12.1 Necessity and Necessities in Knowledge and Morality: An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
It is in the absence of thinking, not merely of power as Hobbes had it, that necessity occurs. This is how Locke put it: ‘Where-ever Thought is wholly wanting, or the power to act or forbear according to the direction of Thought, there Necessity takes place.’Footnote 1 Thinking is therefore the opposite of necessity. We are ignorant of ‘the Nature’ of ‘that thinking thing that is in us, and which we look on as ourselves’, save for the fact that it is free to design her own destiny, misery or happiness.Footnote 2 It is possible to ascertain the centrality of human necessities in Locke’s wider theory of knowledge and human morality as set out in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. First, human beings navigate this world securely through the knowledge provided by necessities.
If any one pretends to be so sceptical, as to deny his own Existence, (for really to doubt of it, is manifestly impossible,) let him for me enjoy his beloved Happiness of being nothing, until Hunger, or some other Pain convince him of the contrary.Footnote 3
Second, the particular knowledge constituted by necessities provides a helpful guide to the correct moral action to be taken towards happiness, as it is necessary to assess whether human desires, which are numerous and constant, are fixed on their proper objects. As a rule of thumb of proper conduct, necessities lead to the preservation of life; while following desires threatens its loss if these desires are not examined with the goal of eternal life in mind. As any reader of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding will see, there is much more to Locke’s epistemology and moral philosophy than human necessities. However, human necessities are the hinge that unites knowledge and morality.
12.1.1 Epistemology and Necessities
In An Essay Concerning Human Understanding Locke traced how ideas originate, in order to distinguish between knowledge and opinion. Matthew Priselac has called the epistemology of that book a ‘genetic structure’ of knowledge.Footnote 4 Naturally, ideas start when the human body experiences the external world and the senses inform the mind of this. Together with awareness of the existence of an infinite and omnipresent God, human necessities unproblematically relate human beings to the reality surrounding them. Thus ‘necessities’ have a fundamental role in avoiding general scepticism. Despite Locke’s adherence to corpuscularianism and his conception that everything is composed of atoms in constant flux, it is clear in his epistemology that human beings are equipped to know what will help them to survive in the world, and more than survive.
That the certainty of Things existing in rerum Naturâ, when we have the testimony of our senses for it, is not only as great as our frame can attain to, but as our Condition needs. For our Faculties being suited not to the full extent of Being, nor to a perfect, clear, comprehensive Knowledge of things free from all doubt and scruple; but to the Preservation of us, in whom they are; and accommodated to the use of Life: they serve to our purpose well enough, if they will but give us certain notice of those Things, which are convenient or inconvenient to us.Footnote 5
Significantly, knowledge depends on ‘the right use’ of the powers that nature had bestowed on us, human beings.Footnote 6 Thus both the burden and the advantage of knowledge lie in the reasoning subject.Footnote 7 This demand for the correct use of reason constitutes, in an important sense, Locke’s theory of the burden of freedom. He shares with Boyle the awareness of the immensity of unknown things – created, after all, by an omnipotent God. There are many phenomena that our senses cannot perceive, of which we consequently know nothing.Footnote 8 However, Locke writes, in this ‘Globe of Earth allotted for our Mansion’ we know what we need to know.Footnote 9
The infinite wise Contriver of us, and all things about us, has fitted our Senses, Faculties and Organs, to the conveniences of Life and the Businesses we have to do here.Footnote 10
Senses allow us to distinguish things and examine them in a manner that allows us to ‘apply them to our Uses’ and diversely ‘accommodate the Exigencies of this Life’.Footnote 11 Hobbes had declared that the fool is wrong. In turn Locke would defend that ‘the skeptic is wrong.’Footnote 12 In this endeavour human necessities appear to be instrumental. Furthermore, the rejection of innate principles in the theory of knowledge that Locke presented in An Essay may be paralleled with Boyle’s rejection of a metaphysical concept of nature as mentioned in Chapter 7. Both concepts were (in their view) of doubtful authority and provenance and prevented the advancement of science. Locke regarded innate principles as putting difficulties in the way of acquiring better understanding of how the faculty of reasoning works.
On this faculty of Distinguishing one thing from another, depends the evidence and certainty of several, even very general Propositions, which have passed for innate Truths; because Men over-looking the true cause, why those Propositions find universal assent, impute it wholly to native uniform Impressions; whereas it in truth depends upon this clear discerning Faculty of the Mind, whereby it perceives two Ideas to be the same or different.Footnote 13
Further, in his important discussion of liberty and necessity in the context of power (Book II, chapter IX), Locke concedes that human beings necessarily want happiness and considers that perfection lies in the determination of human will by choosing what is good.Footnote 14 One could argue that these two claims resemble in practice a description of innate principles, but Locke consistently adheres to the terminology of an elusive principle of necessity. My intention, however, is not to contest Locke’s extraordinary analysis of human morality but to highlight the instrumental role played by human necessities in his epistemological and moral method. An Essay may well be read as an extremely accomplished effort to appease the anxiety of the era struggling to grapple with disparate elements left over from a past theological period by means of a rational moral philosophy. Timothy Stanton has emphasized that Locke took the view that God was the foundation of all morality and that an atheist could accordingly have no morality.Footnote 15 A ‘company of poor insects’ is the comparison Locke used to describe what would become of humanity without God.Footnote 16 At the same time his moral theory is superbly empirical and thus rational, and that is of course its strength. In that empirical perspective the importance of human necessities cannot be doubted because human beings’ sole motivation for action lies in ‘uneasiness’ of mind or body.Footnote 17 ‘Uneasiness’ represented by desire might be natural, such as thirst, hunger, or indeed love, or ‘fantastical’, such as honours.Footnote 18 That the desire for self-preservation moves everyone to act and that the assumption that human needs bring people together, we might recall, appear in the Essays on the Law of Nature and they embody the elements for beginning a political society specified in the Two Treatises of Government – these are necessity, convenience and inclination, as we will see in this chapter.Footnote 19 Desires are numerous, either through natural wants or custom and habit.Footnote 20 At any rate, the most pressing uneasiness, for instance a terrible pain, an addiction to alcohol or a passionate love or hunger determines action in the absence of conflicting desires.Footnote 21
Moreover, everything starts with necessities as he noted in the argument on the origin of ideas set out in Book II.
