Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-18T13:41:12.016Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On expanding accountability in the study of genitive variation: a reply to Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen & Larsson (2023)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 December 2024

ANETTE ROSENBACH*
Affiliation:
UPSET Research Focus Area North-West University Hendrik van Eck Blvd Vanderbijlkpark 1911 South Africa Tanagra Farm PO Box 92 6708 McGregor/ Western Cape South Africa [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen & Larsson (2023) argue for a more liberal inclusion of genitive variants, evoking Labov's principle of accountability (Labov 1969: 737–8, fn. 20, 1972), which calls for the inclusion of all variants that are functionally equivalent and allow variation. They suggest that the term ‘genitive’ should be defined grammatically, as a restrictive modifier to the head noun, rather than semantically in terms of a possessive relation, thus redefining the linguistic variable for English genitive variation. In particular, they include noun modifiers as a third genitive variant (with s-genitives and of-genitives). In this reply I argue that the authors proceed from a notion of ‘genitive’ that is too broad, including variants that are not functionally equivalent and contexts that are not variable, thus actually violating the principle of accountability.

Type
Squib
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1 Introduction

Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen & Larsson (Reference Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen and Larsson2023) (henceforth ‘the authors’) argue for a more liberal inclusion of genitive variants, in particular the inclusion of noun modifiers as a third variant. The authors evoke Labov's principle of accountability (Labov Reference Labov1969: 737–8, fn. 20, Reference Labov1972), which states that it is essential to consider all variants which could have been used within a given context for a study of variation to be able to calculate the correct distribution of the variants, i.e. relative frequencies. Importantly, however, only those contexts should be included that are ‘functionally parallel as well as variable’ (Tagliamonte Reference Tagliamonte2011: 10). In other words, only those variants should be included that are functionally equivalent and that allow variation of all variants.

The authors suggest widening the scope of English genitive variation in three ways to adhere more closely to the principle of accountability:

  1. (a) extension of the definition of ‘genitive’

  2. (b) inclusion of noun modifiers as a third genitive variant

  3. (c) inclusion of non-interchangeable tokens

In the following I argue that the authors proceed from a notion of ‘genitive’ that is too broad (section 2.1). They include variants that are not functionally equivalent (sections 2.1 and 2.2) and contexts that are not variable (section 2.3), thus actually violating the principle of accountability.

2 The scope of genitive variation

2.1 The definition of the ‘same thing’ – or: what counts as ‘genitive’?

The authors are right in claiming that the literature on genitive variation is rather vague in the use of the term ‘genitive’. Strictly speaking, it refers to a morphological genitive marking, a definition which is correctly ruled out by the authors for a study of genitive variation, as it would only allow the s-genitive as a genitive variant,Footnote 2 hence there would not be any variation. Rather, the term ‘genitive’ is conventionally used in studies of genitive variation to indicate a possessive relation between two noun phrases, a possessor (or dependent) and a possessum (or head); see e.g. Rosenbach (Reference Rosenbach2002, Reference Rosenbach2014, Reference Rosenbach2019). The authors (p. 99) reject this definition as

unsatisfactory because only a small proportion of the tokens for all three variants express the meaning of possession. That is, even interchangeable tokens often express many other meanings, including ‘prototypical’ relationships, like kinship, body parts, ownership and part/whole, as well as a wide range of non-prototypical relationships, like undergoer, property, creator, theme …

It is not quite clear from this statement how the authors define ‘possession’, but they suggest that it is construed too narrowly to account for all genitive variants. Note, however, that the linguistic concept of ‘possession’ can indeed include a wide range of semantic relations far beyond the common-sense meaning of ‘possession’ as ownership and thus is much broader than the authors make us believe; see the following definition of possession by McGregor (Reference McGregor and McGregor2009: 1):

it is a relational concept that potentially covers a wide range of conceptual relations between entities, including, for human beings, between persons and their body-parts and products, between persons and their kin, between persons and their representations (e.g. names, photographs), between persons and their material belongings (animate and inanimate items they own), between persons and things they have usership-rights to or control over, between persons and cultural and intellectual products, and so on. For other animates and inanimates a more restricted range of conceptual relations is generally available.

