Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T21:33:26.024Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Random feedback shift registers and the limit distribution for largest cycle lengths

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 February 2023

Richard A. Arratia*
Affiliation:
University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA 90089, USA
E. Rodney Canfield
Affiliation:
University of Georgia, Athens, GA 30602, USA
Alfred W. Hales
Affiliation:
Center for Communications Research, La Jolla, San Diego, CA 92121, USA
*
*Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

For a random binary noncoalescing feedback shift register of width $n$ , with all $2^{2^{n-1}}$ possible feedback functions $f$ equally likely, the process of long cycle lengths, scaled by dividing by $N=2^n$ , converges in distribution to the same Poisson–Dirichlet limit as holds for random permutations in $\mathcal{S}_N$ , with all $N!$ possible permutations equally likely. Such behaviour was conjectured by Golomb, Welch and Goldstein in 1959.

Type
Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

We consider feedback shift registers, linear in the eldest bit (in $\mathbb{F}_2$ ), given as

(1) \begin{equation} x_{t+n} = x_t \oplus f(x_{t+1},x_{t+2},\ldots,x_{t+n-1}). \end{equation}

Here

(2) \begin{equation} f\;:\;\mathbb{F}_2^{n-1} \to \mathbb{F}_2, \end{equation}

is an arbitrary $n-1$ bit Boolean function (the ‘feedback’ or ‘logic’), and we will consider all $2^{2^{n-1}}$ possible $f$ to be equally likely. We write

\begin{equation*} N \;:\!=\; 2^n, \end{equation*}

and note that the map

(3) \begin{eqnarray} \pi _f\;:\;\mathbb{F}_2^n & \to &\mathbb{F}_2^n \nonumber \\[5pt] (x_0,x_1,\ldots,x_{n-1}) & \mapsto & (x_1,\ldots,x_{n-1},x_n) \\[5pt] & = & (x_1,\ldots,x_{n-1},x_0 \oplus f(x_1,\ldots,x_{n-1})). \nonumber \end{eqnarray}

is a permutation on $N$ objects.

In 1959 [Reference Golomb, Welch and Goldstein17], see also Chapter VII of [Reference Golomb16], Golomb, Welch and Goldstein suggest that the flat random permutation in ${\mathcal{S}}_N$ , with all $N!$ permutations $\pi$ equally likely, gives a good approximation to the cycle structure of $\pi _f$ , in the sense that the cycle structure of $\pi _f$ is close to the cycle structure of $\pi$ , in various aspects of distribution, such as the average length of the longest cycle. See [Reference Wolfram and Golomb21], especially the section ‘Cellular Automata and Nonlinear Shift Registers’, which includes an anecdote that Golomb used custom hardware modules in 1956 to experiment on this conjecture, and these ran about 3 million times faster than the general purpose computer on the same problem.

We prove that the longest cycle part of this conjecture is true, and more, namely that $\pi$ and $\pi _f$ have the same limit distributions in the infinite-dimensional simplex $\Delta$ , for the processesFootnote 1 of long cycle lengths, scaled by $N$ . This does not answer other aspects of Golomb’s conjecture, involving the distribution of the number of cycles, or behaviour of short cycles.

There are two natural ways to view the large cycles of the random permutation $\pi _f$ , which we now describe briefly. First, there is the process of largest cycle lengths: write $L_i$ for the length of the $i^{\mathrm{th}}$ longest cycle of $\pi _f$ , with $L_i \;:\!=\; 0$ if the permutation has fewer than $i$ cycles, so that always $L_1+L_2+\cdots = N$ , where $N=2^n$ . Write ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}}={\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}}(N)$ for the process of scaled cycle lengths, ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}}=(L_1/N,L_2/N,\ldots\!)$ . Second, there is the process of cycle lengths taken in age order: pick a random $n$ -tuple, take $A_1$ to be the length of the cycle of $\pi _f$ containing that first $n$ -tuple, then pick a random $n$ -tuple from among those not on the first cycle, take $A_2$ to be the length of the cycle of $\pi _f$ containing that second $n$ -tuple, and so on. Write ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}={\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}(N)=(A_1/N,A_2/N,\ldots\!)$ for the process of scaled cycle lengths in age order. For flat random permutations $\pi$ in place of $\pi _f$ , the limit of $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}$ is called the GEM process (after Griffiths [Reference Griffiths18], Engen [Reference Engen15] and McCloskey [Reference McCloskey20]); it is the distribution of $(1-U_1,U_1(1-U_2),U_1U_2(1-U_3),\ldots\!)$ , where $U,U_1,U_2,\ldots$ are independent and uniformly distributed in $(0,1)$ . The Poisson–Dirichlet process is $(X_1,X_2,\ldots\!)$ where $X_i$ is the $i^{{th}}$ largest of $1-U_1,U_1(1-U_2),U_1U_2(1-U_3),\ldots$ . This construction gives the simplest way to characterise the Poisson–Dirichlet process, PD. For flat random permutations, the limit of $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}$ is PD.Footnote 2 See Section 5.1 for a review of these concepts, including more discussion of age-order and the GEM limit as used in (5). See also [Reference Arratia, Barbour and Tavaré3]. Formally, our result is the following:

Theorem 1. Consider the random permutation $\pi _f$ given by (3), where all $2^{2^{n-1}}$ possible $f$ in (2) are equally likely. Then, as $n \to \infty$ , ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}}(N)$ converges in distribution to $(X_1,X_2,\ldots\!)$ with PD distribution.