Therefore I doubt not but Children, by the exercise of their Senses and Objects, that affect them in the Womb, receive some few Ideas, before they are born, as the unavoidable effects, either of the Bodies that environ them, or else of those Wants or Diseases they suffer, amongst which, (if one may conjencture concerning things not very capable of examination) I think the Ideas of Hunger and Warmth are two: which probably are some of the first that Children have, and which they scarce ever part with again.Footnote 22
He took the view that the order and variety of ideas that a child receives after their birth is very uncertain.Footnote 23 However, he asserted that a certain process occurs when the child is still in the mother’s womb. Intellectual perception accordingly starts through surrounding bodies, necessities and diseases, and specifically with necessities.
12.1.2 Between Aquinas and Henry of Ghent
The aim of freedom, whose existence Locke strongly defends, is that we attain the good we choose. The only determinations in human beings’ moral action that he admits are first that when faced with a decision, the will necessitates (a) to will this or (b) not to will it – tertium non datur;Footnote 24 and second, that individuals will always choose what they think best for themselves in order to achieve happiness. Experience and observation show that people choose the good that they regard as constituting a necessary part of their happiness, which might or might not be ‘the greatest good’.Footnote 25 However, the true perfection of an intellectual nature is to achieve true and solid happiness, and such a person accordingly chooses ‘the proper Object of desire’, that is to say, one that identifies affection and truth.Footnote 26 Locke follows Aquinas in this description of how the objects of desire move to action.Footnote 27 In fact, what Locke accomplished in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding may be understood as recovering a Christian moral language and as transmuting self-interest into terms of necessity, and hence as a vocation to perfection.
Every Man is put under a necessity by his constitution, as an intelligent Being, to be determined in willing by his own thought and judgment, what is best for him to do.Footnote 28
Anything else, Locke concluded, would be determination by some else and thus lack of freedom. In his understanding, the ‘necessity of being happy’ contains a preference for eternal happiness, rather than a present but transient happiness.Footnote 29 However, misjudgements of reason about happiness abound. Moreover, according to Locke, freedom was also honoured when an individual willingly opted for the lowest good, a present pleasure that however causes that individual to lose the chance of eternal bliss – it was a madman’s freedom, but freedom nonetheless.Footnote 30 Locke commented in this context on the classical case of the prisoner who suddenly realized that he had no chains.
Famously, in one of his three solutions to this case contained in Questio 26 of his Quodlibet IX produced in Lent of 1286, the Parisian theologian Henry of Ghent had attributed to the man sentenced to death a licit power (licit potestas) to flee.Footnote 31 On the strength of this solution, Henry is often mentioned as an introductory author in the histories of natural rights, since he utilized a remarkably novel language in this regard.Footnote 32 In answering the question of whether ‘one man sentenced to death can licitly flee if he has the time and place’, Henry declared that if the circumstances of place and time were favourable – for instance ‘he would be without chains and the door would be open’ – the criminal was a ‘homicide’ if he ‘did not provide for himself as he should’ and fled, as necessity compelled him to do. Unlike the necessity of the judge to punish him, the prisoner’s necessity was of a higher calibre and compelled him to search for his freedom.Footnote 33 The condemned man ‘had like a power of using the same body’ in order to guard his life as had the judge in order to punish him.Footnote 34 However, as custodian of the life dwelling in the body, the soul’s power over the body was greater than the judge’s. Henry posed the problem as the criminal’s licit power of using his body, which was also his right (ius suum) according to the law of nature, and if necessary of exercising that right (exsequendi ius suum). ‘Over a certain thing’ Henry had stated ‘there can be a power or right’ (potestas sive ius) in two ways. One, like the ownership in the substance of the thing. In the case of the body, ‘only the soul under God has property in the substance of the body’, and ‘the other like a use in determined actions that can be exercised over the thing,’ hence the judge’s right to enchain etc. (ius in vinculando etc.).Footnote 35
In his discussion of the text, Brian Tierney situates Henry’s novel language in the context of the dawn of the idea of natural rights in the late Middle Ages, tracing how this solution was taken up by another Parisian theologian, Jacques Almain, in around 1500.Footnote 36 Furthermore, Aquinas had discussed the case, explaining that someone sentenced to death ought to act according to reason and not only be guided by the natural instinct of survival. A just individual would escape if he or she was innocent and stay in prison if guilty.Footnote 37
Reason has been given to human beings in order to carry on what nature inclines them to, not randomly, but according to the order of reason. Hence not all defense of themselves is licit, but only that which is done with due guidance.Footnote 38
