Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T02:23:29.056Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

MODEL THEORY OF GALOIS ACTIONS OF TORSION ABELIAN GROUPS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 June 2022

Özlem Beyarslan
Affiliation:
Matematik Bolumu, Boǧaziçi Üniversitesi, 34342 Bebek, Istanbul, Turkey ([email protected])
Piotr Kowalski*
Affiliation:
Instytut Matematyczny, Uniwersytet Wrocławski, pl. Grunwaldzki 2, 50-384 Wrocław, Poland (http://www.math.uni.wroc.pl/~pkowa/)
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We show that the theory of Galois actions of a torsion Abelian group A is companionable if and only if, for each prime p, the p-primary part of A is either finite or it coincides with the Prüfer p-group. We also provide a model-theoretic description of the model companions we obtain.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

A difference field is a field with an endomorphism. If this endomorphism is invertible, then a difference field is the same as an action of the group $({\mathbb {Z}},+)$ by field automorphisms. Model theory of difference fields has been extensively studied for more than 20 years (see, e.g. [Reference Chatzidakis and Hrushovski3, Reference Chatzidakis, Hrushovski and Peterzil4, Reference Macintyre17]). It is also natural to study model theory of fields with actions of an arbitrary (fixed) group, instead of the infinite cyclic group. This topic had not been considered much until recently, we give a short account of earlier works below.

  • Besides the model companion of the theory of algebraically closed fields with automorphisms (ACFA) corresponding to the action of ${\mathbb {Z}}$ , model theory of fields with free group actions has also been considered, which resulted in the theory ACFA $_n$ , see, e.g. [Reference Hrushovski12], [Reference Kikyo and Pillay14], [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 16] and [Reference Moosa and Scanlon19, Proposition 4.12].

  • Actions of the group ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ were considered by Hrushovski, who proved that a model companion does not exist in this case (see [Reference Kikyo13]).

  • Actions of finite groups were considered first by Sjögren in [Reference Sjögren23].

  • Model theory of actions of $({\mathbb {Q}},+)$ on fields was studied in [Reference Medvedev18].

For a fixed group G, the first natural question to be considered is the following: Does a model companion of the theory of fields with G-actions exist? In the examples given above, the corresponding model companions exist, except for the case of the group ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ . If such a model companion exists, then we call this model companion G-transformally closed fields (TCF), and we say that ‘G-TCF exists’.

More recently, Daniel Hoffmann and the second author considered in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10] the case of finite groups (being unaware then of Sjögren’s work from [Reference Sjögren23]). In [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1], the authors of this paper extended some of the results from [Reference Chatzidakis and Hrushovski3] and [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10] into a very natural common context of virtually free groups. This work is a continuation of the general line of research from [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1], however, it goes in a different direction, that is, we consider infinite torsion Abelian groups. Let A be a torsion Abelian group. This paper is almost exclusively devoted to the proof of the following result.

Theorem 1.1. The theory $A-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists if and only if, for each prime p, the p-primary part of A is either finite or it is isomorphic with the Prüfer p-group. Moreover, if the theory $A-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists, then it is simple; and it is strictly simple (that is: simple, not stable and not supersimple) when A is infinite.

Regarding the question of the existence of the theory G-TCF for G coming from a given class of groups, the theorem above is a rare instance of a situation when a full answer is given. For example, we are still far from obtaining a corresponding answer for the class of all finitely generated groups: we showed in [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1] that for virtually free groups the corresponding model companions exist; and we only conjectured in [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1] the opposite implication (this conjecture is confirmed in [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1] in the case of finitely generated commutative groups). It should be also noted that Theorem 1.1 disproves our own [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1, Conjecture 5.12], that is, G-TCF need not exist for a locally virtually free (even locally finite) group G.

Let us fix our (standard) notation here. We denote the set of all prime numbers by ${\mathbb {P}}$ . For $n>0$ , the cyclic group of order n is denoted by $C_n$ , and:

$$ \begin{align*} C_{p^{\infty}}=\operatorname{\mathrm{\underrightarrow{\lim}}}_{n}C_{p^n} \end{align*} $$

is the Prüfer p-group. For any group G and any ordinal number $\alpha $ , we denote by $G^{(\alpha )}$ the direct sum of $\alpha $ copies of G. If a group G acts on a set X, then by $X^G$ we denote the set of invariants of this action. For a field K, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ denotes the (profinite) absolute Galois group of K, that is the group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K^{\operatorname {\mathrm {sep}}}/K)$ , where $K^{\operatorname {\mathrm {sep}}}$ is the separable closure of K.

By a G-field, we mean a field with an action of the group G by field automorphisms. Similarly, we consider G-rings, G-field extensions, etc. By $L_G$ , we denote the natural language of G-fields, where the elements of G serve as unary function symbols.

Remark 1.2. We give here two conditions on an Abelian group A, which are equivalent to the condition appearing in the statement of Theorem 1.1.

  1. (1) The group A does not contain (up to an isomorphism) any of the following two ‘forbidden subgroups’:

    • $C_p^{(\omega )}$ ,

    • $C_p\oplus C_{p^{\infty }}$ .

  2. (2) There is no $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , such that there exists an infinite strictly increasing sequence:

    $$ \begin{align*}C_p^2\cong P_1<P_2<P_3<\ldots,\end{align*} $$
    where each $P_i$ is a finite p-subgroup of A.

We would like to say a few words about the shape of the axioms of the theory A-TCF from the statement of Theorem 1.1. The axioms of ACFA from [Reference Chatzidakis and Hrushovski3] are geometric, that is, they describe the intersections of algebraic varieties with the graph of the generic automorphism. In the case of a finite group, geometric axioms were used in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10] as well, which was the main difference with the approach taken in [Reference Sjögren23]. Using the Bass-Serre theory, the geometric axioms from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10] were ‘glued’ in [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1] to obtain geometric axioms for actions of arbitrary finitely generated virtually free groups. Let us now go back to the axioms from [Reference Sjögren23]. They are not geometric in the above sense, since they describe the properties of certain absolute Galois groups. This is why we call them Galois axioms, and we formalise this notion below. Before that, let us recall that a field K is pseudo algebraically closed (abbreviated PAC), if each absolutely irreducible variety defined over K has a K-rational point.

Definition 1.3. We say that the theory of a G-field K is axiomatised by Galois axioms, if G is the union of its finitely generated subgroups $(G_i)_{i\in I}$ (for convenience, we assume that $0$ is a distinguished element of I and $G_0=\{1\}$ ), such that the theory of the G-field K is implied by the following statements:

  1. (1) the action of G on K is faithful (we say that the G-field K is strict);

  2. (2) K is a perfect field;

  3. (3) for each $i\in I$ , $K^{G_i}$ is PAC;

  4. (4) for each $i\in I$ , we have:

    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(K^{G_i}\right)\cong \mathcal{G}_{i}, \end{align*} $$
    where $(\mathcal {G}_i)_{i\in I}$ is a fixed collection of small profinite groups.

Let us remark here, that the definition of ‘strict’ above extends [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Definition 2.2] in the case of a finite group G.

Clearly, Items $(1)$ and $(2)$ are first order. By [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Chapter 11.3], Item $(3)$ is a first-order condition as well. Since the set of extensions of a field F (inside a fixed algebraic closure of F) of a fixed degree n is ‘uniformly definable’ in F (see, e.g. [Reference Pillay and Polkowska21, Remark 2.6(i)]), and there are finitely many of them in the situation of Definition 1.3 (by the smallness assumption), we see that Item $(4)$ is also first order. We would like to point out that in the case of a group G which is not finitely generated, the field of constants $K^G$ is not definable in the G-field K (it is merely type definable). Hence, there is not much chance for any statement about $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K^G)$ to be first order.

As we have said above, the theory $G-\mathrm {TCF}$ is axiomatised by Galois axioms for a finite G (by [Reference Sjögren23]), which we will also point out in Proposition 2.17. In this paper, we prove a version of this result for torsion Abelian groups satisfying the equivalent conditions from Remark 1.2.

This paper is organised as follows. In Section 2, we collect some general results (originating often from [Reference Sjögren23]) about existentially closed G-fields and we also discuss Hrushovski’s notion of pseudo-existentially closed G-fields. In Section 3, we show a crucial technical result about pronilpotency of certain absolute Galois groups. Section 4 is concerned with the negative (or nonexistence) results. More precisely, we show there the left-to-right implication from Theorem 1.1. Section 5 is about the positive results, that is, we show there the right-to-left implication from Theorem 1.1. In Section 6, we collect several miscellaneous results and observations regarding the model theory of G-fields.

2. General results about G-fields

In this section, we discuss Hrushovski’s notion of pseudo-existentially closed G-fields and we also collect the results about existentially closed G-fields and PAC fields, which will be important in the sequel. We finish this section with some well-known results about chains of theories and we give examples of such chains in the case of group actions on fields.

2.1. Pseudo-existentially closed G-fields and PAC fields

The following notion we learnt from Udi Hrushovski (private communication, 2019). It originated from our attempts to show that if G has a subgroup isomorphic to ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ , then G-TCF does not exist (those attempts will be discussed in Section 6.2).

Definition 2.1. A G-field F is pseudo-existentially closed (abbreviated p.e.c.), if for any G-field extension $F\subseteq K$ , such that the pure field extension $F\subseteq K$ is regular, the G-field F is existentially closed in the G-field K.

We would like to point out that if $G=\{1\}$ , then p.e.c. G-fields are exactly PAC fields (since being PAC is the same as being existentially closed in regular extensions, see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 11.3.5]), which justifies the choice of the term ‘pseudo-existentially closed’ above. We will also use in the sequel the abbreviation ‘e.c.’ for ‘existentially closed’. We recall that a G-field is G-closed if it has no proper algebraic (as pure fields) G-field extensions.

The crucial good property of p.e.c. G-fields is the result below, which is clearly false for e.c. G-fields (consider $H=\{1\}$ ). This result and its proof were pointed out to us by Udi Hrushovski.

Proposition 2.2. Suppose that M is a p.e.c. G-field and $H\leqslant G$ . Then M is a p.e.c. H-field as well.

Proof. Assume that F is a G-field and $F\subseteq K$ is an H-field extension, which is regular (as an extension of pure fields). To conclude the proof, it is enough to construct a field extension of $K\subseteq L$ and an action of G on L, such that $F\subseteq L$ is a G-field extension and $K\subseteq L$ is an H-field extension.

Let W be a set of representatives for $G/H$ , such that $1\in W$ . For each $r\in W$ , we fix a set $rK$ , such that:

  1. (i) $1K=K$ ;

  2. (ii) for all $r,r'\in W$ , if $r\neq r'$ , then $rK\cap r'K=F$ ;

  3. (iii) there is a bijection (denoted by r as well) $r:K\to rK$ , such that for all $x\in F$ , we have $r(x)=r\cdot x$ (the action of G on F).

For any $g\in G$ and $r\in W$ , there are unique $r'\in W$ and $h\in H$ , such that $gr=r'h$ , and we define a bijection $g:rK\to r'K$ by the following commutative diagram:

where $\cdot h$ comes from the given action of H on K. Let us also define:

$$ \begin{align*} Z:=\bigcup_{r\in W}rK. \end{align*} $$

It is easy to see that the above diagram defines an action of G on the set Z, which extends the action of H on K and the action of G on F. For each $r\in W$ , we define a field structure on $rK$ in such a way that $r:K\to rK$ is a field isomorphism. Then for each $g,r,r'$ as above, the map $g:rK\to r'K$ is a field isomorphism as well.

We define now:

$$ \begin{align*} R:=\bigotimes_{r\in W}rK, \end{align*} $$

where the tensor product is taken over the field F. By the universal property of the tensor product (in the category of F-algebras), the action of G on Z uniquely extends to an action of G on R by ring automorphisms. Since the field extension $F\subseteq K$ is regular, the ring R is a domain by [Reference Bourbaki2, Proposition 2 in §17, A.V.141]. Hence, we can take as L the field of fractions of R with the induced action of G.

Remark 2.3. We collect here several observations about e.c., p.e.c. and G-closed fields. Let $H\leqslant G$ .

  1. (0) Any G-closed G-field is perfect [Reference Sjögren23, Proof of Theorem 1], and if K is a perfect G-field, then $K^G$ is also perfect [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Lemma 3.2].

  2. (1) We will give a quick argument showing that a G-field K is e.c. if and only if K is both p.e.c. and G-closed.

    The left-to-right implication is clear (two weakenings). For the right-to-left implication, we assume that K is a G-closed G-field and $K\subseteq M$ is a G-field extension. It is enough to show that the field extension $K\subseteq M$ is regular. By Item $(0)$ above, K is perfect, hence, this extension is separable. Since K is G-closed, K is relatively algebraically closed in M (note that this relative algebraic closure is a G-subfield of M), therefore, the field extension $K\subseteq M$ is regular indeed.

  3. (2) It is also clear that if K is a G-field, which is H-closed, then K is G-closed as well.

  4. (3) Proposition 2.2 says that the opposite happens with the notion of p.e.c.: if K is a p.e.c. G-field, then K is a p.e.c. H-field.

  5. (4) It is easy to find examples of e.c. G-fields, which are not e.c. H-fields (taking $H=\{1\}$ ).

  6. (5) We still do not know whether the existence of G-TCF implies the existence of H-TCF (see Conjecture 6.6 for a special case).

  7. (6) The notion of a p.e.c. G-field and Proposition 2.2 should generalise to the context of an arbitrary theory (instead of the theory of fields) having a stable completion, which is the context considered in [Reference Hoffmann7].

The following result will be crucial in the sequel.

Proposition 2.4. If K is a p.e.c. G-field and G is finitely generated, then the field $K^G$ (the field of constants) is PAC.

Proof. Let us denote $K^G$ by C, and we take an absolutely irreducible variety V over C. Then, the field extension $C\subseteq C(V)$ is regular (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Section 10.2]). Therefore, the ring $R:=C(V)\otimes _CK$ is a domain (again by [Reference Bourbaki2, Proposition 2 in §17, A.V.141]). We define a G-ring structure on R, such that $K\subseteq R$ is a G-ring extension and $R^G=C(V)$ in the obvious way. Then $V(R^G)\neq \emptyset $ , since there is an $R^G$ -rational point corresponding to the identity map. Let L be the fraction field of R. Then the G-action on R extends uniquely to a G-action on L by field automorphisms.

Therefore, we have:

  • the extension $K\subseteq L$ is a G-field extension;

  • the field extension $K\subseteq L$ is again regular, since $L\cong _KK(V_K)$ and $V_K$ is absolutely irreducible, where we consider the base change variety here: $V_K:=V\times _{\operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}}(C)}{\operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}}(K)}$ ;

  • the statement ‘ $V(L^G)\neq \emptyset $ ’ is first order (since G is finitely generated).