The concept of possession can cover core possessive relations such as kin terms (John's mother), body parts (John's arm) and ownership (John's car), as well as more non-prototypical possessive relations such as social relations (John's friend), author or originator (John's poem), disposal or use (John's office), carrier of properties (John's courage), locative relations (London's underground), part/whole relations (the chair's leg) or even temporal relations (Sunday's newspaper), to name just the most common relations (cf. Koptjevskaja-Tamm Reference Koptjevskaja-Tamm2002: 147). Subjective and objective relations, where the head noun is a deverbal noun, as in John's writings (subjective) or John's murder (objective), do not entail a relation between a possessor and a possessum, but they so to speak ‘borrow’ the structure of possessives in English to fill the argument slot of the nominalized verb (cf. Koptjevskaja-Tamm Reference Koptjevskaja-Tamm2002: 166). The problem with defining the concept of possession for a corpus study of English genitive variation is not that it is too narrowly construed but that it covers such a wide and diverse range of conceptual relations.Footnote 3

Instead of defining ‘genitive’ semantically, in terms of possession, the authors provide a grammatical definition and consider any noun phrase functioning as a restrictive modifier of the head noun as a genitive variant (p. 99). This, however, is far too broad. The definition of ‘sameness’ in the sense of Labov (Reference Labov1972) should be based on semantic/functional grounds, not on a grammatical one alone. And while the notion of ‘restrictiveness’ is certainly useful, as it excludes expressions such as a man of honour or a cup of gold, where the of-phrase is a non-restrictive modifier, the authors fail to consider the two different ways in which an adnominal genitive may restrict: on the one hand, specifying (or determiner) s-genitives, as in John's mother, restrict the reference of the head noun, i.e. they identify whose mother it is, and thus may be considered as reference points or referential anchors (e.g. Taylor Reference Taylor1996; Haspelmath Reference Haspelmath1999, inter alia). To function as a referential anchor, the possessor itself must be referential, i.e. refer to a specific entity (Taylor Reference Taylor1996, inter alia). Classifying s-genitives as in lawyer's fees, on the other hand, are not referential (lawyer does not refer to a specific lawyer but generically to lawyers as such); they restrict the denotational class of the head noun, i.e. specify the type of fees (i.e. those typical of lawyers); for illustration see figure 1 (see also Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2019: 763–4).Footnote 4

Figure 1. Different types of adnominal possession

So while specifying and classifying genitives both restrict, they restrict over different semantic domains, i.e. the reference of the matrix noun phrase (specifying genitives) versus the denotational class of the head noun (classifying genitives). Specifying and classifying genitives are not functionally equivalent and thus the authors’ definition of ‘genitive’ as the linguistic variable is too broad.

Specifying genitives as in John's mother/house/office/courage, traditionally called ‘Saxon genitives’, constitute what may be called ‘core possessives’ as there is a ‘possessor’, i.e. somebody (John) who possesses something in the widest sense of the word. It is thus the alternation between specifying (i.e. reference-restricting) adnominal genitive constructions, typically s-genitives and corresponding of-genitives (on the inclusion of noun modifiers see section 2.2 below), that is studied as ‘genitive variation’ (for a detailed list of the inclusion/exclusion criteria see e.g. Bresnan et al. Reference Bresnan, Rosenbach, Szmrecsanyi, Tagliamonte and Todd2017). Classifying genitives as in lawyer's fees or passenger's seat, in contrast, are a more marginal and less productive type of possessive, where the dependent cannot really be called a ‘possessor’ in the strict sense of the term despite the presence of the possessive marker ’s. Classifying s-genitives typically alternate with noun modifiers and usually call for another prepositional variant than of (see also section 2.2 below); cf. Taylor (Reference Taylor1996: chapter 11) and Rosenbach (Reference Rosenbach2006, Reference Rosenbach, Hundt, Nesselhauf and Biewer2007b).

Both types of restrictive modifiers – and thus functionally non-equivalent constructions – are, however, included in the authors’ study as can be seen from their inclusion of tokens like Jennifer's house (specifying s-genitive), the validity of teacher's assessments (classifying s-genitive), fruit salad and audio tape (classifying noun modifiers).Footnote 5

2.2 The inclusion of noun modifiers as a third genitive variant

The authors include noun modifiers as a third variant to genitive variation. Noun modifiers may indeed alternate with genitive constructions in English (Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2007a, Reference Rosenbach, Hundt, Nesselhauf and Biewer2007b, Reference Rosenbach, Traugott and Trousdale2010, Reference Rosenbach2019; Breban et al. Reference Breban, Kolkmann and Payne2019) – however, only in certain contexts and under certain conditions. In a study of genitive variation, we need to focus on those contexts where all three variants (the s-genitive, the of-genitive and noun modifiers) overlap, i.e. are functionally equivalent in the variationist sense,Footnote 6 as illustrated in figure 2.