Writing $\to ^d$ to denote convergence in distribution, we can succinctly summarise the conclusion of Theorem 1 by writing

(4) \begin{equation}{\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}}(N) \to ^d\textbf{X} \;:\!=\;(X_1,X_2,\ldots\!). \end{equation}

We note some easy consequences of Theorem 1. Theorem 1 is equivalent to

(5) \begin{equation}{\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}(N) \to ^d (1-U_1,U_1(1-U_2),U_1U_2(1-U_3),\ldots\!), \end{equation}

with GEM distribution, by a soft argument involving size-biased permutations, originally given by [Reference Donnelly and Joyce13]. By projecting onto the first coordinate,Footnote 3 we see

(6) \begin{equation} \frac{A_1}{N} \to ^d U. \end{equation}

By taking expectations, we see

(7) \begin{equation}{\mathbb{E}\,} \ \frac{A_1}{N} \to \frac{1}{2}. \end{equation}

Of course, the uniform distributional limit in (6) makes no local limit claim; it is plausible that $N \,{\mathbb{P}}(A_1 = i) \to 1$ holds uniformly in $n \lt i \lt N-n$ . For any fixed $i \gt 1$ , the statement $N \,{\mathbb{P}}(A_1 = i) \to 1$ is false. It is true that $N \,{\mathbb{P}}(A_1 = 1) = N \,{\mathbb{P}}(A_1 = N) =1$ . And for any fixed $j\gt 0$ the statement $N \,{\mathbb{P}}(A_1 = N-j) \to 1$ is false; see [Reference Coppersmith, Rhoades and VanderKam10].

We work with the de Bruijn graph $D_{n-1}$ , with edge set $\mathbb{F}_2^n$ and vertex set $\mathbb{F}_2^{n-1}$ ; edge $e = (y_0,y_1,\ldots,y_{n-1})$ goes from vertex $v= (y_0,y_1,\ldots,y_{n-2})$ to vertex $v'= (y_1,\ldots,y_{n-1})$ . The graph $D_{n-1}$ is 2-in, 2-out regular, and a random feedback logic $f$ corresponds to a random resolution of all vertices; the resolution at a vertex $v$ pairs the incoming edges, $0v$ and $1v$ , with the outgoing edges $v0$ and $v1$ . The cycles of a random permutation $\pi _f$ correspond exactly to the edge-disjoint cycles in a random circuit decomposition of the Eulerian graph $D_{n-1}$ .

2. A survey of the Proof of Theorem 1

In this section we survey the proof of Theorem 1 while omitting many necessary technicalities. It is hoped the reader will thus have a better notion of what is happening, and why, as s/he reads the later sections. We begin with the notion of relativisation. Suppose, as for example in the hypotheses of Theorem 1, that one has for each $n=1,2,\dots$ a probability $P_n$ on the permutations of a set ${\mathcal{E}}_n$ . Let $\pi \in{\mathcal{S}}({\mathcal{E}}_n)$ be one such permutation, and let $\boldsymbol{{e}}=(e_1,\dots,e_k)$ be a $k$ -tuple of, for now, distinct elements from the domain ${\mathcal{E}}_n$ . Picturing the permutation $\pi$ as a collection of disjoint cycles, one sees that by ignoring all elements of ${\mathcal{E}}_n$ except for the $e_i$ , these latter are permuted among themselves. That is, starting with $e_i$ , traverse the cycle of $\pi$ containing this element: –

\begin{equation*} e_i,\pi (e_i),\pi ^2(e_i),\dots \end{equation*}

until after one or more steps an element $e_j$ is encountered. (It is possible for the first element so encountered to be $e_i$ , which happens when the traversed cycle contains only a single member of the $k$ -tuple $\boldsymbol{{e}}$ .) Since the $e_i$ are given in a definite order, the induced permutation among these elements is readily identified with an element of ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ , the permutations of the set $\{1,2,\dots,k\}$ . Altogether, we have a function

\begin{equation*} {\textit {rel}}_{n,k} \;:\;{\mathcal {S}}({\mathcal{E}}_n) \times ({\mathcal{E}}_n)_k \rightarrow {\mathcal {S}}_k, \end{equation*}

which we call relativisation. Here, $({\mathcal{E}}_n)_k$ denotes the ordered $k$ -tuples drawn from ${\mathcal{E}}_n$ without replacement. We shall prove: Suppose that for every fixed $k\ge 1$ the sequence of distributions induced on ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ by the functions ${\textit{rel}}_{n,k}$ and the probability distributions $P_n$ tends to the uniform distribution. (For brevity, we say ‘ $P_n$ has the uniform relativisation property’.) Then the large cycle process associated with $P_n$ tends to Poisson–Dirichlet. The proof that the uniform relativisation property implies the Poisson–Dirichlet property appears in Section 5.3, as Lemma 10.