Instead, preservation of life and the natural rights of the soul over the body took precedence in Henry’s discussion. His goal was to determine the criminal’s rights and duties. What is plain, however, is that while Aquinas transferred the moral decision to the individual sentenced to death in the particular situation, and to his or her capacity of reasoning, Henry’s solution is that of the casuistic theologian who determines who had always the better right and even the obligation to exercise the natural right of preservation.Footnote 39 No matter how general the view may be, Tierney has rightly noted the impossibility of regarding Locke’s famous position in the Two Treatises on the right of property over one’s person as a radical departure of scholasticism.Footnote 40 In this context, critiques emphasizing links between the slavery system and Locke’s natural right of property over one’s person (rather than with slavery as the classic institution of ius gentium) need to be complicated with studies on Scholasticism and with perceptions as to how Neoplatonism made it conceptually possible in the first place for this type of appropriation by the soul of everything material, even one’s body.Footnote 41 It is also clear that at the outset people like Henry pursued the autonomy of individuals by means of a robust dualism connecting the soul and God, with no authority in between – certainly the opposite project to slavery. Locke asserted that ‘every Man has a Property in his own Person. This no Body has any Right to but himself. The Labour of his Body, and the Work of his hands, we may say, are properly his’. If taken literally, these statements amount more to an anti-slavery manifesto than a justification for it.Footnote 42 In an era in which commercial exploitation of natural resources and enslavement of human beings became of paramount economic importance, the development of a natural law mingled with civil law notions of property rights seems to have played an ambiguous role. But with a view to what key theologians like Henry wrote on the natural rights of individuals, Locke appears less an original thinker on the question and more a continuator of a tradition favouring autonomy, especially of classic Parisian theologians.Footnote 43
Brian Tierney mainly analysed Locke’s position on natural rights in the Two Treatises. However, in An Essay the philosopher’s use of the prisoner example was not about rights. Intriguingly it seemed to be more in line with Aquinas’s theory of freedom of moral decision, but with an argument that evidences that naturalist ideas of self-preservation had attained centrality in his line of thinking. Locke’s prisoner is all alone, and no one threatens him but the inhospitality of life outside the prison. He is able to decide what to do – but this is the most difficult part, for there is no normative principle that compels him to act beyond his necessary search for happiness. In An Essay this example serves to demonstrate the individual’s power to suspend judgment and examine the morality of each situation before acting. While due examination of the good and evil involved, was ‘all that [he] needs [to do]’, the prisoner was no less free if he chose to ‘stay in his Prison’. Locke depicts this choice as being prompted by the convenience urged by the prisoner’s physical body, but crucially, not its necessities: ‘the darkness of the Night’, ‘the illness of the Weather’ or ‘the want of other Lodgings’ made him prefer to stay.Footnote 44 However, Locke remarked that the highest perfection of an intellectual nature demanded that a human being would be increasingly free from ‘any necessary determination of our will or from a necessary compliance with our desire’.Footnote 45 Locke’s employment of the classical case of the prisoner who finds himself without chains suggests that, in extreme cases, excessive care for the body beyond necessities may prevent people from attaining the superior freedom that awaits them.
12.1.3 Necessary Happiness
This thing that human beings have of searching for true happiness, Locke depicted as the ‘necessity’ of pursuing a higher happiness and ‘the necessity’ of suspending judgment in favour of deliberation in order to achieve that goal.Footnote 46 That he was more inclined to theological optimism is apparent in that in The Reasonableness of Christianity he rejected a parallel ‘necessity of sinning’, thus marking a distance between his ideas and those of Calvinist influence.Footnote 47 Hence, Ian Harris, in his discussion of Locke’s assessment of the consequences of original sin, writes that the capability of human beings to live as good Christians in An Essay is complementary to his theological convictions.Footnote 48 God cares tenderly for human beings. This is not the place to discuss whether John Locke, who was a physician, employs the figure of God the merciful Father – fundamental in any discussion of original sin – with a therapeutic or a theological purpose. However, I would be inclined to consider that both were relevant.Footnote 49
Nevertheless, experience also showed that many people chose the worse before the better, and not always guiltily.Footnote 50 Locke tones down Boyle’s doctrine of ‘scientist as priest’ by teaching that at the end of the day everyone is an experimental philosopher in relation to his or her own moral conduct, which Michael Ben-Chaim has termed the doctrine of experience as a divine gift.Footnote 51 In Locke’s division of sciences, ethics was ‘the skill of Right applying our own Powers and Actions, for the Attainment of things good and useful’.Footnote 52 Bad choices stemmed from lack of skill and impossible situations. The ‘bodily torments’ of a person on the rack or suffering want or disease made it difficult to make a right moral decision. Necessity made one act disgracefully (Necessitas cogit ad turpia), noted Locke, as Robert Burton had also done in his scorn of poverty, which was the mother of all vices and ridicule.Footnote 53 Furthermore, there was the issue of time in the relationship between the distant, but ‘greatest absent good’ – the ‘proper object of our desires’ – and the present fulfilment of a desire.Footnote 54 Ignorance, rash judgment due to passion that prevented deliberation, and so on, resulted in our mistaking desire for a present pleasure for genuine good. As his repeated moral guidance in this direction shows in An Essay, rather than being glorified, ‘desire’ is dissected, isolated and scientifically anatomized. Pleasure could be in itself a way to God or a means to lose eternal life. It depended on the situation that proper reasoning must discern. Alexander Wragge-Morley argues that the Fellows of the Royal Society were of the view that the pleasure obtained through the human senses was both a way to nature and God.Footnote 55 In this regard defining Locke’s discussion of pleasure in An Essay as having a purely hedonistic character ignores the depth of his theological and epistemological background.Footnote 56
Locke used the language of necessities in An Essay to present his position in relation to the weighty problem of liberty and necessity. His solution is rather classic and uncompromising on freedom and virtue, but methodologically novel. Necessities helped him to describe free individuals acting in the world and, as he was persuaded, freely choosing the gift of walking in the world or not towards their Creator.
