Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T11:32:48.815Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Restitution of African Cultural Heritage: Revisiting Natural Law Concepts of Statehood and Property in the Context of Colonial Spoliation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 October 2024

Clemens Danda*
Affiliation:
Postdoctoral Researcher in Private and Cultural Property Law, Cologne, Germany
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In the late nineteenth century, Western Powers launched military campaigns in sub-Saharan Africa resulting in the colonization of vast territories and the spoliation of cultural property. To justify the conquest, they asserted the supremacy of Western culture and disregarded principles of international law in their dealings with African states, communities, and individuals. This article examines colonialist legal justifications such as the denial of statehood of pre-colonial sub-Saharan African societies, the notion that conquest and spoliation were justifiable, and the belief that African legal systems lacked concepts of property. The article details why these arguments contradict well-established nineteenth-century legal principles, particularly state sovereignty and private property, which together form the conceptual basis for the prohibition of spoliation. The universal nature of those principles allows for the nondiscriminatory application and interpretation of historical law and consequently the protection of African pre-colonial states and private as well as public cultural property.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of International Cultural Property Society

Introduction

Following the Napoleonic Wars and the restitution of numerous works of art seized by the French army, the Allied powers established a prohibition against the spoliation of cultural property at the Congress of Vienna in 1814–15. However, during nineteenth-century colonialism, parts of the scholarship argued that these norms could not apply to most non-Western states. They contended that the states affected were not fully integrated into the international legal order, culminating in the denial of their international protection in various contexts, including the spoliation of cultural property.

The article argues that this position contradicts nineteenth-century principles of international law and property theory, which originated from natural law. Those principles provided the grounds for the development of the prohibition of spoliation. The line of argument is complex and leads through several legal domains that could appear as detours. However, to provide well-founded arguments, a comprehensive analysis of selected fundamentals of international law becomes a necessity. First, I will argue that precolonial sub-Saharan African societies often fulfilled the traditional requirements for statehood and should have, therefore, been recognized as such. Secondly, I will show that the colonial conquest and accompanying unequal treaties violated the doctrine of just war and the accepted rules regarding peace treaties, which include provisions regarding transfers of cultural property. Thirdly, I will examine and support the position that the prohibition of spoliation was established (at least) with the Congress of Vienna in 1814–15. Finally, I will go into detail with the decisive argument that international law and its protective norms applied to African states at the time. This argument is based on the understanding that both historical international law and property theory were conceived under natural law as universal, which had a lasting effect on the law of the nineteenth century. To further substantiate this claim, I will additionally examine the interaction between colonial property regulation and African customary private law, which demonstrates that these natural law principles were not merely of theoretical relevance, but had a major and lasting effect on legal practice in the protectorates and colonies.

The line of argument takes historical natural law principles as the standard and refrains from a retroactive application of today’s legal concepts. Instead, it will show that colonial administrators, state officials, and scholars disregarded universal legal principles in pursuit of their imperial objectives. If, instead, these principles are applied in a universal and nondiscriminatory manner, one can reasonably argue that historical African societies and their cultural property were subject to the protective norms of international law. Additionally, Lockean property theory, which also found broad support in the nineteenth century, supports the recognition of Africans’ ownership of their cultural heritage.

Statehood of sub-Saharan African societies

In this first section, I discuss whether precolonial sub-Saharan African societies met the criteria for sovereign states according to the scholarship and state practice of the nineteenth century, considering shifts from earlier natural law doctrine. The protection of cultural property under nineteenth-century international law depends on characterizing these societies as sovereign states or at least international legal persons. In the following, I will examine traditional criteria for statehood and specifically address the standard of civilization as well as the relevance of recognition by other states. The question of whether international law had a universal effect in general and could apply to African societies is examined in more detail below.Footnote 1

Pre-colonial sub-Saharan societies and the requirements for statehood

At the end of the nineteenth and the beginning of the twentieth centuries, the majority of legal theorists made a strict distinction between states that were organized along the lines of Western societies and those that had diverging political structures or simply different cultural expressions. Within this framework, states such as Japan,Footnote 2 Turkey,Footnote 3 and PersiaFootnote 4 were recognized as “semi-sovereign,”Footnote 5 while sub-Saharan African societies were denied legal personality and statehood at the time. This rationale legitimized the occupation of vast African lands as res nullius under international law and private property theory.Footnote 6 Scholars argued that such societies could not be subject to equal standards under international law, but only to a different strata of international law or sui generis imperial law.Footnote 7 In the following, I will argue that these characterizations were untenable in light of the principles of international law originating from natural law, and later firmly established in the nineteenth century.

Traditional requirements for statehood

In the aftermath of the Peace of Westphalia of 1648, the requirements for state sovereignty were effective control over a territory, a permanent population, and a government.Footnote 8 Looking at accounts of the social and political structures of sub-Saharan African societies at the time, they typically appear to have met those requirements. Contemporary ethnological scholars and historians classify these societies as monarchies with well-established political structures.Footnote 9 Ojo/Ekhator, for example, contend that Benin’s legal framework at the time was “[…] well thought out, practicable, and immensely useful in the consolidation of peace […].”Footnote 10 Similar descriptions were given by early explorers such as Olfert Dapper, a Dutch geographer and historian. In 1670 he wrote on the historic Kingdom of Benin, reporting on architecture comparable to European citiesFootnote 11 and complex social hierarchies with provincial rulers subordinate to the king.Footnote 12 As another example, Thomas Edward Bowdich, an explorer of the African Company of Merchants, wrote about the Ashantee court in 1817. He compared the kingdom’s political structure to European constitutions, concluding that it implemented an effective separation of powers.Footnote 13 Monarchic rule was often legitimized based on dynastic or divine origin, as was the case in Europe at the time.Footnote 14 Wallace-Bruce, writing specifically on the question of statehood, concludes that “it is palpably clear that Africa had various independent states on the eve of colonialism.”Footnote 15

The standard of civilization

Despite meeting the traditional requirements for statehood, African states were consistently denied international legal personality and statehood. This was in part based on the argument that they were at a lower level of civilization.Footnote 16 Whilst disregarding traditional criteria for statehood, racial stereotypes were used to reinterpret idiosyncratic cultural expression in art, religion, and broader culture, defined as the decisive metrics. Tzouvala sees a combination of a “logic of biology,” which characterized Africans as less adaptable, and a “logic of improvement,” which asserted that they needed education.Footnote 17 From the perspective of third-world approaches to international law (TWAIL), the criteria of civilization represent a central aspect of horizontal inequality in international law, which exerts its effects today.Footnote 18 However, a closer analysis of the legal term of civilization shows that a shift in interpretation had taken place and that the colonialist’s emphasis on cultural expression as the decisive criterium deviates from the original concept. In its early modern meaning, it denoted a universal ethical standard for all states to act civilized. The concept did not focus on the cultural expressions of a society but posed a set of universal ethical norms. For example, Vattel defines any aggressive state that neglects the rules of just war as savage and uncivilized.Footnote 19 Grotius even argues that the opponent’s cultural expressions are irrelevant in international affairs: “Therefore it was unjust on the part of the Greeks to say, that the Barbarians were their natural enemies, merely on account of the diversity of manners, or because they seemed to be inferior in intellect.”Footnote 20 Much later, Bluntschli, who certainly supported the superiority of Western states, sometimes argued that cultural differences had no place in international law and that the aggressor was the uncivilized actor: “the war of destruction against the godless peoples of Palestine, […] is considered barbarous in the humane legal thinking of today’s world.”Footnote 21 For some, the adherence to such universal ethical norms was even linked to the legitimacy of a state. In this sense, Lormier argued in 1884 that the “measure of ethical life” […] “characterizes civilization,” to then conclude that if a state “ceases to be a State ethically, it ceases to be a State altogether.”Footnote 22

Accordingly, instead of arguing that the standard of civilization was introduced to legitimize colonialism,Footnote 23 it seems more accurate to say that colonialist scholars tried to transform the norm to suit their colonial aspirations. They shifted the emphasis of the universal ethical norm to cultural forms of expression and technological knowledge. At the same, they did not shy away from raising ethical arguments as a pretext for interventions and conquest, in particular, regarding the continuation of the slave trade in Africa. Whilst Western scholars criticized African States for the practice, they failed to note that Western powers not only had created the transatlantic slave trade but had taken considerable time to abolish it. In the colonies of the British Empire, slavery persisted until the conclusion of the apprenticeship system under the Emancipation Act of 1838.Footnote 24 France abolished the slave trade in their colonies only in 1848, while in Brazil, it endured until 1888.Footnote 25 Germany, on the other hand, never fully abolished slavery in its colonies until it lost control over them in the early nineteenth century.Footnote 26 Moreover, taking violations of human rights under continuing colonial rule into account, the uncivilized behavior of Western States lasted well into the twentieth century. Despite the perpetuation of slavery and oppression to a certain degree, the Western states considered themselves to be civilized nations. Nevertheless, in order to still be able to exclude sub-Saharan African societies from the international order, scholars ultimately had to place cultural expression above ethical conduct. Reference to unethical conduct was merely used as a façade to enforce a discriminatory doctrine.Footnote 27

Recognition of statehood

Legal positivists also argued that African societies could only achieve statehood or international legal personality through recognition by Western states.Footnote 28 This position infers that recognition replaces all other criteria for statehood. In practice, however, statehood rarely depends on recognition alone – it rather follows social realities. Historical analysis also shows that nineteenth-century scholars considered both the classical criteria as well as recognition in their assessments,Footnote 29 which indicates that the concepts of sovereignty, international legal personality, and statehood were not coherent during that period.Footnote 30 It is also telling that the element of recognition had not been considered as an indispensable requirement under Art. 3 of the Montevideo Convention of 1933. Footnote 31

Even if we assumed for a moment that recognition had become the essential criterium under nineteenth-century international law, such a shift could not have invalidated already binding international norms established by practice. Regarding historical African-Western relations, Tzouvala speaks of “alternative forms of international normativity and ordering that had been in operation for centuries both in and beyond Europe.”Footnote 32 African States had longstanding trade and diplomatic relations with Western States,Footnote 33 which supports their recognition as international legal entities.Footnote 34 Taking this perspective, later protectorate agreements appear as the continuation of existing trade relations in the regions.Footnote 35 Van der Linden points out that African rulers were also actively taking part in the creation of treaties.Footnote 36 Moreover, protectorate agreements were not considered to have dissolved the protected state under nineteenth-century doctrine,Footnote 37 further implying international legal personality.Footnote 38 The arising contradictions then resulted in the denotation of “semi-sovereignty.”Footnote 39 Koskenniemi instead argues that the protectorate was merely chosen as a front to avoid the application of undesired legal norms and to prevent uprisings.Footnote 40 In fact, many scholars at the time considered colonial protectorate treaties to be ineffective under international law, arguing they were only promises in the moral sense.Footnote 41 Consequently, they were not discussed at the Berlin conference.Footnote 42 In this regard, both Martin Footnote 43 and Nuzzo Footnote 44 point to a further contradiction in the practice of Western states on the international level. If African societies were unable to grant rights in the first place, how could Western states acquire sovereignty and base their territorial claims on these agreements?Footnote 45 Art. 34 General Act of the Berlin Conference on West AfricaFootnote 46 further proves that these agreements were used by the Western powers to assert their territorial claims and trade privileges.