Since K is a p.e.c. G-field, we obtain that $V(K^G)\neq \emptyset $ , which finishes the proof.

Corollary 2.5. Suppose that K is a p.e.c. G-field and $H\leqslant G$ is a finitely generated subgroup. Then the field $K^H$ is PAC. In particular, $K=K^{\{1\}}$ is a PAC field.

Proof. It follows directly from Propositions 2.2 and 2.4.

Remark 2.6. We would like to comment here how the results of this subsection are related to [Reference Sjögren23].

  1. (1) It is stated in [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 2] that if G is an arbitrary group and K is an existentially closed G-field, then $K^G$ is PAC. The proof of [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 2] is basically the same as the proof of Proposition 2.4 above, and we believe that one still has to assume that G is finitely generated for this proof to work (although we do not have a counterexample for the statement with an arbitrary group G).

  2. (2) In [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 3], it is stated that if K is an existentially closed G-field, then K is PAC. Corollary 2.5 is more genera, and its proof is simpler, since it is using Proposition 2.2.

2.2. Existentially closed G-fields

In this subsection, we go through several results which originally appeared in [Reference Sjögren23], namely: Theorems 4, 5 and 6 there. We do it for the sake of completeness and we would like to discuss some issues concerning [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 6] as well.

Suppose that K is a G-field, $C=K^G$ and:

$$ \begin{align*}\varphi:G\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Aut}}(K/C)\end{align*} $$

corresponds to the action of G on K. For a group G, we denote the profinite completion of G by $\widehat {G}$ . For a profinite group $\mathcal {G}$ , we denote the universal Frattini cover of $\mathcal {G}$ by $\widetilde {\mathcal {G}}$ (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Chapter 22]). For a cardinal number $\kappa $ and $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we denote the free pro-p group of rank $\kappa $ by $\widehat {F}_{\kappa }(p)$ (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Remark 17.4.7]).

The lemma below originates from [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 4]. It is also related to [Reference Hoffmann8, Proposition 5.1], where a version of this lemma is proved in a more general context (see Remark 2.3(6)).

Lemma 2.7. There is a unique continuous epimorphism:

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha:\widehat{G}\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(\left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K\right)/C\right), \end{align*} $$

such that the following diagram is commutative:

Moreover, if $(K,G)$ is p.e.c., and G is finitely generated, then the map $\alpha $ is an isomorphism.

Proof. Let us consider a finite Galois extension $C\subseteq C'$ , such that $C'\subseteq K$ . We consider the restriction map:

$$ \begin{align*}r:G\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C'/C).\end{align*} $$

It is enough to show that the map r is onto. Let $H:=r(G)$ and $C_0:=(C')^{H}$ . Then G acts trivially on $C_0$ , hence, $C_0\subseteq C$ and $H=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C'/C)$ , which we needed to show.

For the moreover part, it is shown in the proof of [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 4] (in the e.c. case) that G and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K/C)$ have the same finite quotients, which is enough (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Corollary 16.10.8]), since $\widehat {G}$ is small being topologically finitely generated, which follows from the assumption that G is finitely generated. We sketch below the argument given in [Reference Sjögren23]. Let $\pi :G\to H$ be an epimorphism and $\iota :H\to S_m$ be an embedding, where $S_m$ is the symmetric group on $m=|H|$ generators (m is finite). Then the field of rational functions $K':=K(t_1,\ldots ,t_m)$ has a natural structure of a G-extension of K (given by $\iota \circ \pi $ ). It is easy to see that:

$$ \begin{align*} C(t_1,\ldots,t_m)^H=\left(K'\right)^G, \end{align*} $$

hence, the field of constants of $K'$ has a Galois extension with Galois group isomorphic to H. Since this last condition is first order (G is finitely generated), K is p.e.c., and the extension $K\subset K'$ is regular, the result follows.

We recall (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Definition 22.5.1]) that a continuous epimorphism of profinite groups $f:\mathcal {G}\to \mathcal {H}$ is a Frattini cover, if for any closed subgroup $\mathcal {G}_0\leqslant \mathcal {G}$ , we have that $\mathcal {G}_0=\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $f(\mathcal {G}_0)=\mathcal {H}$ . We give here a connection between Frattini covers and extensions of group actions. It is just a reformulation of [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Lemma 3.7] (see also [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Remark 3.8]).

Lemma 2.8. We assume that:

  • $C\subseteq K$ is a finite Galois extension and $G=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K/C)$ ;

  • $\mathcal {G}_0\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)$ is a closed subgroup;

  • $C':=\left (C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {sep}}}\right )^{\mathcal {G}_0}$ ;

  • $K':=C'K=\left (C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {sep}}}\right )^{\mathcal {G}_0\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)}$ .

Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $K\subseteq K'$ is a G-field extension, where the G-field structure on $K'$ is given by $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K'/C')$ ;

  2. (2) $\mathrm {res}(\mathcal {G}_0)=G=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K/C)$ , where the map:

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\longrightarrow G \end{align*} $$
    is the restriction epimorphism.

Moreover, if any of the equivalent two conditions above holds, then we have:

$$ \begin{align*} [K':K]=[\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C):\mathcal{G}_0]. \end{align*} $$

Proof. We just point out here that both the conditions are equivalent to the fact that the restriction map:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K'/C')\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K/C) \end{align*} $$

is an isomorphism, so $K'$ gets the G-field structure (extending the one on K) using this restriction isomorphism.

We will use the following consequence of an implication from Lemma 2.8 several times.

Proposition 2.9. Suppose that we have a tower of fields $K_2\subseteq K_1\subseteq K$ , such that $K/K_1$ and $K/K_2$ are finite Galois extensions and we set:

$$ \begin{align*} H:=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K/K_1),\ \ \ \ G:=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K/K_2). \end{align*} $$

Assume that for $i\in \{1,2\}$ , $\mathcal {G}_i\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ are closed subgroups, such that:

  1. (1) for $i\in \{1,2\}$ , we have $\mathrm {res}(\mathcal {G}_i)=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K/K_i)$ ,

  2. (2) $\mathcal {G}_1\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)=\mathcal {G}_2\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ and $\mathcal {G}_1\subseteq \mathcal {G}_2$ .

Let $K'$ (respectively $K''$ ) be the H-field (respectively G-field) extension of K given by Lemma 2.8. Then $K'=K''$ and the G-structure on $K'$ expands the H-structure on $K'$ .

Proof. We define:

$$ \begin{align*} C':=\left(K^{\operatorname{\mathrm{sep}}}\right)^{\mathcal{G}_1},\ \ \ \ C'':=\left(K^{\operatorname{\mathrm{sep}}}\right)^{\mathcal{G}_2}. \end{align*} $$

Then we have:

$$ \begin{align*} K'=C'K,\ \ \ \ K''=C''K, \end{align*} $$

and since $\mathcal {G}_1\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)=\mathcal {G}_2\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ , we get that $K'=K''$ .

We have the following commutative diagram:

By the description from Lemma 2.8 of both the G-field structure and the H-field structure on $K'$ , we see that the above diagram implies that the G-action expands the H-action.

Remark 2.10. After assuming Item $(1)$ from Proposition 2.9, Item $(2)$ is equivalent to the following equality:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{G}_2\cap \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_1)=\mathcal{G}_1. \end{align*} $$

The next result generalises an implication from Lemma 2.8 (a version of it, in a more general context, appeared as [Reference Hoffmann7, Corollary 3.47]).

Proposition 2.11. If $(K,G)$ is G-closed, then the restriction map:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C)\end{align*} $$

is a Frattini cover. Hence, if C is PAC and $(K,G)$ is G-closed (for example, when $(K,G)$ is e.c. and G is finitely generated), then this restriction map is the universal Frattini cover.

Proof. Since K is G-closed, we get that C is a perfect field by Remark 2.3(0). Let us consider the restriction map:

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C\right), \end{align*} $$

and we take a closed subgroup $\mathcal {G}\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)$ , such that $\alpha (\mathcal {G})=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}\left (C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K/C\right )$ . It is enough to show that $\mathcal {G}=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)$ . Since $\ker (\alpha )\mathcal {G}=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)$ , we get that:

$$ \begin{align*} \left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\ker(\alpha)}\cap \left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\mathcal{G}}=C. \end{align*} $$

Since the extension $C\subseteq \left (C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\right )^{\ker (\alpha )}$ is Galois ( $\ker (\alpha )$ is clearly a normal subgroup), we get that $(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^{\ker (\alpha )}$ is linearly disjoint from $(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^{\mathcal {G}}$ over C using, for example, the remark below the proof of Corollary 2.5.2 in [Reference Fried and Jarden5] (the remark is for finite extensions, but since both being Galois and linearly disjoint are locally finite notions, it works in general). Since we have:

$$ \begin{align*} C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K\subseteq \left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\ker(\alpha)}, \end{align*} $$

we get that $C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K$ is linearly disjoint from $(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^{\mathcal {G}}$ over C. Since K is G-closed, it is perfect. Hence, the field $C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K$ is perfect as well, and the field extension $C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K\subseteq K$ is regular. Therefore (by the definition of regularity), K is linearly disjoint from $C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}$ over $C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K$ . By the tower property for linear disjointness (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Lemma 2.5.3]), we finally get that K is linearly disjoint from $(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^{\mathcal {G}}$ over C. Therefore, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} K(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}})^{\mathcal{G}}\cong \mathrm{Frac}\left(K\otimes_C(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}})^{\mathcal{G}}\right), \end{align*} $$

hence, the action of G on K extends to an action of G to $K(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^{\mathcal {G}}$ . Since $(K,G)$ is G-closed, we get that $K(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^{\mathcal {G}}=K$ , so $(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^{\mathcal {G}}\subseteq C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K$ , and then, by linear disjointness, $(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^{\mathcal {G}}=C$ . By Galois theory, we get that $\mathcal {G}=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)$ , which finishes the proof.

Remark 2.12. It is easy to see that the opposite implication to the one appearing in Proposition 2.11 is not true. It is enough to take an algebraically closed field C, $K=C(X)$ and $G={\mathbb {Z}}$ acting on K in the ‘classical difference way’, that is $\sigma (X)=X+1$ , where $\sigma $ is a generator of the group ${\mathbb {Z}}$ .

Our first corollary is exactly [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 5] (it was also generalised to a more abstract context in [Reference Hoffmann8, Corollary 5.6]).

Corollary 2.13. If $(K,G)$ is e.c. and G is finitely generated, then we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\cong \widetilde{\widehat{G}}.\end{align*} $$

Proof. It follows directly from Lemma 2.7 and Proposition 2.11.

The next corollary is much weaker than the statement in [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 6], which will be discussed in Remark 2.18(2).

Corollary 2.14. Suppose that $(K,G)$ is e.c., then we have the following.

  1. (1) There is an epimorphism:

    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\longrightarrow \ker\left(\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\to \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C\right)\right). \end{align*} $$
  2. (2) If G is finitely generated, then:

    $$ \begin{align*} \ker(\widetilde{\widehat{G}}\to \widehat{G})\cong \ker\left(\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\to \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C\right)\right), \end{align*} $$
    and there is a monomorphism:
    $$ \begin{align*} \ker(\widetilde{\widehat{G}}\to \widehat{G})\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K). \end{align*} $$

Proof. Since the extension $C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K\subseteq K$ is regular (as in the proof of Proposition 2.11), the restriction map:

$$ \begin{align*} r:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\to \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K) \end{align*} $$

is onto. By Galois theory, we have the following isomorphism:

$$ \begin{align*} \ker\left(\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\to \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C\right)\right)\cong \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K\right) \end{align*} $$

showing Item $(1)$ .

For Item $(2)$ , by Corollary 2.13 we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \ker(\widetilde{\widehat{G}}\to \widehat{G})\cong \ker\left(\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\to \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C\right)\right). \end{align*} $$

Therefore, the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K)$ is projective (as a closed subgroup of the profinite projective group $\widetilde {\widehat {G}}$ , see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 22.4.7]), hence, the map r above has a section, which gives the result.

We point out below that for a finite group G, the theory $G-\mathrm {TCF}$ is axiomatised by Galois axioms, which was shown in [Reference Sjögren23] and [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10]. We include here, a version of the statement from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10], which is convenient for us to work with. For the proof of this version, we need the following result, which may be folklore. We recall that for a profinite group $\mathcal {G}$ , the rank of $\mathcal {G}$ , denoted $\mathrm {rk}(\mathcal {G})$ , is the minimal cardinality of a set of topological generators of $\mathcal {G}$ .

Proposition 2.15. Assume that $\mathcal {H}$ is a profinite group of finite rank. Then, any continuous epimorphism $\pi :\widetilde {\mathcal {H}}\to \mathcal {H}$ is a (the universal) Frattini cover.

Proof. The proof consists of two steps.

Step 1: The result holds if $\mathcal {H}$ is a pro-p group.

Proof of Step 1

Let $r=\mathrm {rk}(\mathcal {H})$ . By [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Lemma 22.7.4], there is an epimorphism $\mathcal {H}\to C_p^r$ (which is a Frattini cover). By [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Lemma 22.5.4], we can assume that $\mathcal {H}=C_p^r$ .

Let us take $B\subset C_p^r$ , such that $|B|=r$ . Since r is finite, B generates the group $C_p^r$ if and only if B is a basis of $C_p^r$ considered as an ${\mathbb {F}}_p$ -vector space. Therefore, the group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}(C_p^r)=\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}_r({\mathbb {F}}_p)$ acts transitively on the family of sets of generators of $C_p^r$ of size r.

By [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Corollary 22.5.3], $\mathrm {rk}(\widetilde {\mathcal {H}})=r$ , and we fix $\widetilde {B}$ , which is a set of generators of $\widetilde {\mathcal {H}}$ of size r. Let B be the image of $\widetilde {B}$ by the universal Frattini cover map and $B':=\pi (\widetilde {B})$ . Then, both B and $B'$ have size r and generate $C_p^r$ . Hence, there is an automorphism of $C_p^r$ taking B to $B'$ . Therefore, $\pi $ is the composition of the universal Frattini cover map and this last automorphism, thus, $\pi $ is a Frattini cover itself.

Let us take a closed subgroup $\mathcal {G}\leqslant \widetilde {\mathcal {H}}$ , such that:

$$ \begin{align*} \pi|_{\mathcal{G}}:\mathcal{G}\longrightarrow \mathcal{H} \end{align*} $$

is a Frattini cover (it exists by [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Lemma 22.5.6]). We aim to show that $\mathcal {G}=\widetilde {\mathcal {H}}$ . For necessary background regarding profinite Sylow theory, we refer the reader to the beginning of Section 3 (see also [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 22.9.2]).