12.2 Necessities, Dominion and Money in the Two Treatises of Government
12.2.1 Dominion for Necessities
In the Two Treatises of Government human necessities connect the arguments as to the divine design of the world, the obligation of natural law and the function of government. The fundamental law of nature in that text is an obligation of self-preservation directing human beings’ lives – it is also practically the only one together with ‘the Fundamental Law of Property’.Footnote 57 Human beings perceive that the desire to preserve themselves is implanted in their hearts. That understanding, in fact a law of reason, obliges an individual first to provide for his or her necessities, and then for those of humankind at large.Footnote 58 The remainder of natural rights derives from that fundamental law of nature. Human beings grasp this obligation quasi-rationally. Moreover, they understand that the obligation to obey the fundamental law of nature of preservation is the result of how the world has been designed by Someone Else.Footnote 59 To defy that design, to disobey the inner call to provide with the products of nature for human necessities, amounts to challenging the subjection owed to the Creator. Hence, human necessities became an important means by which Locke integrated faith and reason. Experienced empirically by everyone and thus showing to human beings the rationality of a creation free willed by God, human necessities are at once contingent and universal, prudential and theoretical. Locke constructed his doctrine of human necessities as the philosopher’s companion to the theologian’s argument of a Maker, hence intended, albeit not always successfully, to be compatible with theological tradition.Footnote 60
In the First Treatise, Locke emphasizes the polemical intent of uniting freedom and political obligation with human necessities. This is first done through a brief critique of the absolutist politics of necessity espoused by Filmer. Next, and more importantly, Locke unites the liberty of natural law and his preferred method of government – popular assembly – by placing the origin of property in the context of the natural desire for self-preservation. Robert Filmer had marked his absolutism by means of ‘Laws of Necessity’. When Kings were absent in wars, subjects must find the sovereign’s will ‘in the Tables of his Laws’. Filmer sought to trace this slavery of ‘Absolute Dominion’ back to Adam and thus to God. Locke argued, however, that Filmer’s purpose had in reality been to leave people with nothing, and thus appease their conscience and convince them by ‘Undeniable proofs of its Necessity’ that they must submit peacefully to that ‘Absolute Dominion’.Footnote 61 In this sense, such a reasoning of necessity annulled conscience. Filmer’s theory had given a theological foundation to a political dominion with absolutist characteristics, that is, with absolute power and dominion of life and death. Against Filmer’s idea that Adam was ‘Proprietor of the world’ with private dominion over it, Locke famously defended a common dominion of all humankind over animals, ‘the dominion of the whole species of Mankind over the inferior Species of Creatures’.Footnote 62 In this early part of the First Treatise, Filmer’s absolutist political dominion soon becomes, in Locke’s hands, a common property over inferior animals. This turns remarkably evident when Locke brings Eve into the picture: had she also not received God’s grant as to be ‘Lady’, as Adam was ‘Lord of the World?’ Thus, Filmer’s theory would have the result of hindering ‘her Dominion over the Creatures or Property in them’.Footnote 63
The point is relevant in relation to the core function of human necessities. If there was someone that had private dominion over ‘the Food and Rayment, and other Conveniences of Life’ – i.e. who had an exclusive right of use – how could the rest of mankind fulfil the commandment of increasing and multiplying? If ‘their Subsistence’ depended on the will of one, dreary results could be expected, as Locke notes, recalling how the multitude are deprived of the ‘conveniences of life’ in ‘the Absolute Monarchies of the World’.Footnote 64 That one had a natural right over another in that respect had been never God’s design: ‘we know God hath not left one Man so to the Mercy of another, that he may starve him if he please’.Footnote 65 The foundation of sovereignty could therefore not be ‘anothers necessity’. Instead, only the consent that someone in need gave – who ended up in that situation through human injustice, chance or lack of industriousness – was valid. That individual preferred to be a subject than to starve, while the sovereign could access only so much power as he or she consented to renounce.Footnote 66 Neither did this principle of sovereignty apply to children, born in need – as Locke wrote in the Second Treatise, ‘the necessities of his Life, the Health of his Body, and the Information of his Mind would require him to be directed by the Will of others and not his own’.Footnote 67 However, a small child’s precarious status never amounted to dominion over the person of the child. Rather the main intention of nature was that humanity be preserved and increased through the care of parents, while even animals may sometimes ‘neglect their own Private good’ in order to care for their baby animals.Footnote 68
Locke did what he was supposed to do in his exposition of natural law, that is, he acknowledged the philosophical tradition and wrote within it.Footnote 69 Although he had a novel contribution to make by arguing the centrality of labour as a means to acquire private property to provide for the necessities of human beings, Locke did not deviate remarkably in style from previous writings on natural law.Footnote 70 However, since his epistemology was radically new, the author of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding imbued his political theory with innovative depth through his scientific method. Reason, for Locke, is like a ‘dark room’, similar to ‘a Closet wholly shut from light’, with small openings through which ‘Ideas of things’ are brought in by means of sensation.Footnote 71 Unconventionally, as we have seen already, he conceived neither of a weakened light of nature nor of reason as active sources of light in themselves. Instead, he regarded experience as crucial for human action. In terms of natural law, this leads to a concentration on questions of material self-preservation. Putting aside the tradition of practical moral reasoning, Locke’s moral reasoning is more about the individual human being mastering ‘the Dominion of Man in his little World of his own Understanding’.Footnote 72 Moreover, the truth of things is outside the individual who thinks and must be discovered in the Maker’s design. It is important to note, however, that rights of dominion over the earth – and not virtue ethics, or other expressions of practical reason – are also at the core of the law of nature in the tradition of natural rights.Footnote 73 A. John Simmons is right in urging a reading of Locke’s moral theory that is multifaceted and has a variety of levels, taking seriously duty-based, rights-based and virtues-based theory, but ultimately becoming none of them.Footnote 74 What Locke never did, however, was to dwell on matters of practical reasoning in the manner that had been understood at least since Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics. In the Two Treatises of Government Locke follows the theological tradition of dominion rights of the type inaugurated early on by Henry of Ghent, as we saw in the previous section, imbuing it with his theory of an experiential discovery of God’s will. This theoretical depth transformed his idea of property rights into a complex theme, so rich that it would be a hollow claim to label him a theorist of capitalism.Footnote 75 Property founded on self-preservation was central to a theological tradition of care for each individual that Locke evidently mastered and useful to address and oppose the already general commentary on self-interest, which, as we saw in the Chapter 8, he rejected from the beginning. Given its capacity to connect the past and the future, property was very fitting a focus for a natural philosopher concerned with necessities. All begins by feeling in one’s body the pain of need, for food and other necessaries, and this awakens the desire, divinely implanted, for self-preservation.
