While the debate about ESG and competition law started in the EU back in the 2000s,Footnote 10 it seems that in the last yearsFootnote 11 the debate is becoming more mainstream. Overall, it might still be said that the discussion has been a very European discussion. Yet, more recently, the debate takes place more globallyFootnote 12 with discussions and work at international fora such as the OECD and the International Competition Network.Footnote 13 In terms of agencies, the European focus is characterised by the Dutch and the Greek authorities taking the leadFootnote 14 and the European Commission aiming to update its horizontal guidelines.Footnote 15 With ESG becoming more mainstream both in corporate and competition law, the sustainability debate is also colouring other previously ‘orthodox’ areas of research, at the intersection of competition and corporate law. For instance, this is the case with regard to questions on how to deal with mergers negatively affecting sustainability;Footnote 16 or the anticompetitive effects of common ownership, a theory that was originally developed exclusively based on finance,Footnote 17 and which is now heavily affected by the ESG debate.Footnote 18

Although much has been written about ESG until now, little (if anything at all) has been said about the interaction between competition and corporate governance policies in the area of ESG. In this chapter, we explore the intersection between competition policy and corporate policies in the area of ESG. We focus on ESG, sustainability, and innovation and highlight core research areas that require thorough academic enquiry in the sustainability/growth conundrum. We suggest that well-suited ESG policies for companies must take into consideration the possibility to operate through a multiplicity of policy tools, in particular corporate law, corporate governance, and competition policy tools. This chapter first provides a basic overview of the ESG debate and corporate behaviour. It then focuses on the interaction between ESG and corporate law and governance, as well as ESG and competition law. The final section explores the interaction of competition law and corporate law in the area of ESG policies. We highlight the necessity of coordinated policies, especially in the field of research and development (R&D) and innovation – that is dynamic efficiency.

2.2 The ESG Debate and Corporate Strategy

The post-WW2 demographic explosion and the unparalleled economic and industrial development are leading our world towards an uncertain future. The ecosystem is highly endangered, which in turn also puts the survival of the human species in question. Big corporations, regardless of who their owners are, put under strain planet Earth and the life that populates it, not only by extracting raw materials up to the level of exhaustion but also by rendering the condition of air, soil, and water less and less suitable for life.

If richer countries have benefited from such overexploitation of the world resources by their economic empires and corporations – raising their living standards at unprecedented levels – poorer countries seem to be paying the price of such reckless entrepreneurial conduct.

The NGOs and international institutions such as the UN have been at the forefront at asking for more sustainable and responsible behaviours by the State, companies, and more generally by every single individual in the face of the present crisis.Footnote 19 This is particularly true for those who consume the biggest slices of the world’s cake.Footnote 20 While States have been stepping up their game, progress has been slow and the focus has also shifted towards private actors, corporations in particular. However, competition lawyers and economists often seem to express a preference for regulation to achieve sustainability.Footnote 21

For competition lawyers and competition economists, regulation has obvious advantages. Most of the time, regulation is seen as being able to address sustainability more directly with a more uniform (or competitively neutral) effect on market participants than private action. This competition-policy centric view may not be agreed upon by other governmental agencies. The desirability, effectiveness, and efficiency of regulation in specific situations seem to be questionable. For example, regulation, in particular traditional command and control regulation, is often considered inefficient.Footnote 22 And, even where regulation might be efficient, other questions around its feasibility and effectiveness might be encountered. These can result, for example, from the political compromises that need to be found at the national or international level, with the effect of favouring the lowest common denominator. Similarly, the most efficient regulation on paper may, in many cases, fall victim to insufficient implementation, jurisdictional/geographical limitations, or other administrative burdens.Footnote 23

In the absence of regulation, private-sector voluntary initiatives have gained importance and are also frequently encouraged by States. Another reason for this shift to private sector initiatives might purely be the scale that such initiatives may achieve. Corporate actions and strategic market choices can have larger effects than State interventions. For example, the environmental improvement derived by Amazon going CO2-neutral would be slightly bigger than if the whole of Sweden went CO2-neutral.Footnote 24 Thus, it is not surprising that the UN’s sustainable development goals directly address private business and their activities.

For private business, the ESG debate is nothing new. In fact, the corporate debateFootnote 25 – especially as enriched by managerial sciences –Footnote 26 has focused for a long time on corporate social responsibility (CSR), that is, a way to embed in management strategy and soft law ESG objectives at large (which at the time were not as precisely detailed as in the modern debate). The older CSR debate was revived several times, decade after decade,Footnote 27 until the recent explosion of the ESG-connected literature.Footnote 28 But if non-corporate literature may have seen CSR as a promising ally towards a greener and more just future, corporate literature often denounced its limited reach in pursuing such objectives – especially in a transnational context.Footnote 29 As a reaction to the often generic and blurred content of CSR codes, corporate governance recently witnessed the emersion of a goal-oriented movement, organised around sustainable development goals (SDG)Footnote 30 – once again strongly inspired by management literature.Footnote 31 As goals are characterised by benchmarking, CSR objectives can finally be given proper tracks and verifiable milestones to reach.Footnote 32

The shifting focus of the ESG policy discourse to companies and to their strategic interaction on the market entails that both competition and corporate law are relevant to the ESG debate. These two areas of law are crucially shaping the behaviour of companies by setting the inner and outer limits of their action; by being teleologically connected, their paths are inevitably destined to be intertwined.

2.3 ESG Policies, Corporate Law and Governance

The ESG debate has touched upon topics that are not new in the corporate law and in corporate governance fields of research. Examples of such popular topics are as follows: short versus long-termism (together with their connection to the corporate ownership structure and to the nature and incentives of corporate owners)Footnote 33 and the shareholder versus stakeholder theories of the corporate purpose.Footnote 34 Ultimately, such topics have been approached in the light of the environmental and social challenges of the twenty-first century. But not only old themes have been revisited and re-coloured. New themes, such as specific ESG-oriented shareholder and bondholder stewardship, now represent a significant share in the corporate governance literature.Footnote 35

Research questioning the desirability of long-termism dates back to the second decade of the twenty-first century; it has represented a prominent voice in the United StatesFootnote 36 and in the UK corporate governance debate.Footnote 37 Such debate has crossed the Anglo-American cultural border, reaching the European Union policy-makersFootnote 38 and also EU Member States’ policy-makers – for instance, the French one, which introduced the Florange Law.Footnote 39 Nobel prize Joseph Stiglitz has identified short-termism as one of the adversaries of sustainable policies and widely advocated for the pursuance of long-term oriented policies.Footnote 40 Stiglitz notices that

[i]nequality has increased markedly in the last third of a century, partially because neoliberal doctrines, reflected in the Washington Consensus led to rewriting the rules of the economy in ways which led to more inequality and slower growth (as a result of excessive focus on financialization and the associated short-termism).Footnote 41

Soon a cascade of corporate governance studies analysing short- versus long-termism from an ESG perspective followed. The relationship between short- versus long-termism and corporate governance can be tackled from different angles. Short-termism has been traditionally seen as a consequence of the pressure exercised on corporate directors by shareholders (especially investment funds) which are supposed to pursue a short-term maximisation of their investments – although such an assumption is clearly questionable as there is no homogeneity among institutional investors from this point of view.Footnote 42

Correctives to such short-termism orientation have been proposed. For instance, Bolton and Samama have proposed the introduction of the ‘loyalty share’, to reward shareholder that engage in long-term commitment to the company.Footnote 43 It has also been argued that directors who are more insulated from shareholders are more likely to adopt long-term strategies.Footnote 44 Or, that more long-termism would set a remedy to the disempowerment of stakeholders.Footnote 45 By contrast, other research has shown that empowering stakeholders in some cases can worsen the effects of short-term strategies.Footnote 46 And, evidence has emerged that shareholders’ short-termism could actually be seen as a correction to the dark sides of managerial long-termism, that is, over-optimism regarding the success of long-term plans.Footnote 47

The general contrast to short-termism as a potential remedy to unsustainable policies has been embraced in research commissioned by the EU Commission: the Ernst & Young’s ‘Study on Directors’ duties sustainable corporate governance’.Footnote 48 But what corporate governance literature has questioned is the very relationship between long-termism and the pursuance of ESG policies. A prominent dissenting opinion against the original identification of short-termism with unsustainable policies has been Mark Roe’s one. Based on Roe’s previous studies, Roe, Spamann, Fried and Wang have also heavily criticised the Ernst and Young’s proposal, not only showing the inappropriate conflation of short-termism with sustainability but also the absence of empirical evidence of such relationship.Footnote 49 Roe and Shapira have also explained that the purported connection between short-termism, pro-shareholder policies and unsustainable strategies has found its way into the general discourse on ESG, thanks to the strong narrative inherent to the terminology adopted in the debate. Good, reliable, long-term commitment versus bad, unreliable, short-term strategiesFootnote 50 prompts policy-makers to adopt the first triad.

Mark Roe has challenged not only the conventional view on the detrimental effects of short-termism for sustainability. He has also demystified another common belief, that is, that short-termism has determined a fall in research and development and consequently in innovation.Footnote 51 Roe’s position is clearly based largely on the fact that the US hosts the largest number of high-tech companies in the world, which clearly invest large sums in research and development and are leading innovators. Jesse Fried has added another important piece to the short-termism puzzle: he has shown that long-term shareholders may well demand even worse value destruction than short-term ones.Footnote 52 This again makes us doubt of the suitability of the promotion of long-term equity holdings for sorting out positive effects on structural investment and innovation.

Fried and Wang have also calculated that the effective distribution of companies’ net income to investors (often held responsible for fund depletion and consequent incapability to invest in innovation) is not as significant as it is often claimed.Footnote 53 Similar results have been found with reference to EU companies, once taking into account new equity issuances.Footnote 54 Short-horizon investors have also been considered as a stimulus to competitiveness, especially with reference to innovation parameters.Footnote 55

Roe’s and Freed & Wang’s observations are extremely useful when it comes to assess the innovation deriving from R&D. But it is worth remembering that disruptive innovation does not necessarily require significant investments in research and development. And corporate law mechanisms underlying disruptive innovation may require taking into consideration corporate law rules different than the ones mentioned by the mainstream literature that focuses on research and development.Footnote 56 Being innovation based upon recombinational dynamics of blocks of knowledge, rules such as the corporate opportunity doctrine, the directors’ duty not to compete and other contractual arrangements such as no-compete clauses may become prominent.Footnote 57 And we have already highlighted that such rules may escape the EU’s competition radar.Footnote 58

Instead of relying on the long-termism argument, part of the ESG debate has invested directly in the shareholder versus stakeholder conundrum – especially tackling the relationship between company and a vast range of stakeholders, among which consumers – hence impinging deliberately on an area (consumers) that has traditionally been competence of competition policies.Footnote 59

During the age of privatisation, European private companies have taken up the role previously carried out by the state in granting the provision of public goods and services,Footnote 60 often achieving questionable results in terms of pricing and efficiency.Footnote 61 In the context of privatisation, the Milton Friedman’s ‘maximising shareholder value’ rationale may not provide a correct representation of the corporate positioning vis-à-vis consumers.Footnote 62 Colin Mayer has advocated for the acknowledgement that ‘a corporation is an employer, investor, consumer, producer and supplier all rolled into one’Footnote 63 and that ‘[t]he repositioning of corporations, capital and control’ is ‘fundamental implications for business, economics and public policy as the Copernican revolution had for astronomy’.Footnote 64 Colin Mayer asserts that companies actually work for solving people’s problems, hence viewing consumers as the recipient of a service more than the target of lucrative business activity.Footnote 65 It goes without saying that among collective problems, we can easily mention the necessity to build up a sustainable future.

As we have shown, the ESG debate in the field of corporate law and governance is very animated, full of controversies, and overall in its nascent phase – even to the extent to which scholars are still debating about the efficiency of corporate law and governance tools for addressing ESG concerns.