Step 2: For each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , any p-Sylow subgroup of $\mathcal {G}$ is a p-Sylow subgroup of $\widetilde {\mathcal {H}}$ as well.

Proof of Step 2

Let $\mathcal {Q}$ be a p-Sylow subgroup of $\mathcal {G}$ . We have $\mathcal {Q} = \mathcal {P} \cap \mathcal {G}$ for a p-Sylow subgroup $\mathcal {P}$ of $\widetilde {\mathcal {H}}$ by [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 22.9.2(a)]. Since $\pi (\mathcal {G}) = \mathcal {H}$ , we get that $\pi (\mathcal {Q})$ and $\pi (\mathcal {P})$ are p-Sylow subgroups of $\mathcal {H}$ (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 22.9.2(c)]), and, thus, $\pi (\mathcal {Q})=\pi (\mathcal {P})$ . By Step 1, the map:

$$ \begin{align*} \pi|_{\mathcal{P}}:\mathcal{P}\longrightarrow \pi(\mathcal{P}) \end{align*} $$

is a Frattini cover, and then we obtain that $\mathcal {Q}=\mathcal {P}$ (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Definition 22.5.1]).

By Step 2, for any normal open subgroup $\mathcal {N}$ of $\widetilde {\mathcal {H}}$ , any p-Sylow subgroup of $\mathcal {G}\mathcal {N}/\mathcal {N}$ is of the form $\mathcal {P}\mathcal {N}/\mathcal {N}$ for a p-Sylow subgroup $\mathcal {P}$ of $\widetilde {\mathcal {H}}$ , and, thus, it is a p-Sylow subgroup of $\widetilde {\mathcal {H}}/\mathcal {N}$ . It follows that $\mathcal {G}\mathcal {N}/\mathcal {N} = \widetilde {\mathcal {H}}/\mathcal {N}$ for any $\mathcal {N}$ as above, and, therefore, we obtain that $\mathcal {G} = \widetilde {\mathcal {H}}$ .

Remark 2.16.

  1. (1) The statement of Step 1 from the proof of Proposition 2.15 has already appeared in [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1] as Lemma 4.4. Unfortunately, we gave an erroneous proof of [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1, Lemma 4.4] (confusing two universal properties).

  2. (2) In the case of pro-p groups, Proposition 2.15 can be generalised to the following statement, which we will need in the sequel:

    $$ \begin{align*} &{Any continuous epimorphism of pro-}p \ {groups of the same finite rank}\\ &{is a Frattini cover}. \end{align*} $$
    It can be proved in the same way as Step 1 in the proof of Proposition 2.15 was shown. Namely, if $\pi :\mathcal {G}\to \mathcal {H}$ is such an epimorphism, and the rank is r, then, by [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Lemma 22.5.4], there are Frattini cover maps:
    $$ \begin{align*} p_1:\mathcal{G}\longrightarrow C_p^r,\ \ \ \ p_2:\mathcal{H}\longrightarrow C_p^r. \end{align*} $$
    Hence, we can replace $\pi $ with $p_2\circ \pi $ and conclude as in the proof of Step 1 above.
  3. (3) It is easy to see that not every epimorphism of profinite (even finite) groups of the same finite rank is a Frattini cover, consider, for example, the following epimorphism:

    $$ \begin{align*} C_6^2\longrightarrow C_6\times C_3. \end{align*} $$

We now point out that for a finite group G, the theory G-TCF is axiomatised by Galois axioms from Definition 1.3.

Proposition 2.17. If G is finite, then a G-field K is existentially closed if and only if K is strict, perfect, the field of constants $C:=K^G$ is PAC and:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\cong \widetilde{G}. \end{align*} $$

Proof. For the left-to-right implication, we notice first that K is strict by [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Lemma 3.4] (see also the remark right after Definition 1.3). Using Remark 2.3(0) and Remark 2.3(1), we obtain that K is perfect. By Proposition 2.4, C is PAC, and by Corollary 2.13, we get that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)\cong \widetilde {G}$ .

For the right-left implication, we observe that C is also perfect (since K is perfect and the extension $C\subseteq K$ is finite) and $C\subseteq K$ is a finite Galois extension, such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K/C)\cong G$ (since G is finite and K is strict). Therefore, the pair $(C,K)$ satisfies the assumptions of [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Theorem 3.29]. By Proposition 2.15 and the assumption $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)\cong \widetilde {G}$ , the restriction map $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)\to \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K/C)$ is a Frattini cover, thus, the pair $(C, K)$ is G-closed in the sense of [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Definition 3.18] (or, equivalently, the G-field K is G-closed by Lemma 2.8). We conclude the proof by using the implication $(4)\Rightarrow (1)$ of [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Theorem 3.29].

Remark 2.18. We would like to point out several general observations concerning Galois axioms and absolute Galois groups.

  1. (1) The original theory ACFA( $={\mathbb {Z}}-\mathrm {TCF}$ ) is not axiomatised by Galois axioms. To see that, we notice first that the Galois axioms in the case of a difference field $(K,\sigma )$ say that K is algebraically closed and $C=\mathrm {Fix}(\sigma )$ is pseudofinite.

    By [Reference Hrushovski11, Section 13.3], any model of ACFA of characteristic $0$ has infinite transcendence degree over ${\mathbb {Q}}$ . By [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Theorems 18.5.6 and 18.6.1], for almost all (in the sense of the Haar measure) $\sigma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}({\mathbb {Q}})$ , the field $\operatorname {\mathrm {Fix}}(\sigma )$ is pseudofinite. Hence, such a difference field $({\mathbb {Q}}^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}},\sigma )$ satisfies the Galois axioms, but it is not existentially closed.

  2. (2) It is stated in [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 6] that if G is finitely generated and finitely presented, and K is an e.c. G-field, then we have:

    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\cong \ker\left(\widetilde{\widehat{G}}\longrightarrow \widehat{G}\right). \end{align*} $$
    The main part of the proof of [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 6] is an argument, which is supposed to show that the monomorphism appearing in Corollary 2.14 is actually an isomorphism. We do not know how to make this argument work, we comment more on it below.
    1. (a) The monomorphism from Corollary 2.14 is an isomorphism in the case of a finite group G, which was shown in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Theorem 3.40(2)].

    2. (b) In [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1, Section 4], we use [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 6] to show [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1, Theorem 4.7] saying that if G is a finitely generated virtually free group, which is neither free nor finite, then the theory G-TCF is not simple, since the absolute Galois group of underlying fields of models of G-TCF are not small. However, if a profinite groups is small, then its image by a continuous epimorphism is also small. Therefore, in order to show [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1, Theorem 4.7], it is enough to use just Corollary 2.14 instead of [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 6].

    3. (c) Nick Ramsey communicated to us a proof of the result saying that for G finitely generated and virtually free, the theory G-TCF is NSOP $_1$ . However, this proof seems to be using the full version of [Reference Sjögren23, Theorem 6].

    4. (d) Example 2.21(2) gives a counterexample for the isomorphism:

      $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\cong \ker\left(\widetilde{\widehat{G}}\longrightarrow \widehat{G}\right)\end{align*} $$
      in the case of $G=C_{p^{\infty }}$ , which is obviously not finitely generated.
    5. (e) Similar issues were discussed in a more general context in [Reference Hoffmann8] (see [Reference Hoffmann8, Conjecture 5.7] and [Reference Hoffmann8, Remark 5.8]).

2.3. Chains of theories

In this subsection, we collect several well-known results about chains of theories. They can be found, for example, in [Reference Medvedev18] or [Reference Kasal and Pierce20], but we include them here for the sake of completeness.

Let L be a language and T be an L-theory. It is easy to see that T is closed under consequences (that is: $T\models \phi $ if and only if $\phi \in T$ ) if and only if:

$$ \begin{align*} T=\bigcap_{M\models T}\operatorname{\mathrm{Th}}(M). \end{align*} $$

From now on, all the theories we consider are closed under consequences.

Suppose that $L\subseteq L'$ are languages, T is an L-theory and $T'$ is an $L'$ -theory. We have the following obvious result.

Fact 2.19. The following are equivalent.

  1. (1) $T\subseteq T'$ .

  2. (2) $\mathrm {Mod}(T')\subseteq \mathrm {Mod}(T)$ ’, i.e. for each $M'\models T'$ , we have $M'\models T$ .

For the general notion of a model companion of the theory T, we refer the reader to [Reference Hodges6, Section 7.1]. If a model companion of T exists, then it is unique and we denote it by $T^{\mathrm {mc}}$ . All the particular theories considered in this paper are universal, hence, inductive, and then a model companion exists if and only if the class of existentially closed models of T is elementary, and then $T^{\mathrm {mc}}$ coincides with the axiomatisation of this class. The following result is crucial and it appeared in [Reference Medvedev18] and [Reference Kasal and Pierce20].

Proposition 2.20. Suppose we have an increasing sequence of languages $(L_m)_{m>0}$ and $L_m$ -theories $(T_m)_{m>0}$ . If the model companions $(T^{\mathrm {mc}}_m)_m$ form an increasing sequence as well, then the model companion of $T_{\infty }:=\bigcup _m T_m$ exists and we have:

$$ \begin{align*} T_{\infty}^{\mathrm{mc}}=\bigcup_{m=1}^{\infty}T^{\mathrm{mc}}_m. \end{align*} $$

Moreover, if all the theories $T^{\mathrm {mc}}_m$ are simple, then the theory $T_{\infty }^{\mathrm {mc}}$ is simple as well.

Proof. Let us denote:

$$ \begin{align*} L_{\infty}:=\bigcup_{m=1}^{\infty}L_m,\ \ \ T^{\prime}_{\infty}:=\bigcup_{m=1}^{\infty}T^{\mathrm{mc}}_m. \end{align*} $$

It is easy to see, and it is pointed out, e.g. in [Reference Medvedev18, Theorem 2] that $T^{\prime }_{\infty }$ inherits all the ‘local’ properties enjoyed by all the theories $T^{\mathrm {mc}}_m$ . In particular, $T^{\prime }_{\infty }$ is model complete, and if all the theories $T^{\mathrm {mc}}_m$ are simple, then the theory $T^{\prime }_{\infty }$ is simple as well. Therefore, it is enough to show that each model of $T_{\infty }$ embeds into a model of $T^{\prime }_{\infty }$ . We will actually show that this last embedding property is also ‘local’.

Let us fix $M\models T_{\infty }$ . We need to show that the theory $\mathrm {diag}^+(M)\cup T^{\prime }_{\infty }$ is consistent, where $\mathrm {diag}^+(M)$ is the set of all atomic $L_{\infty }$ -sentences with parameters from M which are true in M. Since we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{diag}^+(M):=\bigcup_{m=1}^{\infty}\mathrm{diag}^+\left(M|_{L_m}\right), \end{align*} $$

the result follows.

Example 2.21. We give here an argument showing that for any $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , the theory $C_{p^{\infty }}-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists, which may be considered as a ‘baby case’ of the right-to-left implication in Theorem 1.1.

  1. (1) By Fact 2.19 and Proposition 2.20, it is enough to check that if $(K,\sigma )\models C_{p^{m+1}}-\mathrm {TCF}$ , then $(K,\sigma ^p)\models C_{p^{m}}-\mathrm {TCF}$ . Let $C=\operatorname {\mathrm {Fix}}(\sigma )$ and $C'=\operatorname {\mathrm {Fix}}(\sigma ^p)$ . Consider the following commutative diagram with exact rows:

    where the description of the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)$ comes from Proposition 2.17. Hence, we have:
    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(C'\right)=\mathrm{res}^{-1}\left(pC_{p^{m+1}}\right)=p{\mathbb{Z}}_p\cong {\mathbb{Z}}_p. \end{align*} $$
    Since $C\subseteq C'$ is a finite field extension and C is a (perfect) PAC field, then $C'$ is (perfect) and PAC as well [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Corollary 11.2.5]. Hence, $(K,\sigma ^p)$ satisfies the Galois axioms for the theory $C_{p^{m}}-\mathrm {TCF}$ by Proposition 2.17.
  2. (2) By Item $(1)$ , it is easy to see that if K is an e.c. $C_{p^{\infty }}$ -field, then we have:

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\cong {\mathbb{Z}}_p.\end{align*} $$
  3. (3) If A is any divisible group, K is an A-field, and $C=K^A$ , then $C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K=C$ , since there are no nontrivial homomorphisms from a divisible group into a profinite group. Therefore, for an A-closed field K, the extension $C\subseteq K$ is regular (since C is perfect and $C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K = C$ ), hence, C is algebraically closed (since, by linear disjointness, $KC^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}$ has a natural structure of an A-extension of K). In particular, if $K\models C_{p^{\infty }}-\mathrm {TCF}$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)=1$ , where $C=K^{C_{p^{\infty }}}$ is the field of absolute constants.

Example 2.22. We discuss here what may happen if the model companions from Proposition 2.20 exist, but they do not form an increasing chain.

  1. (1) The theories $(C_{p^{m}}^2-\mathrm {TCF})_{m>0}$ do not form an increasing chain. To see that let us take:

    $$ \begin{align*}(K,\sigma,\tau)\models C_{p^{2}}^2-\mathrm{TCF},\ \ \ C=\operatorname{\mathrm{Fix}}(\sigma,\tau),\ \ \ C'=\operatorname{\mathrm{Fix}}(\sigma^p,\tau^p).\end{align*} $$
    Then, we have:
    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)/\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C')\cong \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C'/C)\cong C_p^2.\end{align*} $$
    By Proposition 2.17 and [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 22.7.6] (this is a result of Tate saying that projective pro-p groups are pro-p free), we get $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)\cong \widehat {F}_2(p)$ . Since $[\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C):\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C')]=p^2$ , we get by [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 17.6.2] (the profinite Nielsen-Schreier formula) that:
    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(C'\right)\cong \widehat{F}_{p^2+1}(p)\ncong \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C).\end{align*} $$
    In particular, by Proposition 2.17, the $C_p^2$ -field $(C',\sigma ^p,\tau ^p)$ is not existentially closed, so we get:
    $$ \begin{align*}C_{p}^2-\mathrm{TCF}\nsubseteq C_{p^{2}}^2-\mathrm{TCF}.\end{align*} $$
    This observation can not be immediately made into a proof of the nonexistence of the theory $C_{p^{\infty }}^2-\mathrm {TCF}$ , for which we will need the results of Section 3.
  2. (2) As was noted in [Reference Kasal and Pierce20, Theorem 4], a model companion of the theory $T_{\infty }$ (in the notation from Proposition 2.20) may still exist, even when the theories $(T^{\mathrm {mc}}_m)_m$ do not form an increasing chain. We come across such a situation in the case of actions of torsion Abelian groups. Namely, let us define:

    $$ \begin{align*} C_{{\mathbb{P}}}:=\bigoplus_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}C_p\cong \operatorname{\mathrm{\underrightarrow{\lim}}}_mC_{p_1\ldots p_m}, \end{align*} $$
    where ${\mathbb {P}}=(p_i)_{i>0}$ is an enumeration of the set of all primes. Then, one can see (similarly as in Item $(1)$ above) that:
    $$ \begin{align*} C_2-\mathrm{TCF}\nsubseteq C_6-\mathrm{TCF}, \end{align*} $$
    but (by Theorem 1.1) the theory $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -TCF still exists.