The core doctrine about God’s natural design for human beings, on which the concept of property is founded, appears in the crucial paragraph 86, on which the First Treatise hinges. In this way, Filmer’s idea of Adam’s being granted exclusive private dominion is definitively demolished. Locke devotes the remainder of the text to confute Filmer’s argument as to a sacred authority that God granted to Adam. Thus the reader is led to the Second Treatise to read Locke’s robust explanation of the origins and content of government, or in other words, of the origins of dominion as imperium and authority. Due to his close commentary on Filmer in the previous paragraph on the origin of property and in order to avoid confusion, Locke writes in paragraph 86, he would state plainly his own case.Footnote 76
God having made Man, and planted in him, as in all other Animals, a strong desire of Self-preservation, and furnished the World with things fit for Food and Rayment and other Necessaries of Life, Subservient to his design, that Man should live and abode for some time upon the Face of the Earth, and not that so curious and wonderful a piece of workmanship by its own Negligence, or want of Necessaries, should perish again, presently after a few moments continuance: God, I say, having made Man and the World thus, spoke to him, (that is) directed him by his Senses and Reason, as he did the inferior Animals by their Sense, and Instinct, which he had place in them to that purpose, to the use of those things, which were serviceable for his Subsistence, and given him as means of his Preservation.Footnote 77
The obligation to preserve oneself and mankind was not only the outcome of the design of nature, but the very will of God planted in our heart, a will that human reason could understand and pursue through a natural right to use things, or in other words, through property. Reason thus confirmed Revelation while the reality that reason grasped was antecedent to the letter of the Bible.Footnote 78 Moreover, all this revolved around the needs of human beings, the necessaries created to satisfy them and God’s plan that it ought to be so.
And thus Man’s Property in the Creatures, was founded upon the right he had, to make use of those things that were necessary or useful to his Being.Footnote 79
In the wonderful paragraph 86, Locke made much of the innate principle of self-preservation through necessities, the only innate principle he admitted on the grounds that it was not planted in reason. In the Second Treatise it exceptionally appeared ‘writ in the Hearts of all Mankind’ and gave certainty to the law of nature.Footnote 80 Human beings were therefore connected to their material surroundings through necessities. Here Locke dwelt as what in fact he was, a medical doctor, a philosopher of needs and a theologian too, in the original care of a God that was merciful to his creatures in providing them with necessaries for their subsistence. Crucially that was the manner in which God had originally designed the world, governed by a fundamental law of nature that bound a man ‘to preserve himself’ and, as stated in the Second Treatise, ‘when his own Preservation’ came not in competition he ought ‘as much as he can, to preserve the rest of Mankind’.Footnote 81 The desire for (self)-preservation substantiated the law of nature that, as Locke repeatedly affirms, in turn generated the radical equality of human beings, endowed with similar faculties, a community of nature and, hence, without subordination among them. Since this was the reason and foundation of Adam’s property, ‘[e]very Man had a right to the Creatures, by the Same Title Adam had’.Footnote 82 Every creature ‘of the same species’ was ‘born to all the same advantages of Nature’.Footnote 83 The question of subsistence and preservation, despite its naturalistic and Hobbesian overtones, was squarely placed within theological tradition, and more so in its connection with the right over natural things or necessaries.
Whether we consider natural Reason, which tells us, that Men, being once born, have a right to their Preservation, and consequently to Meat and Drink, and such other things, as Nature affords to their Subsistence: or Revelation, which gives us an account of those Grants God made of the World to Adam, and to Noah, and his Sons, ‘tis very clear, that God, as King David says, Psal. CXV. xvj. Has given the Earth to the Children of men, given it to Mankind in common.Footnote 84
The same idea appears, among others, in the famous De vita spirituale animae by the French theologian Jean Gerson (1363–1429).
There is the natural dominion, a gift of God, by which the creature has a right directly from God to draw other inferior things for her use and conservation, available to all equally and inalienably, according to the original justice or natural integrity.Footnote 85
M. J. Silverthorne writes that Hobbes held that self-preservation was a right, ‘Iuris naturalis fundamentum primum’ and not a law; while Locke, sharing Pufendorf’s vocabulary of obligation, transformed it into a desire planted by God, which became both a law of preservation and a right.Footnote 86 Blending old Scholasticism with the thinking of Hobbes and Pufendorf in relation to natural law, natural rights and property, but also utilizing an original method based on natural sciences and theology, the process of Locke’s thinking generated the useful new idiom of necessities. Not fear, but necessities and convenience – and hence the hazard of protecting property from the uncertainties of the state of nature is Locke’s most peculiar principle, which he dovetailed with principles and theories drawn from the theological tradition.