Figure 2. The (simple) web of English genitive variation (cf. Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2019: 790)

Looking more closely, however, the web of English genitive variation is more complex. Noun modifiers, just like s-genitives, are not a homogeneous class, and they enter into different types of alternations with different types of s-genitives and of-genitives.

Typically, noun modifiers have classifying function. In lawyer fees the noun modifier lawyer defines a type of fee and not whose fees; likewise passenger in passenger seat describes a type of seat. Classifying noun modifiers may alternate with classifying s-genitives (lawyer's fees, passenger's seat). While classifying noun modifiers may sometimes alternate with a corresponding of-phrase (the fees of lawyers), they usually call for another prepositional variant, as illustrated in (1) below.

  1. (1)

    1. (a) a women's magazine, a women magazine, a magazine for women

    2. (b) a passenger's seat, a passenger seat, a seat for passengers

    3. (c) a summer's day, a summer day, a day in summer

Noun modifiers may also have identifying function as in the FBI director or the barn door, helping to identify the referent of the noun phrase, in other words a specific director or door. As such, they may alternate with specifying s-genitives and of-genitives as in (2); cf. Rosenbach (Reference Rosenbach2007a, Reference Rosenbach, Traugott and Trousdale2010, Reference Rosenbach2019).

  1. (2)

    1. (a) the FBI's director, the director of the FBI, the FBI director

    2. (b) the barn's door, the door of the barn, the barn door

In order to have identifying function, however, the noun modifier itself must be referential, which is a problem, as noun modifiers are not full noun phrases and as such are not referential. However, proper nouns may inherit their unique reference as modifiers (cf. Schlücker Reference Schlücker2013: 466; Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2019: 765–6), thus allowing alternations such as in (2a).

That said, not every proper noun modifier has identifying function; see the examples in (3), where the proper noun modifiers specify a type of grunt in (3a), or accent (3b) or gaze (3c), i.e. they all have classifying meaning in the widest sense, answering the question of ‘what type of X?’ rather than ‘whose X?’.

  1. (3)

    1. (a) Crowe repeated the movement, adding a Monica Seles grunt. (Kathy Reichs, Fatal Voyage, 331)Footnote 7

    2. (b) “Enid dahling”, the turd mocked in a David Niven accent, … (Jonathan Franzen, The Corrections, 331)

    3. (c) Larke fixed him with a sincere Sheriff of Mayberry gaze (Kathy Reichs, Fatal Voyage, 17)

Common noun modifiers as in the barn door may receive a referential interpretation by the context, when a barn has been mentioned previously, though they could also be interpreted referentially by a bridging inference, i.e. our world knowledge that tells us that if there is a barn door there (usually) must also be a (specific) barn (see also Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2019: section 3.4).

Thus, isolating cases of noun modifiers with identifying meaning in a corpus study is a challenge as, strictly speaking, we need to evaluate every single occurrence and, if the noun modifier is a common noun, consider the broader context to be able to determine if the noun modifier may indeed be interpreted referentially and have identifying meaning and thus can be equivalent to a specifying s-genitive.

It is also important to note that identifying noun modifiers are typically not used with core possessive relations such as ownership, kin relations, or body parts (Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2007a; Breban Reference Breban2018), so while we can say the woman's house/father/arm, we cannot say *the woman house/father/arm. There are exceptions to this rule (e.g. the Whitelaw house), but the use of noun modifiers with these semantic relations is infrequent (Schlücker Reference Schlücker, Ackermann, Simon and Zimmer2018: 294; Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2019: section 3.3). Breban et al. (Reference Breban, Kolkmann and Payne2019) propose a hierarchy of semantic relations, which defines the likelihood of a specifying s-genitive as opposed to a proper noun modifier. Their ‘possessor’ relation, defined as ownership, is most strongly associated with specifying s-genitives (e.g. Subway's sandwich shop), while their ‘name’ relation is most strongly associated with proper noun modifiers (e.g. the Sainsbury family). While the type of semantic relation does not appear to be a categorical context for either specifying s-genitives or (proper) noun modifiers – at least not within the selected semantic relations tested in Breban et al.'s (2019) experimental study – it turns out to be an important constraint on the choice of a noun modifier as a genitive variant and should thus be considered in a quantitative study, something not done by the authors. Instead, the authors define what they call ‘semantic relation’ as what turns out to be (mainly) the factor of animacy (p. 104), i.e. they code the head and the dependent for ‘animate’, ‘group/institution’, ‘locative’, though they also code ‘quantity/amount' (e.g. bit, chunk, piece, part)Footnote 8 and for specific name relations where the dependent is a collective proper noun naming a corporation or agency (e.g. NBC).