Remark 2.23. The situation from Proposition 2.20 also appears in a differential context. In [Reference Kowalski16], the second author gave geometric axioms of the model companion of the theory of fields with finitely many commuting Hasse-Schmidt derivations using increasing chains of theories. This last result was generalised in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski9] to actions of formal groups on fields (an iterative Hasse-Schmidt derivation corresponds to an action of the formalisation of the additive group).

3. Absolute Galois groups

In this section, we begin our proof of Theorem 1.1 (the main result of this paper) by describing the absolute Galois groups of certain fields of invariants.

First, we collect several notions from the theory of profinite groups, which we will often use in the sequel without any references. Proofs of these results can be found in [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Chapter 22.9]. The classical Sylow theory for finite groups generalises smoothly to the profinite context after replacing the notion of a p-subgroup with the notion of a closed pro-p subgroup. In particular, for $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ and a profinite group $\mathcal {G}$ , p-Sylow subgroups of $\mathcal {G}$ exist, and they are conjugate. We also have the corresponding results about pronilpotent groups, that is: a profinite group $\mathcal {G}$ is pronilpotent if and only if it is the product of its unique p-Sylow subgroups. If $\mathcal {G}$ is a pronilpotent group and $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , then we denote by $\mathcal {G}_{(p)}$ the unique p-Sylow subgroup of $\mathcal {G}$ . Throughout this section, ‘cl’ denotes the topological closure (in an ambient profinite group).

We will need a very general result about pronilpotent groups stated below. It may be folklore, but we were unable to find it in the literature.

Proposition 3.1. Let $\mathcal {G}$ be a profinite group, $(I,\leqslant )$ be a directed partially ordered set and $(P_i)_{i\in I}$ be a direct system of closed pronilpotent subgroups of $\mathcal {G}$ (ordered by inclusion). Then, the subgroup:

$$ \begin{align*}P_{\infty}:=\mathrm{cl}\left(\bigcup_{i\in I}P_i\right)\end{align*} $$

is pronilpotent as well.

Proof. For each $i\in I$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*}P_i=\prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}(P_i)_{(p)}.\end{align*} $$

By [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 22.9.2(a)], for each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we get that $\left ((P_i)_{(p)}\right )_{i\in I}$ is a direct system of pro-p groups (ordered by inclusion). For $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we define:

$$ \begin{align*} P_{\infty,p}:=\mathrm{cl}\left(\bigcup_{i\in I}(P_i)_{(p)}\right). \end{align*} $$

Since for each $i\in I$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*} P_i\subseteq \prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}P_{\infty,p}, \end{align*} $$

(it follows from $(P_i)_{(p)}\subseteq P_{\infty ,p}$ for each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ ), we obtain that:

$$ \begin{align*} P_{\infty}\subseteq \prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}P_{\infty,p}. \end{align*} $$

Therefore, it is enough to show that each $P_{\infty ,p}$ is a pro-p group. To ease the notation, we assume that each $P_i$ is a pro-p group, and we aim to show that $P_{\infty }$ is a pro-p group as well.

Let us fix a p-Sylow subgroup $P\leqslant \mathcal {G}$ . For each $i\in I$ , we define:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{X}_i:=\left\{g\in \mathcal{G}\ |\ P_i\subseteq gPg^{-1}\right\}. \end{align*} $$

Since for any fixed $x\in \mathcal {G}$ , the map $g\mapsto g^{-1}xg$ is continuous, it is easy to see that for each $i\in I$ , the set $\mathcal {X}_i$ is closed. Since all p-Sylow subgroups of $\mathcal {G}$ are conjugate, each $\mathcal {X}_i$ is nonempty and $(\mathcal {X}_i)_{i\in I}$ a direct system ordered by the reversed inclusion. Since $\mathcal {G}$ is compact, we get that:

$$ \begin{align*} \bigcap_{i\in I}\mathcal{X}_i\neq \emptyset. \end{align*} $$

Let us take $g\in \bigcap _{i\in I}\mathcal {X}_i$ . Then for each $i\in I$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*} P_i\subseteq gPg^{-1}. \end{align*} $$

Since $gPg^{-1}$ is pro-p, $P_{\infty }$ is also pro-p, which finishes the proof.

We state below a crucial result about absolute Galois groups of fixed subfields of A-closed fields, where A is a torsion Abelian group. Let us fix such a group A and we present it as:

$$ \begin{align*} A=\operatorname{\mathrm{\underrightarrow{\lim}}}_{i\in I}A_i \end{align*} $$

for finite Abelian groups $A_i$ , such that $A_0=\{0\}$ ( $0$ appearing in the subscript is the smallest element in $(I,\leqslant )$ ). For each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we denote its p-power torsion subgroup by $A_{(p)}$ (which can be considered as its p-Sylow subgroup). Let us fix an A-field K. For each $i\in I$ , we denote:

$$ \begin{align*} K_i:=K^{A_i}, \end{align*} $$

and we have the following short exact sequence:

where $\mathrm {res}_i$ is the appropriate restriction map.

Theorem 3.2. Suppose that K is A-closed and strict. Then we have the following.

  1. (1) For each $i\in I$ , the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ is pronilpotent.

  2. (2) Suppose that for each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , the group $A_{(p)}$ is finite. We enumerate the set of all primes ${\mathbb {P}}=(p_n)_{n>0}$ and set:

    $$ \begin{align*} A_n:=A_{(p_1)}\oplus \ldots \oplus A_{(p_n)}. \end{align*} $$
    Let us take $j,n\in {\mathbb {N}}$ . If $j\leqslant n$ , then the restriction map:
    $$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_n:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)_{(p_j)}\longrightarrow A_{(p_j)} = \left(A_n\right)_{(p_j)} \end{align*} $$
    is a Frattini cover.

Proof. We proceed to show Item $(1)$ , and then we will notice that under the extra assumptions of Item $(2)$ , the proof of Item $(1)$ gives the stronger conclusion from Item $(2)$ . The following claim is crucial for our proof of Item $(1)$ , and the proof of this claim is rather long. Since K is a strict A-field, for each $i\in I$ , we will identify $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K/K_i)$ with $A_i$ .

Claim. For each $i\in I$ , there is a closed subgroup $W_i\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ , such that:

  1. (1) the profinite group $W_i$ is pronilpotent;

  2. (2) we have:

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_i(W_i)=A_i; \end{align*} $$
  3. (3) for each $i,j\in I$ , if $i\leqslant j$ , then we have:

    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)\cap W_j=W_i. \end{align*} $$

Before proving the Claim, we will quickly see that it implies Item (1) from Theorem 3.2. Let W be the common intersection of all $W_i$ ’s with $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ and $K':=(K^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}})^W\!$ . By the Claim and Proposition 2.9, the action of A on K extends to $K'$ . Since K is A-closed, we get $K=K'$ . Therefore, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)=W$ , and for each i, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \ker(\mathrm{res}_i)=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\subseteq W_i. \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathrm {res}_i(W_i)=A_i$ , we get that $W_i=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ , so all the profinite groups $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ are pronilpotent.

Proof of Claim

For each $i\in I$ and $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , let $n_{i,p}$ be the cardinality of the finite p-group $(A_i)_{(p)}$ . We define the following set of infinite tuples:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Cl}_i:=\left\{x\in \prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)^{n_{i,p}}\ |\ x \text{ satisfies the conditions (i)--(iii) below}\right\}.\end{align*} $$

Before stating the conditions (i)–(iii), we fix the obvious presentation of a tuple $x\in \prod _{p\in {\mathbb {P}}}\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)^{n_{i,p}}$ :

$$ \begin{align*}x=\left(x_{(p)}\right)_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}},\ \ \ \ x_{(p)}\in \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)^{n_{i,p}}.\end{align*} $$

We give the conditions defining the set $\mathrm {Cl}_i$ below.

  1. (i) For each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we have:

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_i\left(x_{(p)}\right)=(A_i)_{(p)}. \end{align*} $$
  2. (ii) For each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , the group $\mathrm {cl}(\langle x_{(p)}\rangle )$ is a pro-p subgroup of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ .

  3. (iii) For each $p,q\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , if $p\neq q$ , then:

    $$ \begin{align*} [x_{(p)},x_{(q)}]=1, \end{align*} $$
    i.e. the coordinates of the tuple $x_{(p)}$ commute with the coordinates of the tuple $x_{(q)}$ .

For each $x\in \mathrm {Cl}_i$ , we define:

$$ \begin{align*} W_i^x:=\mathrm{cl}(\langle x\rangle). \end{align*} $$

Subclaim 1. For each $i\in I$ , we have the following.

  1. (1) $\mathrm {Cl}_i\neq \emptyset $ .

  2. (2) $\mathrm {Cl}_i$ is a closed subset of $\prod _{p\in {\mathbb {P}}}\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)^{n_{i,p}}$ .

  3. (3) For each $x\in \mathrm {Cl}_i$ , the profinite group $W_i^x$ is pronilpotent and $\mathrm {res}_i(W_i^x)=A_i$ .

Proof of Subclaim 1

For the proof of Item $(1)$ , we notice that there is a closed subgroup $W_i\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ by [Reference Ribes and Zalesskii22, Lemma 2.8.15], such that:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_i|_{W_i}:W_i\longrightarrow A_i \end{align*} $$

is a Frattini cover. By [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Corollary 22.10.6(b)], the universal Frattini cover $\widetilde {A_i}$ of the commutative profinite group $A_i$ is pronilpotent. Since $W_i\to A_i$ is a Frattini cover, there is a continuous epimorphism $\widetilde {A_i}\to W_i$ (see the condition (b) in [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 22.6.1]), which implies that the profinite group $W_i$ is pronilpotent as well. We have the following decomposition:

$$ \begin{align*} W_i=\prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}(W_i)_{(p)}. \end{align*} $$

For each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_i\left((W_i)_{(p)}\right)=(A_i)_{(p)}. \end{align*} $$

Hence, there is $x_{(p)}\in (W_i)_{(p)}^{n_{i,p}}$ , such that $\mathrm {res}_i(x_{(p)})=(A_i)_{(p)}$ . Thus, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} x:=\left(x_{(p)}\right)_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}\in \mathrm{Cl}_i, \end{align*} $$

and $\mathrm {Cl}_i$ is nonempty.

For the proof of Item $(2)$ , it is clear that the conditions (i) and (iii) from the definition of $\mathrm {Cl}_i$ are closed. Since any closed pro-p subgroup of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ is contained in a Sylow pro-p subgroup of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ , x satisfies the condition (ii) for a prime p if and only if the tuple $x_{(p)}$ is contained in a p-Sylow subgroup of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ . Hence, it is enough to check that this last condition on the tuple $x_{(p)}$ is closed. Let us fix P, a p-Sylow subgroup of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ . We set $n:=n_{i,p}$ and consider the following function:

$$ \begin{align*} \Psi:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)\times P^{n}\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)^{n},\ \ \ \ \Psi(g,(x_1,\ldots,x_n))=\left(gx_1g^{-1},\ldots,gx_ng^{-1}\right). \end{align*} $$

Since all p-Sylow subgroups of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ are conjugate, the set of tuples $x_{(p)}$ satisfying our last condition coincides with the image of the function $\Psi $ . Since $\Psi $ is a continuous function between compact topological spaces, its image is closed.

Item $(3)$ is obvious from the definition of the group $W_i^x$ .

From Item $(3)$ in Subclaim 1, we see that for each $i\in I$ , there is a closed pronilpotent subgroup $W_i\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ , such that $\mathrm {res}_i(W_i)=A_i$ . To finish the proof of the Claim, we need to find such $W_i$ ’s satisfying the extra condition saying that for $i\leqslant j$ , we have $W_j\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)=W_i$ . First, we will find $W_i$ ’s satisfying the following weaker condition: $W_i\subseteq W_j$ (for $i\leqslant j$ ).

For each $i,j\in I$ , such that $i\leqslant j$ , we define the following coordinate projection map:

$$ \begin{align*} \pi^j_i:\prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_j)^{n_{j,p}}\longrightarrow \prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_j)^{n_{i,p}}, \end{align*} $$

where the projections are induced by the inclusions $(A_i)_{(p)}\leqslant (A_j)_{(p)}$ . We define:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Cl}_i^j:=\pi^j_i(\mathrm{Cl}_j)\cap \prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)^{n_{i,p}}. \end{align*} $$

Subclaim 2. For each $i,j\in I$ , such that $i\leqslant j$ , we have the following.

  1. (1) $\mathrm {Cl}_i^j\subseteq \mathrm {Cl}_i$ .

  2. (2) $\mathrm {Cl}_i^j\neq \emptyset $ .

  3. (3) $\mathrm {Cl}_i^j$ is closed.

Proof of Subclaim 2

To show Item $(1)$ , we consider the following commutative diagram with exact rows:

The right part of this diagram is a Cartesian square, that is $\mathrm {res}_j^{-1}(A_i)=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ . Therefore, each $x\in \mathrm {Cl}_i^j$ satisfies Condition (i) from the definition of the set $\mathrm {Cl}_i$ . Since Conditions (ii) and (iii) are clearly satisfied for any $x\in \mathrm {Cl}_i^j$ , Item $(1)$ is proved.

For Item $(2)$ , it is enough to notice (by the same Cartesian square argument as above) that the condition $\mathrm {res}_j(W_j)=A_j$ implies that:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_i\left(W_j\cap \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)\right)=A_i. \end{align*} $$

Item $(3)$ is obvious, since $\pi ^j_i$ is a continuous map between compact topological spaces.