In order to underpin the argument, we will examine selected English, French, and German protectorate agreements closed with sub-Saharan African rulers. Typically, they did not overtly encroach on internal sovereignty but regulated trade relationships and other aspects of external sovereignty.Footnote 47 British agreements repeatedly acknowledged the internal sovereignty of African societies. For example, one agreement refers to “the principal chiefs holding authority on the south Bank of the River Congo.”Footnote 48 However, Van der Linden points to the vagueness of the language regarding internal aspects.Footnote 49 Sometimes, such agreements granted extensive influence over internal affairs: “The Chiefs […] hereby engage to assist the British Consular or other officers in the execution of such duties as may be assigned to them.”Footnote 50 French agreements typically did not extend to the cession of internal sovereignty: “The French Republic will not interfere in the government or in the internal affairs of Baol. The rights of the Teigne (king) and his successors remain absolutely the same as in the past.”Footnote 51 German agreements also repeatedly left internal sovereignty untouched. The agreement with Mlapa, King of Togo, says the following: “so that [King Mlapa] may be enabled to preserve the independence of his territory. [He] will not cede any part of his country with rights of sovereignty to any foreign power […].”Footnote 52

Besides such agreements closed in the context of trade relations, Western Powers also recognized African states in the aftermath of military campaigns, which illustrates that recognition often followed military realities rather than legal assessments. This was the case when the British recognized Ashanti sovereignty in the Anglo-Ashanti Treaty of Friendship of 1817. Footnote 53 The same accounts for the Treaty of Wuchale of 1889, in which Italy recognized the Ethiopian empire.Footnote 54 Western powers also acknowledged sovereignty when they saw no contradiction to their economic and political interests.Footnote 55 These scenarios all suggest that sub-Saharan African states were already sovereign beforehand. It had just been the case that they were forced to prove it militarily. This approach ultimately results in the doctrine of the right of the strongest, which is beyond legal argumentation.

In conclusion, given that the traditional criteria for statehood were often fulfilled by African sub-Saharan Societies and that recognition of their sovereignty took place within early trade and protectorate relations as well as after military conflicts, the argument can be made that these societies had been sovereign states. Therefore, both unilateral annexations as well as treaties such as the General Act of the Berlin Conference on West Africa of 1885Footnote 56 could not affect their sovereignty. As a second consequence, only those territorial acquisitions or cessions of sovereignty that were based on valid legal agreements could be considered effective.Footnote 57 As we have already seen, the protectorate and other colonial treaties generally only provided for the transfer of external sovereignty. However, in order to cover other scenarios, the next chapter will also take unequal treaties in the context of military threats and occupations into account.

The colonial conquest and accompanying treaties under historical international law

Taking a closer look at the legality of colonial conquest and colonial treaties

Colonial conquest and the just war doctrine

Western powers frequently found themselves dissatisfied with the external control that they gained through protectorate agreements. Consequently, they sought to expand their influence by directly conquering territories or asserting further dominance over internal affairs.Footnote 58 Regarding the legal effect of conquest, there were two competing legal doctrines discussed in nineteenth-century scholarship. The first argues for an unconditional right to go to war (liberum ius ad bellum),Footnote 59 which is sometimes related to the Hobbesian state of nature paradigm where human interaction unfolds in the absence of any reciprocal rights and obligations.Footnote 60 Historically, however, the liberum ius ad bellum typically represented an aspect of internal sovereignty. For example, Bodin introduces the right to wage war in his discussion on internal sovereignty. Only a legitimate ruler could declare war, as opposed to any private undertaking.Footnote 61 Against this historical background, the nineteenth-century doctrine of liberum ius ad bellum appears to overemphasize a preliminary aspect of internal sovereignty when dealing with the much broader question of the legality of the war. More important, however, is that this reading introduces contradictions into the existing framework. It not only runs against the right to self-determination of other states, but it generally disregards the fundamental peacekeeping function of international law altogether. Simon examined the development of liberum ius ad bellum in detail and came to the conclusion that it never gained enough prominence in state practice and the political discourse to be considered predominant.Footnote 62 Instead, he suggests that its relevance had been overstated by twentieth-century legal historians.Footnote 63

The much older bellum iustum doctrine dictates to the contrary, that wars are only lawful in situations of self-help or self-defence. It can be traced back to Roman law,Footnote 64 and was later upheld by natural law scholars such as Grotius Footnote 65 and Vattel. Footnote 66 Simon argues that this principle remained dominant during the nineteenth century.Footnote 67 As a central source, he refers to Bluntschli, who wrote that the legitimacy of wars remained a question of international law,Footnote 68 rejecting unrestrained acts of war. Simon also describes a “discourse of legitimacy,” which means that wars always had been justified politically throughout the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.Footnote 69 For example, the French campaign of 1792 had been legitimized as a “just defense of a free people against the aggression of a king.”Footnote 70 The same accounts for the political justifications of the Franco-Prussian war of 1871.Footnote 71 Applying the same rationale, Western powers tried to legitimize their colonial military campaigns based on self-defense. Westlake writes in 1894 that “except in the case of unprovoked aggression justifying conquest, an uncivilized population has rights which make its free consent necessary to the establishment over it of a government possessing international validity.”Footnote 72 Accordingly, military operations were typically referred to as punitive expeditions, implying retaliation for the violation of the rights of Western powers such as those agreed upon in a protectorate agreement. The Sack of Benin of 1897, for example, was explained as a retaliation for the violation of bilateral trade agreements and the killing of members of a British mission to Benin. Whatever the historical assessment of those incidents ultimately might be,Footnote 73 the submission of the entire Kingdom of Benin can hardly be considered a proportionate retaliatory response.

In summary, given the unbroken tradition of a discourse of legitimacy, it is sound to argue that the bellum iustum doctrine was considered to be the predominate doctrine, which, at the same time, puts the relevance of liberum ius ad bellum into perspective. Acknowledging the necessity of a just cause for war fundamentally alters the legal assessment of any conquest and occupation. Regarding spoliation in particular, it is often overlookedFootnote 74 that the doctrine of just war precludes the unlawful occupier from acquiring private and public cultural property. This specifically excludes legitimations based on military necessity and compensation for war expenses. Hence, the spoliation and confiscation of both private and public cultural property during the period of colonialization of sub-Saharan states requires historically sound justification. In general, it seems unlikely that such a justification can be provided.

Validity of protectorate and cession treaties in colonial contexts

Western powers also tried to acquire territory and sovereignty by means of cession of territory. To name some British examples, this was the case with the Lagos Treaty of 1861,Footnote 75 the treaty with the King of Bagroo and his chiefs of the same year, and the treaty regarding the territory of Badagry.Footnote 76 The French concluded various cession treaties with African rulers starting from the beginning of the nineteenth century.Footnote 77 The violent colonial context necessitates the historical analysis of each agreement and the intricate discussion of the requirements of valid international treaties in the nineteenth century. According to Lindley, the validity of international agreements requires the absence of fraud or coercion.Footnote 78 However, this intuitive rationale is challenged in the context of peace negotiations. In addition, the agreements must have been comprehensible to the local representatives in terms of language and the legal concepts used.Footnote 79 The support for these requirements was not necessarily motivated by a desire to protect Africans, but, rather, to create a title that the Western powers could recognize as valid among each other. However, as a consequence, colonial agreements still required free and informed consent from the perspective of legal doctrine.Footnote 80 Van der Linden additionally points out that some protectorate treaties were kept vague in order to give Western powers a margin of discretion in the “twilight zone between cession and protectorate,”Footnote 81 which again introduced challenges to interpretation.Footnote 82

The most problematic treaties are undoubtedly those imposed on African societies through threats of force. In theory, peace treaties served the goal of ending the cause of warFootnote 83 – typically the alleged aggression by the enemy. The peace treaty would then arrange for compensation for the costs of war. Hence, the validity of peace treaties was based on the just war doctrine.Footnote 84 Vattel provides a corresponding passage in his writings: “[The aggressor] must restore what he has unjustly taken, must reimburse the expenses of the war, and repair the damages.”Footnote 85 However, taking practical consideration into account, he also argues that the pact sunt servanda principle prevails over fairness.Footnote 86 Only “forced submission to conditions which are equally offensive to justice and all the duties of humanity” cannot be tolerated.Footnote 87 Grotius follows the same line of thought, arguing that peace treaties serve to end the cause of war and provide for compensation.Footnote 88 At the same time, they are binding even if concluded under coercion. However, the validity of unequal treaties always remains undetermined to some degree: “It does not follow that the party who has extorted some such promise by an unlawful war can retain what he has received without violating the honor and duty of a good man, or even can compel the other to hold to the agreement, whether sworn or not. For, essentially and in its nature, the transaction remains unjust.”Footnote 89 Whilst both scholars emphasize the imperative to achieve peace even by tolerating unequal peace agreements, they still provide a pathway for (later) revocation based on unfairness. Despite repeated invocation of pacta sunt servanda, revisions remained thinkable.Footnote 90 This was certainly the case where the cession of territory threatened the existence of a state.