12.2.2 Private Property and Money
Reason, evil passions, freedom under God, the public good and money at once heighten and shatter this divine natural law that the Creator wanted for his workmanship. Human beings entered societies gradually when they understood that the state of nature held difficulties and dangers, and that it would be more convenient for their preservation to unite for a common project of public good. They also established governments, whose end was the protection and preservation of their lives, liberties and estates – i.e. their property.Footnote 87 The property in their lives and liberty, and the private property in their estates is what individuals wanted to protect by uniting in civil societies. Private property was therefore usual in the state of nature, and so was its accumulation. As a matter of fact, as soon as human beings started to use the goods of creation, private property begun.
Both in the state of nature and in civil society human beings are free. Submission to an absolute power always entails going against the law of self-preservation.Footnote 88 For in order to survive, one must never subject oneself to ‘the inconstant, uncertain, unknown Arbitrary Will of another Man’, but only to legislative power that has been consented to, and only to the extent of the trust put in it.Footnote 89 According to the Two Treatises, human beings have been created with all the potential to become prosperous and happy individuals. Hence, the freedom of human beings did not originate in government. Union in a society entrusted with a government became the most pressing and rational course of action due to the existence of ‘degenerate Men’ – corrupt individuals ‘biassed by their Interest’ – who were unable to apply the law of nature and that threatened the life and property of others with violence.Footnote 90 The state of nature lacked a settled and well-known law, an objective and known judge and a power to back the implementation of legal decisions, and all this was what people chose when they united in commonwealths under government to achieve ‘the Preservation of their Property’. In Locke’s often repeated triad, life, liberty and estate constitute ‘Property’. Correspondingly, a violator of the law of nature or a bad government would endanger property and ‘impoverish, harass, or subdue’ the members of the commonwealth.Footnote 91
With all this Locke made clear that Filmer’s supposition that Adam was attributed private dominion was unnecessary. Perhaps with the aim of endowing private property with positive content that would not resonate with ideas of evil and sin, Filmer had defended its adamite and biblical origin, to explain how the earth and its goods, granted to the children of God, had become private. Instead, God had willed that in the world common property becomes private property naturally when human beings appropriate for their use the goods necessary for their preservation.Footnote 92 The human reason that God also gave to human beings in the moment of creation enables human beings ‘to make use of it [the World in Common] to the best advantage of Life, and convenience’, their ‘support and comfort’.Footnote 93
Therefore, it is proper of the rationality of human beings to thrive in all respects and to make use of the earth in that sense. But is must be underlined that the entirety of creation has never been common. Each individual human being that has been created in history is master of their soul and body. His or her ‘Person’ is his or her ‘Property’. As a consequence, ‘Labour’ is also ‘the unquestionable Property of the Labourer’.Footnote 94 Thus ‘labour’ allows human beings to ‘fix’ their property in the necessaries of life. ‘Acorns’, ‘apples’ and ‘turfs’ belong to the individual or the master and owner of servants and animals that picks, cuts and eats them.Footnote 95 In fact, Locke notes, since the commonality of property comprises necessaries and conveniences that allow the subsistence of human beings, finding the origin of private property ‘in the consent of all Mankind’ would have meant the death of all, and an absurd death at that.Footnote 96 Instead, private property was founded in the individual’s right to the necessaries for her preservation, in the state in which ‘Nature’ has provided them, and by mixing them with her labour, making them her own. Locke’s solution underlines the positive aspect of private property and he also emphasizes that it is not mere survival that is at stake under natural law, but people’s ‘benefit and the greatest Conveniencies of Life they were capable to draw from it’.Footnote 97 Human beings had therefore in themselves the ‘great Foundation of property’.Footnote 98 Private property started with the appropriation of necessities and materialized through the hard work and ingenuity that multiplied the value of things. For ‘Nature and the Earth furnished only the almost worthless Materials’.Footnote 99 In a word, God ‘gave’ the world ‘to the use of the Industrious and Rational’, not to the ‘Fancy or Covetousness of the Quarrelsom and Contentious’. ‘Labour’ therefore constitutes human beings’ title to the goods of the world necessary for their preservation. Locke added the caveat that natural law obliged one not to take more than one may consume and enjoy. Beyond that, a violation of the law of nature occurred if foods and goods spoiled in one’s possession. That is, ‘the measure of Property, Nature has well set, by the Extent of Mens Labour and the Conveniency of Life’.Footnote 100 Allowing fruit to rot or meat to putrefy was an offence against the law of nature that was, significantly, liable to be punished by anyone.Footnote 101 By this means the concept of property escalates from being common property in the first natural stage to also being private property in a second natural moment, but still with a token of equality for preservation.