Locative noun modifiers easily alternate with specifying genitive constructions as in (4a), where Quebec history alternates with Quebec's history and the history of Quebec, paraphrasable as ‘Quebec has a history’. However, locative noun modifiers that do not convey a HAVE relation (in the widest sense) do not seem to alternate with s-genitives and of-genitives; see e.g. (4b) or (4c), where the locative proper noun modifiers specify an IN relation (the house in Kensington) or TO relation (the bus to Sligo) rather than a HAVE relation and do not allow a corresponding s- or of-genitive (*Kensington's house/ *the house of Kensington, *Sligo's bus/ *the bus of Sligo); see also Rosenbach (Reference Rosenbach2019: 778–9).

Note that in all examples in (4) the locative noun modifier helps to identify the referent of the noun phrase. This suggests that having identifying function is a necessary but not a sufficient criterion for a noun modifier to alternate with specifying genitives – the relation expressed must be a possessive one, i.e. a HAVE relation.

  1. (4)

    1. (a) …, but she's also interested in Quebec history. (Kathy Reichs, Death du Jour, 72)

    2. (b) There must be paperwork on it somewhere. At the Kensington house, I should guess? (Elizabeth George, Playing for the Ashes, 162)

    3. (c) On Tuesdays evenings, a bus headed for Sligo goes by on the main road sometime around five,… […] but even four-fifteen would be cutting it close for the Sligo bus (Tana French, The Searcher, 125)

These are only a few examples to demonstrate that, firstly, noun modifiers, like s-genitives, may have both classifying and identifying/specifying meaning, though in contrast to s-genitives, the classifying function is the core function of noun modifiers while their identifying/specifying function is more marked. These are different functions that should not be lumped together in a study of genitive variation. Secondly, the range of contexts in which noun modifiers may have identifying function and alternate with specifying s-genitives is restricted and in ways we do not fully understand yet. Accordingly, the area of overlap where all three genitive variants may alternate is still a bit of a black box. More research is needed to further specify those contexts of usage that do – and do not – allow such alternation.

Figure 3 modifies the (simple) web of variation between s-genitives, of-genitives and noun modifiers, introduced at the beginning of this section in figure 2, by distinguishing the different types of s-genitives and noun modifiers and how they enter into different types of alternation with each other and with of-genitives.Footnote 9 Core usages of the constructions are given in the centre and are shaded more darkly, against more marginal uses, placed at the periphery in lighter grey. I follow the authors in assuming that of-genitives typically have restrictive function, though note that more research is needed to more firmly establish this claim empirically. Also, my notion of ‘specifying’ is confined to reference-restricting dependents. Non-restrictive modifier and classifying uses of of-phrases are considered more marginal here. The boldness of the arrows stands for the strength of the alternation, distinguishing between (a) the most productive alternation, i.e. the one between specifying s-genitives and of-genitives, (b) the more constrained alternation between specifying noun modifiers and the other genitive variants, and (c) the weakest potential for alternation in the case of classifying uses of the of-genitive as indicated by the lighter, dotted lines.

Figure 3. The complex web of English genitive variation

2.3 Categorical vs non-interchangeable contexts

The authors further argue, to my mind correctly, that the interchangeability of individual genitive constructions is not a necessary criterion for inclusion as coders’ judgements can be subjective. Rather, the procedure is to first determine classes of contexts that categorically allow one variant only (‘categorical contexts’) and then exclude all such tokens from the analysis (cf. Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2014: 223–5). This may result in the inclusion of tokens that may not seem interchangeable (as in (5), cited from Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2014: 224), but which could alternate in theory because we do not know any good reason why they shouldn't.