As highlighted in the previous section, public intervention in the ESG arena seems to rely heavily upon private initiative. But given the fact that private initiative is still surrounded by a high degree of uncertainty, it is inevitable that private and public powers will keep on passing each other the torch. While competition law is often placed among the private law area, it often uses traditional command and control mechanisms known traditionally in the area of public intervention. In contrast, corporate law is more clearly in the realm of private law – although some of its rules – especially those pertaining to securities – can be described as public too. With both fields affecting corporate behaviour substantially, these two fields need increasing dialogue. In certain cases, such a dialogue will end with exacting from each other a degree of intervention that the other area is not able to offer. In other cases, the same dialogue may well end up requiring a common and coordinated intervention in the same field. These two potential kinds of interaction are, respectively, the subject of the two following sections. We will start by highlighting the progress of competition law with reference to the pursuance of ESG objectives, and we will finally highlight the necessity of joint competition and corporate law intervention in the area of technological innovation.

2.4 ESG Policies and Competition Policy

In the competition field, ESG is not frequently discussed. But a similar debate develops under the heading of competition and sustainability or the more concrete UN implementation of SDGs. Yet, while the exact boundaries between ESG and SDG are sometimes difficult to draw, a certain overlap between SDGs and ESG cannot be denied. One may see SDGs and ESG as overlapping but different in the way they are pursued. And while we have seen some attempts to allow reporting of companies on SDG,Footnote 66 the ESG debate has a different origin. To simplify, one may say that SDGs set out goals, while ESG is more about methods and processes within companies and their reporting on a range of environmental and social matters. Given that this area of research is rather new, we also acknowledge that the semantic fields of such new terms may be rather blurred at times, as such terms are given more and more detailed meaning by their contextual application.

The above-mentioned difference in meaning also explains the different focus of the debates in corporate and competition law. The corporate debate and its focus on long-term versus short-termism can be understood if one takes into account the process orientation of ESG. As such, this debate has much less prominence in competition law. In competition law, the debate is more focused on sustainability broadly and only lightly touches upon the SDGs as points of orientation to gain a better understanding of what sustainability actually is.

However, certain elements about the long- versus short-term focus can also be observed in the context of the sustainability debate in competition law. For example, the time horizon for the expected benefit is sometimes a matter of discussion, especially with regard to what time horizon should be employed when measuring sustainability benefits such as a reduction in CO2 emissions. While the time frame, for example, in merger cases is usually short to medium (up to five years), the full benefits of CO2 reductions now may only be experienced in 50 years. Here, the debate is normative as well as technical. On the normative side, one might question whether the importance of, for example, CO2 reduction and the delayed nature of benefits derived from action today justify a different approach.Footnote 67 From a more technical point of view, the question of the time horizon presents itself as a question of proof rather than policy.Footnote 68 Crucial is here the discount rate applied to such future benefit,Footnote 69 an argument can be made about ‘discounted away’ sustainability benefits because future costs might be grossly underappreciated as the example of climate change shows.Footnote 70 Recently, the Dutch Competition Authority’s draft guidelines address this matter and suggest the use of the standard social-cost-benefit tools of Dutch government agencies. The draft guidelines also suggest that avoided environmental damage should be monetised by means of environmental or ‘shadow’ prices.Footnote 71

While this area shows the tension between an approach that takes a long-term perspective from short-term ones, the debate in competition law is more outcome-focused. The questions are to what extent the enforcement of competition law can support or hinder the achievement of sustainability.Footnote 72 In other words, to what extent competition law can be a sword in the fight for more sustainability or to what extent sustainability outcomes might serve as a shield against prohibitions against certain actions by competition law.Footnote 73 The possibly closest link to the debates in corporate governance is stakeholders, that is, constituencies whose interests are affected by corporate action can also be heavily affected by the above-mentioned sword and shield perspective on competition law. The calculation of gains and losses born by different stakeholders can form a bridge between the debates in competition law and corporate law, where the sustainability impact on such stakeholders may come under scrutiny. In fact, an analysis of the stakeholder interests can provide grounding for the theoretical debates and help quantifying the overall welfare effects of the combination of competition and corporate law policy on each stakeholder.

The interaction between competition and sustainability as the first point of reference might be provided by economics. Sustainability and competition economics both highlight resource efficiency, innovation, and the role of the private sector. Moreover, economics is the most important tool to understand the market forces at play and this is crucial to determine the dynamics harming or supporting sustainability.

Foundational on the interaction between sustainability and competition is Elinor Ostrom’s work on the sustainable management of common pool resources.Footnote 74 Her Nobel prize-winning work explored the tragedy of the commons. It showed that rational profit maximisers in unfettered competition lead to disastrous outcomes for that commons. It moreover showed that in reality co-operation rather than competition can be expected.Footnote 75 Ostrom’s foundational work focuses on real-world cases where cooperation takes place. Yet micro-economists do not frequently study sustainability initiatives by private parties. There are theoretical micro-economic studies by even fewer authorsFootnote 76 which apply the standard assumptions and models used in competition economics, including the rational profit maximiser assumption for firms. These suggest that, in general, competition will lead to greater sustainability gains where consumers value sustainability. These papers highlight that there are only a few situations where cooperation has positive outcomes on sustainability. Instead, they suggest that government regulation is a more efficient solution. This literature attributes such findings mainly to the fact that profit-maximising firms have limited incentives to invest in sustainability. It is here where the first points of interaction with the corporate law and governance become apparent. Where corporate law and governance prescribe profit maximisation, the theories about the relationship between competition and sustainability have the most explanatory force. However, the further corporate law and governance move away from the profit maximisation maxim, the harder it becomes to apply these theories.

A second important avenue in the sustainability competition debate is the question of sustainable innovation as both sustainability and competition law and policy recognise the importance of companies in driving innovation. Where sustainability is explored as a dynamic parameter of competition – that is, one that consumers value as a non-price quality variable –Footnote 77 a dynamic innovation-focused assessment seems adequate. In this context, one may ask whether more competition or more cooperation will foster sustainability innovation. General models from the study of the interaction between competition and innovation suggest that a more nuanced assessment is required: one that takes into account practices and specific situations. In other words, the answer to the Schumpeter-Arrow debate over innovation in a competitive or monopolistic setting is best answered on a case-by-case basis, by examining the concrete situation.Footnote 78 Similarly, innovation in sustainability needs to be assessed in a concrete situation.

Equipped with these insights, it becomes clear that competition law needs to take a flexible approach. On the one hand, competition leading to innovation in terms of sustainability needs to be protected; and on the other hand, cooperation needs to be possible where it fosters innovation that leads to sustainability. We will explore the two different scenarios that can, as highlighted before,Footnote 79 also be compared to competition law as a sword to protect sustainable innovation and sustainable innovation as a shield.

2.5 ESG Policies, Competition Law, and Corporate Law: Another Missing Connection?

As already stressed, some of the EU research on corporate policy strategies and ESG objectives have been highly criticised for the absence of their consistency and lack of empirical analysis.Footnote 80 More thorough research in the field is needed. Given that such research, as well as the research on sustainability and competition law, are in fieri, it might not be surprising that there has been no research on the interaction between corporate and competition law. In fact, both policy areas are still heavily occupied with themselves. Nonetheless, we firmly believe that sustainability and ESG objectives are crucial in the long run and that corporate and competition policies will inevitably interact in the ESG area. Hence, it is necessary to anticipate and facilitate such encounters, by foreseeing potential conflicts and by softening sharp edges.

At the most basic level, the competition law and sustainability debate is a debate about outcomes with a focus on the extent to which competition law is a useful and viable tool. The ESG and SDG debate in corporate law and governance seems more process-focused, aimed at identifying means that allow for measurement and reporting, but academics are also studying contractual tools for forcing the pursuance of such objectives.Footnote 81

Chapter 14 already deals with the potential ESG clash in competition and corporate law policies in the fields of common ownership. Nonetheless, we do not believe that this will necessarily represent the ESG’s main stumbling block. We have highlighted and believed in the importance of the special role of dynamic innovation for more sustainable growth. What is essential is that EU policy-makers avoid treating corporate law and governance and competition law in isolation in the pursuance of such a goal. Instead, it needs to be ensured that both legal regimes are streamlined and that potential stumbling blocks presented by their interaction are addressed.

The 2020 COVID-19 crisis illustrates the importance of swift innovation as the necessity of finding a vaccine in a very short time. In such catastrophic events, even a small acceleration towards new inventions can be hugely important and can have beneficial effects on a global scale. Dynamic efficiency is crucial for the future of our planet, for the environment and for increasing productive efficiency – hence producing less waste.Footnote 82

The attention to innovation also brings into focus other questions on border between corporate and competition law. For example, as we have explained in Chapter 8, corporate opportunity rules and the directors’ duty not to compete with the company may have a direct effects on innovation. A large incumbent company, often with a corporate venture capital division, is able to purchase a vast array of innovative start-ups and develop or shutdown at its discretion a whole range of different innovations.Footnote 83 In these situations, the competition among such different innovative solutions is withdrawn from market mechanisms and market forces. Instead, innovation becomes subject to a balance of interests within the incumbent corporation where the best innovations might not be developed for instance because it does not fit with the incumbent industrial strategy.

The debates around the tech companies and their corporate venture capital divisions have highlighted the problem: and both corporate law and competition law may find themselves unable to sufficiently address any such obstacle to innovation. And as we have highlighted elsewhereFootnote 84 corporate opportunity rules may facilitate the exercise of such power by the incumbent company and competition law authorities and courts may find that such arrangements are not subject to competition law as they occur within the corporation. Similar concerns are raised by an alternative version of the same corporate strategy adopted by incumbent corporations. In the case of killer mergers, the incumbent has the intention of shutting down the potential competitor. While in these cases competition law may apply, the tools are not well adjusted to such problems.Footnote 85 The potential restriction of competition is carried out through corporate means and seems to be hard to control through the traditional competition law analysis, which may be ill suited for tackling dynamic competition issues at large.

While these specific examples highlight some of the interactions between corporate law and competition law in the in context of innovation for sustainability, we can also take a broader perspective. And if we widen our perspective, we may well see that the interaction between corporate strategy – as affected by corporate law and governance – and competition law is only destined to increase in quality and in dimension. If the core objective of corporate strategy is increasingly found in the reconciliation between profit-maximising strategies and ESG objectives, corporate strategy may more and more depart from the dualistic idea of either competing or colluding on prices. The overall paradigm shifts in the business world that is highlighted by corporations adopting ESG or SDG polices – cannot be without effects on fundamental paradigms of competition law. This is so in particular because competition law risk losing touch with the business reality that is affected by corporate law and governance changes. This risk of a disconnect might occur where competition theory still conceives the corporation as pure profit maximiser – and does not ponder the ESG variables and the way they might modify the conception of the corporate interest in the future.

2.6 Conclusions

The theoretical challenge represented by the encounter of corporate and competition policies in the ESG area seems considerable – as well as very exciting – given the vast number of issues that must be solved. In this chapter, we have only attempted to sketch out some interesting aspects of a future discussion likely to occupy vast areas of the corporate and competition literature in the coming years. Anecdotally, it is often said that both doctrine and jurisprudence strive to bring within their competence areas of the law that traditionally belong to other fields. But this is not the case for ESG, especially when it comes to find practical real-world solutions. The challenge is so that the hope rests upon corporate action. Yet, corporate and competition lawyers seem critical of corporate action and easily denounce them as insufficient and ineffective when it comes to pursuing ESG objectives.Footnote 86 Such an attitude, demanding that someone else provides viable and effective solutions, seems a common psychological reaction: when challenges are tough, we may perceive them as insurmountable and are tempted to stand by and look for an external rescuer. But it is equally true that such external rescue is unlikely to come. Therefore, action is needed.