The passing from common to private property was meant to happen from the beginning and was not a consequence of the original sin. This is well highlighted by contrasting Locke’s theory of the use of goods with an example drawn from English canon law of the Middle Ages. One of the special characteristics of canon law is that it regulates many aspects of the lives of persons called to perfection – i.e. to live in accordance with the law of the Gospel and within monasteries.Footnote 102 What canon lawyers stated in these instances was not meant to be generalized because they would hardly make any sense in the absence of a monk’s previous vows. The Summa De iure canonico tractaturus to Gratian Decretum by the canonist Magister Honorius of Kent is one of the main works of the French and Anglo-Norman school of the last decade of the twelfth century. It contains one good example of the transition of common to private property within the bounds of the monastery, constituting a legal space under the imposition of a law of common property.Footnote 103 For canon lawyers, common property was a precept of natural law through monks’ vows that meant that nothing is one’s own, ‘neither bread nor hood’. One ought to give only to a monk in need, otherwise one was always required to ask the prior before giving, because through the vow, monks ‘did not only renounce property, but also pleasure’ (of sharing). The interest in this issue lies in the level of detail with which it is presented. However, can the monk say that this bread is mine, when it is cut for his use (fractus), or chewed (masticates)? The canonist’s radical answer was that the thing stops being common when use by another is no longer possible.Footnote 104
Certainly God had not imposed such a law of common property on human beings. But he obliged commitment to a personal law of self-preservation, fulfilled through private property and, to the extent that this was possible, in the service of the entire humankind. Preservation is at issue also in the case Locke presented concerning a conqueror in a just war who assumes the right to reparations from the vanquished. Despite having the law on its side, the victorious commonwealth could never gain dominion over what was needed to ensure the survival of children. Since the fundamental law of nature was ‘that all, as much as may be, should be preserved’, if there was not enough money available to compensate in full the losses incurred as well as ensure the survival of the children, the former must give way to the latter to the extent that their survival is secured.Footnote 105
It appears that big families and even cities emerged in the state of nature, and ‘possessions enlarged with the need of them’.Footnote 106 However, in the beginning ‘right and conveniency’ worked together:
This left no room for Controversie about the Title, nor for Incroachment on the Right of others; what Portion a Man carved to himself, was easily seen; and it was useless as well as dishonest to carve himself too much, or take more than he needed.Footnote 107
This manner of living, still in the state of nature, ‘out of the bounds of Societie’, changed dramatically with the invention of something imperishable, money, and the ‘tacit Agreement of Men to put a value on it’.Footnote 108 Now people started to desire goods beyond necessity, to long for things that were not really useful.Footnote 109 Such objects as diamonds or pieces of yellow metal could be exchanged for perishable things that have intrinsic value which ‘depends only on their usefulness to the Life of Man’.Footnote 110 Individuals could then possess more land that they needed and produce, dig and build more that they could use, with the purpose of exchanging the surplus for money, gold and silver. Hoarding up money could be done without violating the law of nature, and ‘without injury to any one, these metalls not spoileing or decaying in the hands of the possessor’.Footnote 111 The Two Treatises describes this entire process that a monetary economy enables mostly as a positive evolution, the result of the ingenuity and industriousness of human beings as rational creatures. In paragraph 43 of the Second Treatise Locke explains that it is ‘Labour’ that ‘puts the greatest part of Value upon Land’. That appears plainly from his calculation of the productivity of acres of wasteland in America as compared to that of fertile and well-cultivated soil in Devonshire (England) at least to be 10/1000.Footnote 112
However, Locke seemed to be in two minds in his normative appraisal of the contribution of money in relation to human beings. With the employment and foundation of ‘Labour’, money was clearly the means that facilitated ‘the Benefit of Mankind’ by producing a greater amount of product from the same land. It was also money that made possible ‘the desire of having more than Men needed’. Moreover, securing protection and encouragement ‘to the honest industry of Mankind’ was how the philosopher envisaged a wise and godlike Prince. Intriguingly, Locke noted that as soon as something that has the function of money appears, an individual ‘will begin presently to enlarge his Possessions’.Footnote 113 Was that something he considered to be wrong in the conduct of an individual? It does not seem to be Locke’s opinion, since
the exceeding of the bounds of his just Property not lying in the largeness of his Possession, but the perishing of any thing uselessly in it.Footnote 114
The chapter on ‘Property’ contains a long explanation to the effect that the function of private property is to provide for necessities. When money appears, ‘the temptation to enlarge possession’ beyond necessities accompanies it. However, this is apparently not merely to satisfy the evil concupiscence, amor sceleratus habendi.Footnote 115 Despite Locke’s proverbial ambiguity, it is possible to argue that the accumulation of property that money enables has ultimately a public function of providing for the necessities of the nation and even of mankind, if regulated by law. But this requirement seems to be only possible within a commonwealth – either on a domestic or a larger scale – that gives rise to an even more pressing need to leave the state of nature after the invention of money.
12.2.3 Preservation, Government and the Public Good
Indeed, money is not the last word in Two Treatises of Government. Locke’s decisive proposal in that text is to put the public good at the centre both of the act of constituting a nation and its government. By constituting the end of government, necessities and preservation again serve the purpose of establishing the theoretical foundation in the Second Treatise. In this way, the private dominion of necessities of the First Treatise becomes the justification of imperium and dominion as authority. In view of the extent of the critique of his individualism, it is surprising to ascertain that a communitarian and political Locke emerges from a textual analysis of the concluding part of the text second treatise. Furthermore, he arrived at that position by underscoring the law of nature of self-preservation of the people. The public good seems, therefore, to be the political articulation of the moral theory of self-preservation analysed so far.