The set $\mathrm {Cl}_i^j$ has the following interpretation: for any $x\in \mathrm {Cl}_i^j$ , there is $y\in \mathrm {Cl}_j$ such that $W_i^x\subseteq W_j^y$ , so $W_i^x$ extends to $W_j^y$ . We want to have this extension property ‘all the way along $(I,<)$ ’: in particular, for $i_1\leqslant i_2\leqslant i_3\leqslant \ldots $ , we want to find $x_1$ , such that $W_{i_1}^{x_1}$ extends to $W_{i_2}^{x_2}$ , which extends to $W_{i_3}^{x_3}$ , etc. To this end, for any $i_1\leqslant i_1\leqslant \ldots \leqslant i_{n}$ from I, we define:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Cl}_{i_1}^{i_2,i_3}:=\pi^{i_2}_{i_1}\left(\mathrm{Cl}_{i_2}^{i_3}\right),\ \ \ \mathrm{Cl}_{i_1}^{i_2,\ldots,i_{n}}:=\pi^{i_2}_{i_1}\left(\mathrm{Cl}_{i_2}^{i_3,\ldots,i_{n}}\right). \end{align*} $$

To convey the main idea in a proper way, it is more convenient to continue in the special case when $I={\mathbb {N}}$ and $\leqslant $ is the standard ordering on ${\mathbb {N}}$ . We will point out later what one needs to do in the general case. We define:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Cl}_0^{\infty}:=\bigcap_{n=2}^{\infty}\mathrm{Cl}_0^{2,\ldots,n}. \end{align*} $$

As it was argued several times before in this proof, the compactness of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_0)=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ implies that the set $\mathrm {Cl}_0^{\infty }$ is nonempty. Let us take $x_0\in \mathrm {Cl}_0^{\infty }$ . It follows from the definition of $\mathrm {Cl}_0^{\infty }$ that there is a sequence $(x_i\in \mathrm {Cl}_i)_{i\geqslant 0}$ , such that for each $i\geqslant 0$ we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \pi^{i+1}_i\left(x_{i+1}\right)=x_i. \end{align*} $$

Let us define:

$$ \begin{align*} V_i:=W_i^{x_i}\leqslant \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i). \end{align*} $$

Then the profinite groups $V_i$ ’s are pronilpotent, they project onto the corresponding $A_i$ ’s and we have $V_i\subseteq V_{i+1}$ . So we have achieved the first step of approximating the conditions on $W_i$ from the statement of the Claim. We will correct these $V_i$ ’s to satisfy the conditions from the Claim fully. This is a very general procedure, we start from the following commutative diagram of inclusions, which summarises our situation:

For each $0\leqslant i<j$ , we define:

$$ \begin{align*}V_{i,j}:=V_j\cap \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i),\ \ \ \ V_{i}^{(1)}:=\operatorname{\mathrm{cl}}\left(\bigcup_{j>i}V_{i,j}\right). \end{align*} $$

It is finally the right moment to use Proposition 3.1, and thanks to this result, each profinite group $V_{i}^{(1)}$ is pronilpotent. Clearly, $V_{i}^{(1)}$ ’s project again onto $A_i$ ’s, and we have:

$$ \begin{align*}V_{i}\subseteq V_{i}^{(1)}\subseteq V_{i+1}^{(1)}. \end{align*} $$

For each $i\geqslant 0,n>0$ , we define now:

$$ \begin{align*} V_i^{(n+1)}:=\left(V_i^{(n)}\right)^{(1)},\ \ \ \ V_i^{(\omega)}:=\operatorname{\mathrm{cl}}\left(\bigcup_{n=1}^{\infty}V_i^{(n)}\right). \end{align*} $$

Again, $V_i^{(\omega )}$ ’s are pronilpotent, they project onto $A_i$ ’s and we have $V_i^{(\omega )}\subseteq V_{i+1}^{(\omega )}$ . We can continue like this using transfinite induction as long as we wish. However, this procedure must finish after some (ordinal) number of steps — it is possible that countably many steps are enough, but for sure, it is enough to take:

$$ \begin{align*} \kappa:=\left|\mathrm{Aut}\left(K^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)\right|{}^+ \end{align*} $$

of them. Then, for each $i>0$ , we define:

$$ \begin{align*} W_i:=V_i^{(\kappa)}, \end{align*} $$

and, by the construction, these $W_i$ ’s satisfy the conditions of the Claim, which finishes the proof of the Claim in the case of $(I,\leqslant )=({\mathbb {N}},\leqslant )$ .

We sketch now how one can proceed in the case of an arbitrary directed poset $(I,\leqslant )$ . We choose a maximal antichain $\mathcal {A}$ in I. Without loss of generality, $\mathcal {A}$ is infinite (otherwise, I can be taken to be ${\mathbb {N}}$ ). Then, we can assume that:

$$ \begin{align*} (I,\leqslant)=\left([\mathcal{A}]^{<\omega},\subseteq\right), \end{align*} $$

which is the set of finite subsets of $\mathcal {A}$ ordered by the inclusion relation. For any $n>0$ , let $I_n$ denote the subset of I consisting of subsets of $\mathcal {A}$ of cardinality n. Then we have:

and we can repeat the previous argument with taking an extra care about all the elements of $I_n$ at each level n. Namely, for any $i\in I$ we define:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Cl}_i^1:=\bigcap_{a\in \mathcal{A}}\mathrm{Cl}_{i}^{ia}, \end{align*} $$

where $ia:=i\cup \{a\}$ . The set $\mathrm {Cl}_i^1$ is nonempty by the arguments as above. Then, we define:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Cl}_{i}^{2}:=\pi^{ia}_{i}\left(\mathrm{Cl}^{1}_{ia}\right),\ \ \ \mathrm{Cl}_{i}^{n+1}:=\pi^{i_2}_{i_1}\left(\mathrm{Cl}^{n}_{ia}\right), \end{align*} $$

and we can continue as in the case of $I={\mathbb {N}}$ above.

Hence, we have obtained the subgroups $W_i\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ for each $i\in I$ , which satisfy Items $(1)$ and $(2)$ from the Claim, and such that for each $i,j\in I$ , if $i\leqslant j$ , then $W_i\subseteq W_j$ . To correct these $W_i$ ’s to satisfy Item $(3)$ from Claim, one can just repeat the procedure described in the case of $I={\mathbb {N}}$ .

As it was explained immediately after the statement of the Claim, Item $(1)$ (from the statement of Theorem 3.2, which we are still proving) directly follows from the Claim, whose proof was just finished above.

We proceed now towards the proof of Item $(2)$ . Having the extra assumptions from Item $(2)$ , we:

  • set $r_{n,p}$ as the rank (rather than just the cardinality) of $(A_n)_{(p)}$ ;

  • replace Condition (i) from the proof of the Claim with the following condition:

    • (i’) $\left \langle \mathrm {res}_n\left (x_{(p)}\right )\right \rangle =(A_n)_{(p)}$ .

Condition (i’) is still closed, since there is a fixed finite set of sequences of length $r_{n,p}$ generating the group $(A_n)_{(p)}$ .

We consider now the following commutative diagram:

By Remark 2.16(2), any continuous epimorphism of pro-p groups of the same finite rank is necessarily a Frattini cover. Hence, the map $\mathrm {res}_{j+1}$ restricted to $(V_{j+1})_{(p_j)}$ is a Frattini cover as indicated in the diagram above. Since:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_{j+1}\left((V_j)_{(p_j)}\right) = \mathrm{res}_j\left((V_j)_{(p_j)}\right) = (A_j)_{(p_j)} = (A_{j+1})_{(p_j)}, \end{align*} $$

we get that $(V_{j+1})_{(p_j)}=(V_{j})_{(p_j)}$ . Hence, for each $n\geqslant j$ , we have: $(V_n)_{(p_j)}=(V_j)_{(p_j)}$ .

Therefore, if we repeat the process of getting $W_n$ ’s from $V_n$ ’s appearing at the end of the proof of Item $(1)$ , then for each $n\geqslant j$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} (W_n)_{(p_j)}=(V_n)_{(p_j)}. \end{align*} $$

Since for each $n\geqslant j$ , $(V_n)_{(p_j)}$ is a Frattini cover of $(A_n)_{(p_j)}$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_n)=W_n$ , the proof is finished.

Remark 3.3. Item $(1)$ in Theorem 3.2 cannot be improved towards the conclusion from the statement of Item $(2)$ . To see that, let us consider an existentially closed $C_{p^{\infty }}^2$ -field K and let $A_n:=C_{p^{n}}^2$ . By the Claim from the beginning of Section 4, the restriction map:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)\longrightarrow A_n=C_{p^{n}}^2 \end{align*} $$

is not a Frattini cover.

4. Negative results

This section is mostly about the proof of the left-to-right implication from Theorem 1.1. Using Remark 1.2(2), we assume that there is an infinite strictly increasing sequence:

$$ \begin{align*} P_1=C_p^2<P_2<P_3<\ldots, \end{align*} $$

such that each $P_i$ is a finite p-subgroup of A. We aim to show that the theory A-TCF does not exist.

Assume that the theory A-TCF exists, and let K be an $|A|^+$ -saturated and existentially closed A-field. We will reach a contradiction.

By Theorem 3.2(1), for each $i\in I$ , the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ is pronilpotent, hence, it decomposes as:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)=\prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}. \end{align*} $$

By Corollary 2.5, for each $i\in I$ , the field $K_i$ is PAC. Hence (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Theorem 11.6.2]), the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ is projective and each pro-p group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}$ is projective. As in Example 2.22(1), $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}$ is pro-p free, so there is a cardinal $\kappa _i$ , such that:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}\cong \widehat{F}_{\kappa_i}(p). \end{align*} $$

Claim. For each $i\in I$ , such that $C_p^2=P_1\subseteq A_i$ , the restriction map:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}\longrightarrow (A_i)_{(p)} \end{align*} $$

is not a Frattini cover.

Proof of Claim

Assume that the Claim does not hold, and let us take $i\in I$ as above, such that the map:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_i:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}\longrightarrow (A_i)_{(p)} \end{align*} $$

is a Frattini cover. Let r be the rank of $(A_i)_{(p)}$ . By our assumption, r is finite and $r\geqslant 2$ . Since the map $\mathrm {res}_i$ is a Frattini cover, we get that $r=\mathrm {rk}(\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)})$ , hence, (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Corollary 22.5.3]) $r=\kappa _i$ .

For any $j\in I$ , such that $i\leqslant j$ , we have the following commutative diagram:

Hence, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} t_j:=\left[\widehat{F}_{\kappa_j}(p):\widehat{F}_{r}(p)\right]=\left[(A_j)_{(p)}:(A_i)_{(p)}\right]. \end{align*} $$

Therefore, by our main assumption on the sequence of groups $(A_i)_i$ , the indices $t_j$ go to infinity when $j\rightarrow \infty $ . This leads to a contradiction by the profinite version of the Nielsen-Schreier formula [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 17.6.2], which we observe below.

Since r is finite, $\kappa _j$ is finite as well for each $j\geqslant i$ , and we have:

$$ \begin{align*} r=1+t_j(\kappa_j-1). \end{align*} $$

Since $r\geqslant 2$ , then for each $j\geqslant i$ , we have $\kappa _j-1>0$ . Since $t_j$ ’s go to infinity with j, then the constant r tends to infinity as well, which is obviously a contradiction.

Using the Claim above, we obtain that for each $i\in I$ , such that $C_p^2\subseteq A_i$ , the map:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_i:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}\longrightarrow \left(A_i\right)_{(p)} \end{align*} $$

is not a Frattini cover, which is witnessed by a closed proper subgroup $H_i<\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}$ , such that:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_i(H_i)=\left(A_i\right)_{(p)}. \end{align*} $$

Without loss of generality, $H_i$ is a maximal proper closed subgroup of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}$ . Since the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}$ is pro-p, we get that:

$$ \begin{align*} \left[\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}:H_i\right]=p. \end{align*} $$

Hence, by Lemma 2.8 (applied to $\mathcal {G}_0:=H_i\times \prod _{q\neq p}\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)_{(q)}$ ), for each such $i\in I$ , there is an $A_i$ -field extension $K\subset L_i$ of degree p. Since K is $|A|^+$ -saturated, there is an A-field extension $K\subset L$ of degree p, which gives our final contradiction (K is an existentially closed A-field, so it is also A-closed) and finishes the proof of the left-to-right implication in Theorem 1.1.

5. Positive results

This section is about the proof of the right-to-left implication in Theorem 1.1. Similarly, as in Section 3, we start this section with a very general result, which will be needed later.

Proposition 5.1. Let $K_1\supseteq K_2 \supseteq K_3 \supseteq \ldots $ be a decreasing tower of fields, and let:

$$ \begin{align*} K_{\infty}:=\bigcap_{n=1}^{\infty}K_n. \end{align*} $$

We assume that $K_{\infty }$ is PAC, and that the field extension $K_{\infty }\subseteq K_1$ is algebraic. Let V be an algebraic variety over $K_{\infty }$ , such that for all $n>0$ , we have $V(K_n)\neq \emptyset $ . Then $V(K_{\infty })\neq \emptyset $ .

Proof. Let $V=V_1\cup \ldots \cup V_d$ be the decomposition of V into irreducible components over $K_{\infty }^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}$ . We assume that the result does not hold (for this fixed tower $(K_n)_n$ ) and take a counterexample V, which is minimal with respect to $(\dim (V),d)$ . We will reach a contradiction.

Since $K_{\infty }$ is PAC, we have $d>1$ . Without loss of generality, we may assume that for each n, the set:

$$ \begin{align*} Q_n:=V(K_n)\cap V_1\left(K_{\infty}^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right) \end{align*} $$

is nonempty. Let $W_n$ be the Zariski closure of $Q_n$ for each n inside $V_1\left (K_{\infty }^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\right )$ . Then, for each n, we have the following:

  • $W_n$ is nonempty;

  • $W_n$ is defined over $K_n$ ;

  • $W_n\subseteq V_1$ ;

  • $W_n(K_n)\neq \emptyset $ ;

  • $W_n$ ’s form a descending chain.

Hence, there is a variety W, such that for $n\gg 0$ , we have $W=W_n$ . Therefore, W is defined over $K_{\infty }=\bigcap K_n$ , and W satisfies the assumption of the statement we are proving. But, since $W\subseteq V_1$ and $d>1$ , either $\dim (W)<\dim (V)$ or the number of irreducible components (over $K_{\infty }^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}$ ) of W is smaller than d (actually, if $\dim (W)=\dim (V)$ , then $W=V_1$ , so W is absolutely irreducible). By minimality of V, we get $W(K_{\infty })\neq \emptyset $ . But then $V(K_{\infty })\neq \emptyset $ , a contradiction.

Remark 5.2.

  1. (1) The conclusion of Proposition 5.1 can be easily strengthened by replacing the variety V with a constructible set. By a constructible set defined over a field M, we just mean a quantifier-free formula in the language of rings with parameters from M. If we evaluate this formula on $M^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}$ , then we get a ‘classical’ constructible set which is a Noetherian topological space with the induced Zariski topology, and its irreducible components are constructible sets as well (defined over $M^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}$ ). To make the proof of Proposition 5.1 work in this context, one only needs to notice that since for an absolutely irreducible variety W over a PAC field C, we have that $W(C)$ is Zariski dense in W [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Proposition 11.1.1], then any absolutely irreducible constructible set over C has a C-rational point as well.