Specifically, in the context of spoliation and translocation of cultural property, the doubts regarding the validity of unequal treaties resurface. The inclusion of cultural property in peace agreements in the nineteenth century reveals that the dispossession of cultural property already required justification. Acquisition by mere occupation was already rejected at the time.Footnote 91 For example, the Armistices of Bologna and the later Treaty of Tolentino signed in 1796 and 1797 between the Papal States and the French Republic, foresaw the transfer of more than one hundred paintings and other works of art to the French.Footnote 92 Relevant parts of the European public and even French military personnel still opposed the confiscations.Footnote 93 In the context of colonial treaties, both the lack of legitimate cause for war and coercion were often present. Vattel specifically refers to treaties concluded between Cortés and the Empire of Mexico, arguing that all subversive countermeasures by the Mexicans would have been legitimate.Footnote 94 Regarding cultural property specifically, the Congress of Vienna and the subsequent restitutions provide the blueprint to understand the inner workings of unequal peace treaties. The peace treaties with the French were initially tolerated to achieve peace. However, the transfers were still considered illegitimate,Footnote 95 and their restitution did not require a new legal basis (actus contrarius).Footnote 96 In particular, restitution clauses were not deemed a necessity.Footnote 97 A main negotiator at the Congress of Vienna, Lord Viscount Castlereagh, argued that the spoliation had been “contrary to every principle of justice and the usages of modern warfare” and that the concluded armistices did not provide a valid title for the acquisition of spoils.Footnote 98 These same principles apply to colonial conquest. The analysis will typically lead to the conclusion that the agreement concluded during an unjustified occupation under duress is invalid.

The protection of cultural property under nineteenth-century international law

The prohibition of spoliation

The origins of the prohibition of spoliation

Having explored the relevance of the just war doctrine for the assessment of colonial conquest and unequal treaties, I will shortly turn to the already well-studied development of the prohibition of spoliation. Throughout ancient and medieval times, conquest and taking spoils to compensate for war expenses were considered lawful.Footnote 99 Grotius, for example, argued in favor of acquisition by occupation.Footnote 100 However, while he held that enemy property was not protected under Roman or modern international law,Footnote 101 he pleaded for moderation based on moral grounds.Footnote 102 It should also be noted that he repeatedly contextualizes claims for compensation with just causes for war,Footnote 103 which completes the contradiction. How could the aggressor legally acquire spoils in an unlawful war? Vattel then draws the consequence from this, declaring that cultural property may only be seized to weaken the enemy’s military efforts or for punishment in just wars.Footnote 104 He unambiguously connects compensation by spoliation to just causes of war.

Much later, the Congress of Vienna (see above) implicitly adopted this rationale, representing the first distinct historical moment where the practice of unjustified spoliation was rejected as a means of acquisition during unjust wars.Footnote 105 Accordingly, Jenschke Footnote 106 and Sandholz Footnote 107 argue that the norm was established in the aftermath of the Napoleonic campaigns and at the Congress of Vienna.Footnote 108 In addition to the repatriation of their cultural property, the Papal State and Austria,Footnote 109 as well as Egypt under Ottoman rule,Footnote 110 passed laws restricting the export of cultural goods, which further supports the argument. However, contemporary scholars in part reference older state practices when trying to determine the adoption of the prohibition as a binding norm.Footnote 111 They date it to the mid-eighteenth centuryFootnote 112 or the beginning of the nineteenth century.Footnote 113 This article does not go into the details of this discussion, it simply supports the majority opinion that the ban was at least introduced with the Congress of Vienna, which is sufficient for the argument regarding the period of colonization of sub-Saharan Africa.

The prohibition of spoliation in the second half of the nineteenth century

A legal text often cited as the central source regarding the protection of cultural property during the second half of the nineteenth century is the Lieber Code of 1863.Footnote 114 Its articles, 31, 34, and 36, mainly provide that “ownership is to be settled by the ensuing treaty of peace,” mirroring the primary peacekeeping function of peace treaties discussed above. Aligned with national provisions on lawful conduct during the seizure of property,Footnote 115 the Code further provides that “in no case shall [such works] be sold or given away […] nor shall they ever be privately appropriated, or wantonly destroyed or injured.” The provisions reflect traditional concepts regarding the seizure and acquisition of cultural property by means of negotiation. Hence, the Lieber Code did not introduce an all-encompassing prohibition of spoliation of cultural property, it referred to peace treaties. It is also silent in regard to protecting existing private property positions in peace negotiations.

Scholars at the time, instead, emphasized the significance of safeguarding private and cultural property during times of war.Footnote 116 Bluntschli explains the underlying rationale for the protection of private property: “Since the war is not being waged against civilians, there is no reason in the law that private law should perish or be subjected to the whim of the enemy.”Footnote 117 Given its peaceful cultural purpose, cultural property cannot be seized.Footnote 118 However, he also considers private cultural property to be the subject of peace treaties.Footnote 119 Like his predecessors, he emphasizes the principle of pacta sunt servanda in the context of peace treaties,Footnote 120 but makes an exception where the existence and development of the conquered state are at stake.Footnote 121 The argument regarding the development of the state is potentially linked to the much later reference to the doctrine of self-determination in the twentieth century.Footnote 122 Bluntschli’s contemporary Fiore held a similar view, arguing that cultural property cannot be seized,Footnote 123 and that coerced contracts are invalid where physical violence is involved.Footnote 124 Just as with Grotius and Vattel, the tension between banning spoliation and unequal peace treaties is tolerated by these later authors, given the greater political goal to end violent conflicts. However, the fundamental legal principles of just cause and free consent cannot be set aside completely. Bluntschli was, therefore, forced to uphold the just war doctrine whilst dissociating it from the practical consequences of war and unequal treaties.Footnote 125

Leaving the question of unequal treaties unanswered, the Brussels International Declaration concerning the Laws and Customs of War of 1874 Footnote 126 at least clarified the questions of spoliation during an ongoing war. What we discover is an idiosyncratic convergence of the protection of private and cultural property. The Brussels Declaration provides that “[…] Private property cannot be confiscated” (Art. 38), and that “the property of municipalities, that of institutions dedicated to religion, charity, and education, the arts and sciences even when State property, shall be treated as private property” (Art. 8). The declaration differentiates between state property usable for military purposes (Art. 53) and public property designated for cultural activities, civil functions, or religious practices that fall under the protective framework of private property and, therefore, cannot be seized (Art. 56). This understanding extends the rationale that wars are not waged against civilians and their private property, extending it to public goods that serve civilian use remaining consistent with the civilian-combatant dichotomy.Footnote 127 Hence, cultural property is not only protected by (international) public law but also under national private law, holding significance for the causes of action for restitution (e.g. replevin or the rei vindicatio). These provisions and the underlying concept were later incorporated, identically, in the Hague Conventions of 1899 and 1907 (Arts. 46 and 56). The seamless continuation indicates that the ban on the spoilation of private and public cultural property was perceived as a firmly established norm. Since international conventions were often regarded as the formal recognition of already established customary norms,Footnote 128 it is perfectly reasonable that the Brussels provisions only codified already binding customary norms.

In summary, looking at state practice we find restitutions taking place in parallel to a discourse of legitimacy, reaffirming just cause as the fundamental requirement for war, spoliation, and compensation.Footnote 129 Positivists later stressed the necessity of conventions,Footnote 130 a requirement met through the incorporation of the ban on spoliation in the Brussels Declaration of 1874 and the later Hague Conventions of 1899 and 1907. Hence, the norms safeguarding cultural and private property were established prior to the Berlin Conference of 1884-85,Footnote 131 which marked the onset of the most aggressive phase of colonial conquest of the nineteenth century. Scholarly doctrine and conventions seem to undermine these principles by tolerating the transfer of cultural property based on unequal peace treaties. However, they also provide exceptions for cases of straightforward violent coercion, or where the existence and development of a state are under threat. Concerning colonial cessions, protectorate treaties, and resulting transfers of cultural property, their validity should, therefore, be evaluated case-by-case to establish whether requirements for consent were fulfilled or whether exceptions apply.

The conceptual foundation of the prohibition of spoliation in universal international law principles

Universality and non-retroactivity

After the examination of the temporal scope of the prohibition of spoliation, I will now turn to the pivotal and overarching question, asking whether African societies were subject to international law and the prohibition of spoliation. First, the article argues that due to the universal claims of natural law, international law had at least a self-binding effect on Western states, including their interactions with non-Western states. Second, the article argues that the prohibition of spoliation specifically represents an expression of universal natural law principles; in particular, those of state sovereignty and the right to property. The prohibition was introduced during a period that directly relied on natural law as the central source of international law.Footnote 132 By limiting the universal principles of state sovereignty, private property, and, subsequently, the protection of cultural property to Western states, scholars and statesmen in the nineteenth century disregarded the universal and, therefore, nondiscriminatory structure of natural law. Natural law principles could not simply be abrogated to the detriment of third parties by agreements inter partes or later positivist demands. This even aligns with the central goal of TWAIL to achieve “a more just international legal order.”Footnote 133 However, we should not reject Western international law, but rediscover and insist on the nondiscriminatory character of its natural law concepts. It is crucial to address fears that such an endeavor contradicts the principle of non-retroactivity.Footnote 134 However, it seems clear that we cannot equate the interpretation of nineteenth-century law from the perspective of natural law principles with the retroactive application of today’s laws. The reference to universal principles of natural law does not obscure the history of international law but outlines its conceptual foundations.