In this paper, we propose that enquiring about the interaction between competition and corporate ESG policies is a good starting point, and that we may need to focus especially on dynamic innovation. This may represent the first step for tackling the wider debate. While it may look like a small step, it is crucial in fact. If the environmental and social challenges are so hard, the best human talents have to be employed. And only well-suited and well-coordinated competition and corporate policies can grant that financial resources and incentives for innovative projects along their path of a more sustainable future.

3 Not-for-Profit Organisations and Competition Law

Okeoghene Odudu
3.1 Introduction

A not-for-profit organisation is one that is barred from distributing net earnings to individuals who exercise control over the organisation, such as members, officers, directors, or trustees.Footnote 1 The organisation may be funded by donors (philanthropists), government, service users, or a combination of all three and may benefit from charitable status, special tax advantages, or a special institutional status (e.g. be public body).Footnote 2 It is common for professional associations, healthcare service providers, and educational establishments to operate on a not-for-profit basis.Footnote 3 There are often claims that competition law does not or should not apply to entities that operate on a not-for-profit basis.Footnote 4 This chapter considers how competition law assesses the actions of entities operating on a not-for-profit basis. Implicit in this presentation is an assumption that similar concerns arise in all competition law jurisdictions. While the points made are thus of general application, they are illustrated with examples from the United States, EU, and United Kingdom. Section 3.2 explains why operating on a not-for-profit basis is not accepted as a reason to exclude an entities activities from the scope of competition law. Section 3.3 considers situations in which competition law is applied to non-profit providers and in which it is generally accepted that no modification is required. Section 3.4 considers situations in which competition law is applied to not-for-profit providers, but it is not applied in the same way as it is applied to for-profit providers – competition law is modified. The modification manifests itself as a heightened threshold for intervention; a reluctance to apply standard presumptions of harm and enhanced need for evidence to establish an infringement; an increased willingness to accept and a broader menu of acceptable justifications; and finally, a reluctance to impose sanctions on not-for-profit providers. Section 3.5 concludes by considering when and why competition law ought to be modified on account of the entity engaged in contested conduct operating on a not-for-profit basis.

3.2 The Relevance of Competition Law in Markets Served by Non-Profits

Markets are relied on to produce sufficient quantities of desirable goods and services. The market is at is best when it is responsive to voice, voice involving patrons communicating their concerns to the provider of goods or services.Footnote 5 Providers of goods and services are most responsive to voice when it is possible for those exercising voice to exit, i.e. obtain goods or services from an alternative provider. Exit is important for two reasons. First, the possibility of exit reduces the cost of exercising voice. Voice is costly if patrons have no option but to continue receiving goods or services from the supplier after exercising voice, even if the patrons concerns are not addressed.Footnote 6 Secondly, the possibility of exit motivates suppliers to take the voice of patrons seriously.Footnote 7 When the possibility of exit exists, firms have incentives to continually improve the quality of their goods and services; provide new types of goods and services; and to minimise the resources consumed in the production of their goods and services.Footnote 8 In the absence of a possibility of exit, firms need not be responsive to voice and instead can be said to possess market power. Those with market power face a reduction in the incentives to improve, or to provide new offerings, or to minimise the resources being consumed.Footnote 9

Competition law plays a central role in ensuring the effectiveness of voice in relation to entities operating on a for-profit basis. To what extent is competition law’s role in ensuring that voice is effective, relevant to non-profit entities? Theories of the not-for-profit form suggest that such entities exist because the for-profit market will fail to provide the relevant goods and servicesFootnote 10; because they can be trusted to provide higher quality goods and services in situations of high information asymmetry between buyers and sellersFootnote 11; or because they are trusted where contracts are difficult to monitor and enforce.Footnote 12 What is important is that not-for-profit entities are argued to exist for reasons that differ from the reasons for profit entities exist. This then gives rise to claims for different treatments under competition law on three distinct grounds. Firstly, on the idea that an inability to distribute profits removes the incentive (though crucially, not the ability) to restrict competition.Footnote 13 Second, there is an idea that not-for-profit organisations ought to be trusted not to act in a manner determinantal to their patrons.Footnote 14 A third basis for the claim of special treatment is that the specific regulatory oversight to which the not-for-profit entity is subject will either satisfy the concerns that competition law is designed to address or trump any obligation competition law would seek to impose.Footnote 15

Philipson and Posner formalise a model in which not-for-profit providers are not responsive to voice, i.e. they not only exercise market power, but also do so in a manner that is harmful to patrons.Footnote 16 The empirical literature also supports the view of there being nothing inherent in the not-for-profit organisational form that would render the concerns of competition law otiose.Footnote 17 Since not-for-profit entities do exercise market power and the exercise of market power by not-for-profit entities does have at least the potential to be harmful, legislatures, competition authorities, and courts have concluded that operating on a not-for-profit basis is insufficient to warrant exclusion from competition law scrutiny.Footnote 18 Rather than the nature of the organisations operating in the market, focus is instead placed on the nature of the activities being performed – competition law being applied to all activities that can be described as economic or commercial in character.Footnote 19 After all, like all organisations, the not-for-profit organisation must decide whether to compete or cooperate with other organisations in the pursuit of its aims.Footnote 20

3.3 Competition Law Unmodified

What has been the experience of applying competition rules to entities operating on a not-for-profit basis? The most obvious examples arise in relation to self-regulatory bodies of the liberal professions.Footnote 21 Professional associations operating on a non-profit basis have been condemned for creating barriers that prevent non-members of the association from offering services competing with those offered by their members;Footnote 22 attempting to fix the price or other terms on which their members might do business;Footnote 23 and for limiting the ability of members to promote their services as against other members.Footnote 24 Trade association’s not representing professions, but operating on a not-for-profit basis, are also condemned if they play a role in fixing terms and conditions (including price and profit margins) on which their members will supply goods or services – matters which should be settled by competitive forces.Footnote 25

Many examples can be found of competition law being applied to cooperatives and mutual organisations providing, for example, insurance and pensions.Footnote 26 Other prominent examples of not-for-profit entities being scrutinised under competition law involve state-owned enterprises operating on a not-for-profit basis being condemned for excluding others from the market or reserving the market to themselves.Footnote 27 Equally important is the role merger control has played in ensuring that the option for exit (and the role exit plays in strengthening voice) is preserved even when all in the market operate on a not-for-profit basis. So, for example, the Bundeskartellamt has prevented mergers between public hospitals operating on a not-for-profit basis.Footnote 28 In the UK, the competition authority reviewed a merger between two charities, which, though operating on a not-for-profit basis and primarily as a grant making body raising funds and distributing them to independent scientists, obtain intellectual property rights that result from the research it funds. The risk that the licensing of IPRs might not occur in a way beneficial to society was the focus of the competition authority’s concern.

As with the for-profit sector, price-fixing, market sharing, and market foreclosure have been the main issues addressed. Harmful conduct has been found, notwithstanding the fact that the entities involved operate on a not-for-profit basis. And the need to ensure an environment in which the incentive to improve are maintained has remained paramount. Competition concerns are therefore to be addressed in the normal way, notwithstanding the fact that some entities to be scrutinised operate on a not-for-profit basis. What is also true is that not-for-profit entities have continued to operate, notwithstanding the need to comply with competition law and that competition law has been sufficiently flexible to take account of the not-for-profit form within the existing framework of the law.

3.4 Competition Law Modified

Although it is the case that the standard competition law framework is applicable and applied to not-for-profit entities, it is not the case that operating on a not-for-profit basis does not matter. Competition law can be seen to be modified in four ways when courts and competition authorities are called on to assess the compatibility of a not-for-profit providers’ conduct with the law. First, the court or authority may operate a heightened threshold for intervention. Second, the authority may modify the mode of assessment that it applies when it scrutinises not-for-profit entities. Third, the authority may admit or be amenable to a greater range of justifications than is otherwise the case. Finally, the authority may be influenced by the not-for-profit nature of the organisation when it comes to imposing sanctions.

3.4.1 Threshold of Intervention

One way in which not-for-profit providers are treated differently is that a higher threshold may be required to trigger intervention by a competition authority. A good example of this is the examination of the higher education market, in which the UK government has sought to harness the power of choice and competition.Footnote 29 To better understand how the market for undergraduate education in England functions, in October 2013, the competition authority launched a call for information.Footnote 30

One question raised in the call for information was whether all institutions charging a uniform fee for all undergraduate courses resulted from either express or tacit collusion.Footnote 31 Is it is plausible for multi-product firms, in a non-concentrated market, to arrive at identical prices for undergraduate courses, when their cost structures differ and particularly when in relation to graduate courses there is wide price variation? This pattern of pricing would seem to provide reasonable grounds for suspecting an infringement.Footnote 32 In Dyestuffs, considering price increases applied by 10 firms to a small range of dyes, when each firm produced between 1,500 and 3,500 of some 6,000 dyes, the European Commission felt that:

[i]t is not conceivable that without detailed prior agreement the principle producers … should several times increase by identical percentages the prices.Footnote 33

Considering not-for-profit providers of higher education, however, the UK competition authority declined to take further action on the basis that it ‘has received no complaints or evidence of either explicit or tacit collusion between higher education institutions with respect to fee setting’.Footnote 34 The competition authority seems to set a high threshold for intervention, suggesting that in order to launch an investigation into collusion by not-for-profit entities, it would require ‘evidence that would amount to a compelling case of anti-competitive behaviour’.Footnote 35

A further example of the reluctance to intervene can be seen in the UK competition authorities open letter to the head teachers of almost 30,000 State schools. The letter draws attention to the high price of school uniforms, caused in part by 74% of schools requiring parents to purchase uniforms from a single, named retailer or from the school itself. This created a captive market for chosen suppliers, allowing them to charge an additional £52 million per year. The letter advises schools either to cease specifying from whom uniforms may be obtained, or to award the right to supply on a basis that takes into account the cost to parents. Further, the letter urges parents to complain to school governors if they are dissatisfied with the schools’ decision to use an exclusive supplier. The letter does not however warn, as it could and arguably should, that the school’s licencing of their logo, crest, or uniform design to a supplier or retailer is clearly subject to competition law and all the consequences that this entails.

3.4.2 Mode of Assessment

One of the most celebrated illustrations of the mode of assessment being modified arose when a number of universities operating on a not-for-profit basis, including eight Ivy league schools, adopted a common policy on how to award financial aid.Footnote 36 The aim was to enable able students to access the best available education regardless of their ability to pay and to create a more diverse student body by making education available to the economically disadvantaged.Footnote 37 It was first agreed among the schools that each would cease to provide merit based aid.Footnote 38 Additionally, it was agreed that no student would be awarded more aid than was justified by financial need (determined by a common formula). By ensuring that aid was granted only to the extent that a student was needy, a greater number of needy students would benefit from financial aid.Footnote 39 To what extent is the granting of this eleemosynary support subject to antitrust scrutiny?