  2. (2) If we do not put assumptions on the intersection of the tower of fields, then Proposition 5.1 fails, we give an example below. For $n>0$ , let:

    $$ \begin{align*} K_n:=\left({\mathbb{F}}_3^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{{\mathbb{Z}}_{p_1}\times \ldots\times {\mathbb{Z}}_{p_n}} \end{align*} $$
    (we enumerate the primes ${\mathbb {P}}=(p_n)_{n>0}$ ). Each field extension ${\mathbb {F}}_3\subset K_n$ is infinite algebraic, so, by [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Corollary 11.2.4], each field $K_n$ is PAC. Therefore, it is enough to take an absolutely irreducible variety V over ${\mathbb {F}}_3$ , such that $V({\mathbb {F}}_3)=\emptyset $ , for example:
    $$ \begin{align*} V=V(Y^2-X^3+X+1) \end{align*} $$
    (we could have taken any finite field in place of ${\mathbb {F}}_3$ , see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Example 11.2.9]).

We proceed towards the right-to-left implication in Theorem 1.1. Let us fix first a ‘good’ torsion Abelian group B of a special kind, that is, we assume that for all $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , the p-primary part subgroup $B_{(p)}$ is finite. We also fix an enumeration of the primes ${\mathbb {P}}=(p_n)_{n>0}$ , and for each $n\in {\mathbb {N}}$ , we define the finite subgroup of B:

$$ \begin{align*} B_n:=B_{(p_1)}\oplus \ldots \oplus B_{(p_n)}. \end{align*} $$

Then $(B_n)_n$ is an increasing sequence, such that $B=\bigcup _n B_n$ as in the assumptions of Theorem 3.2(2). Let K be a B-field, and, as usual, we define $K_n$ as $K^{B_n}$ . The main point is to show the following result below. We would like to point out that the conditions $(1)$ $(3)$ below are exactly the Galois axioms from Definition 1.3 (see Remark 5.4).

Theorem 5.3. The B-field K is existentially closed if and only if the following conditions hold:

  1. (1) K is strict and perfect;

  2. (2) for each $n\in {\mathbb {N}}$ , $K_n$ is PAC;

  3. (3) we have:

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\cong \ker\left(\widetilde{\widehat{B}}\longrightarrow \widehat{B}\right)=\prod_{t>0}\ker\left(\widetilde{B_{(p_t)}} \longrightarrow B_{(p_t)}\right),\end{align*} $$
    and for each $n>0$ , we have
    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n) \cong \widetilde{B_n}\times \prod_{t>n}\ker\left(\widetilde{B_{(p_t)}} \longrightarrow B_{(p_t)}\right). \end{align*} $$

Proof. For the implication ‘ $\Rightarrow $ ’, we notice first that any e.c. B-field is strict and perfect (see, e.g. [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Lemma 3.1] and [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Lemma 3.4], which hold for an arbitrary group), so we get Item $(1)$ . Item $(2)$ follows from Corollary 2.5. We proceed to show Item $(3)$ . Let us fix $n\in {\mathbb {N}}$ . By Theorem 3.2(1), the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_n)$ is pronilpotent, hence, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)=\prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)_{(p)}. \end{align*} $$

We need to show that for any $j>0$ , we have:

  1. (i) if $j\leqslant n$ , then:

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)_{(p_j)}\cong \widetilde{B_{(p_j)}};\end{align*} $$
  2. (ii) if $j> n$ , then:

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)_{(p_j)}\cong \ker\left(\widetilde{B_{(p_j)}}\longrightarrow B_{(p_j)}\right).\end{align*} $$

Since $K_n$ is PAC, we get that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_n)$ is projective as well as $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_n)_{(p)}$ for each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ . In the situation of Item (i), we get what we want directly from Theorem 3.2(2).

In the situation of Item (ii), we consider the following short exact sequence:

Since $K_j=K^{B_j}$ and $K_n=K^{B_n}$ , we get (using that K is a strict B-field) the following:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n/K_j)\cong B_j/B_n\cong B_{(p_{n+1})}\oplus \ldots \oplus B_{(p_j)}.\end{align*} $$

By the isomorphism above and Theorem 3.2(2), we get the following short exact sequence:

which gives the desired description of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_n)_{(p_j)}$ .

For the implication ‘ $\Leftarrow $ ’, let us assume that K is a B-field satisfying the conditions $(1)$ $(3)$ above. We need the following conclusion of the Galois axioms in this case.

Claim 1. K is B-closed.

Proof of Claim 1

Let $K\subseteq K'$ be an algebraic B-field extension. We aim to show that $K'=K$ . For each $n>0$ , $K\subseteq K'$ is an algebraic $B_n$ -field extension. Let $K_n':=(K')^{B_n}$ and $\mathcal {G}_n\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_n)$ be a closed subgroup, such that:

$$ \begin{align*} K_n'=\left(K^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\mathcal{G}_n}. \end{align*} $$

Let:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_n:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)\longrightarrow B_n=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K/K_n) \end{align*} $$

be the restriction map. By Lemma 2.8, we obtain that:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_n(\mathcal{G}_n)=B_n. \end{align*} $$

By our assumption, the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_n)$ is pronilpotent and for each $t\leqslant n$ the map:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{res}_n:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)_{(p_t)}\longrightarrow B_{(p_t)}=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K/K_n)_{(p_t)} \end{align*} $$

is a (necessarily universal) Frattini cover. Hence, for each $t\leqslant n$ , we obtain:

$$ \begin{align*} (\mathcal{G}_n)_{(p_t)}=\widetilde{B_{(p_t)}}=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n)_{(p_t)}. \end{align*} $$

In particular, for any $n>0$ , we obtain (by taking $t=n$ ):

(*) $$ \begin{align} (\mathcal{G}_n\cap \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K))_{(p_n)}=\widetilde{B_{(p_n)}}\cap \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)=\ker\left(\widetilde{B_{(p_n)}} \longrightarrow B_{(p_n)}\right)=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)_{(p_n)}. \end{align} $$

However, for each $n>0$ , we have (see Lemma 2.8):

$$ \begin{align*} \left(K^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\mathcal{G}_n\cap \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)}=K'. \end{align*} $$

Hence, there is a closed subgroup $\mathcal {H}\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ , such that for every $n>0$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{H}=\mathcal{G}_n\cap \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K),\ \ \ \ K'=\left(K^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\mathcal{H}}. \end{align*} $$

By $(*)$ , we get that for each $n>0$ :

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{H}_{(p_n)}=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)_{(p_n)}. \end{align*} $$

Therefore, $\mathcal {H}=\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ and $K=K'$ , which we needed to show.

The next claim is just a restatement of the Galois axioms.

Claim 2. For any $n>0$ , we have the following commutative diagram with exact rows (where, for clarity, we skip the trivial groups):

From now on, we identify all the isomorphic objects appearing in Claim 2. For $n>0$ , we define:

$$ \begin{align*}K_{(n)}:=\left(K^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\widetilde{B_n}}.\end{align*} $$

Since we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{B_n} \cdot \prod_{t>0}\ker\left(\widetilde{B_{(p_t)}}\to B_{(p_t)}\right)= \widetilde{B_n}\times \prod_{t>n}\ker\left(\widetilde{B_{(p_t)}} \to B_{(p_t)}\right),\end{align*} $$

we get by Claim 2 that:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(K_{(n)}\right) \cdot \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K) =\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n),\end{align*} $$

hence, we obtain:

$$ \begin{align*}K_{(n)}\cap K=K_n.\end{align*} $$

Since $K_n\subseteq K$ is a finite Galois extension, we obtain that $K_{(n)}$ is linearly disjoint from K over $K_n$ (see [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Corollary 2.5.2] and the discussion below its proof). We define now:

$$ \begin{align*}K_{(n)}':=K_{(n)}K\cong K_{(n)}\otimes_{K_n}K.\end{align*} $$

From the isomorphism above, $K_{(n)}'$ is naturally a $B_n$ -field extension of K, and we also note that $K_{(n)}'$ is strict and perfect.

Claim 3. The fields $K_{(n)}'$ form a decreasing tower, and we have the following:

$$ \begin{align*}\bigcap_{n=1}^{\infty}K_{(n)}'=K.\end{align*} $$

Proof of Claim 3

From the definition of the field $K_{(n)}'$ and Claim 2, we obtain that:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(K_{(n)}'\right)=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\cap \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_{(n)})=\ker\left(\widetilde{B_n}\to B_n\right). \end{align*} $$

Hence, we get (‘cl’ below denotes the topological closure inside the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ ):

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{cl}\left(\bigcup_{n=1}^{\infty} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(K_{(n)}'\right)\right) & = \mathrm{cl}\left(\bigcup_{n=1}^{\infty} \ker\left(\widetilde{B_n}\to B_n\right)\right) \\ &= \ker\left( \widetilde{\widehat{B}} \to \widehat{B} \right)\\ &= \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K), \end{align*} $$

which yields the claim by the Galois theory.

By Claim 3, we see that the fields $K_{(n)}'$ approximate our field K. The next claim says that they also ‘logically approximate’ K, in the sense that these fields have better and better model-theoretic properties.

Claim 4. For each $n>0$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*}K_{(n)}'\models B_n-\mathrm{TCF}.\end{align*} $$

Proof of Claim 4

From the definition of the $B_n$ -field $K_{(n)}'$ , it follows that:

$$ \begin{align*}\left(K_{(n)}'\right)^{B_n}=K_{(n)}.\end{align*} $$

Since $K_n\subseteq K_{(n)}$ is an algebraic field extension and $K_n$ is PAC, we get that $K_{(n)}$ is PAC as well. By the definition of $K_{(n)}$ , we get that:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(K_{(n)}\right)\cong \widetilde{B_n}, \end{align*} $$

hence, by Proposition 2.17, we obtain that the $B_n$ -field $K_{(n)}'$ is existentially closed.

We are ready to show that K is an existentially closed B-field. Let us take a quantifier-free $L_{B}$ -formula $\varphi (x)$ over K and a B-field extension $K\subseteq K'$ , such that:

$$ \begin{align*} K'\models \exists x\varphi(x). \end{align*} $$

We aim to show that $K\models \exists x\varphi (x)$ .

Let $N>0$ be, such that $\varphi (x)\in L_{B_N}$ . Since K is B-closed (Claim 1), the field extension $K\subseteq K'$ is regular. Let us take an arbitrary $n\geqslant N$ . Since the field extension $K\subseteq K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ is algebraic, $K'$ is linearly disjoint from $K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ over K (by the definition of regular extensions). Therefore, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} K'K^{\prime}_{(n)}\cong K'\otimes_KK^{\prime}_{(n)}, \end{align*} $$

and the field $K'K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ has a natural $B_n$ -field structure extending those on $K'$ and $K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ over K. Since the formula $\varphi (x)$ is quantifier free, we have $K'K^{\prime }_{(n)}\models \exists x\varphi (x)$ . Since $K_{(n)}'$ is an existentially closed $B_n$ -field (Claim 4), we have $K_{(n)}'\models \exists x\varphi (x)$ .

For each $n\geqslant N$ , the $B_N$ -field $K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ is bi-interpretable with the pure field $(K^{\prime }_{(n)})^{B_N}$ (see [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Remark 2.3]). To proceed, we need the following claim. The notion of ‘uniform bi-interpretability’ from this claim will be explained in the beginning of its proof. In this claim, we also set $K_{(\infty )}':=K$ and $K_{(\infty )}:=K_N$ .

Claim 5. The bi-interpretability between the $B_N$ -field $K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ and the pure field $(K^{\prime }_{(n)})^{B_N}$ is uniform with respect to $n\in \{N,N+1,\ldots ,\infty \}$ . In particular, there is a quantifier-free formula $\psi (y)$ in the language of fields with parameters from $K_N$ , such that for all $n\in \{N,N+1,\ldots ,\infty \}$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*} K_{(n)}'\models \exists x\varphi(x)\ \ \ \ \Leftrightarrow\ \ \ \ \left(K_{(n)}'\right)^{B_N}\models \exists y\psi(y). \end{align*} $$

Proof of Claim 5

If G is a finite group of order e, F is a G-field and $M:=F^G$ , then (see [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski10, Remark 2.3]) there are M-bilinear maps:

$$ \begin{align*} m,a:M^e\times M^e\longrightarrow M^e, \end{align*} $$

such that $(M^e,m,a)$ is naturally bi-interpretable with the field F. Similarly, in the case of the G-action, there are M-linear maps:

$$ \begin{align*} g_1,\ldots,g_e:M^e\longrightarrow M^e, \end{align*} $$

such that $(M^e,m,a,g_1,\ldots ,g_e)$ is bi-interpretable with the G-field F.

To prove our claim, it is enough to show that there are fixed $K_N$ -bilinear maps, which give $K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ the $B_N$ -field structure for each $n\in \{N,N+1,\ldots ,\infty \}$ (we use the above observation for a fixed $G=B_N$ and where $F=K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ and $M=(K^{\prime }_{(n)})^{B_N}$ vary with n). To this end, it is enough to show that for all $n\in \{N,N+1,\ldots ,\infty \},$ we have:

(†) $$ \begin{align} K^{\prime}_{(n)}\cong \left(K^{\prime}_{(n)}\right)^{B_N}\otimes_{K_N}K. \end{align} $$

We have the following commutative diagramFootnote 1 of field extensions, where the arrows are the inclusions and the Galois groups are indicated over some of the arrows:

Thanks to the diagram above, we see that:

  • the field $K^{\prime }_{(n)}$ is the compositum of the fields $\left (K^{\prime }_{(n)}\right )^{B_N}$ and K;

  • the fields $\left (K^{\prime }_{(n)}\right )^{B_N}$ and K are linearly disjoint over $K_N$ .

Hence, we get the isomorphism from $(\dagger )$ above.

Let us take the quantifier-free formula $\psi (y)$ in the language of fields from Claim 5. This formula corresponds to (or even: ‘this formula is’, see Remark 5.2(1)) a constructible set V defined over $K_N$ . By Claim 5, it is enough to show that $V(K_N)\neq \emptyset $ . By Claim 5 again, we get that for each $n\geqslant N$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*} V\left(\left(K^{\prime}_{(n)}\right)^{B_N}\right)\neq \emptyset. \end{align*} $$

By Claim 3, we obtain that:

$$ \begin{align*} \bigcap_{n=N}^{\infty}\left(K^{\prime}_{(n)}\right)^{B_N}=K_N. \end{align*} $$

Therefore, Remark 5.2(1) implies that $V(K_N)\neq \emptyset $ , which finishes the proof thanks to Claim 5. (One could also arrange the original formula $\varphi (x)$ in such a way that the resulting formula $\psi (x)$ defines a variety. Then, using Proposition 5.1 (rather than Remark 5.2(1)) would be enough.