International law as a universal framework

Whether based on the notion of an international community (civitas maximas) or the self-interest of states, natural law provides universal rights and obligations equally applicable to all states erga omnes. Regarding the topic of sovereignty, the standard for civilization has already been uncovered as a universal ethical concept (see above). Vattel describes natural law in this universal and equal manner: “Since men are naturally equal […] nations composed of men […] are naturally equal, and inherit from nature the same obligations and rights.”Footnote 135 In addition to this universal nature, natural law principles were in part also thought to be binding jus cogens vis-à-vis conventions and customs. Vattel states that “every nation is bound to relinquish [an unjust or unlawful custom] since nothing can oblige or authorize her to violate the law of nature.”Footnote 136 This concept of universal jus cogens was later upheld by many scholars in the nineteenth century.Footnote 137 Halleck writes in 1874: “Customs […] which are unjust and illegal, and in violation of natural and divine law, have no binding force.”Footnote 138 The same accounts for Bluntschli, who held that treaties contradicting recognized human rights or jus cogens are void.Footnote 139 This specifically applies in times of war, as noted by Lorimer in Reference Lorimer1884: “The rights of civilisation, as jura universalia, impose corresponding duties, officia or debita universalia, which limit not only the means which belligerents may jurally employ, but the manner in which they may employ them.”Footnote 140 Nineteenth-century international lawyers took the universal application of fundamental ethical principles for granted. However, they failed to recognize the consequences of this concept in the context of colonialism. They simply ignored arising contradictions; in particular, when they held African states and communities accountable for alleged violations of universal ethical and legal principles – particularly the practice of slavery – while denying them equal enjoyment of universal rights.Footnote 141 It should also be noted that universality and non-discrimination are relevant in the context of the persistent objector rule, which could be brought up as a defense for the Western states in this context. While the objection to a custom by a state – in our case the prohibition on spoliation – is tolerated, it cannot be effective against individual states. Furthermore, if the prohibition is, instead, considered to be a peremptory norm (jus cogens) – as is the case todayFootnote 142 – the consistent objector argument would not be available in the first place.

Private Property as a universal right

Modern private property theory finds its fundamentals in universal natural law reasoning. First, from the perspective of international law, the protection of property is mediated through the state. Accordingly, foreign acts related to property in the state are ineffective. This also follows from the notion of state sovereignty. During times of war and when spoliation occurs, however, the protection of property as a mere derivative of the state’s sovereignty seems insufficient. In my view, it is also the underlying understanding of the Brussels Declaration and the Hague Conventions – which determine that public cultural property follows private property protection – and that the prohibition of spoliation finds its ultimate foundation not in a state’s sovereignty but in universal property rights. Early modern doctrine maintained that private property emerged from a state of nature before communities started to hold land and goods in common. This was also the understanding of both Grotius Footnote 143 and Vattel. Footnote 144 However, it was still debated whether property could be considered a natural right based on labor (natural right theory)Footnote 145 or if it originated from the social contract of the community (contract theory).Footnote 146 The latter concept suggests that the existence of property depends on a society’s sovereignty, meaning the attribution of land and goods by the state. In this debate, however, important scholars and sources supported the natural rights theory. This includes, for example, scholars like Blackstone: “[…] Every m[a]n [is] entitled to enjoy [property] whether out of society or in it.”Footnote 147 and Art. 2 of the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen of 1789, which conceives property as a natural and imprescriptible right.Footnote 148 Thiers reaffirmed the theory in Reference Thiers1848, stating that “property is a permanent fact, universal in all times and in all cultures.”Footnote 149

However, I do not contend that the natural rights theory prevails over the contract theory. Instead, they potentially complement each other: During times of peace, the fate of property depends on its regulation by the state. At this stage, the international law dimension of private property remains mediated through the state’s sovereignty. Natural rights, however, come into the foreground where unjust expropriations or conflicts between states occur. This is particularly true whenever a society collapses because of an internal conflict, war, or occupation. In such scenarios, individual rights require protection beyond mediation via sovereignty. As said, this rationale underlies the concepts formalized by the Brussels Declaration and the Hague Conventions. The important contribution of these documents was to emphasize the extension of protection to public cultural property used for civil purposes. Based on natural rights, the ban on spoliation offers protection irrespective of the recognition of the host state’s sovereignty. From this follows for the colonial context, that both the private property of Africans and their public cultural property should have been recognized as such, even when the sovereignty of their state was rejected!

Customary African law and colonial regulation

Examining the tension between colonial regulation and African customary private law

Western scholars certainly struggled to understand African customary law and relate it to the universal principles of sovereignty and property, as discussed above. However, scholars still granted local inhabitants basic protection over their possessions – another tacit recognition that universal natural law concepts applied. However, the main issue of colonial regulation and the scholarly debate concerned the redistribution of land, whilst movables, including cultural property, were typically not discussed or regulated. Following Lockean and natural law property theories, they mostly agreed that cultivated land and movable property belonged to the inhabitants,Footnote 150 which is reflected by British, French, and German colonial land regulations.Footnote 151 Before we look at European scholarship and colonial regulation, we should first have a look at African private and communal rights, which were the topic of the (often misled) discussion.

African customary property and possessory rights

Precolonial African states and communities had established complex legal rules regarding individual, tribal, and familial property. Our knowledge of the historical details, however, remains somewhat limited given the oral tradition.Footnote 152 These legal positions were sometimes characterized by Western scholars as mere relative obligations between chiefs, communities, families, and individual members in the context of status relationships.Footnote 153 However, we now understand that they were instead conceived as communal or familial propertyFootnote 154 administered by an elder leader.Footnote 155 Individual rights were often designed as possessory rights, which were not freely tradeable.Footnote 156 However, the systems always allowed determining the possessor of a specific right in the land (usus fructus, administration rights)Footnote 157 or a movable.Footnote 158 , Footnote 159 The right to use land could also be subject to sale or mortgage if the members of the community were involved.Footnote 160 Ultimately, control lay with the community and not with the individual when it came to valuable goods. This solution mirrors European concepts of public property, property held in trust, the medieval dominium of a guild or a house,Footnote 161 and, specifically, cultural property understood as an inalienable heritage.Footnote 162 Western Scholars recognize art collections as aggregated assets, arguing for the restitution of individual pieces to restore their integrity.Footnote 163 Moreover, non-individualistic forms of property were rarely subject to abolition in the West, a prominent exception being the Fideicommissum,Footnote 164 which, in turn, shows that even in modern times, forms of common property or possession are by no means alien to Western law. In summary, collective forms of property were recognized in domestic Western settings and the same recognition should have been afforded to African customary rights. To simply assume that there were no sufficient rules and rights regarding land and property seems discriminatory per se. Instead, the modification of the well-known Roman law principle to “ubi societas, ibi proprietas” appears more intuitive.

The relation of African customary law to colonial treaties and regulation

Colonial treaties often acknowledged the property rights of local inhabitants, which aligned with the principle in international law that mere cession of territory did not affect land ownership.Footnote 165 For example, while the German-Cameron agreement foresaw complete cession of territory and sovereignty, it guaranteed the continuation of land rights: “The land now cultivated by us and the land on which cities are built shall remain the property of the present owners and their legal successors.”Footnote 166 When read in context, the same is inferred by the Lagos Treaty of 1861 regarding the cession of Lagos Island to Britain: “[…] in the transfer of lands, the stamp of [the souverain] affixed to the document will be proof that there are no other native claims upon it […].”Footnote 167 Similar provisions can again be found in the treaty regarding the cession of the Badagry territory to Britain.Footnote 168 The broad recognition of private positions within colonial treaties was then transposed into internal colonial regulations, but the latter did not typically override local law. The relationship was, rather, one of continuity and subsidiarity. Under English law, only local laws that conflicted with Western moral standards were considered invalid, which, for example, included laws concerning slavery. In this regard, a Privy Council decision from 1722 is commonly cited: “The laws and customs of the conquered country shall hold place unless where they are contrary to our religion, or enact anything that is malum in se or is silent, for in all such cases the laws of the conquering country shall prevail.”Footnote 169 Blackstone also endorsed the continuity concept.Footnote 170 It then persisted into the late nineteenth century and was followed by the Supreme Court Ordinance of 1876 regarding the Gold Coast Colony,Footnote 171 and in Nigeria and Ghana.Footnote 172 It is reasonable to assume – but is subject to further case study – that the customs on cultural and private property typically fulfilled the requirements.

Following the same logic of subsidiarity and continuity, German regulation left customary law to the local inhabitants.Footnote 173 The contemporary scholar Gerstemeyer went further and asserted that customary laws also applied in private relations between local inhabitants and German citizens.Footnote 174 As far as individual rights were concerned, the land ordinances in German East Africa required that customary law positions be taken into account and that agreements should be concluded with local communities.Footnote 175 Anyone could acquire land ownership by providing proof that they had enclosed the land for two years. Similar arguments hold for German-occupied Cameroon,Footnote 176 where the KronlandgesetzFootnote 177 and the EnteignungsverordnungFootnote 178 acknowledged customary rights. However, since the terra nullis doctrine was applied, land distribution was still often enforced violently, and legal uncertainties prevailed in practice.Footnote 179 Decisive for the case of cultural property, however, was that movables were not regulated, which means that potentially discriminatory regulation in the context of ownership of landFootnote 180 did not extend to movable cultural goods.Footnote 181 Following the continuation principle, local customary law applied to these goods.

Recognition of individual rights by scholarship

However, in some cases, treaties and internal regulations remained silent on the question of individuals’ rights.Footnote 182 Relevant answers must, therefore, be derived from the scholarly literature of the nineteenth century. Following the above-described natural law concepts and the Lockean notion of acquisition of property by labor, individuals could acquire rights over land by cultivation and movables by their production. Nuzzo has provided us with an overview of the scholarship on this question.Footnote 183 Nineteenth-century scholar Fiore argued that land could not be occupied if it had already been cultivated by Africans.Footnote 184 Catellanis stated that private rights persisted despite the right of the colonial powers to occupy empty territory.Footnote 185 Even Bluntschli, who denied Africans their property rights, admitted that local inhabitants could not be displaced against their will.Footnote 186 In general, the scholarship agreed that arbitrary occupation of cultivated land was generally unlawful. This strongly suggests that rights to movable property persisted – cultural property is typically the result of labor or the cultivation of a specific site.