  1. (5)

    1. (a) The release of 14 people arrested in the first crackdown on antigovernment protesters

    2. (b) ?? 14 people arrested in the first crackdown on antigovernment protesters’ release

However, this is only a safe procedure if we indeed know the categorical contexts, and apply them. While there is a longstanding research tradition into ‘classic’ genitive variation, i.e. the variation between the s-genitive and the of-genitive (see Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2014 for an overview), research into noun modifiers as potential genitive variants is relatively recent, either focusing on the constructional gradience between noun modifiers and s-genitives (Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2006, Reference Rosenbach2007a, Reference Rosenbach, Hundt, Nesselhauf and Biewer2007b, Reference Rosenbach, Traugott and Trousdale2010, Reference Rosenbach2019) or solely on proper noun modifiers and their semantic overlap with s-genitives (e.g. Breban Reference Breban2018; Breban et al. Reference Breban, Kolkmann and Payne2019). The few categorical contexts for noun modifiers given by the authors (p. 102), i.e. title nouns (President Biden), proper nouns (Pennsylvania Steel Company) and appositives (fitness expert Dr Jones) are all important and correct, but they are not sufficient. While most specifying s-genitives may be converted into a corresponding of-genitive, unless they are, for example, idiomatic or fixed expressions (e.g. Murphy's Law) or elliptic (this book is John's), noun modifiers do not alternate that easily with s-genitives and of-genitives. We currently do not know why, for example, John's house doesn't alternate with *the John house but the Whitelaws’ house may alternate with the Whitelaw house. Is there a rule that bans first names as identifying noun modifiers or are there exceptions?Footnote 10 While interchangeability of individual tokens is not the ultimate criterion, the examples above do raise the question of what constrains the alternation of noun modifiers with the other genitive variants. Research into noun modifiers and their alternation with genitive constructions is still in its infancy and we are simply not in a position yet to be sure we know most critical categorical contexts when including noun modifiers as genitive variants (see also Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2019: section 4.2).

The addition of a third genitive variant, i.e. noun modifiers, also raises the important question of how to define a categorical context when there is a choice between three variants instead of the usual two. The authors excluded those cases from their study ‘where only one variant was possible because of a categorical rule’ (p. 102). This is the standard procedure for dealing with categorical contexts in the case of two variants. If only one variant can be used in a certain context, the other one is automatically ruled out. With three variants, however, this procedure needs to be modified. How should we deal with contexts ruling out one variant but allowing the other two ? The authors do not explicitly discuss this type of situation in their article, but they (p.c.) confirm that for them it is sufficient if there is a choice between two of the variants within a given context, not necessarily all three of them. However, the notion of variation by definition implies choice, and there is no true choice if one variant is categorically ruled out. Potential choice and thus variation is limited to the space of overlap in the use of all variants (see also figure 2 above). So, in the case of three variants we must redefine what constitutes a categorical context as a context where one (or two) of the variants cannot be used.

In the following I will point out two such contexts which rule out one of the three genitive variants, i.e. (i) the context of matrix noun phrases not determined by the definite article the and (ii) the context of possessors not determined by the, both contexts included in the authors’ study.

Genitive constructions that are indefinite or start with a determiner other than the definite article the do not allow specifying s-genitives. To understand why this is the case we need to consider the different ways in which definiteness can be expressed in the different genitive constructions; table 1 illustrates the structural positions of the possessors/dependents.

Table 1. The various genitive constructions in noun phrase structure

Specifying s-genitives (as in the school's) are in (central) determiner position, (typically) rendering the matrix genitive construction definite.Footnote 11 A corresponding of-genitive or noun modifier thus must be definite, too, and can only start with the and no other determiner, as the determiner slot is already taken by the s-genitive, disallowing any other determiner (cf. also Rosenbach Reference Rosenbach2014: 224; Bresnan et al. Reference Bresnan, Rosenbach, Szmrecsanyi, Tagliamonte and Todd2017: section 3.1). For this reason, of-genitives and noun modifiers, as in this director of the school/ this school director or a director of the school/ a school director, do not alternate with s-genitives. That this context is, however, included in the authors’ study is apparent from the examples in (6) to (10).