Henceforth we specialise to the particular sequence $P_n$ of interest: the sets ${\mathcal{E}}_n$ are the binary $n$ -tuples ${\mathbb{F}_2}^n$ , and $P_n$ assigns equal weight to each of the $2^{N/2}$ shift register permutations $\pi _f$ (and no weight to other permutations), where $N=2^n$ . Let $S_{n,k}$ denote the Cartesian product

\begin{equation*} \{ f\;:\;{\mathbb {F}_2}^{n-1}\rightarrow {\mathbb {F}_2}\} \times ({\mathbb {F}_2}^n)^k \,. \end{equation*}

For technical reasons we define the relativisation function ${\textit{rel}}_{n,k}$ on the set $S_{n,k}$ , see Definition (8) in Section 4.10. Nevertheless, pairs $(f,{\mathbb{E}\,})$ in which $\boldsymbol{{e}}$ contains a repeated element may be safely ignored by the reader for now, and only the primary objective be kept in mind: to show that as $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ varies over $S_{n,k}$ the coverage of ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ under the relativisation function ${\textit{rel}}_{n,k}$ is approximately uniform.

Roughly speaking, this objective is accomplished by partitioning the set $S_{n,k}$ into blocks such that the restriction of ${\textit{rel}}_{n,k}$ to each block of the partition yields an almost uniform coverage of ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ . The description of these blocks involves the notion of toggle. Let $v\in{\mathbb{F}_2}^{n-1}$ and $f$ be a feedback function; then the toggle of the function $f$ at the point $v$ is the function $f_v$ which disagrees with $f$ only at the argument $v$ :

\begin{equation*} f_v(w) = \begin {cases} f(w) & w\neq v \\[5pt] 1\oplus f(w) & w=v \, . \end {cases} \end{equation*}

That is, we have toggled a single bit in the truth table of $f$ . Toggling a feedback function has a predictable effect on ${\textit{rel}}_{n,k}(\pi _f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ . In particular, for $x\in{\mathbb{F}_2}, v\in{\mathbb{F}_2}^{n-1}$ , if $xv=\pi _f^i(e_a)$ and

\begin{equation*} \{\pi _f(e_a),\pi _f^2(e_a),\dots,\pi _f^i(e_a)\} \cap \{e_1,\dots,e_k\} = \emptyset, \end{equation*}

and, (with $a\lt b$ ), $\bar{x}v=\pi _f^j(e_b)$ , and

\begin{equation*} \{\pi _f(e_b),\pi _f^2(e_b),\dots,\pi _f^j(e_b)\} \cap \{e_1,\dots,e_k\} = \emptyset, \end{equation*}

then (let the reader check by drawing a picture)

\begin{equation*} {\textit {rel}}_{n,k}(\pi _{f_v},\boldsymbol{{e}}) = {\textit {rel}}_{n,k}(\pi _{f},\boldsymbol{{e}})\circ (a,b), \end{equation*}

where $(a,b)$ denotes a transposition in ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ . The blocks in our partition of $S_{n,k}$ arise as follows: given $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})\in{S_{n,k}}$ , we determine, in a way explained below, a subset of size $m$ ,

\begin{equation*} V=\{v_1^{\#},\dots,v_m^{\#}\}\subseteq {\mathbb {F}_2}^{n-1} \,, \end{equation*}

and define the block containing $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ to be the $2^m$ different toggles $(f_U,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ , $U$ ranging over subsets of $V$ . Here, $f_U$ denotes function $f$ toggled at all $v\in U$ . For the block to be well defined, it must be the case that the choice of $V$ will be the same for all $f_U$ as for $f$ . This necessitates the introduction of a subset $H\subseteq{S_{n,k}}$ , the ‘happy event’, see equation (42) in Section 4.8. It turns out that the happy event is almost all of $S_{n,k}$ , $|H|/|{S_{n,k}}|\to 1$ , and for $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})\in H$ the blocks are well defined. Moreover for each such block we have an ordered sequence of transpositions $(a_i, b_i)\in{\mathcal{S}}_k$ ( $1\le i\le m)$ with