Rejection of African claims by Western courts

However, Western courts often rejected property claims and justified spoliations or expropriations, creating not only tension with natural law principles but, as we have seen, also with colonial treaties, colonial regulation, and scholarly opinion.Footnote 187 Whilst this is a topic of national law, some aspects should be noted here. In general, there appears to be a problematic link between the historical denial of African private property claims and some decisions by today’s courts. The infamous 1919 UK Privy Council decision in Re Southern Rhodesia exemplifies the discriminatory rationale: “It would be idle to impute to such people some shadow of the rights known to our law and then to transmute it into the substance of transferable rights of property as we know them.”Footnote 188 Without relying on the underlying racist rationale, later decisions have sometimes rejected restitution claims based on private property.Footnote 189 Typically, they argue that restitution is a question of diplomacy and public law only. However, in most systems, such court decisions can only affect the parties involved due to the subjective constraints of the res judicata doctrine.Footnote 190 Hence, the decision may be limited to the specific case at hand without establishing a broader effect. In jurisdictions with binding precedents, however, such decisions can be overruled by arguing human rights violations under the per incuriam rule. Decisions such as in Re Southern Rhodesia clearly stood in contradiction to international legal principles, colonial treaties and regulations, and scholarship, which undermines their relevance within the system.Footnote 191

Conclusion

The argument for the restitution of African cultural heritage leads through many legal fields. This article revisits the treatment of African states and their private or public cultural property under the international law of the nineteenth century. Typically, African states were denied international recognition, and their communities, families, and individuals were deprived of their private rights. The article argues that the colonialist interpretation of international law at the time was not compatible with nineteenth-century law. Instead, natural law principles regarding state sovereignty and property were already well-established and perceived as universal by early modern international legal scholars. The formulation of these principles and Europe’s own experience of spoliation culminated in the prohibition of spoliation of cultural property. Western natural law scholars had already established a nondiscriminatory universal framework that was only later adapted to imperial interests. However, the Western powers still struggled to deny the natural law foundations of international law when it came to the questions of African sovereignty and customary private law. The conclusion of colonial treaties and the subsidiary application of African private law are proof of these tensions. Established universal natural law principles and state practice of the late nineteenth century, therefore, allow for an interpretation of nineteenth-century law that provides equal protection for African cultural property under both international law and African customary private law.

Footnotes

1 See below, Chapter on ‘The Conceptual Foundation of the Prohibition of Spoliation in Universal International Law Principles,’ particularly the Subchapter on ’Universality and Non-Retroactivity.

2 Tzouvala Reference Tzouvala2020, 51.

4 Spira Reference Spira2020, 334.

5 Tzouvala Reference Tzouvala2020, 52.

6 Compare the passage on occupation in Martens Reference Martens1883, 351.

7 Saksena Reference Saksena2019, 10; Sylvest Reference Sylvest2008, 410 et seq.

8 Gebeye 2021, 15.

9 For example, Kochakova Reference Kochakova, Claessen and Oosten1996, 49; Edo Reference Edo2010, 1–7; cf. also Bradbury Reference Bradbury1957, 42 et seq.

10 Ojo and Ekhator Reference Ojo and Ekhator2020, 40.

11 Dapper Reference Dapper1670, 486.

12 Ibid., 491.

13 Bowdich Reference Bowdich1819, 252 et seq.

14 Cf. Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 74.

15 Wallace-Bruce Reference Wallace-Bruce1985, 583.

16 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 72 et seq.

17 Tzouvala Reference Tzouvala2020, 48 et seq.

18 E.g. Anghie Reference Anghie2006, 742.

19 Vattel Reference Vattel2008 [1758], book III, chap. IX § 167; Book III Chap. III § 34.

20 Grotius [1625] Reference Grotius and Whewell1853, book III chap. XXII, nr. X, 353.

21 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1872, 298.

22 Lormier Reference Lormier1884, 71.

23 The Institute de Droit International exemplifies this shift of the universal standard to a mere designation for Western culture by describing itself as the organ of “legal conscience/consciousness of the civilized world” (Art. 1 Statue of the Institute of International Law, Ghent 1873).

24 Green Reference Green1991, 158.

25 Kolchin Reference Kolchin1987, 49.

27 Compare Vázquez-Bermúdez Reference Vázquez-Bermúdez2019, 53.

28 Oppenheim Reference Oppenheim1905, 110; van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 73. For an introduction to the theories about the legal nature of the Congo Free State see Smets Reference Smets2020.

29 Crawford Reference Crawford2006, 12.

30 This resembles the overemphasized dichotomy of natural law and legal positivism. In this regard see Vec Reference Vec, Besson and d’Aspremont2017 who argues that in the late nineteenth century, there was a methodological pluralism of natural law and positivist approaches.

31 Inter-American Convention on the Rights and Duties of States, signed on December 26, 1933 in Montevideo.

32 Tzouvala Reference Tzouvala2020, 47.

33 Wallace-Bruce Reference Wallace-Bruce1985, 582.

34 Concerning restitution Schöneberg Reference Schöneberg2021, 34; compare Martin Reference Martin2021, 51 et seq; Raič Reference Raič2002, 35.

35 Martin Reference Martin2021, 49.

36 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 79 et seq.

37 Jellinek Reference Jellinek1882, 18 et seq and 53; Westlake, Reference Westlake1894, 184. The British Foreign Jurisdiction Act of 1843 commonly grounds territorial claims in derivative acquisition: “Whereas by treaty, capitulation, grant, usage, sufferance, and other lawful means Her Majesty hath power and jurisdiction within divers countries and places out of Her Majesty`s dominions.” Cf. Grotius, 1625, Book III Chap. 3 XXII argues in favor of the sovereignty of protected tributaries.

38 Jellinek Reference Jellinek1882, 29 and 55, Korman Reference Korman1996, 129; Lindley Reference Lindley1926, 181 et seq.

39 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 90.

40 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2004, 124–125.

41 Cf. the references at van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 74.

43 Martin Reference Martin2021, 52.

45 Lindley Reference Lindley1926, 173 acknowledges this tension.

46 General Act of the Berlin Conference on West Africa, 26 February 1885.

47 Such was the case for the Kingdom of Benin, see Kiwara-Wilson Reference Kiwara-Wilson2016, 6.

48 Engagement with chiefs holding authority on the South Bank of the River Congo. Slave Trade. Commerce. Humans Sacrifices. Religion, 27.3. 1876, cited from Hertslet Reference Hertslet1880, 36.

49 Cf. Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 220 et seq.

50 Cited in Hertslet Reference Hertslet1967, 120.

51 Agreement between the King of Baol and the French Republic of March 1883, cited after Lindley Reference Lindley1926, 184.

52 Erster Schutzvertrag Togo 1884.

53 Commentators of the nineteenth century acknowledged that the negotiations and the treaties could be seen as grounds for recognition of sovereignty, see e.g. Ellis Reference Ellis1893, 143.

54 For details see Elliesie Reference Elliesie2017 [1889].

55 An interesting example – outside of the African context – is the recognition of the Kingdom of Hawaii. To prevent occupation, the kingdom gave itself a Western-style constitution and was subsequently recognized by the United States from 1826 to 1893 (see Merry Reference Merry2000, 77 et seq).

56 General Act of the Berlin Conference on West Africa, 26 February 1885.

57 Alexandrowicz Reference Alexandrowicz1973, 80.

58 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 145 et seq.

59 For details see Hendrik 2018.

60 Hobbes Reference Hobbes1650, Pt. I, Ch. 14, II. The principle does not take into account the bilateral and multilateral realities that emerged after the end of the state of nature.

61 See Bodin Reference Bodin and Oswald1592, First book 1–2; compare Lee Reference Lee2021, 193.

62 Simon Reference Simon2018, 135.

63 Simon Reference Simon2018, 124.

64 Draper Reference Draper1964, 82 et seq.

65 Grotius [1625] Reference Grotius and Whewell1853., book III chap. XXII, nr. X, 353.

66 Compare Vattel Reference Vattel2008 [1758], book III, chap. XI; in the context of restitution O’Keefe Reference O’Keefe2006, 5 et seq.

68 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1868, 289.

69 Abel Reference Abel1871, 137 cited in Simon Reference Simon2018, 131.

70 War declaration of the French National Assembly, 20 April 1792.

71 Simon Reference Simon2018, 130.

72 Westlake Reference Westlake1894, 139.

73 The mission is now commonly acknowledged by historians as a provocative act by the British in the wider strategy to overthrow the King (Oba). As direct proof for this theory accounts James Phillip’s dispatch to the Foreign Office before the mission: “I therefore ask for His Lordship’s permission to visit Benin City in February next, to depose and remove the King of Benin and to establish a native council in his place and to take such further steps for the opening up of the country as the occasion may require.” cited from Kiwara-Wilson Reference Kiwara-Wilson2016, 6 et seq.

74 O’Keefe Reference O’Keefe2006, 5 goes straight into the discussion of the ius ad bello.

75 Smith Reference Smith1979, 140–141 Appendix C; Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 109.

76 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 110.

77 Hertslet Reference Hertslet1967, 634 et seq.

78 Lindley Reference Lindley1926, 166.

79 Lindley Reference Lindley1926, 173.

80 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 89.

81 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 158.

82 Cf. Westlake Reference Westlake1894, 139 et seq.

83 Halleck, Reference Halleck1861, 852.

84 This is also the unanimous view today, cf. Chechi Reference Chechi2008, 173 fn. 68.

85 Vattel, Reference Vattel and Chitty1883, Book IV, Chap. I, § 18, cf. also § 14 on “unjust conquerors.”

86 Vattel, Reference Vattel and Chitty1883, Book IV, Chap. I, § 11 and 19, Chap. IV § 36.

87 Vattel, Reference Vattel and Chitty1883, Book IV, Chap. 4, § 19; cf. Halleck, Reference Halleck1861, 861.

88 Cf. Grotius 1625, Book III, Chap. XIII, III.

89 Grotius Reference Grotius and Campbell1814 [1625], book III, chap. XIX, 11.

90 From a more theoretical standpoint, one could argue, that occupations accompanied by spoliation and unequal contracts were merely tolerated given the political realities, but never granted everlasting legal effect as they contradicted fundamental legal principles. In this sense, political power may obfuscate the legal realities, but this effect vanishes with the oppression. The restitutions after the Congress of Vienna give an example of this deeper logic underlying the somewhat harsh doctrine on peace treaties.

91 Zhang, Reference Zhang2018, 965; Gilks, Reference Gilks2013, 115 et seq.

92 See Verri Reference Verri1985, 84.

93 Zhang, Reference Zhang2018, 966 et seq; Verri Reference Verri1985, 84.

94 Vattel, Reference Vattel and Chitty1883, Book IV, Chap. I, § 18, cf. also § 14 on “unjust conquerors”.

95 Naturally, French scholars had a different point of view on the matter, cf. Pradier-Fodere Reference Pradier-Fodere1897, 986 et seq.