  1. (6) ten or twenty photos of Taylor (example (14) in Biber et al. Reference Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen and Larsson2023: 123)

  2. (7) a CIA leak (example (21) in Biber et al. Reference Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen and Larsson2023: 124)

  3. (8) a squad of angry army reservists (example (30) in Biber et al. Reference Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen and Larsson2023: 124)

  4. (9) remnants of a more civilized time (example (34) in Biber et al. Reference Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen and Larsson2023: 125)

  5. (10) an enigmatic pattern of egg size variation (example (54) in Biber et al. Reference Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen and Larsson2023: 126)

The authors do acknowledge that ‘the of-genitive is categorically required when the head noun is indefinite (i.e. some members of his cabinet)’ (Biber et al. Reference Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen and Larsson2023: 97). It is not explicitly said why this context was still included – most likely because it only rules out specifying s-genitives but not of-genitives and noun modifiers. As argued above, however, if a context excludes a variant and thus no longer allows variation between all three genitive variants, this context must be excluded. As constructions with of-genitives and noun modifiers are neutral as to the definiteness of the matrix noun phrase and allow an initial determiner, the authors’ dataset will severely overrepresent these variants, which distorts the subsequent statistical analysis.

The expression of definiteness of the possessor is another context that rules out one variant, in this case noun modifiers. While the possessor in a specifying s-genitive and of-genitive is a full noun phrase, noun modifiers are nouns or nominals and thus cannot be independently determined. So, while a specifying s-genitive as in [a school]'s director can be converted into a corresponding of-genitive (the director of a school), there is no corresponding noun modifier. A [school director] determines the head noun director and not school. And the [school director], although correctly expressing the definiteness of director, fails to express the indefiniteness of the possessor school. The three specifying genitive variants can thus only overlap in the context of definite possessors in definite matrix noun phrases starting with the. This categorical context has not been considered in the authors’ study, as is apparent from examples from their database such as the base of her rib cage (p. 124), the breeding of his Blue Wyandotte bantam (p. 124) or the failure of a student enrolled at a campus during spring semester (p. 126), to name just a few.

Table 2 briefly summarizes how the definiteness of the head and the possessor can be expressed across all three variants.

Table 2. The expression of definiteness in the various genitive constructions

3 Summary – and a look forward

The authors include all restrictive modifiers in their study of genitive variation, not distinguishing between specifying and classifying functions and as such include contexts that are not functionally equivalent in the Labovian sense. In addition, they include contexts that are not variable across all three variants, in particular constructions with of-genitives and noun modifiers that are not determined by the, a context incompatible with specifying s-genitives, as well as possessors not determined by the, a context incompatible with noun modifiers. In their attempt to more accurately adhere to Labov's principle of accountability, the authors are actually violating it.

Yet, I would like to conclude on a more positive note. I applaud the authors for having taken up the challenge of including noun modifiers into a study of genitive variation, which will, I hope, stimulate further research into what contexts allow their alternation and what governs it. Indispensable, in my view, is the separation of specifying and classifying functions when selecting the variants. A study of genitive variation should then either focus on what I would like to call ‘primary genitive variation’, i.e. the variation between specifying genitives as in (11), or on ‘secondary genitive variation’, i.e. the variation between classifying genitives/modifiers as in (12), bearing in mind that the latter usually have prepositional variants other than with of as in (12b).

  1. (11)

    1. (a) the FBI's director, the director of the FBI, the FBI director

    2. (b) the barn's door, the door of the barn, the barn door

  2. (12)

    1. (a) lawyer's fees, lawyer fees, the fees of lawyers

    2. (b) the passenger's seat, the passenger seat, the seat for passengers

The main challenge when studying these alternations is to determine the contexts of use where all three genitive variants overlap in usage, and not only two as assumed by the authors. Let me spell out some absolute minimum requirements for identifying variable contexts for the three specifying genitive variants, i.e. primary genitive variation as in (11), in addition to the categorical contexts provided by the authors on p. 102:

  1. 1. Reference-restricting relation between possessor and possessum (head)

    1. a. The possessor is referential/specific (or can be interpreted referentially).

    2. b. The matrix genitive noun phrase refers to a specific referent.

  2. 2. Expression of a ‘possessive relation’, possibly defined as

    1. a. a HAVE relation in the widest sense or expressing a subjective or objective relation,Footnote 12 and/or

    2. b. replaceability by a possessive pronoun (my, your, her, his, its, our, their)

  3. 3. Focus on definite matrix noun phrases and possessors starting with the.