Remark 5.4. As noted in the Introduction (below Definition 1.3), to see that the Galois axioms from Theorem 5.3 are first order, it is enough to show that all the absolute Galois groups $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)$ appearing there are small. It is clear that if the profinite group $\mathcal {G}$ is the product of its p-Sylow subgroups $\mathcal {G}_{(p)}$ , then $\mathcal {G}$ is small if and only if each $\mathcal {G}_{(p)}$ is small. By Theorem 5.3, the profinite groups $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K_i)_{(p)}$ are small, because they are topologically finitely generated.

Therefore, for a torsion Abelian group B, such that for all $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , the p-power torsion subgroup $B_{(p)}$ is finite, we get that the theory B-TCF exists, and it is axiomatised by Galois axioms from the statement of Theorem 5.3.

We can conclude now the proof of our main result.

Proof of Theorem 1.1

Since the left-to-right implication was proved in Section 4, it is enough to show the right-to-left implication and the moreover part of Theorem 1.1.

For the right-to-left implication, let us assume that for each prime p, the p-primary part of A is either finite or it is the Prüfer p-group. We decompose A as:

$$ \begin{align*} A=A_f\oplus A_{\infty}, \end{align*} $$

where for each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we have that $(A_f)_{(p)}$ is finite and $(A_{\infty })_{(p)}=C_{p^{\infty }}$ or $(A_{\infty })_{(p)}$ is trivial. Let us set:

$$ \begin{align*} P_{\infty}:=\{p\in {\mathbb{P}}\ |\ (A_{\infty})_{(p)}=C_{p^{\infty}}\}=(p_i)_{i>0}, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} P_{0}:=\{q\in {\mathbb{P}}\ |\ (A_f)_{(q)}\neq 0\}=(q_i)_{i>0},\qquad \end{align*} $$

and for any $m\in {\mathbb {N}}$ and $n>0$ , we define:

$$ \begin{align*} A^{(m)}:=A_f\oplus\bigoplus_{p\in P_{\infty}}C_{p^{m}},\ \ \ \ \ \left(A_f\right)_n:=\bigoplus_{k=1}^n\left(A_f\right)_{(q_k)},\ \ \ \ \ \left(A^{(m)}\right)_n:=\left(A_f\right)_n\oplus\bigoplus_{k=1}^nC_{p_k^{m}}. \end{align*} $$

Then A is the increasing union of the subgroups $A^{(m)}$ and each $A^{(m)}$ satisfies the assumptions on the group B in the statement of Theorem 5.3. By Theorem 5.3 and Remark 5.4, for each $m\in {\mathbb {N}}$ , the theory $A^{(m)}$ -TCF exists and it is axiomatised by the Galois axioms. By Fact 2.19 and Proposition 2.20, it is enough to show that if $K\models A^{(m+1)}-\mathrm {TCF}$ , then $K|_{L_{A^{(m)}}}\models A^{(m)}-\mathrm {TCF}$ . The proof of this last assertion does not differ much from the proof appearing in Example 2.21. Let us take $n\in {\mathbb {N}}$ , and let us set $P_n:=p_1\ldots p_n$ . Then, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} (A^{(m)})_n=P_n(A^{(m+1)})_n. \end{align*} $$

Let us also denote:

$$ \begin{align*} K_n:=K^{\left(A^{(m+1)}\right)_n},\ \ \ \ \ K_n':=K^{\left(A^{(m)}\right)_n}. \end{align*} $$

By Theorem 5.3(3), we get:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K_n) & \cong \widetilde{\left(A^{(m+1)}\right)_n}\times \prod_{t=n+1}^{\infty}\ker\left(\widetilde{\left(A^{(m+1)}\right)_{(p_t)}} \longrightarrow (A^{(m)})_{(p_t)}\right) \\ &\cong \widetilde{\left(A_f\right)_n} \times \prod_{t=n+1}^{\infty}\ker\left(\widetilde{(A_f)_{(q_t)}}\longrightarrow (A_f)_{(q_t)} \right) \times {\mathbb{Z}}_{P_n}\times \prod_{t=n+1}^{\infty}p_t^{m+1}{\mathbb{Z}}_{p_t} \\ &\cong \widetilde{\left(A_f\right)_n} \times \prod_{t=n+1}^{\infty}\ker\left(\widetilde{(A_f)_{(q_t)}}\longrightarrow (A_f)_{(q_t)} \right) \times \prod_{t=1}^{\infty}{\mathbb{Z}}_{p_t}, \end{align*} $$

where ${\mathbb {Z}}_{P_n}$ denotes ${\mathbb {Z}}_{p_1}\times \ldots \times {\mathbb {Z}}_{p_n}$ (by [Reference Fried and Jarden5, Corollary 22.7.8], for each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we have $\widetilde {C_p}={\mathbb {Z}}_p$ , hence, $\widetilde {C_{P_n}}={\mathbb {Z}}_{P_n}$ ). We have the following commutative diagram with exact rows (generalising the one from Example 2.21):

Therefore, we obtain:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(K_n'\right) & = \mathrm{res}^{-1}\left(P_n(A^{(m+1)})_n\right) \\ &\cong \widetilde{\left(A_f\right)_n}\times \prod_{t=n+1}^{\infty}\ker\left(\widetilde{(A_f)_{(q_t)}}\longrightarrow (A_f)_{(q_t)} \right) \times P_n{\mathbb{Z}}_{P_n}\times \prod_{t=n+1}^{\infty}p_t^{m+1}{\mathbb{Z}}_{p_t}\\ &\cong \widetilde{\left(A_f\right)_n} \times \prod_{t=n+1}^{\infty}\ker\left(\widetilde{(A_f)_{(q_t)}}\longrightarrow (A_f)_{(q_t)} \right) \times \prod_{t=1}^{\infty}{\mathbb{Z}}_{p_t}\\ &\cong \widetilde{\left(A^{(m)}\right)_n}\times \prod_{t>n}\ker\left(\widetilde{\left(A^{(m)}\right)_{(p_t)}} \longrightarrow (A^{(m)})_{(p_t)}\right). \end{align*} $$

By Theorem 5.3(3), we get that $K|_{L_{A^{(m)}}}\models A^{(m)}-\mathrm {TCF}$ .

For the moreover part, we need to show that the theory $A-\mathrm {TCF}$ is strictly simple (that is: simple, not stable and not supersimple) for A infinite. For simplicity, by Proposition 2.20, it is enough to show that each theory $A^{(m)}$ -TCF is simple. We use [Reference Hoffmann7, Corollary 4.31], which (very conveniently for us) says that for any group G, if the theory $G-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists, then it is simple if and only if the underlying fields of its models are bounded. Let us take $K\models A^{(m)}-\mathrm {TCF}$ . By Theorem 5.3, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\cong \prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}\ker\left(\widetilde{\left(A^{(m)}\right)_{(p)}} \longrightarrow \left(A^{(m)}\right)_{(p)}\right). \end{align*} $$

Each universal Frattini cover above is a small profinite group being finitely generated. Hence, each kernel above is small as well being an open subgroup of a small profinite group. Therefore, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ is small, since all its pro-p components are small. As a result, the field K is bounded and the theory $A-\mathrm {TCF}$ is simple. Since K is PAC and not separably closed (if $A\neq 0$ ), by [Reference Kim15, Fact 2.6.7], the theory of the pure field K is not stable, so the theory $A-\mathrm {TCF}$ is also not stable. To see that $A-\mathrm {TCF}$ is not supersimple (if A is infinite), it is enough to look at any strictly increasing sequence of finite subgroups of A and consider the corresponding strictly decreasing tower of definable subfields of invariants of K.

Remark 5.5.

  1. (1) Example 2.21 can be generalised in the following way. Let us take A, satisfying the equivalent conditions from Remark 1.2, and let $K\models A-\mathrm {TCF}$ . From the above proof of the right-to-left implication in Theorem 1.1, we have that:

    $$ \begin{align*} A-\mathrm{TCF} = \bigcup_{m=1}^{\infty} A^{(m)}-\mathrm{TCF}. \end{align*} $$
    In particular, $K\models A^{(1)}-\mathrm {TCF}$ and the description of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(K)$ comes from Theorem 5.3(3), that is:
    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K)\cong \ker\left(\widetilde{\widehat{B}}\longrightarrow \widehat{B}\right), \end{align*} $$
    where we have:
    $$ \begin{align*} B:=A_f\oplus \bigoplus_{p\in P_{\infty}}C_p \end{align*} $$
    for $A_f$ and $P_{\infty }$ defined as in the beginning of the proof of Theorem 1.1 in this section.
  2. (2) By expressing A as:

    $$ \begin{align*} A=\operatorname{\mathrm{\underrightarrow{\lim}}}_{m,n}\left(A^{(m)}\right)_n, \end{align*} $$
    where again the finite subgroups $\left (A^{(m)}\right )_n$ come from the beginning of the proof of Theorem 1.1 in this section, we see that the theory A-TCF is axiomatised by Galois axioms in the sense of Definition 1.3.

Example 5.6. We can now give several examples of existentially closed A-fields. The ones from Items $(2)$ and $(3)$ below are in the spirit of (but, of course, much easier than) Hrushovski’s “non-standard Frobenius” from [Reference Hrushovski11]. Let us define:

$$ \begin{align*} C_{{\mathbb{P}}}:=\bigoplus_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}C_p,\ \ \ \ {\mathbb{P}}=(p_i)_{i>0},\ \ \ \ P_n:=p_1\ldots p_n. \end{align*} $$

  1. (1) A $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field is a field K with a collection of automorphisms $(\sigma _p)_{p\in {\mathbb {P}}}$ , such that for all $p,q\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we have $\sigma _p\sigma _q=\sigma _q\sigma _p$ ; and for each $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we have $\sigma _p^p=\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}$ . A $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field is strict if and only if for all $p\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , we have $\sigma _p\neq \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}$ . By Theorem 5.3, it is easy to see that if K is a strict and perfect $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field, then K is e.c. if and only if all the fields of constants:

    $$ \begin{align*}K_n:=\mathrm{Fix}\left(\sigma_{p_1}\right)\cap \ldots \cap \mathrm{Fix}\left(\sigma_{p_n}\right)\end{align*} $$
    are pseudofinite.
  2. (2) Let $q\in {\mathbb {P}}$ , and for each $n>0$ , we define the following $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field:

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{K}_{q,n}:=\left({\mathbb{F}}_{q^{P_n}};\operatorname{\mathrm{Fr}}^{P_n/p_1},\ldots,\operatorname{\mathrm{Fr}}^{P_n/p_n},\operatorname{\mathrm{id}},\operatorname{\mathrm{id}},\ldots\right). \end{align*} $$
    Note that each $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field $\mathbf {K}_{q,n}$ is bi-interpretable with the difference field $({\mathbb {F}}_{q^{P_n}},\operatorname {\mathrm {Fr}})$ . Let $\mathcal {U}$ be a nonprincipal ultrafilter on the set of positive integers, and we define the following ${\mathbb {C}}_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field:
    $$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{K}_{q}:=\left. \prod_{n>0}\mathbf{K}_{q,n} \middle/ \mathcal{U}. \right. \end{align*} $$
    By Łoś Theorem and Item $(1)$ , $\mathbf {K}_{q}$ is an existentially closed $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field of characteristic q.
  3. (3) Let us define:

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{K}_{0}:=\left. \prod_{n>0}\mathbf{K}_{p_n,n} \middle/ \mathcal{U}, \right. \end{align*} $$
    where each $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field $\mathbf {K}_{p_n,n}$ comes from Item $(2)$ above. Similarly, as in Item $(2)$ , $\mathbf {K}_{0}$ is an existentially closed $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field of characteristic $0$ .
  4. (4) Let us take $q\in {\mathbb {P}}$ and define:

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{H}:=\prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}p{\mathbb{Z}}_p<\widehat{{\mathbb{Z}}}\cong \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}({\mathbb{F}}_q),\ \ \ \ K:=\left({\mathbb{F}}_q^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\mathcal{H}}. \end{align*} $$
    Then, we have:
    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K/{\mathbb{F}}_q)\cong \widehat{{\mathbb{Z}}}/\mathcal{H}\cong \prod_{p\in {\mathbb{P}}}C_p \cong \widehat{C_{{\mathbb{P}}}}.\end{align*} $$
    Hence, K becomes naturally a $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field. It is clear from Item $(1)$ that K is an e.c. $C_{{\mathbb {P}}}$ -field.

Remark 5.7.

  1. (1) We note that if we consider in Example 5.6(2) the bi-interpretable difference field $({\mathbb {F}}_{q^{P_n}},\operatorname {\mathrm {Fr}})$ and take the ultraproduct in the language of difference fields, then the result is completely different: we would obtain a pseudofinite field of characteristic q with the Frobenius automorphism.

  2. (2) However, if we do the same in Example 5.6(3), then we get a pseudofinite field of characteristic $0$ with an automorphism of an infinite order, which should be generic in some sense. More precisely, we consider the following difference fields:

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{K}_n:=\left({\mathbb{F}}_{q_n},\operatorname{\mathrm{Fr}}\right),\ \ \ \ q_n:=p_n^{P_n}=p_n^{p_1\ldots p_n} \end{align*} $$
    and their nonprincipal ultraproduct. Very similar difference fields were considered in [Reference Zou24], that is: the difference fields from [Reference Zou24] are also ultraproducts of finite Frobenius difference fields, but the order of growth of the cardinality of the finite fields in [Reference Zou24] seems to be much faster than in our case.

6. Miscellaneous results

In this section, we collect some results about model theory of group actions on fields, which did not fit to the course of the proof of the main result of this paper (Theorem 1.1). More precisely, we:

  • provide another argument for the nonexistence of the theory A-TCF for certain torsion Abelian groups A,

  • describe what we are able to prove for groups containing ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ ,

  • discuss briefly the case of nontorsion Abelian groups.

6.1. Another negative argument

In this subsection, we present briefly, a different negative argument in the special case of $A=C_p^{(\omega )}$ . This was our original argument, and we think that it may have an independent interest. Intuitively, the crucial property implying the nonexistence of the theory $A-\mathrm {TCF}$ here is some kind of an auto-duplication of A inside A, i.e. A has a proper subgroup, which is isomorphic to A.

We present $C_p^{(\omega )}$ as $\operatorname {\mathrm {\underrightarrow {\lim }}} C_p^{n}$ , and for a $C_p^{(\omega )}$ -field K, we set as usual $K_n:=K^{C_p^{n}}$ . Let $C=\bigcap _n K_n$ be the field of absolute constants of K. By a compactness argument and the Galois theory, we obtain the following.