96 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1866, 52 et seq.

97 Scovazzi 2012, 11; Quynn Reference Quynn1945, 447 adds that this “could be more tactfully handled by the king privately.”

98 Stahn Reference Stahn2023, 25.

99 Such was held by Roman and Medieval scholars, e.g. Thomas Aquinas, for details see Hartung Reference Hartung and Sophia2009, 25.

100 Grotius 1625, Book III, Chap. VI, II.

101 Grotius 1625, Book III, Chap. V, I et seq.

102 Grotius 1625, Book III, Chapters XII and XIII, cf. O’Keefe 2009, 8.

103 Grotius 1625, Book III, Chapters VI, I and XIII, I.

104 Ibid, § 161, 162.

105 Savoy Reference Savoy2010, 188; Zhang Reference Zhang2018, 965 argues that restitutions in this period confirm the existence of the already established prohibition of spoliation.

106 Jenschke Reference Jenschke2006, 362 et seq.

107 Sandholtz Reference Sandholtz2010, 149.

108 Cf. Chechi Reference Chechi2008, 165 “first substantial effort of the modern era to develop a legal framework for this issue.”

109 In particular the Papal state (Lex Pacca of 1820) and Austria (Bestimmungen über die Ausfuhr und den Verkehr mit Kunstwerken und Seltenheiten von 1818).

110 Compare Ali Pascha Reference Ali Pascha, Dolezalek, Savoy and Skwirblies2021 [1835], 188–194.

111 Cf. O’Keefe Reference O’Keefe2006, 8.

113 Zhang Reference Zhang2018, no. 93; Nahlik Reference Nahlik1976, 1071–1072; Sandholtz Reference Sandholtz2007, 39 et seq. Arguing for recognition with the Hague Convention II 1899 Visscher Reference Visscher1949, 827–828; against the existence of the norm in the nineteenth century Miles Reference Miles2017, 14–17.

114 Lieber Reference Lieber1863.

115 1. Theil, 9. Titel § 193 General State Laws for the Prussian States from 1794; Phillimore Reference Phillimore1901, 230; Proudhon, 1901 no. 2, p. 230.

116 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1868, 289; cf. Vidari Reference Vidari1865, 138, cf. Twiss Reference Twiss1875, 124.

117 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1868, 289.

118 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1874, 68.

119 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1866, 27.

120 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1870, Arts. 408 and 704.

121 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1870, Arts. 411, 412, 415.

122 See Arts. 1(2), 55 UN Charter; Art. 2 Declaration on the Granting of Independence to Colonial Countries and Peoples (UNGA Resolution 1514 (XV), 4 December 1960) includes the free development of culture within the framework of the right to self-determination; cf. Chechi Reference Chechi2008, 171

123 P. Fiore Reference Fiore1884, 1664 and 1747.

124 Borchard/Fiore 1918, Arts 756 et seq.

125 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1868, 290.

126 Project of an International Declaration concerning the Laws and Customs of War, Brussels, 27 August 1874.

127 Chechi Reference Chechi2008, 173 draws the parallel conclusion that privately owned cultural property becomes “distinct from other civilian property.”

128 Cf. Nüremberg International Military Tribunal 1946 [1947], 248–249; Wheaton Reference Wheaton1916, 22–23; Verdross Reference Verdross1955, 362. In this context, nineteenth-century positivistic demands should generally be understood as calls to transpose customary norms into formal conventions rather than as one for immediate reliance on positive law alone.

129 Simon Reference Simon2018, 130.

130 Zhang Reference Zhang2018, 950 et seq.

131 Sarr and Savoy Reference Sarr and Savoy2018, 48.

132 The necessity of natural jus cogens is later again emphasized by Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1872, 237.

133 Eslava and Pahuja Reference Eslava and Sundhya2011, 108.

135 Vattel Reference Vattel2008 [1758], Preliminaries, § 11.

136 Vattel Reference Vattel2008 [1758], Preliminaries, § 26.

137 Alvik Reference Alvik2018, 218.

138 Halleck Reference Halleck1874, 9.

139 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1872, no. 410.

140 Lormier Reference Lormier1884, 71; compare Reddie Reference Reddie1851, 347.

141 Mihatsch and Mulligan Reference Mihatsch, Mulligan and Lavallée2022, 43.

142 The prohibition of spoliation is considered jus cogens today, see Loucaides Reference Loucaides2004, 685.

143 Grotius Reference Grotius and Campbell1814 [1625], Book II, chap. II, II

144 Vattel Reference Vattel2008 [1758], Book I, chap. XVIII, § 203.

145 Locke, Reference Locke1823 [1690], Chap. V. § 27.

146 Grotius Reference Grotius and Campbell1814 [1625], Book II, Chap. II, II.

147 Blackstone Reference Blackstone1796, 134.

148 However, in other important human rights documents of the time direct reference to natural rights theory is hardly to be found. See for example, the Fifth Amendment to the United States Constitution from 1791 and Art. 8 § 32 of the short-lived Imperial Act guaranteeing the Basic Rights of the German People of 1848.

149 Thiers Reference Thiers1848, 10.

150 Compare Danquah Reference Danquah1928, 198.

151 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 205 et seq.

152 Ojo and Ekhator 2021, 39 et seq; German Museums Association 2013, 153.

153 Elias Reference Elias1956, 168.

154 See, for example, Chinwuba Obi Reference Chinwuba and Nwankwo1963, 66.

155 Liversage Reference Liversage1945, 5.

156 Such an obligation-based system is reminiscent of the European feudal and the modern federal systems.

157 Plessis Reference Plessis2011, 53 et seq.

158 Elias Reference Elias1956, 168.

159 Common law and civil law doctrine also struggle to develop a coherent theory of property that does not subdivide property into mere rights of usage (bundle of rights theory); cf. Holdsworth Reference Holdsworth1925, 465.

160 Danquah Reference Danquah1928, 198.

161 Tomba Reference Tomba2019, 99.

162 O’Keefe Reference O’Keefe2006, 5.

163 Yves Huguenin-Bergenat Reference Huguenin-Bergenat2010, 256.

164 Cf. Beckert Reference Beckert2004.

165 Cf. Westlake Reference Westlake1894, 130.

166 Erster Schutzvertrag Kamerun 1884.

167 Smith Reference Smith1979, 140–141 Appendix C; Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 109.

168 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 110.

169 Privy Council Anonymous [1722] 2 P Wms 75 cited from Turton Reference Turton1836, 182; also referenced by the Supreme Court of Georgia in State v Campbell, T.U.P. Charlton 166, 1808.

170 Blackstone 1765–Reference Blackstone1769, 105.

171 Sinitsina Reference Sinitsina1987, 45; for details see Fenin-Addo Reference Fenin-Addo1990.

172 Elias Reference Elias1963, 144; for more details on legal pluralism in Africa see Quashigah Reference Quashigah2008.

173 Cf. Art. 4 Schutzgebietsgesetz in der Fassung der Bekanntmachung vom 10. September 1900, Deutsches Reichsgesetzblatt 1900, no. 40: 812–817

174 Gerstemeyer Reference Gerstemeyer1910 , 26; Kuprechta Reference Kuprechta2020, 154.

175 See § 2 Verfügung des Reichskanzlers, betr. die Ausführung der Allerhöchsten Verordnung vom 26. November 1895, 27.11.1895: “so ist den Rechten der Eingeborenen nach Möglichkeit Rechnung zu tragen und zunächst auf eine Vereinbarung im gütlichen Wege Bedacht zu nehmen […].”

176 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 202 et seq.

177 Allerhöchste Verordnung über die Schaffung, Besitzergreifung und Veräußerung von Kronland und über den Erwerb und die Veräußerung von Grundstücken im Schutzgebiete von Kamerun, vom 15. Juni 1896, Kolonialblatt 1896, pp. 435 bis 437.

178 Kaiserliche Verordnung über die Enteignung von Grundeigentum in den Schutzgebieten Afrikas und der Südsee, vom 14. Februar 1903, Kolonialblatt, p. 121.

179 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 205 et seq.

180 For French legislation compare the loi du 26 Juillet 1873 (loi Warnier) regarding immovable property; for German law see the Allerhöchste Verordnung, betr. die Rechtsverhältnisse an unbeweglichen Sachen in Deutsch-Ostafrika, vom 24. Juli Reference Allerhöchste1894; compare also Bennett Reference Bennett2004, 375.

181 Surun Reference Surun2020, 127.

182 Van der Linden Reference Van der Linden2017, 108 et seq.

184 Fiore Reference Fiore1882, 105–106.

185 Catellani Reference Catellani1885, 579–580 and 588–590.

186 Bluntschli Reference Bluntschli1872, 168.

187 Ibid, 170 et seq; Sylvest Reference Sylvest2008, 416.

188 Re Southern Rhodesia [1919] AC 211.

189 Cour d’appel, Paris, 5th April 2004, arrêt 2002/09897, The Federal Republic of Nigeria, c/ M. X., aff.; confirmed by the Cour de cassation, 20th September 2006, N° 04-15599; Cour d’appel Paris, 6th of June 1989, arrêt 88/20267, M. Y. c/ The Islamic Republic of Iran,; and Cass. Civ. 1re, 04 avril 1991, pourvoi n°89-18020.

190 Compare for example Chand Reference Chand1894, 493 et seq.

191 In 1931 a British government report accordingly concluded that Re Southern Rhodesia was not in accordance with the company’s charter, since it required legal agreement with the local representatives, see Maugham Reference Maugham1932, 2. Compare also the Southern Rhodesia Order in Council of the 20 October 1898.