While the authors did include important factors such as animacy, length, final sibilancy and register in their study, it would also be necessary to code for factors known to be vital in the use of specifying noun modifiers as genitive variants, such as e.g. (a) the type of possessive relation, and (b) the type of noun class of the possessor:

  1. a. proper noun vs common noun, and

  2. b. for proper nouns: first names and other names.Footnote 13

A study including both specifying and classifying uses of genitives would be interesting for a quantitative study looking at the distribution of similar or related (and not necessarily functionally equivalent) constructions, but it is not clear how such a study could be done within the variationist approach, which relies on the comparison of functionally equivalent and variable variants. Rather, it would have to be a study rooted in theoretical frameworks suitable for the study of similar and/or related constructions, such as Construction Grammar (e.g. Goldberg Reference Goldberg1995; Zehentner Reference Zehentner2019) or versions of Exemplar Theory (e.g. Bybee Reference Bybee2006; Bresnan Reference Bresnan2021).

Footnotes

I am grateful to Joan Bresnan for most helpfully commenting on previous versions of this reply and to the ELL editors and reviewers for valuable suggestions.

2 On the controversial status of the English possessive 's as an inflectional ending or a clitic see e.g. Anderson (Reference Anderson, Börjars, Denison and Scott2008).

3 See Rosenbach (Reference Rosenbach2019: section 3) on the concept of ‘possession’ and operationalizing it for the study of ‘classic’ English genitive variation (i.e. the variation between the s-genitive and the of-genitive) in terms of referentially anchoring (i.e. reference-restricting) possessive relations; see also further below. In section 3 I will extend this operationalization to include noun modifiers as variants.

4 There is another type of s-genitive in Present-day English, i.e. measure genitives (an hour's delay, one dollar's worth of chocolate), which combines properties of both specifying and classifying s-genitives; cf. Payne & Huddleston (Reference Payne, Huddleston, Rodney and Geoffrey2002: 470). I will ignore measure genitives in this reply as they have barely been studied, though it should be noted that some measure s-genitives do alternate with noun modifiers and of-genitives, e.g. the ten-month layoff vs the ten-months’ layoff (vs the layoff of ten months); see also Rosenbach (Reference Rosenbach2006: 113–14).

5 See Biber et al. (Reference Biber, Szmrecsanyi, Reppen and Larsson2023: 107) for citing these examples from their database.

6 See Rosenbach (Reference Rosenbach2019) for an in-depth discussion on the (non-)equivalence of noun modifiers with specifying s-genitives; see also Breban (Reference Breban2018) and Breban et al. (Reference Breban, Kolkmann and Payne2019).

7 The highlighting of noun modifiers and s-genitives in cited examples is always mine throughout this squib.

8 Quantifying relations as in a bit/piece of cheese should actually be excluded from a study of genitive variation as the possessor/dependent is not referentially restricting the head. Rather, the relation is the other way round, with the head (bit, piece) individuating the possessor/dependent (cheese). Such partitives and pseudopartitives do not alternate with s-genitives (*cheese's bit/piece).

9 Note that figure 3 still is a simplification as it ignores measure genitives (an hour's delay), to-genitives (servant to the king) and other prepositional constructions potentially expressing specifying function (rarely, see e.g. the director for the FBI) or classifying function (commonly, see e.g. a magazine for women, a day in summer).

10 Classifying noun modifiers may occasionally occur with a first name, e.g. A Pete speciality (Kathy Reichs, Fatal Voyage, 93), to be read as ‘a speciality typical of Pete’.

11 On the vexed issue of the (in)definiteness with specifying s-genitives see e.g. Taylor (Reference Taylor1996: 185–204) and Rosenbach (Reference Rosenbach2019: sections 3.2 and 4.2).

12 Subjective and objective relations with nominalized verbal head nouns (John's writings/murder) in principle allow variation between noun modifiers and specifying s-genitives and of-genitives: the eye's movement vs the movement of the eye vs the eye movement.

13 I suspect that the dispreference for identifying/specifying noun modifiers to occur with first names (*the John house/son/poem/courage/office) is categorical, though only an explorative quantitative study will be able to establish this. If it turns out to be a categorical context, some of the most standard genitives (e.g. John's house etc.) will have to be excluded from a study of genitive variation including noun modifiers.