Lemma 6.1. Suppose that K is a strict $C_p^{(\omega )}$ -field, which is $\aleph _0$ -saturated. Then, there are $a_1,a_2,\ldots \in K$ , such that for each n, we have:

  • $K=K_n(a_1,\ldots ,a_n)$ ;

  • $[C(a_n):C]=p$ ;

  • the extension $C\subseteq C(a_1,\ldots ,a_n)$ is Galois, and

    $$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C(a_1,\ldots,a_n)/C)\cong C_p^n. \end{align*} $$

Using Lemma 6.1, we can show the following improvement of Lemma 2.7 in this case (note that the profinite completion $ C_p^{\times \omega }=\widehat {C_p^{(\omega )}}$ is not small).

Proposition 6.2. Suppose that K is an $\aleph _0$ -saturated and strict $C_p^{(\omega )}$ -field. Consider the following commutative diagram from Lemma 2.7:

Then the map $\alpha $ is an isomorphism of profinite groups.

Proof. We take $a_1,a_2,\ldots \in K$ given by Lemma 6.1. Then, for each $n>0$ , the extension $C\subset C(a_1,\ldots ,a_n)$ is Galois, with Galois group being naturally isomorphic to $C_p^n$ . Hence, we obtain the following commutative diagram originating from Lemma 2.7:

where s is the section of the inclusion map $C_p^n\to C_p^{\times \omega }$ and $t_n$ is an isomorphism. Let $\varphi _n$ denote the following composition map:

Then the map:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{\underleftarrow{\lim}}}_n(\varphi_n):\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C)\longrightarrow C_p^{\times \omega}\end{align*} $$

is the inverse map to the map $\alpha $ from Lemma 2.7.

We need the following general result, which is rather obvious.

Lemma 6.3. Let $\Phi :G\to H$ be an isomorphism of groups and assume that $G-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists. Then $H-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists and we have:

$$ \begin{align*}H-\mathrm{TCF}=L_{\Phi}(G-\mathrm{TCF}),\end{align*} $$

where $L_{\Phi }$ is the natural bijection (induced by $\Phi :G\to H$ ) between the set of all the $L_G$ -sentences and the set of all the $L_H$ -sentences.

The next result uses the ‘auto-duplication’ idea alluded to in the beginning of this subsection.

Proposition 6.4. Suppose that $C_p^{(\omega )}-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists. Then, for any existentially closed $C_p^{(\omega +1)}$ -field, its obvious reduct is an existentially closed $C_p^{(\omega )}$ -field.

Proof. For each $i>0$ , let $L_i:=L_{\mathrm {rings}}\cup \{\sigma _1,\ldots ,\sigma _i\}$ be the language of $C_p^i$ -fields. Let $L_{\omega }:=\bigcup _iL_i$ be the language of $C_p^{(\omega )}$ -fields and $L_{\omega +1}:=L_{\omega }\cup \{\sigma _0\}$ be the language of $C_p^{(\omega +1)}$ -fields.

For each $n>0$ , we have the following group isomorphisms:

$$ \begin{align*}s:C_p^{(\omega)}\longrightarrow C_p^{(\omega)}\times C_p,\ \ s(\sigma_i)=\sigma_{i-1};\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}c_n:C_p^{(\omega)}\longrightarrow C_p^{(\omega)},\ \ \sigma_0\mapsto \sigma_1,\sigma_1\mapsto \sigma_2,\ldots,\sigma_n\mapsto \sigma_{n+1},\sigma_{n+1}\mapsto \sigma_{0},\sigma_{>n+1}\mapsto \sigma_{>n+1}.\end{align*} $$

There are the corresponding bijections of languages:

$$ \begin{align*}L_s:L_{C_p^{(\omega)}}\longrightarrow L_{C_p^{(\omega)}\times C_p},\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ L_{c_n}:L_{C_p^{(\omega)}}\longrightarrow L_{C_p^{(\omega)}}.\end{align*} $$

By Lemma 6.3 and our assumption, the theory $C_p^{(\omega +1)}-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists. It is enough to show that:

$$ \begin{align*}C_p^{(\omega)}-\mathrm{TCF}\subset \left(C_p^{(\omega)}\times C_p\right)-\mathrm{TCF}.\end{align*} $$

Take $\psi \in C_p^{(\omega )}-\mathrm {TCF}$ . Then, there is $n>0$ , such that $\psi \in L_n$ . By Lemma 6.3, $L_s(\psi )\in C_p^{(\omega +1)}-\mathrm {TCF}$ . By Lemma 6.3 again, $L_{c_n}(L_s(\psi ))\in C_p^{(\omega +1)}-\mathrm {TCF}$ . Since $L_{c_n}(L_s(\psi ))=\psi $ , the result follows.

Theorem 6.5. The theory $C_p^{(\omega )}-\mathrm {TCF}$ does not exist.

Proof. Suppose that the theory $C_p^{(\omega )}-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists and we will reach a contradiction. By Proposition 6.4, there is a $C_p^{(\omega +1)}$ -field K, such that:

$$ \begin{align*} K\models C_p^{(\omega+1)}-\mathrm{TCF},\ \ \ \ \ K|_{L_{\omega}}\models C_p^{(\omega)}-\mathrm{TCF}. \end{align*} $$

Let us set:

$$ \begin{align*} C:=K^{C_p^{(\omega)}},\ \ \ \ \ C'=K^{C_p^{(\omega+1)}}. \end{align*} $$

Then, we have $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C/C')=C_p$ and:

$$ \begin{align*} [\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C'):\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)]=p=[\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C'):\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C)]. \end{align*} $$

By Proposition 6.2, we also have:

$$ \begin{align*} \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\cap K/C')\cong C_p^{\times (\omega+1)}. \end{align*} $$

Hence, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C^{\operatorname {\mathrm {alg}}}\cap K/C)$ is a codimension one ${\mathbb {F}}_p$ -subspace of $C_p^{\times (\omega +1)}$ , and it may be identified with $C_p^{\times \omega }$ .

By Lemma 2.11, we have the following isomorphism:

$$ \begin{align*}\Psi:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C')\longrightarrow \widehat{F_{\omega+1}(p)}, \end{align*} $$

and $\Psi \left (\operatorname {\mathrm {Gal}}(C)\right )=\widehat {F_{\omega }(p)}$ , which is a contradiction, since the index $[\widehat {F_{\omega +1}(p)}:\widehat {F_{\omega }(p)}]$ is infinite.

6.2. Groups containing ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$

Let G be an arbitrary group. The notion of a p.e.c. G-field, which we discussed in Section 2.1, was pointed out to us by Udi Hrushovski in an attempt to show the following.

Conjecture 6.6. If G has a subgroup isomorphic to ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ , then the theory $G-\mathrm {TCF}$ does not exist.

We discuss below a strategy for a proof of Conjecture 6.6, explain where the problem is with this strategy and give a weaker statement, which can be still proved using this strategy.

First, Hrushovski’s proof of the nonexistence of $({\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}})$ -TCF (see [Reference Kikyo13] and [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1, Section 5.1]) gives a stronger result, which we formulate below.

Theorem 6.7 Hrushovski

There is no $\aleph _0$ -saturated and p.e.c. $({\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}})$ -field K, such that:

  • the primitive third root of unity $\zeta _3$ belongs to K;

  • we have:

    $$ \begin{align*}(1,0)\cdot \zeta_3=\zeta_3^2,\ \ \ \ \ (0,1)\cdot \zeta_3=\zeta_3^2.\end{align*} $$

The hope was that if (in the situation of Conjecture 6.6) K is an $\aleph _0$ -saturated and e.c. (even just p.e.c.) G-field, then its reduct to ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ would contradict Theorem 6.7 using Proposition 2.2. However, the problem is that the induced action of ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ on K need not satisfy the conditions from Theorem 6.7. Actually, if $G={\mathbb {Q}}\times {\mathbb {Q}}$ , then this induced action never satisfies the conditions from Theorem 6.7.

It is easy to give algebraic conditions on the group G yielding the conditions from Theorem 6.7, which we do below.

Proposition 6.8. Suppose that:

  • there is $H\leqslant G$ , such that $H\cong {\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ ,

  • there is $N<G$ of index $2$ , such that $H\nsubseteq N$ .

Then, the theory $G-\mathrm {TCF}$ does not exist.

Proof. Assume that the theory $G-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists and we will reach a contradiction. By our assumptions, there is a group homomorphism $\varphi :G\to C_2$ such that $\varphi (H)=C_2$ . Since we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}({\mathbb{Q}}(\zeta_3)/{\mathbb{Q}})\cong C_2,\end{align*} $$

the above homomorphism $\varphi $ gives ${\mathbb {Q}}(\zeta _3)$ the G-field structure, such that the reduct of this structure to H satisfies the conditions from Theorem 6.7. Since the theory $G-\mathrm {TCF}$ exists, we can extend the G-field ${\mathbb {Q}}(\zeta _3)$ to an existentially closed and $\aleph _0$ -saturated G-field K, and in this case, the strategy described above works, giving a contradiction with Theorem 6.7.

We give below an explicit (although, looking a bit strange) statement, which easily follows from Proposition 6.8.

Corollary 6.9. If ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ embeds into G, then the theory $(G\times C_2)-\mathrm {TCF}$ does not exist.

Proof. We take G to play the role of N from Proposition 6.8, and we also set:

$$ \begin{align*}H:=\langle ((1,0),a),((0,1),a)\rangle,\end{align*} $$

where we identify ${\mathbb {Z}}\times {\mathbb {Z}}$ with its image in G and take a as the generator of $C_2$ .

6.3. Arbitrary Abelian groups

It is tempting to extend Theorem 1.1 to the case of an arbitrary Abelian group. However, there are the following problems.

  1. (1) On the negative argument side, it is not clear even how to show that the theory $({\mathbb {Q}}\times {\mathbb {Q}})-\mathrm {TCF}$ does not exist, as was pointed out in Section 6.2.

  2. (2) Regarding the positive argument side, it may be also unclear how to deal, e.g. with the case of $C_{p^{\infty }}\times {\mathbb {Q}}$ . We can present this group as:

    $$ \begin{align*} C_{p^{\infty}}\times {\mathbb{Q}}=\operatorname{\mathrm{\underrightarrow{\lim}}}_n C_{p^n}\times \frac{1}{n!}{\mathbb{Z}}, \end{align*} $$
    but, since the group $C_{p^n} \times {\mathbb {Z}}$ is not finite, we can not use only the Galois axioms, and we should also consider direct limits with respect to the Bass-Serre theory (see [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski1]). This may be doable, but such methods thematically do not fit to this paper, and this circle of topics will be picked up elsewhere.

Acknowledgements

We are very thankful to the referee for a careful and useful report.

We would like to thank Daniel Hoffmann, Udi Hrushovski and Nick Ramsey for their comments. The second author would like to thank the members of the model theory group in Wrocław for their constructive remarks during model theory seminars at Wrocław University.

This work was partially done in the Nesin Mathematics Village (Şirince, Izmir, Turkey), and we would like to thank the village for its hospitality.

Competing Interests

None.

Footnotes

Ozlem Beyarslan was supported by the Türkiye Bilimsel ve Teknolojik Araştirma Kurumu (Tübitak) 1001 grant no. 119F397.

Piotr Kowalski was supported by the Narodowe Centrum Nauki grant no. 2018/31/B/ST1/00357 and by the Tübitak 1001 grant no. 119F397.

1 We thank Junguk Lee for drawing a version of this diagram for us.

References

Beyarslan, Özlem and Kowalski, Piotr, Model theory of fields with virtually free group actions, Proc. London Math. Soc., 118(2) (2019), 221256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourbaki, N., Algebra II: chapters 4–7, Elements of Mathematics (Springer, Berlin Heidelberg, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chatzidakis, Z. and Hrushovski, E., Model theory of difference fields, Trans. AMS, 351(8) (2000), 29973071.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chatzidakis, Z., Hrushovski, E. and Peterzil, Y., Model theory of difference fields. II. Periodic ideals and the trichotomy in all characteristics, Proc. London Math. Soc. (3), 85(2) (2002) 257311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fried, M. D. and Jarden, M., Field arithmetic, 3rd ed., Ergebnisse der Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete. 3. Folge / A Series of Modern Surveys in Mathematics (Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, 2008).Google Scholar
Hodges, W., A Shorter Model Theory (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1997).Google Scholar
Hoffmann, D. M., Model theoretic dynamics in Galois fashion, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 170(7) (2019), 755804.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, D. M., On Galois groups and PAC substructures, Fundamenta Mathematicae, 250 (2020), 151177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, D. M. and Kowalski, P., Existentially closed fields with $G$ -derivations, Journal of London Mathematical Society, 93(3) (2016), 590618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, D. M. and Kowalski, P., Existentially closed fields with finite group actions, Journal of Mathematical Logic, 18(1) (2018), 1850003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hrushovski, E., The Elementary Theory of the Frobenius Automorphisms. Preprint (24 July 2012), available on http://www.ma.huji.ac.il/~ehud/FROB.pdf.Google Scholar
Hrushovski, E., The Manin-Mumford conjecture and the model theory of difference fields, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 112 (2001), 43115.10.1016/S0168-0072(01)00096-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kikyo, H., On generic predicates and automorphisms, 2004, Available on http://repository.kulib.kyoto-u.ac.jp/dspace/bitstream/2433/25825/1/1390-1.pdf.Google Scholar
Kikyo, H. and Pillay, A., The definable multiplicity property and generic automorphisms, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 106 (2000), 263273.10.1016/S0168-0072(00)00024-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, B., Simplicity theory, Oxford Logic Guides (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kowalski, P., Geometric axioms for existentially closed Hasse fields, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 135 (2005), 286302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macintyre, A., Generic automorphisms of fields, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 88(2) (1997), 165180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Medvedev, A., $\mathbb{Q}$ ACFA, 2015, Available on http://arxiv.org/abs/1508.06007.Google Scholar
Moosa, R. and Scanlon, T., Model theory of fields with free operators in characteristic zero, Journal of Mathematical Logic, 14(2) (2014), 1450009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kasal, Ö. and Pierce, D., Chains of theories and companionability, Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 143(11) (2015), 49374949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pillay, A. and Polkowska, D., On PAC and bounded substructures of a stable structure, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 71(2) (2006), 460472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ribes, L. and Zalesskii, P., Profinite Groups, (Springer, New York, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sjögren, N., The model theory of fields with a group action, Research Reports in Mathematics, Department of Mathematics (Stockholms universitet, 2005). Available on http://www2.math.su.se/reports/2005/7/.Google Scholar
Zou, T., Pseudofinite difference fields and counting dimensions, Journal of Mathematical Logic, 21(1) (2021), 2050022.CrossRefGoogle Scholar