References

Abel, Carl. 1871. Letters on International Relations before and during the War of 1870, Vol. 2. London: Tinsley brothers.Google Scholar
Agreement between the King of Baol and the French Republic of March 1883.Google Scholar
Allerhöchste, Verordnung, betr. die Rechtsverhältnisse an unbeweglichen Sachen in Deutsch-Ostafrika vom 24. Juli 1894.Google Scholar
Alexandrowicz, C.H. 1973. The European-African Confrontation: A Study in Treaty Making , Volume 1. Leyden: Sijthoff.Google Scholar
Ali Pascha, Mehmed. 2021. Antikenverordnung für Ägypten (1835): Kulturgutschutz nach europäischem Modell – zum Schutz vor Europäern . In Beute. Eine Anthologie zu Kunstraub und Kulturerbe, edited by Dolezalek, Isabelle, Savoy, Bénédicte, and Skwirblies, Robert, 188–94. Berlin: Matthes & Seitz.Google Scholar
Alvik, Ivar. 2018. “Protection of Private Property in the Early Law of Nations.“ Journal of the History of International Law 20, no. 2: 217–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anghie, Antony. 2006. “The Evolution of International Law: Colonial and Postcolonial Realities.” Third World Quarterly 25, no. 5: 739753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, TW 2004. Customary Law in South Africa. Cape Town: Juta.Google Scholar
Beckert, Jens. 2004. Unverdientes Vermögen Soziologie des Erbrechts, Theorie und Gesellschaft. Frankfurt/New York: Campus Verlag.Google Scholar
Bestimmungen über die Ausfuhr und den Verkehr mit Kunstwerken und Seltenheiten von 1818, Hofkanzley-Decret vom 28. December 1818.Google Scholar
Blackstone, William. 1765–1769. Commentaries on the Laws of England , Volume I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Blackstone, William. 1796. Commentaries on the Laws of England , Volume I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bluntschli, Johann Casper. 1866. Das moderne Völkerrecht der civilisirten Staten als Rechtsbuch dargestellt. Nördlingen: Beck.Google Scholar
Bluntschli, Johann Casper. 1866. Die Bedeutung und die Fortschritte. Berlin: Lüderitzsche Verlagsbuchhandlung.Google Scholar
Bluntschli, Johann Casper. 1868. Das moderne Völkerrecht der civilisirten Staten als Rechtsbuch dargestellt. Nördlingen: Beck.Google Scholar
Bluntschli, Johann Casper. 1870. Le Droit International Codifié. Paris: Guillaumin.Google Scholar
Bluntschli, Johann Casper. 1872. Das moderne Völkerrecht der zivilisierten Staaten, als Rechtsbuch dargestellt, Nördlingen: Beck.Google Scholar
Bluntschli, Johann Casper. 1874. Das moderne Kriegsrecht der civilisirten Staaten. Nördlingen: Beck’sche Buchhandlung.Google Scholar
Bodin, Jean. 1592. Respublica (German translation by Oswald, Johann). Mümpelgard: Bassaeus.Google Scholar
Bowdich, Thomas Edward. 1819. Mission from Cape Coast Castle to Ashantee. With a Descriptive Account of That Kingdom. London: Murray.Google Scholar
Bradbury, R.E. 1957. The Benin Kingdom and the Edo-speaking Peoples of South-western Nigeria, Vol. 1. London: International African Institute.Google Scholar
Catellani, Enrico Levi. 1885. Le colonie e la conferenza di Berlino. Turin: Unione Tipografico-Editrice.Google Scholar
Chechi, Alessandro. 2008. “The Return of Cultural Objects removed in Times of colonial Domination and International Law: The Case of the Venus of Cyrene.” The Italian Yearbook of International Law Online 18, no. 1: 159181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chand, Hukm. 1894. A Treaties on the Law of Res Iudicata: Including The Doctrines of Jurisdiction, Bar by Suit, and Lis Pendens. London: William Clowes & Sons.Google Scholar
Chinwuba, Obi, and Nwankwo, Samuel. 1963. Modern Family Law in Southern Nigeria. London: University of London.Google Scholar
Crawford, James R. 2006. The Creation of States in International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Danquah, Joseph Boakye. 1928. Akan Laws and Customs and the Akim Abuakwa Constitution. London: G. Routledge & Sons.Google Scholar
Dapper, Olfert. 1670. Umständliche und Eigentliche Beschreibung von Africa (Reprint 2012). Saarbrücken: Frölich & Kaufmann.Google Scholar
Draper, G.I.A.D. 1964. The Origins of the Just War Tradition. New Blackfriars 46, no. 533: 8288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edo, Victor. 2010. “The Practice of Democracy in Nigeria: The Pre-Colonial Antecedent.” LUMINA 21, no. 2: 17.Google Scholar
Elias, Taslim Olawale. 1956. The Nature of African Customary Law. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Elias, Taslim Olawale. 1963. The British Commonwealth: Ghana and Sierra Leone. London: Stevens & Sons.Google Scholar
Elliesie, Hatem. 2017 [1889]. Völkerrechtliche Beziehungen zwischen Äthiopien und Italien im Lichte des Vertrages von Uccialli/Wuchale. Köln: Rüdiger Köppe Verlag.Google Scholar
Ellis, Alfred Burton. 1893. A History of the Gold Coast of West Africa. London: Alfred Burton.Google Scholar
Engagement with chiefs holding authority on the South Bank of the River Congo. Slave Trade. Commerce. Humans Sacrifices. Religion, 27.3. 1876.Google Scholar
Erster Schutzvertrag Kamerun 1884, Urkunde vom 12.07. 1884.Google Scholar
Erster Schutzvertrag Togo 1884, Vertrag mit König Mlapa/Togo vom 5.7.1884.Google Scholar
Eslava, Luis, and Sundhya, Pahuja. 2011. “Between Resistance and Reform: TWAIL and the Universality of International Law.” 3(1).Trade L. & Dev 3, no. 1: 103130.Google Scholar
Fenin-Addo, R. 1990. “The Native Jurisdiction Ordinance, Indirect Rule and the Subjects Well-Being: The Abuakwa Experience 1899-1912.” Research Review 6, no. 2: 2944.Google Scholar
Fiore, Pasquale. 1882. Trattato di diritto internazionale pubblico, Vol 2. Turin: Unione Tipografico-Editrice.Google Scholar
Fiore, Pasquale. 1884. Trattato di diritto internazionale pubblico, Vol. 3. Turin: Unione Tipografico-Editrice.Google Scholar
German Museums Association. 2013. Guidelines for German Museums Care of Collections from Colonial Contexts. Berlin: German Museums Association.Google Scholar
Gerstemeyer, Johannes. 1910. Das Schutzgebiet nebst der Verordnung betr. die Rechtsverhältnisse in den Schutzgebieten und dem Gesetz über die Konsulargerichtsbarkeit in Anwendung auf die Schutzgebiete sowie die Ausführungsbestimmungen und ergänzenden Vorschriften. Berlin: J. Guttentag.Google Scholar
Gilks, David. 2013. “Attitudes to the displacement of cultural property in the wars of the French Revolution and Napoleon.” The Historical Journal 56, no. 1: 113143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, William. 1991. British Slave Emancipation: The Sugar Colonies and the Great Experiment 1830-1865. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Grotius, Hugo. [1625] 1814. The Rights of War and Peace: Including the Law of Nature and of Nations (Translated by Campbell, A. C.). London: Boothroyd.Google Scholar
Grotius, Hugo. [1625] 1853. The Rights of War and Peace: An abridged Translation (Translated by Whewell, W.). Cambridge: University Press.Google Scholar
Halleck, Henry Wagner. 1874. Elements of International Law and Laws of War. Philadelphia PA: J.B. Lippincott & Co.Google Scholar
Halleck, Henry Wagner. 1861. International Law Or, Rules Regulating the Intercourse of States in Peace and War. New York: D. Van Nostrand.Google Scholar
Hartung, Hannes. 2009. “Praeda bellica in bellum justum? The legal development of war-booty from the 16th century to date: A chance of bettering museum practice?“ In War Booty, A Common European Cultural Heritage, edited by Sophia, Nestor. Stockholm: Livrustkammaren.Google Scholar
Hertslet, Edward. 1880. A Complete Collection of the Treaties and Conventions, and Reciprocal Regulations, at Present Subsisting between Great Britain and Foreign Powers. London: Butterworth.Google Scholar
Hertslet, Lewis. 1967. The Map of Africa by Treaty , Vol. I (British Colonies, Protectorates and Possessions in Africa). London: Harrison and Sons.Google Scholar
Hertslet, E. 1967. Map of Africa by Treaty, 3rd edition, Vol. II. London: Frank Cass.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. 1650. Elements of Law. Paris: Jacob Dupuys.Google Scholar
Holdsworth, William. 1925. History of English Law, Vol. 7. Methuen: Northwestern University.Google Scholar
Huguenin-Bergenat, Yves. 2010. Kulturgüter bei Staatensukzession. Die internationalen Verträge Österreichs nach dem Zerfall der österreichisch- ungarischen Monarchie im Spiegel des aktuellen Völkerrechtsuenin-Bergenat Kulturgüter bei Staatensukzession. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jellinek, Georg. 1882. Die Lehre von den Staatenverbindungen. Vienna: O. Haering.Google Scholar
Jenschke, Christoff. 2006. “In Kriegen erbeutet: Zur Rückgabe geraubter Kulturgüter im Völkerrecht.“ Osteuropa 56: 361370.Google Scholar
Inter-American Convention on the Rights and Duties of States was signed on 26 December 1933 in Montevideo.Google Scholar
Kiwara-Wilson, Salome. 2016. “Restituting Colonial Plunder: The Case for the Benin Bronzes and Ivories.” DePaul Journal of Art, Technology & Intellectual Property Law 23, no. 2: 375425.Google Scholar
Kochakova, Natalia.1996. “The sacred ruler as the ideological centre of an early state: The precolonial states of the Bight of Benin Coast.” In Ideology and the Formation of Early States, edited by Claessen, J.M. and Oosten, J., 4866. Leiden/New York/Köln: E.J. Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolchin, Peter. 1987. Unfree Labour. American Slavery and Russian Serfdom. Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Korman, Sharon. 1996. The Right of Conquest, The Acquisition of Territory by Force in International Law and Practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Koskenniemi, Martii. 2004. The Gentle Civilizer of Nations, The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870–1960. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kuprechta, Karolina. 2020. “Kulturgüter aus der Kolonialzeit und Restitution: Änderungen ohne Änderungen.“ In Raubkunst und Restitution – Zwischen Kolonialzeit und Washington Principles, edited by Weller et alia, 153–65. Zürich: Dike.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, Dan. 2021. The Right of Sovereignty: Jean Bodin on the Sovereign State and the Law of Nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lieber, Francis. 1863. Instructions for the Government of the Armies of the United States in the Field. New York: D. Van Nostrand.Google Scholar