Scholarship of the twentieth century tended to highlight the novelty of the centrality of labour in the Two Treatises and its influence on Adam Smith and Karl Marx.Footnote 116 It was again Locke’s wonderful ambiguity and the liberal use he made of his knowledge of economy and theology that emboldened him to describe labour as the main source of economic value. The background to this lay in the Book of Genesis: God ‘put [Adam] in the Garden of Eden to work it and take care of it’.Footnote 117 In response to Macpherson’s pro-capitalist thesis about Locke, John Dunn noted how inadequate it was to view Locke as the ‘convinced lyricist of the moral sufficiency of any system of economic production’.Footnote 118 Dunn went on to describe Locke as a Calvinist calling to labour, and he introduces an incomparable quote from a letter from Locke to his friend William Molyneux dated 19 January 1694:
I think every one, according to what way Providence has placed him in, is bound to labour for the public good, as far as he is able or else he has no right to eat.Footnote 119
Locke’s argument on the theological centrality of labour is strong and consistent and, Dunn argues, he considered the human being with respect to society and family as ‘a recipient of the commands of God’, and not merely as ‘economic producer, a proprietor of his labour’. However, it may be the case that Dunn’s answer on economic spiritualism was framed to a certain extent by the fact that he was responding to Macpherson’s argument concerning economic materialism.Footnote 120 To set this out plainly, in this quote, ‘labour’ and ‘public good’ are equally important and the latter has the greater textual relevance in the Two Treatises of Government overall.Footnote 121
Locke started his discussion of political society with two principal forms of society – marriage and civil society – into which a human being enters ‘under strong Obligations of Necessity, Convenience, and Inclination’.Footnote 122 It is tempting to suggest an analogy between commonwealth and marriage in the Two Treatises: where of the two the former demands more from a person than the latter. Both require express consent – tacit consent is not enough – and by incorporating him to the Commonwealth a man
by his uniting himself thereunto, annexed also, and submits to the Community those Possessions, which he has or shall acquire that do not already belong to any other Government.Footnote 123
However, it is not necessary to press this point further but only to highlight the level of life commitment that signifies membership of the commonwealth for Locke – far from the notorious ‘possessive individualism’.Footnote 124 The reason for renouncing the ‘Empire’ that human beings had in the state of nature and subjecting themselves to the power of another’s ‘Dominion’ was the insecurity involved in maintaining power over one person and possessions. The rights existed, but their enjoyment was always at potential risk of being threatened by others. After entering the commonwealth things change quite radically in the sense that one is no longer alone with one’s family, but
with others who are already united, or have a mind to unite for the mutual Preservation of their Lives, Liberties and Estates, which I call by the general Name, Property.Footnote 125
The preservation of property is now mutual. Self-preservation is easier in a commonwealth because there are laws, rulers and judges – individuals have given up their power to do whatever they thought appropriate in order to maintain self-preservation and to punish the crimes against the law of nature. However, the commonwealth represents a more complex situation because laws must be laid down to provide for the public good.Footnote 126 No one, moreover, after having given up equality, liberty and executive power, would be satisfied with mere survival in civil society. Instead, people seek to better their condition with respect to the state of nature: ‘[f]or not rational creature can be supposed to change his condition with an intention to be worse’. In fact, the ultimate state of a flawed government is exactly that, when things no longer function, and the situation is worse than the state of nature. It amounts to what we would call today a failed state, lacking proper administration of justice, power to direct the military and the capacity to ‘provide for the Necessities of the publick’.Footnote 127 Legislation that is properly in force, objective judges, and executive power must be in place to achieve the goal of ensuring the ‘Peace, Safety and publick good of the People’.Footnote 128
Therefore, governments must carry out their role with care.Footnote 129 The more primitive and golden time with almost no covetousness of the first governments was over. In its place, ‘Ambition and Luxury’ would lead to constant attempts to increase power without attending to the business for which the government was established.Footnote 130 A good government ought to meet the obligations placed upon it by the people ‘for their good, and the Preservation of their Property’.Footnote 131 Human beings had no arbitrary power over their life or liberty, as this power lay with God. Furthermore, they only had power over the life, liberty and property of others to the extent required to meet the obligation of self-preservation. Consequently, they could not confer greater jurisdiction on the government than they had. That was, in a sense, the responsibility of rational creatures. Locke wrote of legislators in the following terms:
Their Power in the utmost Bounds of it, is limited to the publick good of the Society. It is a Power, that hath no other end but preservation, and therefore can never have a right to destroy, enslave, or designedly to impoverish the Subjects.Footnote 132
Remarkably, legislative power is not only immediately concerned with preservation of the commonwealth, but beyond the domestic limits it is bound to comply with a universal obligation: ‘the fundamental law of nature’ being ‘the preservation of Mankind’.Footnote 133 Thinking with Hobbes that the whole community or commonwealth is, as a body, in the state of nature with respect to the other ‘States or persons’ outside the commonwealth, his conclusion is relatively un-Hobbesian.Footnote 134 The Executive Power and its prerogative (a ‘Power to do good’) acts together with the legislator. It intervenes in ‘All Accidents and Necessities that may concern the Publick’, sometimes acting in the absence of law, or even against the letter of the law, if it is ‘for the publick good’.Footnote 135 Property must be respected in the commonwealth, in the sense that it cannot be touched without the owner’s consent, which Locke justifies on two grounds. First, because individuals entered the political society to protect their property. Hence, they must have a right to their property in accordance with the laws of the community. Second, and more importantly, if supreme power lies with the legislator (in the form of either a lasting assembly or a monarch), situations may arise in which the individuals in the assembly or the monarch develop ‘a distinct interest from the rest of the community’ and seek to enrich themselves by taking from the people.Footnote 136 In fact this potential for abuse of power is the key reason why the people always remain the supreme power. Although he might have looked with personal disdain on the desire to accumulate riches, it does not seem that Locke was troubled by individuals’ ‘disproportionate and unequal possession’, to which the people at large have consented and even facilitated by means of money and other artificial means of representing value.Footnote 137 However, Locke’s conception of property cannot be merely fixed as ‘property of unlimited amount as a natural right of the individual’.Footnote 138 What made Locke’s case for the protection of property vital was that it offered the means to ensure people’s preservation. And for that reason, in his view, the people could get rid of any government, even of the legislative power – whose end is ‘the preservation of the Community’ – that is perceived by the people, consistently and unequivocally, to go against ‘this Fundamental, Sacred and unalterable Law of Self-Preservation’.Footnote 139 However, Locke asked, who can say whether the moment has arrived to overthrow a government that has abandoned the goals of safety and public good? Quis iudicabit? Since ‘God and Nature’ never allow the neglect of self-preservation, the response is that it is people who judge whether they must appeal to heaven in relation to their case.Footnote 140
The reasoning of Locke’s Two Treatises is that within government, the purpose of which is the preservation of all, the accumulation of property through labour and money will provide for the necessities of the nation, and even of all mankind