The US Department of Justice’s essential objection was that the schools were effectively setting a maximum discount or a minimum price.Footnote 40 Such price restraints are among the more serious violations of competition law. Such conduct is ordinarily subject to a per se prohibition. Antitrust scrutiny is warranted notwithstanding that the entities operate on a not-for-profit basis.Footnote 41 Is a per se assessment warranted in relation to entities operating on a not-for-profit basis? As the presumption of harm underpinning the per se approach has developed in the context of for-profit firms, the argument has been made that the per se approach should not be invoked or relied on in relation to not-for-profit firms.Footnote 42 Consequently, there was great reluctance to subject the arrangement to the per se mode of analysis and instead the court wished for a more in-depth examination to be conducted and harm to be more specifically articulated and demonstrated.Footnote 43

3.4.3 Range of Justifications

The fact that the entities operate on a not-for-profit basis can encourage courts and agencies to accept a broader range of justifications than is generally available.Footnote 44 In relation to not-for-profit providers, there is much sympathetic commentary advocating the inclusion of a broader range of considerations in the competition law assessment than is typically admitted.Footnote 45 In the Ivy league financial aid case, it was not unarguable that promoting economic diversity and educational access on a not-for-profit basis may justify any harm arising from a restriction of competition.Footnote 46 This reflects a general tendency to at least listen to arguments that harm arising from a restriction imposed by not-for-profit providers are necessary to achieve a greater good. Accepting this argument forces competition law to confront a number of issues. What types of benefit or value are acceptable for a not-for-profit organisation to pursue when those benefits or values conflict with those promoted by competition law?Footnote 47 Who must be the beneficiary of the conduct and what justifies those harmed by the anti-competitive conduct being compelled to pay for that benefit?Footnote 48

An opportunity to confront these issues arose when the competition authority in the United Kingdom considered whether the centralised system used to apply for places at higher education institutions could harm competition between institutions, to the detriment of students.Footnote 49 Both the limit on the number of courses a student may apply for and the inability to apply to both the University of Oxford and the University of Cambridge can be described as restrictions of choice.Footnote 50 Yet, if these restrictions could be cognised as restrictions of competition, the competition authority seemed willing to accept that the restriction could be justified on the ground that it enabled ‘a more in-depth assessment of each candidate’.Footnote 51 Such a justification was put forward in a letter published in the Times Higher Education Supplement to justify the prohibition on applying to both Oxford and Cambridge, claiming:

If a significant proportion of the applicants to whom [Oxford] offered places were liable to go instead to Cambridge, then to avoid lots of places going to waste, we would have to treat admissions as a central university process, playing the statistics of large numbers rather than selecting the students for our own colleges.Footnote 52

The competition authority seemingly accepts that ‘since each additional choice that an applicant makes puts a cost on the institution, it may be efficient to restrict the number of choices that each applicant can make’.Footnote 53 What is unusual about such an approach is that the identified benefits would appear to accrue to the institutions rather than to the students and so there appears to be an acceptance that benefits to not-for-profit institutions may offset harm to the users such institutions are intended to serve.Footnote 54

3.4.4 Sanctions

Even when an unjustified restriction of competition is identified, competition authorities might be reluctant to impose sanctions on entities operating on a not-for-profit basis. The not-for-profit organisation may thus be said to benefit from what might be described as ‘soft’ enforcement. Two examples can be offered. In England and Wales, an infringement of competition law was committed when six State-owned health care providers exchanged information about the price each would charge for privately funded health care services.Footnote 55 No sanction was imposed notwithstanding the fact that information exchange relating to price ranks among the most egregious of competition law infringements. Instead, the competition authority was satisfied by assurances that the information exchange had ceased and that the parties would provide their staff with training on competition law compliance.

An even more striking example is the investigation into the operation of 50 schools that operate on a not-for-profit basis.Footnote 56 The schools had exchange detailed information about the fees that they intended to charge for their education services. The information exchange was organised by the bursar of Sevenoaks School, to whom the participant schools submitted details of their current fee levels, proposed fee increases (expressed as a percentage), and the resulting intended fee levels. The Sevenoaks bursar subsequently circulated this information among the Participant schools in tabular form. The information exchanges resulted in higher fees being charged than would otherwise have been the case and the procedure in force at the time meant that it was not possible to consider whether the arrangement was justifiable.Footnote 57 Although the regular and systematic exchange among competitors of each other’s pricing intentions is a serious infringement, the competition authority decided to limit the penalties to £10,000. Such lenient treatment of such a serious violation was based in part in recognition that ‘the Participant schools are all non-profit making charitable bodies’.Footnote 58

3.5 Why Modify?

Although not-for-profit entities may enter the market with a sense of or commitment to public service, there is nothing inherent in the organisational form to ensure this outcome. Do effective alternatives to voice, reinforced by the possibility of exit exist in relation to not-for-profit providers? Is competition law the best mechanism to ensure the effectiveness of voice and exit in the non-profit context and are competition authorities best placed to ensure compliance by not-for-profit entities? In a market occupied exclusively by not-for-profit entities, it may be that a regulatory regime exits in which the concerns of competition law are already accounted for or in which the concerns can be decentralised by granting concurrent powers. An important consideration, however, is that not-for-profit entities operate in markets that are also served by for-profit entities – the so-called, mixed markets. Some of the claims of non-profit exceptionalism apply only when a market is served exclusively by not-for-profit entities.Footnote 59 Exit and voice therefore remain important mechanisms through which patrons maximise the benefit they obtain from service provision by non-profit entities. It is for this reason that the actions of not-for-profit entities remain within the scope of competition law. Though competition law applies and has been applied to the activities of not-for-profit providers, a reluctance to apply competition law full bloodied can be observed. What explains the reluctance to apply and tendency to modify the law?

A first point is that the extent to which activities of not-for-profit organisations, as distinct from the organisations themselves, fall within the scope of competition law can at times be difficult to determine. A case in point is the raising of funds to finance activities that each organisation will separately provide free at point of use. Can it be argued that fundraisers are selling something tangible to donors (separate from the services offered free at point of use) such that fundraising itself warrants competition law scrutiny?Footnote 60 There is undoubtedly competition for donations, since there are more organisations and causes seeking funds than there are funds.Footnote 61 The economic literature shows that competition for donations increases the cost of raising funds (and by a greater amount than the increase in total funds raised).Footnote 62 Suppressing competition can therefore reduce the cost of fundraising and leave more resources available to promote the organisations mission.Footnote 63 Is it objectionable for competition to be suppressed?Footnote 64

In Dedication & Everlasting Love to Animal v. Humane Society of the United States, in which it was alleged that the Humane Society of the United States monopolised the market for donations to support of animal welfare, fundraising by not-for-profit organisations was not considered to be an antitrust issue.Footnote 65 At the same time, it has been recognised that collective fundraising or a fundraising monopoly may make it more difficult for those not part of the collective effort to raise funds and it may be difficult for them to gain an allocation of the funds raised – the ability of new organisations to raise funds for new causes may be impacted.Footnote 66 Can it be right that no antitrust scrutiny is possible when the impact on competition is not necessarily beneficial or benign?

A second point is that the modifying tendencies are not always triggered. This then makes it clear that something other than non-for-profit status is at work. Operating on a not-for-profit basis could function as a proxy for trustworthiness or selflessness and so it remains the case that ‘those who stand to profit financially from restraints of trade cannot be trusted to determine which restraints are in the public interest and which are not’.Footnote 67 If the non-distribution constraint does not exclude the possibility of an entity acting in the interests of the organisation or its members rather than the consumer, it would seem that competition law is applied unmodified. This would account for the sustained scrutiny applied to self-regulatory bodies and cooperatives, notwithstanding that they operate on a not-for-profit basis.

A third point is that there remains a lingering sense that competition law does not provide an appropriate frame of reference with which to view the activities of not-for-profit entities.Footnote 68 The sense that competition law is somehow trespassing motivates the imposition of high evidential burdens, not only to establish violations but also to even launch an investigation. Recognising that being subject to a competition law investigation is not costless, even in relation to compliant behaviour, justifies the increased thresholds, particularly when bearing such cost necessarily results in reduced resources being available for activities in the general interest.Footnote 69 The same may be true of the modified approach to sanctions. The modifying tendencies are to be understood as simple recognition that it is not in the public interest to enforce competition laws against all conduct falling within the literal scope of the prohibition.

3.6 Conclusion

While there will always be claims that competition law does not or should not apply, there is nothing inherent in the not-for-profit form to justify this claim. Particularly, there is nothing to indicate that applying competition law has been harmful to the causes served by non-profit providers; there are clear indications that competition law has been applied in a way that addresses real harm to patrons; and modifications are made, when appropriate, to ensure that the mission served by not-for-profit entities is not harmed by the application of competition law. All this should leave us confident that competition law can pierce the veil of the not-for-profit form and examine (in its own small way) whether the public interest is genuinely being served.

Footnotes

1 Corporate Law, Antitrust, and the History of Democratic Control of the Balance of Power

Michelle Meagher is Senior Policy Fellow at the UCL Centre for Law, Economics and Society, and co-founder of the Inclusive Competition Forum and the Balanced Economy Project. This work builds on a previous article by the author, Michelle Meagher, ‘Powerless Antitrust’ (2019) 2(1) Competition Policy International Antitrust Chronicle. The author would like to thank the editors for their helpful substantive input. All errors remain the author’s own.

1 Adolf A Berle and Gardiner C Means, The Modern Corporation & Private Property (Macmillan Company 1932) 3.

2 WG Roy, Socializing Capital (Princeton University Press 1997) 41, 48.

3 JW Hurst, The Legitimacy of the Business Corporation (University of Virginia 1970) 43.

4 For a useful ‘potted history’ of the corporation, particularly in America, see N Lamoreaux and W Novak, ‘Introduction’ in Lamoreaux and Novak (eds), Corporations and American Democracy (Harvard University Press 2017) 1–33.

5 Ellis Hawley, The New Deal and the Problem of Monopoly (Princeton University Press 1966) vii.

6 Berle and Means (n 2) 3.

8 Roy (n 3).

11 Sandeep Vaheesan, ‘The Profound Nonsense of Consumer Welfare Antitrust’ (2019) 64 Antitrust Bull 479; Roy (n 3) 190.

12 KS Rahman, Democracy against Domination (Oxford University Press 2016) 13.

13 Karl Polanyi, Great Transformation (2nd ed Beacon Press 2001) 136.

14 Fred Block, ‘Introduction’ in Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation (Farrar & Reinhart 1944) xxii.

15 Polanyi (n14) 60.

16 Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 4.

17 Sanjukta Paul, ‘Antitrust as Allocator of Coordination Rights’ (2020) 67(2) UCLA L Rev 380.

18 Roy (n 3) 48–50; Hurst (n 4) 16.

19 This was also the case in nineteenth century America. Roy (n 3)41.

20 Hurst (n 4) 15–18; Joseph S Davis, Essays in the Earlier History of Corporations (Harvard University Press 1917)

21 Eric Hilt, ‘Early American Corporations and the State’ in Lamoreaux and Novak (eds), Corporations and American Democracy (Harvard University Press 2017) 40; Roy (n 3) 52.

22 William Dalrymple, The Anarchy (Bloomsbury Publishing 2019).

23 Hilt (n 22) 41.

26 Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 8.

27 Barry E Hawk, ‘English Competition Law Before 1900’ (2018) 63 Antitrust Bull 42.

28 Edward Darcy Esquire v Thomas Allen of London Haberdasher [1602] 77 ER 1260.

29 Hawk (n 28).

30 David Millon, ‘The Sherman Act and the Balance of Power’ (1988) 61 S Cal L Rev 1219, 1249.

32 Charles River Bridge v Proprietors of the Warren Bridge, 36 US (11 Pet) 496 (1837).

33 Nikolas Bowie, ‘Why the Constitution Was Written Down’ (2019) 71 Stan L Rev 1397; Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 7.

34 Nikolas Bowie, ‘Why the Constitution Was Written Down’ (2019) 71 Stan L Rev 1397, 1407; Hurst (n 4).

35 Bowie (n 35) 1477.

36 Trustees of Dartmouth College v Woodward, 17 US (4 Wheat) 518 (1819).

37 Henshaw quoted in R L Grossman, F T Adams, and C Levenstein, ‘Taking Care of Business: Citizenship and the Charter of Incorporation (1993)’ 3 New Solutions a Journal of Environmental and Occupational Health Policy 7–18.

38 Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 12.