Lindley, Mark Frank. 1926. The Acquisition and Government of Backward Territory in International Law: Being a Treatise on the Law and Practice Relating to Colonial Autonomy. London: Longmans, Green and Co. Ltd.Google Scholar
Liversage, Vincent. 1945. Land Tenure in the Colonies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Labadie, Camille. 2021. “Decolonizing collections: A legal perspective on the restitution of cultural artifacts.” In The Decolonisation of Museology: Museums, Mixing, and Myths of Origin, edited by Bergeron, Yves et Rivet, Michèle. COFOM Study Series 49, no. 2: 132146 or online 1–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John 1823 [1690]. Second Treaties of Government. London: Thomas Tegg; W. Sharpe and Son.Google Scholar
Lormier, James 1884. The Institutes of the Law of Nations, Vol. II. Edinburgh and London: William Blackwood and Sons.Google Scholar
Lorimer, James. 1884. “La doctrine de la reconnaissance, fondement du droit international.” Revue de droit international et de législation comparée, no. 1: 333395.Google Scholar
Loucaides, Loukis. 2004. “The Protection of the Right to Property in Occupied Territories.” The International and Comparative Law Quarterly 53, no. 3: 677690.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, Michael. 2010. “Sklaverei, Knechtschaft und Kolonialismus im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert” (book review). H-Soz-Kult, 3.9.2010, available from hsozkult.de/publicationreview/id/reb-11717.Google Scholar
Martens, Fyodor Fyodorovich. 1883. Völkerrecht: Das internationale Recht der civilisirten Nationen systematisch dargestellt, Vol. 1. Berlin: Weidmann.Google Scholar
Martin, Edward. 2021. The Application of the Doctrine of Intertemporality on Contentious Proceedings. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maugham, Justice. 1932. Report to the Governor of Northern Rhodesia by the Commissioner. London: H.M. Stationery Office.Google Scholar
Merry, Sally Engle. 2000. Colonizing Hawai’i: The Cultural Power of Law. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mihatsch, Moritz and Mulligan, Michael. 2022. “Sovereignty in Africa and the specter of Wilson.” In The End of Western Hegemonies?, edited by Lavallée, Marie-Josée, 3562. Wilmington: Vernon Press.Google Scholar
Miles, Margaret. 2017. “War and Passion: Who Keeps the Art?“ Journal of International Law 49, no. 1: 522.Google Scholar
Nahlik, Stanislaw E. 1976. “International Law and the Protection of Cultural Property in Armed Conflicts.” Hastings LJ 27: 1069–987.Google Scholar
Nuzzo, Luigi. 2017. “Territory, Sovereignty, and the Construction of the Colonial Space.” In International Law and Empire: Historical Explorations, edited by Koskenniemi, M., Rech, W., and Fonseca, J.M., 263–92. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nüremberg International Military Tribunal. 1946 [1947]. American Journal of International Law 41: 248249.Google Scholar
O’Keefe, Roger. 2006. The Protection of Cultural Property in Armed Conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ojo, Idahosa, and Ekhator, Eghosa. 2020. “Pre-colonial legal system in Africa: An assessment of indigenous laws of Benin Kingdom before 1897.” Journal of Benin and Edo Studies 5: 3873.Google Scholar
Oppenheim, Lassa. 1905. International Law: A Treatise. London: Longmans, Green and Co.Google Scholar
Phillimore, Robert. 1901. “Booty of war.” Journal of Comparative Legislation and International Law, no. 2: 214230.Google Scholar
Plessis, Elmien du. 2011. “African Indigenous Land Rights in a Private Ownership Paradigm.” Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 14, no. 7: 4569.Google Scholar
Pradier-Fodere, Paul. 1897. Traité de droit international public europeen et americain suivant les progres de la science et de la pratique contemporaines, Vol. 7. Paris: Pedone.Google Scholar
Project of an International Declaration concerning the Laws and Customs of War Brussels, 27 August 1874.Google Scholar
Quynn, Dorothy Mackay. 1945. “The Art Confiscations of the Napoleonic Wars.” The American Historical Review 50, no. 3: 437460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quashigah, Kofi. 2008. “The historical development of the legal system of Ghana: An example of the coexistence of two systems of law.” A Journal of Legal History 14, no. 2: 95114.Google Scholar
Raič, David, 2002. Statehood and the Law of Self-Determination. The Hague: Kluwer Law International.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reddie, James. 1851. Inquiries in International Law, Public and Private. Edinburgh and London: William Blackwood and Sons.Google Scholar
Saksena, Priyasha. 2019. “Jousting Over Jurisdiction: Sovereignty and International Law in Late Nineteenth-Century South Asia.” Law and History Review 28, no. 2: 409457.Google Scholar
Sandholtz, Wayne. 2007. Prohibiting Plunder, How Norms Change. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandholtz, Wayne. 2010. “Plunder, Restitution, and International Law.” International Journal of Cultural Property 17, no. 2: 147176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarr, Felwine, and Savoy, Bénédicte. 2018. The Restitution of African Cultural Heritage. Toward a New Relational Ethics, Ministerial Report No. 2018-26 (Eng. Version). Paris: French Ministry of Culture.Google Scholar
Savoy, Bénédicte. 2010. Kunstraub. Napoleons Konfiszierungen in Deutschland und die europäischen Folgen. Mit einem Katalog der Kunstwerke aus deutschen Sammlungen im Musée Napoléon. Wien: Böhlau.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schöneberg, Sophie. 2021. Was soll zurück? Die Restitution von Kulturgütern im Zeitalter der Nostalgie. München: C.H. Beck.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stahn, Carsten. 2023. Confronting Colonial Objects: Histories, Legalities, and Access to Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schutzgebietsgesetz in der Fassung der Bekanntmachung vom 10. September 1900, Deutsches Reichsgesetzblatt 1900, no. 40: 812817.Google Scholar
Simon, Hendrik. 2018. “The myth of liberum ius ad bellum: Justifying war in 19th-century legal theory and political practice.” European Journal of International Law 29, no.1: 113136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinitsina, Irina. 1987. “African Legal Tradition: J. M. Sarbah, J. B. Danquah, N. A. Ollennu.” Journal of African Law 31, no. 1–2: 4457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smets, Maxim. 2020. Le rêve d’un roi: Congo Free State and Its Unlikely Existence in 19th-Century International Law. Leuven: KU Leuven.Google Scholar
Smith, Robert. 1979The Lagos Consulate 1851–1861. Berkely: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Southern Rhodesia Order in Council of the 20 October 1898.Google Scholar
Spira, Sebastian. 2020. “Civilisation, Protection, Restitution: A Critical History of International Cultural Heritage Law in the 19th and 20th Century.” JHIL 22: 329354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Surun, Isabell (ed.). 2020. La France et l’Afrique 1830–1962. Neuilly: Atlande.Google Scholar
Sylvest, Casper. 2008. “Our Passion for Legality’: International Law and Imperialism in Late Nineteenth-Century Britain.” Review of International Studies 34, no. 3: 403423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thiers, Adolphe. 1848. The Rights of Property: A Refutation of Communism & Socialism. London: R. Groombridge & Sons.Google Scholar
Tomba, Massimiliano. 2019. Insurgent Universality: An Alternative Legacy of Modernity. New York: Oxford Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turton, T.E.M. 1836. “The Appeal-Rescinding Act (To Amicus Curiae).” The Calcutta Monthly Journal 2: 179–81.Google Scholar
Twiss, Travers. 1875. The Law of Nations. Considered as Independent Political Communities. Oxford/London: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Tzouvala, Ntina. 2020. Capitalism As Civilisation A History of International Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van der Linden, Mieke. 2017. The Acquisition of Africa (1870–1914) The Nature of International Law. Leiden: Brill Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vattel, Emer de. 2008 [1758]. The Law of Nations: Or, Principles of the Law of Nature Applied to the conduct and affairs of Nations and Sovereigns (translated by Thomas Nugent). Philadelphia: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Vattel, Emer de. 1883. Vattel. 1883. The Law of Nations: Or, Principles of the Law of Nature Applied to the conduct and affairs of Nations and Sovereigns (translated by Chitty, Joseph). Philadelphia: T&J.W. Johnson.Google Scholar
Vázquez-Bermúdez, Marcelo. 2019. First Report on General Principles of Law, UN Doc A/CN.4/732.Google Scholar
Vec, Miloš. 2017. Sources in the 19th Century European Tradition. The Myth of Positivism.“ In Oxford Handbook on the Sources of International Law, edited by Besson, Samantha and d’Aspremont, Jean, 121145. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Verdross, Alfred. 1955. Völkerrecht. Wien: Springer Verlag CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verfügung des Reichskanzlers, betr. die Ausführung der Allerhöchsten Verordnung vom 26. November 1895, 27.11.1895.Google Scholar
Verri, Pietro. 1985. “The condition of cultural property in armed conflicts – From Antiquity to World War II.” International Review of the Red Cross, no. 246.Google Scholar
Vidari, Ercole. 1865. Del rispetto della proprietà privata dei popoli belligeranti. Milan: Fratelli Borroni.Google Scholar
Visscher, Charles. 1949. International Protection of Works of Art and Historic Monuments. Washington: Dept. of State, 827828.Google Scholar
Wallace-Bruce, Nii Lante. 1985. “Africa and International Law – the Emergence to Statehood.” Journal of Modern African Studies 23, no. 4: 575602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
War declaration of the French National Assembly, 20 April 1792.Google Scholar
Westlake, John. 1894. Chapters on the Principles of International Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wheaton, Henry. 1916. Wheaton’s Elements of International Law. London: Stevens and Sons.Google Scholar
Zhang, Yue. 2018. “Customary International Law and the Rule Against Talking Cultural Property as Spoils of War.” Chinese Journal of International Law 17, no. 4: 943989.CrossRefGoogle Scholar