References

Anderson, Stephen R. 2008. The marker of the English ‘Group Genitive’ is a special clitic, not an inflection. In Börjars, Kersti, Denison, David & Scott, Alan K. (eds.), Morphosyntactic categories and the expression of possession, 193218. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Biber, Douglas, Szmrecsanyi, Benedikt, Reppen, Randi & Larsson, Tove. 2023. Expanding the scope of grammatical variation: Towards a comprehensive account of genitive variation across registers. English Language and Linguistics 28(1), 95133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Breban, Tine. 2018. Proper names used as modifiers: A comprehensive functional analysis. English Language and Linguistics 22(3), 381401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Breban, Tine, Kolkmann, Julia & Payne, John. 2019. The impact of semantic relations on grammatical alternation: An experimental study of proper name modifiers and determiner genitives. English Language and Linguistics 23(4), 797826.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bresnan, Joan. 2021. Formal grammar, usage probabilities, and auxiliary contraction. Language 97(1), 108–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bresnan, Joan, Rosenbach, Anette, Szmrecsanyi, Benedikt, Tagliamonte, Sali A. & Todd, Simon. 2017. Syntactic alternations data: Datives and genitives in four varieties of English. Stanford Digital Repository. http://purl.stanford.edu/qj187zs3852Google Scholar
Bybee, Joan. 2006. From usage to grammar: The mind's response to repetition. Language 82(4), 711–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Adele. 1995. Constructions: A Construction Grammar approach to argument structure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Haspelmath, Martin. 1999. Explaining article-possessor complementarity: Economic motivation in noun phrase syntax. Language 75(2), 227–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koptjevskaja-Tamm, Maria. 2002. Adnominal possession in the European languages: Form and function. Sprachtypologie und Universalienforschung 55, 141–72.Google Scholar
Labov, William. 1969. Contraction, deletion, and inherent variability of the English copula. Language 45(4), 715–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Labov, William. 1972. Sociolinguistic patterns. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
McGregor, William. 2009. Introduction. In McGregor, William (ed.), The expression of possession, 112. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Payne, John & Huddleston, Rodney. 2002. Nouns and noun phrases. In Rodney, Huddleston & Geoffrey, K. Pullum et al., The Cambridge grammar of the English language, 323534. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenbach, Anette. 2002. Genitive variation in English: Conceptual factors in synchronic and diachronic studies. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenbach, Anette. 2006. Descriptive genitives in English: A case study in constructional gradience. English Language and Linguistics 10(1), 77118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenbach, Anette. 2007a. Emerging variation: Determiner genitives and noun modifiers in English. English Language and Linguistics 11(1), 143–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenbach, Anette. 2007b. Exploring constructions on the web: A case study. In Hundt, Marianne, Nesselhauf, Nadia & Biewer, Carolin (eds.), Corpus linguistics and the web, 167–90. Amsterdam: Rodopi.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenbach, Anette. 2010. How synchronic gradience makes sense in the light of language change (and vice versa). In Traugott, Elizabeth C. & Trousdale, Graeme (eds.), Gradience, gradualness and grammaticalization, 149–79. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenbach, Anette. 2014. English genitive variation: The state of the art. English Language and Linguistics 18(2), 215–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenbach, Anette. 2019. On the (non-)equivalence of constructions with determiner genitives and noun modifiers in English. English Language and Linguistics 23(4), 759–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlücker, Barbara. 2013. Non-classifying compounds in German. Folia Linguistica 47(2), 449–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlücker, Barbara. 2018. Genitives and proper name compounds in German. In Ackermann, Tania, Simon, Horst & Zimmer, Christian (eds.), Germanic genitives, 275–99. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tagliamonte, Sali A. 2011. Variationist sociolinguistics: Change, observation, interpretation. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Taylor, John R. 1996. Possessives in English. An exploration in Cognitive Grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zehentner, Eva. 2019. Competition in language change: The rise of the English dative alternation. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Different types of adnominal possession

Figure 1

Figure 2. The (simple) web of English genitive variation (cf. Rosenbach 2019: 790)

Figure 2

Figure 3. The complex web of English genitive variation

Figure 3

Table 1. The various genitive constructions in noun phrase structure

Figure 4

Table 2. The expression of definiteness in the various genitive constructions