39 Roy (n 3) 54.

40 Footnote Ibid. at 148, 149.

41 Herbert Hovenkamp, Enterprise and American Law, 1836–1937 (Harvard University Press 1991) 56–9.

42 Technically the particular procedure in use was the ‘information in the nature of quo warranto’ which had less onerous requirements. James L. High, A Treatise on Extraordinary Legal Remedies: Embracing Mandamus, Quo Warranto, and Prohibition (1874). I will refer simply to ‘quo warranto’ for ease of exposition.

43 Helen M Cam, ‘Historical Revisions XXXVIII – The Quo Warranto Proceedings under Edward I’ (1926) 11 History 143–148.

44 Few privileges were in fact revoked. The process was rather used as a form of revenue generation through the collection of fines. See Cam (n 44).

45 Discussed at Section 1.3.2.

46 Daniel Crane, ‘The Dissociation of Incorporation and Regulation in the Progressive Era and the New Deal’, in Lamoreaux and Novak (eds), Corporations and American Democracy (Harvard University Press 2017) 112.

47 Herbert Hovenkamp, ‘The Classical Corporation in American Legal Thought’, 76 Geo LJ 1593, 1669–72.

48 Martin Sklar, The Corporate Reconstruction of American Capitalism, 1890–1916: The Market, the Law, and Politics (Cambridge University Press 1988) 99; Naomi Lamoreaux and Laura Philips Sawyer, ‘Voting Trusts and Antitrust: Rethinking the Role of Shareholder Litigation in Public Regulation, 1880s to 1930s’ (2021) Law Hist Rev, 39(3), 569–600; Crane (n 47) 113.

49 Roy (n 3) 176–220.

50 Roy (n 3) 179.

51 Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 13; Roy (n 3) 145.

52 Lamoreaux and Sawyer (n 49).

53 Hilt (n 22) 41.

54 Crane (n 47) 111; Laura Philips Sawyer, American Fair Trade: Proprietary Capitalism, Corporatism, and the ‘New Competition’, 1890–1940 (Cambridge University Press 2018); Gerald Berk, ‘Neither Markets nor Administration: Brandeis and the Antitrust Reforms of 1914’ (1994) 8 Studies in American Political Development 24, 28; Millon (n 31) 1255; Hovenkamp, ‘The Classical Corporation in American Legal Thought’ (n 48) 34; Hovenkamp, Enterprise and American Law (n 42) 37–8.

55 Robert Lowe, Vice President of the Board of Trade, who was the mastermind behind the Joint Stock Companies Act of 1856, declared: ‘From then to now [incorporation] was a privilege. We hope to make it a right’, quoted in John Micklethwait and Adrian Wooldridge, The Company (Modern Library 2005) 58. See also Thomas Linzey, ‘Awakening the Sleeping Giant: Creating a Quasi-Private Cause of Action for Revoking Corporate Charters in Response to Environmental Violations’ (1995) 13 Pace Envtl L Rev 219, 222 (noting that general incorporation elicited a ‘shift in public opinion towards routine acceptance of a corporation’s right to exist.’); Roy (n 3) 17.

56 As discussed in Section 1.3.2. Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 3.

57 Crane (n 47) 113–114.

58 William Cary, ‘Federalism and Corporate Law: Reflections upon Delaware’ (1974) 83 Yale LJ Number 666.

59 Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 13.

60 Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 14.

61 Hovenkamp (n 42) 266.

62 Roy (n 3) 176–220.

63 Footnote Ibid. at 18

64 Footnote Ibid. at 210; Sklar (n 49) 99.

65 State v Standard Oil Co, 49 Ohio St 137, 184 (1892).

66 Hovenkamp (n 48) 1669; Roy (n 3) 15–16.

67 Roy (n 3) 279.

68 Hurst (n 4) 74.

69 Crane (n 47) 110. See also KS Rahman, ‘The New Utilities: Private Power, Social Infrastructure, and the Revival of the Public Utility Concept’ (2018) 39 Cardozo L Rev 1628–34 (tracing the ‘common genealogical roots’ of corporate governance, antitrust and the public utility concept as responses to the problem of private power and the need to ensure accountability).

70 Sklar (n 49) 103; Hawk (n 28).

71 Hovenkamp (n 42) 274.

72 Sanjukta Paul, ‘Reconsidering Judicial Supremacy in Antitrust’ (2020) 31 Yale LJ. See also Sanjukta Paul, ‘Antitrust as an Allocator of Coordination Rights’ (n 18).

73 Hawk (n 28) 40.

74 Sanjukta Paul, ‘Reconsidering Judicial Supremacy in Antitrust’ (2020) 31 Yale LJ.

76 Mogul Steamship Company, Ltd. V. McGregor, Gow & Company, 21 Q.B.D. 544 (1889).

77 Sir Peter Roth QC, ‘The Continual Evolution of Competition Law’ (Speech at the 36th Blackstone Lecture, Oxford, 9 November 2018) www.catribunal.org.uk/sites/default/files/2018-12/The%20Continual%20Evolution%20of%20Competition%20Law.pdf accessed on 9 September 2021.

78 As quoted in Sir Peter Roth QC, ‘The Continual Evolution of Competition Law’ (Speech at the 36th Blackstone Lecture, Oxford, 9 November 2018) www.catribunal.org.uk/sites/default/files/2018-12/The%20Continual%20Evolution%20of%20Competition%20Law.pdf accessed on 9 September 2021.

79 By the late 1800s, at least 21 states had put common law restraint of trade onto a statutory and/or constitutional footing. But these laws were not vigorously enforced. Sklar (n 49) 93.

80 Hovenkamp, Enterprise and American Law (n 42) 266; Roy (n 3) 191.

81 Hutchison, ‘Progressive Era Conceptions of the Corporation’ (2017) 2017(3) Colum Bus L Rev 1017.

82 William Novak, ‘Law and the Social Control of American Capitalism’ (2010) 60 Emory LJ 377, 393–4.

83 Crane (n 47) 116; Hutchison (n 82) 1022; Sklar (n 49); Melvin Urofsky, ‘Proposed Federal Incorporation in the Progressive Era’ (1982) 26(2) Am J Legal Hist 160–183.

84 Hovenkamp, Enterprise and American Law (n 42) 247.

85 Millon (n 31)

86 Footnote Ibid. See also Roy (n 3) 197 (‘The limp legislation was as much an admission that the changes [in American industry] were irreversible as it was a futile gesture to restore a competitive world that had never existed.’).

87 Sandeep Vaheesan, ‘Accommodating Capital and Policing Labor: Antitrust in the Two Gilded Ages’ (2019) 78 Md L Rev 766.

88 Ramsi A. Woodcock, ‘Inconsistency in Antitrust’(2013) 68 U Miami L Rev 105.

89 Discussed in Section 1.3.2.

90 Hilt (n 22) 51–52.

91 Lamoreaux and Novak (n 5) 12.

92 Lamoreaux and Philips Sawyer (n 49).

94 See for an exception, eg, Lynn Stout, ‘The Shareholder Value Myth’ (2013) Cornell Law Faculty Publications Paper 771 http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/facpub/771 accessed on 9 September 2021.

95 JN Gordon, ‘The Rise of Independent Directors in the United States, 1950–2005: Of Shareholder Value and Stock Market Prices (2006) 59 Stan L Rev 1465.

96 Dodge v Ford Motor Company, 204 MI 459, 170 NW 668 (MI 1919).

97 William Bratton and Michael Wachter, ‘Shareholder Primacy’s Corporatist Origins’ (2008) 34 J Corp L 99, 102.

98 Footnote Ibid. at 99.

99 Footnote Ibid. at 121–2, 148–9.

100 Roy (n 3) 172–74.

101 Paul (n 73).

102 Frank H. Easterbrook and Daniel R. Fischel, The Economic Structure of Corporate Law (Harvard University Press 1991).

103 Milton Friedman, ‘A Friedman Doctrine – the Social Responsibility of Business Is to Increase Its Profits’ The New York Times (New York, 13 September 1970).

104 Henry Hansmann and Rainier Kraakman, ‘The End of History for Corporate Law’ (2001) 89 Geo LJ 439, 439 (‘There is no longer any serious competitor to the view that corporate law should principally strive to increase long-term shareholder value.’)

105 Luigi Zingales, ‘Towards a Political Theory of the Firm’ (2017) 31 J Econ Perspect 113–130.

106 Michelle Meagher, ‘Powerless Antitrust’ (2019) 2(1) Competition Policy International Antitrust Chronicle.

107 Accountable Capitalism Act, 115th Congress (2017–18) S. 3348.

108 Administration of Justice Act 1938, s 9.

109 Ewan McGaughey and Mathew Lawrence, The Green Recovery Act (Common Wealth 2020) section 21 www.common-wealth.co.uk/interactive-digital-projects/green-recovery-act#1 accessed 9 September 2021.

110 Walter Jacobs at 252, as cited in Keay, ‘Public Interest Petitions’ (1999) 20 Company Lawyer 296.

2 ESG Policies at the Intersection between Competition and Corporate Law

1 M Jensen and W Meckling, ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure’ (1976) 3 J Financ Econ 305.

2 J Armour and J McCahery (eds) After Enron: Improving Corporate Law and Modernising Securities Regulation in Europe and the US (Hart Publishing, 2006).

3 See for instance the vast set of papers collected on the European Corporate Governance Institute official website https://ecgi.global/content/sustainable-corporate-governance.

6 F Madrakhimova, ‘History of Development of Corporate Social Responsibility’ (2013) 4 J Bus Econ 509, 515.

9 See eg A Witt, The More Economic Approach to EU Antitrust Law (Hart 2016); J Blockx, ‘The Limits of the “More Economic” Approach to Antitrust’ (2019), 42(4) World Compet 475–496.

10 See CECED (IV.F.1/ 36.718) Commission Decision 2000/ 475/ EC [2000] OJ L187/47; H Vedder, Competition Law and Environmental Protection in Europe: Towards Sustainability? (Europa Law Publishing 2003).

11 See eg S Kingston, Greening EU Competition Law and Policy (Cambridge University Press 2012), J Nowag, Environmental Integration in Competition and Free-Movement Laws (Oxford University Press 2017); OECD (2020), Sustainability and Competition, OECD Competition Committee Discussion Paper, www.oecd.org/daf/competition/sustainability-and-competition-2020.pdf (accessed 16 Feb 2022); European Commission, Directorate-General for Competition, Competition policy brief 2021-01 in September 2021, European Commission, 2021, https://data.europa.eu/doi/10.2763/962262 (accessed 16 Feb 2022); OECD (2021), Environmental Considerations in Competition Enforcement, OECD Competition Committee Discussion Paper, www.oecd.org/daf/competition/environmental-considerations-in-competition-enforcement.htm (accessed 16 Feb 2022), and the near exponential growth of literature since 2020.

12 See, for example, A Miazad, ‘Prosocial Antitrust’ (March 11, 2021) Hastings Law Journal (forthcoming, 2021), available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3802194 (accessed 16 Feb 2022).

13 See OCED papers in (n 11); Hungarian Competition Authority, ‘Sustainable Development and Competition Law – Survey Report: Special Project for the 2021 ICN Annual Conference’ (30.09.2022) www.gvh.hu/en/gvh/Conference/icn-2021-annual-conference/special-project-for-the-2021-icn-annual-conference-sustainable-development-and-competition-law (accessed 16 Feb 2022).

14 ACM, 2nd Draft Guidelines Sustainability Agreements: Opportunities Within Competition Law (2021) www.acm.nl/sites/default/files/documents/second-draft-version-guidelines-on-sustainability-agreements-oppurtunities-within-competition-law.pdf (accessed 16 Feb 2022); HCC, ‘Staff Discussion Paper on Sustainability Issues and Competition Law’ www.epant.gr/en/enimerosi/competition-law-sustainability/item/download/1896_9b05dc293adbae88a7bb6cce37d1ea60.html (accessed 16. Feb 2022); R Inderst, E Sartzetakis, and A Xepapadeas, Joint Technical Report on Sustainability and Competition for the HCC and the ACM (Jan 2021) www.epant.gr/en/enimerosi/competition-law-sustainability/item/download/2165_f998b905c20c0426f068e512186c6ec4.html (accessed 16 Feb 2022).

15 See European Commission (n 11).

16 See I Lianos with D Katalevsky, ‘Merger Activity in the Factors of Production Segments of the Food Value Chain: – A Critical Assessment of the Bayer/Monsanto merger’ CLES Policy Paper Series 2017/1 www.ucl.ac.uk/cles/sites/cles/files/cles-policy-paper-1-2017.pdf (accessed 16 Feb 2022).

17 J Azar, M Schmalz and I Tecu, ‘Anticompetitive Effects of Common Ownership’ (2018) 73 J Fin 1513.

18 J Azar et al., ‘The Big Three and Corporate Carbon Emissions around the World’ (2021) J Fin Econ; see also Chapter 14, in this book.

19 See, for example, World Commission on Environment and Development, Our Common Future (Oxford University Press 1987).

20 See, for example, D Schlosberg and L Collins, ‘From Environmental to Climate Justice: Climate Change and the Discourse of Environmental Justice’ (2014) 5(3) WIREs Clim Change, 359–374; H Shue, Climate Justice: Vulnerability and Protection (Oxford University Press 2014); D Schlosberg, J Dryzek, and R Norgaard, The Oxford Handbook of Climate Change and Society (Oxford University Press 2011); L Meyer & D Roser, ‘Climate Justice and Historical Emissions’, (2010) 13(1) Crit Rev Int Soc Polit Phil, 229–253.

21 Instead of many see, for example, Maarten Pieter Schinkel and Yossi Spiegel, ‘Can Collusion Promote Sustainable Consumption and Production?’ (2017) Int J Ind Org 371–398.

22 For an overview on see: D Cole and P Grossman ‘When Is Command-and-Control Efficient? Institutions, Technology, and the Comparative Efficiency of Alternative Regulatory Regimes for Environmental Protection’ (1999) Wisconsin Law Rev 887–938.

23 Pacheco et al., ‘Governing Sustainable Palm Oil Supply: Disconnects, Complementarities, and Antagonisms between State Regulations and Private Standards’ (2020) 14:3 Regulat Govern 568–598.

24 Amazon emitted 2020 around 60.64 million tons of CO2 in 2020 see, https://fortune.com/2021/06/30/amazon-carbon-footprint-pollution-grew/ (accessed 15 Feb. 2022), Sweden emitted around 45.5 million tons of CO2 in 2020, see www.statista.com/statistics/449823/co2-emissions-sweden/ (accessed 15 Feb. 2022).

25 W Katz, ‘Responsibility and the Modern Corporation’ (1960) 3 J Law Econ 75–85.

26 R Eells, ‘The Traditional Corporation’, in The Meaning of Modern Business (Columbia University Press, 1960) 38–49.

27 J Hetherington, ‘Fact and Legal Theory: Shareholders, Managers, and Corporate Social Responsibility’ (1968) 21 Stan L Rev 248; A Carroll, ‘A Three-Dimensional Conceptual Model of Corporate Performance’ (1979) 4 Acad Manag Rev 497–505; E Epstein, ‘The Corporate Social Policy Process: Beyond Business Ethics, Corporate Social Responsibility, and Corporate Social Responsiveness’ (1987) 29 Calif Manage Rev 99–114.

28 A Carroll and J Brown, ‘Corporate Social Responsibility: A Review of Current Concepts, Research, and Issues’ (2018) Corp Soc Responsib.

29 G Frynas, ‘The False Developmental Promise of Corporate Social Responsibility: Evidence from Multinational Oil Companies’ (2005) 81 Int Aff 581–598.

30 H Grove and M Clouse, ‘Focusing on Sustainability to Strengthen Corporate Governance’ (2018) 2 Corp Govern Sustain Rev 38–47.

31 T Tsalis et al., ‘New Challenges for Corporate Sustainability Reporting: United Nations’ 2030 Agenda for Sustainable Development and the Sustainable Development Goals’ (2020) 27 Corp Soc Responsib Environ Manag 1617–1629.

32 See a practical ‘mise en oeuvre’ of the relationship between CSR and SDG in the KPMG report titled: ‘Sustainable Development Goals (SDGs): Leveraging CSR to Achieve SDGs’ https://assets.kpmg/content/dam/kpmg/in/pdf/2017/12/SDG_New_Final_Web.pdf

33 See infra text corresponding to n 37 ff.

34 See infra text corresponding to n 56 ff.

36 M Roe, ‘Corporate Short-Termism – in the Boardroom and in the Courtroom’ (2013) Bus Lawyer 977.

37 C Mayer, Firm Commitment: Why the Corporation Is Failing Us and How To Restore Trust In It (Oxford University Press 2013).

38 Directive (EU) 2017/828 of the European Parliament and of the Council of 17 May 2017 amending Directive 2007/36/EC as regards to the encouragement of long-term shareholder engagement, OJ L 132, 20.5.2017, pp. 1–25.

39 LOI no. 2014-384 du 29 mars 2014 Visant à Reconquérir l’Economie Réelle, JORF n 0077 du 1 avril 2014, Texte no. 3. See the Florange Act in comparative perspective in F Alogna, et al., ‘The Shareholder in France and the United States: A Comparative Analysis of Corporate Legal Priorities’, Business & Law Review, Business & Law Association (Association Droit & Affaires (AD&A)) Paris (2020).

40 J Stiglitz, Rewriting the Rules of the American Economy: An Agenda for Growth and Shared Prosperity (WW Norton & Company, 2015).

41 J Stiglitz, ‘An Agenda for Sustainable and Inclusive Growth for Emerging Markets’ (2016) 38 J of Policy Model 693, 702.

42 And note that the same kind of fund may also adopt differentiated strategies. See K Greenfield, ‘The Puzzle of Short-Termism’ (2011) 46 Wake Forest L Rev 627, 638–639.

43 P Bolton and F Samama, ‘Loyalty‐Shares: Rewarding Long‐Term Investors’ (2013) 25 J Appl Corp Finance 86.

44 See the seminal statement by M Lipton, ‘Takeover Bids in the Target’s Boardroom’ (1979) 35 Bus Lawyer 101.

45 See the literature cited by M Roe, ‘Stock Market Short-Termism’s Impact’ (2018) 167 U Pa L Rev 71, 109.

46 H Almeida et al., ‘Do Short-Term Incentives Affect Long-Term Productivity?’, European Corporate Governance Institute–Finance Working Paper 662 (2020).

47 M Barzuza and E Talley, ‘Long-Term Bias’ (2020) Colum Bus L Rev 104.

48 Ernst & Young’s ‘Study on Directors’ Duties Sustainable Corporate Governance’ (April 2020), available at https://op.europa.eu/en/publication-detail/-/publication/e47928a2-d20b-11ea-adf7-01aa75ed71a1/language-en, 9–31.

49 M Roe et al., ‘The European Commission’s Sustainable Corporate Governance Report: A Critique’, available at SSRN (2020).

50 M Roe, and R Shapira. ‘The Power of the Narrative in Corporate Lawmaking’, available at SSRN 3703882 (2020).

51 Roe (n 45).

52 J Fried, ‘The Uneasy Case for Favoring Long-Term Shareholders’ (2014) 124 Yale LJ 1554.

53 J Fried and C Wang, ‘Short-Termism and Capital Flows’ (2019) 8 Rev Corp Finance Stud 207.

54 J Fried and C Wang, ‘Short‐Termism, Shareholder Payouts and Investment in the EU’ (2021) 27 Eur Financ Manag 389.

55 M Giannetti and X Yu, ‘Adapting to Radical Change: The Benefits of Short-Horizon Investors’ (2021) 67 Manag Sci 4032.

56 M Corradi, Corporate Opportunities, A Law and Economics Analysis (Hart, 2021) Ch 5.

58 See Chapter 8 in this book and also M Corradi and J Nowag, ‘Enforcing Corporate Opportunity Rules: Antitrust Risks and Antitrust Failures’, forthcoming on European Business Law Review.

59 On consumer welfare, H Hovenkamp, ‘Distributive Justice and the Antitrust Laws’ (1982) 51 Geo Wash L Rev 1; B Orbach, ‘The Antitrust Consumer Welfare Paradox’ (2001) 7 J Compet Law and Econ 133.

60 D Bös, ‘Privatization in Europe: A Comparison of Approaches’ (1993) 9 Oxford Rev Econ Policy 95.

61 K Schmidt, ‘The Costs and Benefits of Privatization: An Incomplete Contracts Approach’ (1996) 12 J Law, Econ, and Organ 1; For the distributional consequences of privatizations, see N Birdsall and J Nellis, ‘Winners and Losers: Assessing the Distributional Impact of Privatization’ (2003) 31 World Development 1617.

62 C Mayer, Prosperity: Better Business Makes the Greater Good (Oxford University Press, 2018) 2. Mayer’s theses were criticized by L Bebchuk and R Tallarita, ‘The Illusory Promise of Stakeholder Governance’, available at SSRN 3544978 (2020), to whom Mayer reacted with a further paper: C Mayer, ‘Shareholderism Versus Stakeholderism – A Misconceived Contradiction. A Comment on ‘The Illusory Promise of Stakeholder Governance’ by Lucian Bebchuk and Roberto Tallarita’, European Corporate Governance Institute-Law Working Paper 522 (2020).

63 Footnote Ibid. at 4.

64 Footnote Ibid. at 5.

65 C Mayer, ‘The Future of the Corporation and the Economics of Purpose’, ECGI Finance Working Paper 710/2020. These principles have been adopted by a recent policy document by the British Academy, ‘Principles for Purposeful Business’, that sets general principles and supports the idea that ‘[r]egulation should expect particularly high duties of engagement, loyalty and care on the part of directors of companies to public interests where they perform important public functions’; The British Academy, ‘Principles for Purposeful Business’ (2019) www.thebritishacademy.ac.uk/publications/future-of-the-corporation-principles-for-purposeful-business/.

66 See KPMG, ‘How to Report On the SDGs: What Good Looks Like and Why It Matters (Feb 2018), https://assets.kpmg/content/dam/kpmg/xx/pdf/2018/02/how-to-report-on-sdgs.pdf

67 It can, for example, be compared to innovation questions where similar questions can arise. Yet, the benefits of CO2 reductions might be their very nature be felt even later. On the comparison to innovation questions see Hellenic Competition Commission, Staff Discussion Paper on Sustainability Issues and Competition Law (2020), available www.epant.gr/en/enimerosi/competition-law-sustainability/item/download/1896_9b05dc293adbae88a7bb6cce37d1ea60.html (accessed 05 Oct 2020) para 25.

68 K Coates & D Middelschulte, ‘Getting Consumer Welfare Right: The Competition Law Implications of Market-Driven Sustainability Initiatives’ (2019) 15:2–3 Eur Compet J 321.

69 In general, see also R Inderst, E Sartzetakis, and A Xepapadeas, Joint Technical Report on Sustainability and Competition for the HCC and the ACM (Jan 2021) www.epant.gr/en/enimerosi/competition-law-sustainability/item/download/2165_f998b905c20c0426f068e512186c6ec4.html (accessed 16 Feb 2022).

70 Hellenic Competition Commission, Staff Discussion Paper on Sustainability Issues and Competition Law (2020), available at www.epant.gr/en/enimerosi/competition-law-sustainability/item/download/1896_9b05dc293adbae88a7bb6cce37d1ea60.html (accessed 05 Oct 2020) para 111.

71 Footnote Ibid. at para 50.

72 This framework is developed in Julian Nowag, Environmental Integration in Competition and Free-Movement Laws (Oxford University Press 2017) 1–12.

73 See Simon Holms, ‘Climate Change, Sustainability and Competition Law’ 8:2 (2020) J Antitrust Enforc 355.

74 See E Ostrom, Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action (Cambridge University Press 1990).

75 Picking up on theme of competition leading to suboptimal outcomes, see Maurice Stucke and Ariel Ezrachi, Competition Overdose (Harper Business 2020).

76 See, for example, M P Schinkel and Y Spiegel, ‘Can Collusion Promote Sustainable Consumption and Production?’ (2017) Int J Ind Organ 371–398. L Treuren and M P Schinkel, ‘Can Collusion Promote Sustainable Consumption and Production? Not Beneficially Beyond Duopoly’ (March 1, 2018) Amsterdam Law School Research Paper No. 2018-02, Amsterdam Center for Law & Economics Working Paper No. 2018-01; F Martinez, S Onderstal and M P Schinkel, ‘Can Collusion Promote Corporate Social Responsibility? Evidence from the Lab’ (Nov 2019) Tinbergen Institute Discussion Paper TI 2019-034/VII; M P Schinkel and L Tóth, ‘Compensatory Public Good Provision by a Private Cartel’ (January 2020) Tinbergen Institute Discussion Papers 19-086/VII.

77 See, for example, C Volpin, ‘Sustainability as a Quality Dimension of Competition: Protecting Our Future (Selves)’ (July 2020) CPI Antitrust Chronicle 9–18.

78 For a good overview of the Schumpter-Arrow debate and questions regarding specific market conditions in Pharma, see Michael A. Carrier, ‘Two Puzzles Resolved: Of the Schumpeter–Arrow Stalemate and Pharmaceutical Innovation Markets’ (2007) Iowa L Rev 393.

79 See text to n 73.

80 See Section 2.3.

81 J Armour, L Enriques, T Wetzer, ‘Green Pills: Making Corporate Carbon Commitments Credible’ (November, 2021).

82 OECD, Towards a Green Growth (2011); www.oecd.org/greengrowth/48012345.pdf. But some do not see in innovation a solution to environmental issues. See M Cohen, ‘Ecological Modernization and Its Discontents: The American Environmental Movement’s Resistance to an Innovation-driven Future’ (2006) 38 Futures 528. Amore balanced approach in. A Grunwald, ‘Diverging Pathways to Overcoming the Environmental Crisis: A critique of Eco-modernism from a Technology Assessment Perspective’ (2018) 197 J of Clean Prod 1854.

83 Corradi, Corporate Opportunities (n 56) Chapter 6.

84 See Corradi Nowag (n 58).

85 M Corradi and J Nowag, ‘Enforcing Corporate Opportunity Rules: Antitrust Risks and Antitrust Failures’ Eur Bus Law Rev 2022 (forthcoming).

86 R. Tallarita, Portfolio Primacy and Climate Change available at SSRN 3912977 (2021).

3 Not-for-Profit Organisations and Competition Law

Professor of Competition Law, Faculty of Law; Director of the Centre for European Legal Studies; Fellow in Law, Emmanuel College, University of Cambridge.

1 H Hansmann, ‘The Role of Nonprofit Enterprise’ (1980) 89 Yale LJ 835–901.

2 S Rose-Ackerman, ‘Altruism, Nonprofits, and Economic Theory’ (1996) 34 J Econ Lit 701, 723–725.

3 Footnote Ibid. at 701–728. Although both public (government) and private not for profit organisations are treated as equivalents in this chapter, there is some evidence that they may behave differently and thus warrant different treatment: D Almond, J Currie, and ESimeonova, ‘Public vs Private Provision of Charity Care? Evidence from the Expiration of Hill-Burton Requirements in Florida’ (2011) 30 J Health Econ 189–99

4 C Capps, D Carlton, and G David, ‘Antitrust Treatment of Nonprofits: Should Hospitals Receive Special Care?’ (2020) 58 Economic Inquiry 1183–1199; F Entin, T Fletcher, and J Teske, ‘Hospital Collaboration: The Need for an Appropriate Antitrust Policy’ (1994) 29 Wake Forest L Rev 107–68.

5 AO Hirschman, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty; Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States (Harvard UP 1970) 34. Voice is broader than complaints and is defined at page 30 as ‘any attempt at all to change, rather than to escape from, an objectionable state of affairs.’

6 Footnote Ibid. at 39.

7 Footnote Ibid. at 82.

8 Capps, Carlton, and David (n 4) 1183–99.

9 F M Scherer, ‘Schumpeter and Plausible Capitalism’ (1992) 30 J Econ Lit 1416, 1425–30.

10 B Weisbrod, The Nonprofit Economy (Harvard UP 1988); and R Steinberg, ‘Economic Theories of Nonprofit Organizations’ in W Powell and R Steinberg (eds), The Nonprofit Sector: A Research Handbook (2nd ed, Yale UP 2006) 117–39.

11 HB Hansmann, ‘The Role of Nonprofit Enterprise’ (1980) 89 Yale LJ 835–901.

12 M Jegers, Managerial Economics of Non-Profit Organizations (Routledge 2008) 16–21.

13 JP Newhouse, ‘Toward a Theory of Nonprofit Institutions – Economic Model of a Hospital’ (1970) 60 Am Econ Rev 64–74; W Lynk, ‘Nonprofit Hospital Mergers and the Exercise of Market Power’ (1995) 38 J Law and Econ 437–61. Lynk’s article was then criticised in D Dranove and R Ludwick, ‘Competition and Pricing by Nonprofit Hospitals: A Reassessment of Lynk’s Analysis’ (1995) 18 J Health Econ 87–98.

14 P Francois, ‘Not For Profit Provision of Public Services’ (2003) 113 Economic Journal C53-C61. It is clear that such trust can be mis-placed: see R Herzlinger, ‘Can Public Trust in Nonprofits Governments Be Restored?’ (1996) 74 Harv Bus Rev 97–107.

15 See Herzlinger and W Krasker, ‘Who Profits from Nonprofits’ (1987) 65 Harv Bus Rev 93–106 (summarizing and challenging the exceptionalism claimed by not for profit organizations); S Srikanth, ‘College Financial Aid and Antitrust: Applying the Sherman Act to Collaborative Nonprofit Activity’ (1994) 46 Stan L Rev 919, 936 (arguing that a restriction of competition may advance overall social welfare), and M Schlesinger, T Marmor, and R Smithey, ‘Nonprofit and for-Profit Medical Care: Shifting Roles and Implications for Health Policy’ (1987) 12 J Health Pol Pol’y L 427–457 (arguing for regulation based on type of organization)

16 T Philipson and R Posner, ‘Antitrust and the Not For Profit Sector’ (2009) 52 JLE 1–18.

17 D Haas-Wilson and C Garmon, ‘Hospital Mergers and Competitive Effects: Two Retrospective Analyses’ 2011 18 Int’l J Econ Bus 17–32; F Sloan, et al., ‘Hospital Ownership and Cost and Quality of Care: Is There a Dime’s Worth of Difference?’ (2001) 20 J Health Econ 1–21 (finding not for profits may produce at lower cost, but do not offer greater quality); P Born and C Simon, ‘Patients and Profits: The Relationship between Hmo Financial Performance and Quality of Care’ (2001) 20 Health Affairs 167–174 (finding that for profit providers do not provide a higher nor lesser quality of care); Capps, Carlton, and David (n 4) 1183–1199 (find the mere fact that an entity operates on a not for profit basis does induce it to provide higher levels of public benefit)

18 Under US antitrust law see: Goldfarb v Virginia State Bar, 421 US 773, 786–787 (1975); US v Brown University, 5 F3d 658, 666 (3d Cir 1993). Under EU and UK competition law, see Case C-244/94 Fédération Française des Sociétés d’assurance v Ministère de L’agriculture et de la Pêche ECLI:EU:C:1995:392, para 21; Case CE/2890-03 Exchange of Information on Future Fees by Certain Independent Fee–Paying Schools [20 November 2006] Decision of the Office of Fair Trading, paras 1312–1316.

19 Under US antitrust law, see: Goldfarb v Virginia State Bar, 421 US 773, 786–787 (1975). Under EU competition law see: Case 155/73 Giuseppe Sacchi ECLI:EU:C:1974:40, para 14; Case C-41/1990 Klaus Höfner and Fritz Elser v Macrotron Gmbh ECLI:EU:C:1991:161, para 19.

20 Note the general paradox that competition is designed to enhance cooperation: P Rubin ‘Emporiophobia (Fear of Markets): Cooperation or Competition?’ (2014) 80 South Econ J 876–889.

21 See Commission, ‘Report on Competition in Professional Services’ (Communication) COM (2004) 83 final https://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/TXT/?uri=celex%3A52004DC0083; Commission, ‘Professional Services – Scope for more reform: Follow-up to the Report on Competition in Professional Services (Communication) COM (2004) 83’ COM (2005) 405 final https://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/AUTO/?uri=celex:52005DC0405; OECD, ‘Competition In Professional Services’ DAFFE/CLP(2000)2; Monopolies Commission (UK), Professional Services: a report on the general effect on the public interest of certain restrictive practices so far as they prevail in relation to the supply of professional services (Cmnd 4463, 1970); L Terry, ‘The European Commission Project Regarding Competition in Professional Services’ (2009) 29 Nw J Int’l L & Bus 1

22 Office of Fair Trading, The control of entry regulations and retail pharmacy services in the UK para. 2.20–2.22, 3.8–3.12, 3.18–3.22; NMa Press Release, ‘Pharmacies in Assen and Tilburg Must Lift Restrictions on Competition’ (22 June 2004) www.acm.nl/en/publications/publication/5859/NMa-Pharmacies-in-Assen-and-Tilburg-Must-Lift-Restrictions-on-Competition; NMa Press Release, ‘Suspects Pharmacies in Assen of Restricting Competition’ (2 April 2003) www.acm.nl/en/publications/publication/5994/NMa-Suspects-Pharmacies-in-Assen-of-Restricting-Competition; NMa Press Release, ‘NMa Suspects Pharmacies in Breda of Restricting Competition’ (6 June 2003) www.acm.nl/en/publications/publication/5862/NMa-Suspects-Pharmacies-in-Breda-of-Restricting-Competition; NMa Press Release, ‘NMa fines Dutch National Association of General Practitioners for Illegal Establishment Recommendations’ (9 January 2012) www.acm.nl/en/publications/publication/6719/NMa-fines-Dutch-National-Association-of-General-Practitioners-for-illegal-establishment-recommendations; The Competition Authority (Ireland), ‘Competition in Professional Services: general medical practitioners’ (2010) paras 2.59, 3.3, 6.17–6.31, 7.1–7.20, 8.8–8.13

23 Finnish Competition Authority, ‘Finnish Competition Authority Yearbook 2003’ www.kkv.fi/globalassets/kkv-suomi/julkaisut/vuosikirjat/kilpailuvirasto/2003/kivi-vuosikirja-2003-en.pdf accessed 24 November 2019; and respectively, see Co-operation & Competition Panel (UK), ‘North Yorkshire and York PCT and York Hospitals NHS Foundation Trust Conduct Complaint’ (22 March 2012) http://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/20130513202829/http://www.ccpanel.org.uk/content/cases/North_Yorkshire_and_York_PCT_and_York_Hospitals_NHS_Foundation_Trust_Conduct_Complaint/120322_York_PCT_Assura_conduct_complaint_PUBLISHED.pdf

24 Monopolies and Mergers Commission (UK), Services of Medical Practitioners: A report on the supply of the services of registered medical practitioners in relation to restrictions on advertising (Cm 582, 1989) paras 7.6, 7.21, and 8.5 (action taken under section 7(1)(c) and (2) of the Fair Trading Act 1973). Consider also The Competition Authority (Ireland) (n 22) para 5.1–5.16; the Commission’s approach: ‘Professional Services: overview’ (European Commission, 14 December 2012) https://ec.europa.eu/competition/sectors/professional_services/overview_en.html accessed 24 November 2019; F Miller, ‘Competition Law and Anticompetitive Professional Behaviour Affecting Health Care’ (1992) 55 MLR 453, 479; Monopolies Commission (n 21) para 214, 251–52 and 272.

25 Joined Cases 209 to 215 and 218/78 Heintz van Landewyck SARL v Commission ECLI:EU:C:1980:248, para 85–89; Office of Fair Trading, ‘Trade associations, professions and self-regulating bodies’ (2004) OFT 408.

26 Case C-244/94 Fédération Française des Sociétés d’Assurance ECLI:EU:C:1995:392, para 21; Case C-67/96 Albany International BV v SBT ECLI:EU:C:1999:430, para 85; See also Case C-250/92 Gøttrup-Klim Grovvareforening v Dansk Landbrugs Growareselskab AmbA (DLG) ECLI:EU:C:1994:413.

27 Commission Decision 90/456/EEC of 1 August 1990 concerning the provision in Spain of international express courier services [1990] OJ L233/19; Case C-41/90 Höfner and Elser v Macrotron GmbH ECLI:EU:C:1991:161; Case C-475/99 Ambulanz Glöckner ECLI:EU:C:2001:577.

28 ‘Bundeskartellamt prohibits for the first time merger between public hospitals’ (Bundeskartellamt, 13 December 2006) www.bundeskartellamt.de/SharedDocs/Meldung/EN/Pressemitteilungen/2006/13_12_2006_Krankenhausuntersagung_eng.html (last accessed 10 Nov 2021).

29 Para 14 of Schedule 1 of The Restrictive Trade Practices Act 1976 had previously placed the provision of primary, secondary or further education, and university or other higher education beyond the reach of competition law. These exclusions are not carried over into the Competition Act 1998.

30 Office of Fair Trading, ‘Call for information on the undergraduate higher education sector in England’ (October 2013) https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/media/533559bd40f0b62e99000015/HE-CFIs.pdf. The competition authority’s interest in examining this market was motivated by ‘changes to the financing of undergraduate courses (with an increase in the funding resulting from student fees and a decrease in direct funding from government)’; Office of Fair Trading, ‘Higher Education in England: An OFT Call for Information’ (March 2014) OFT 1529, para 1.3, note 5, para 2.4; para 3.11–3.14).

31 Office of Fair Trading, ‘Higher Education in England: An OFT Call for Information’ (n 30) para. 6.4

32 The threshold for investigation set out in section 25 of the Competition Act 1998. The ‘reasonable suspicion’ threshold is not a high bar (see, by analogy, para 7 of the Competition Appeal Tribunal judgment in ACS v OFT).

33 Re Cartel in Aniline Dyes, para 7; and Case 48/69 Imperial Chemical Industries Ltd v Commission of the European Communities (Dyestuffs) ECLI:EU:C:1972:70, para 1–6, 54, and 83–87.

34 Office of Fair Trading, ‘Higher Education in England: An OFT Call for Information’ (n 30) paras 1.17, 6.5, and 6.7.

35 Footnote Ibid. at paras 6.10 and 6.14 (emphasis added).

36 An account and analysis is given in S Salop and L White, ‘Policy Watch: Antitrust Goes to College’ (1991) 5 J Econ Perspect 193–202; D Carlton, G Bamberger, and R Epstein ‘Antitrust and Higher Education: Was There a Conspiracy to Restrict Finiancial Aid’ (1995) 26 Rand J Econ 131–147.

37 US v Brown University, 805 F Supp 288 (ED Pa 1992) 292; US v Brown University, 5 F3d at 664. Schools were concerned that hitherto admission had been determined by ability to pay rather than on merit-based criteria: US v Brown University, 805 F Supp 288 (ED Pa 1992) 304–305.

38 US v Brown University, 805 F Supp at 293.

39 Carlton, Bamberger, and Epstein (n 36) 142–144; Compare with the situation in the United Kingdom, in which the regulator sought to discourage Universities from offering discounts: Donald MacLeod, ‘Universities warned against offering cash for places’ (Guardian, 25 May 2006) www.theguardian.com/education/2006/may/25/highereducation.choosingadegree

40 S Salop and L White, ‘Policy Watch: Antitrust Goes to College’ (1991) 5 J Econ Perspect 193, 194–195; Carlton, Bamberger, and Epstein (n 36) 132–133. A key element in the characterisation of the financial aid package is offered before the applicant accepts an offer of a place at the school. This may be distinguished from support that institutions offer to students that have already accepted offers or already commenced study at the school. This latter type of support is not available to prospective customers (students) but is limited to those already in receipt of the education service, cf Office of Fair Trading, ‘Assessment of Market Power’ (OFT 415, September 1999) 6.

41 US v Brown University, 5 F3d at 667–668.

42 See Arizona v Maricopa County 457 US 322 (1982) and California Dental Association v FTC, 526 US 756, 771 (1999) n 10; Goss v Memorial Hosp System, 789 F2d 353 (5th Cir 1986); Northwest Wholesale Stationers, Inc v Pac Stationery & Printing Co, 472 US 284, 105 S Ct 2613, 86 L Ed 2d 202 (1985); Wright v Southern Mono Hosp Dist, 631 F Supp 1294 (ED Cal 1986); Everhart v Jane C Stormont Hosp, 1982-1 Trade Cas (CCH) 64703, 1982 WL 1833 (D Kan 1982); Srikanth (n 15) 938–39; Notes ‘Antitrust and Nonprofit Entities’ (1981) 94 Harv L Rev 802–820, 808–814.; Carlton, Bamberger, and Epstein (n 36) 144–46; P Kolovos ‘Antitrust Law and Nonprofit Organizations: The Law School Accreditation Case’ 71 NYU L Rev (1996) 689–731; ‘Notes: United Charities and the Sherman Act’ (1982) 91 Yale LJ 1593, 1597 fn 25; and T Greaney, ‘Antitrust and Hospital Mergers: Does the Nonprofit Form Affect Competitive Substance?’ (2006) 31 J Health Pol Pol’y L 511, 521–25. Improving Healthcare: A Dose of Competition A Report by The Federal Trade Commission and Department of Justice (July, 2004), chapter 4: www.ftc.gov/sites/default/files/documents/reports/improving-health-care-dose-competition-report-federal-trade-commission-and-department-justice/040723healthcarerpt.pdf

43 US v Brown University, 805 F Supp 288, 300–301 (ED Pa 1992); US v Brown University, 5 F3d at 672.

44 US v Brown University, 5 F3d at 675–678.

45 Srikanth (n 15) 940–43.

46 US v Brown University, 805 F Supp at 678. The Ivy league schools entered settlement agreements so there is no final judgment.

47 See ‘Notes: United Charities and the Sherman Act’ (n 42) 1603–1611.

48 C Cicoria, ‘European Competition Law and Nonprofit Organizations: A Law and Economics Analysis’ (2006) 6 Global Jurist Topics 1, 40–42.

49 Office of Fair Trading, ‘Higher Education in England: An OFT Call for Information’ (n 30) para 6.24–6.30.

50 The importance of choice has also been emphasised by the UK Competition Appeal Tribunal: see, for example, Genzyme v OFT [2004] CAT 4, paras 255, 468 and 585.

51 Office of Fair Trading, ‘Higher Education in England: An OFT Call for Information’ (n 30) para 6.29.

52 Letters, Dangerous combination, September 5, 2013

53 Office of Fair Trading, ‘Higher Education in England: An OFT Call for Information’ (n 30) para 6.35.

54 This contradicts the identified limitation that even, in public service markets, any restriction must be ‘to the benefit of students’ or users: Office of Fair Trading, ‘Higher Education in England: An OFT Call for Information’ (n 30) para 6.35.

55 See Letter to NHS Trusts with Private Patient Units enclosing competition law compliance guidance http://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/20140402161850/http://www.oft.gov.uk/shared_oft/public-markets/PPUs.pdf and Press release: NHS Trusts with Private Patient Units provide assurances to OFT to ensure competition compliance (16 August 2012) https://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/ukgwa/20121003141315/http://www.oft.gov.uk/news-and-updates/press/2012/71-12.

56 Office of Fair Trading Press Release, ‘OFT issues statement of objections against 50 independent schools’ (9 November 2005) https://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/20080908111732/http://www.oft.gov.uk/news/press/2005/214-05.

57 Exchange of Information on Future Fees by Certain Independent Fee–Paying Schools (n 18) paras 1359–1375, 1381–1383 [See SI 2004/1261 of UK Competition Act 1998].

58 Footnote Ibid. at para 1427.

59 E Searing, ‘Charitable (Anti)Trust: The Role of Antitrust Regulation in the Nonprofit Sector’ (2014) 5 Nonprofit Policy Forum 261, 262; Srikanth (n 15) 948, 955.

60 S Rose-Ackerman, ‘Charitable Giving and “Excessive” Fundraising’ (1982) 97 Q J Econ 193–212; S Rose-Ackerman, ‘Altruism, Nonprofits, and Economic Theory’ (n 2) 710–15; T Norgard, ‘How Charitable Is the Sherman Act?’ (1999) 83 Minn L Rev 1515, 1533–34, 1543–45; ‘Notes: United Charities and the Sherman Act’ (n 42) 1598–1600.

61 J Saxton and M Guild, ‘It’s Competition, but Not as We Know It’ (nfpSynergy, October 2010) 4–6, 10–11, 25–28.

62 See for example Rose-Ackerman, ‘Charitable Giving and Excessive Fundraising’ (n 60) 193–212.

63 Philipson and Posner, ‘Antitrust and the Not For profit Sector’ (n 16) 7–9.

64 See ‘Notes: United Charities and the Sherman Act’ (n 42); Office of Fair Trading, ‘Assessment of Market Power’ (n 40) 8.

65 50 F3d 710 (9th Cir 1995). See also Charitable Donation Antitrust Immunity Act of 1997, Pub L No 105-26, 111 Stat 241 (1997). The decision is often contrasted with that of Virginia Vermiculite v WR Grace Co 156 F 3d 535 (4th Cir 1998). However in this later case it is the conduct or the donor rather than the not for profit recipient that is being challenged. In the UK, see ME/1074/02 Completed merger between the Imperial Cancer Research Fund and the Cancer Research Campaign (https://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/ukgwa/20090903210627/http://www.oft.gov.uk/advice_and_resources/resource_base/Mergers_home/mergers_fta/2002/imperial-cancer; ME/4034/09 Seniorlink Eldercare/ Aid Call resulting from the completed merger between Help the Aged and Age Concern, para 10 (https://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/ukgwa/20161129204513/https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/media/555de35440f0b669c4000091/Seniorlink.pdf)

66 ‘Notes: United Charities and the Sherman Act’ (n 42) 1603–1605.

67 E Elhauge, ‘The Scope of Antitrust Process’ (1991) 104 Harv L Rev 667, 672.

68 Office of Fair Trading, ‘Higher Education in England: An OFT Call for Information’ (n 30) paras 1.15, 6.15–6.23; Department for Business, Innovation and Skills, ‘Competition Issues in the Further Education Sector’ (October 2013) BIS Research Paper Number 141, 5 https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/248707/bis-13-1235-competition-issues-in-the-further-education-sector.pdf, noting that ‘The strong focus on social obligations means that many providers need to work closely with other local stakeholders and providers to develop a comprehensive skills offer that meets the needs of their community. While there can be important efficiency gains from working together, cooperation can provide an opportunity for anti-competitive agreements to be made.’

69 Exchange of Information on Future Fees by Certain Independent Fee–Paying Schools (n 18) para 36

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×