\begin{equation*} {\textit {rel}}_{n,k}(\pi _{f_U},\boldsymbol{{e}}) = {\textit {rel}}_{n,k}(f,\boldsymbol{{e}}) \circ (a_{i_1},b_{i_1})\circ \cdots \circ (a_{i_{\ell }},b_{i_{\ell }}), \end{equation*}

where $U=\{i_1,\dots,i_{\ell }\}$ . For $m$ sufficiently large, almost all such sequences of transpositions yield $2^m$ compositions which cover ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ almost uniformly. (Lemma 7 in Section 4.9 proves that for all $k,\epsilon$ there is an $m$ such that the distribution induced on ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ is within $\epsilon$ of uniform in total variation for all but an $\epsilon$ fraction of possible sequences.)

Let us say something about how, given $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})\in{S_{n,k}}$ , the $m$ -subset $V$ of ${\mathbb{F}_2}^{n-1}$ is chosen. The pair $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ determines $k$ segments

(8) \begin{equation} e_a, \pi _f(e_a), \dots, \pi _f^t(e_a) (1\le a\le k), \end{equation}

in which the length $t$ is taken to be approximately $N^{3/5}$ . For this length it is almost certain that not only are the initial edges $e_a$ distinct, but in fact all $k\times (t+1)$ of the edges $\pi _f^i(e_a)$ are distinct. This feature is included in the definition (42) of event $H$ . Given that $\pi _f$ acts by shifting left and bringing in one new bit on the right, each sequence (8) is equivalent to a binary sequence

\begin{equation*} e_{a,0} e_{a,1} \cdots e_{a,n-1} \cdots e_{a,n+t-1}, \end{equation*}

of length $n+t$ . To be considered for membership in $V$ , an $(n-1)$ -tuple $v^{\#}$ must appear in two of these binary sequences; that is, for some $a\lt b$ and some bit $x\in \{0,1\}$

\begin{equation*} xv^{\#} = e_{a,i}\cdots e_{a,i+n-1}\; \textit {and}\; \bar {x}v^{\#} = e_{b,j}\cdots e_{b,j+n-1}. \end{equation*}

One may ask as $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ varies uniformly over $S_{n,k}$ what is the probability of finding such leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeats $(i,j)$ in various regions of the plane? Remarkably, such points when rescaled as $(i/N^{1/2},j/N^{1/2})$ constitute, in the limit with respect to total variation distance, a familiar Poisson process. Thanks to this limiting behaviour we can estimate not only the probability of finding $v^{\#}$ ’s which satisfy the above minimal constraint for $V$ -membership, but also the probability of finding $m$ $v^{\#}$ ’s lying in a much more stringently constrained geometry, which geometry implies $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})\in H$ . Section 4 is devoted to proving these properties of $H$ and $V$ under the assumption that the probabilities in question can be approximated by a Poisson process.

We conclude our survey by saying how this last assumption is justified. We present in Section 3 an algorithm called sequential editing which begins with $k$ random binary sequences (referred to as coin toss sequences) and edits them in such a way that the result of the editing is a set of $k$ sequences which could have been produced by choosing $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})\in{S_{n,k}}$ and forming the $k$ segments (8). Even more, the probability of obtaining a particular set of sequences is exactly the same, whether we choose $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ and form (8), or flip $k(n+t)$ coins and perform sequential editing. (This is proven in Theorem 5 of Section 3.6).

Moreover, there is a ‘good event’ $G$ , $G\subseteq{\mathbb{F}_2}^{(n+t)k}$ , such that when the initial coin toss sequence $C$ belongs to $G$ the leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeats in the edited sequence appear in exactly the same locations $(i,j)$ as they do in $C$ . Since $G$ is almost all of ${\mathbb{F}_2}^{(n+t)k}$ (Theorem 4 in Section 3), the study of the $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ -induced pairs is reduced to the study of leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeats in $k$ random sequences. This new process is by no means easily evaluated, but fortunately it is in the realm of the Chen–Stein method as presented and extended in [Reference Arratia, Goldstein and Gordon6]. In such a manner the above described approximation is justified.

Looking back at this survey, it appears that the components in the proof of Theorem 1 have been described almost in the reverse order that they appear in the sequel. May we wish that in the end the determined reader will understand the proof forwards and backwards.

3. Comparisons with coin tossing sequences

Throughout this section these conventions will be observed: $a_i,b_i,C_i$ denote bits; $v_i$ denotes an $(n-1)$ -long sequence of bits; and $e_i$ denotes an $n$ -long sequence of bits. A tool used in the proof of Theorem 1 is to compare the bit sequence $b_0,b_1,\dots b_{n+t}$ generated by a randomly chosen feedback logic $f$ with a coin toss sequence, denoted in this section $C_0,C_1,\dots, C_{n+t}$ . A bit sequence $b_i$ generated by a feedback logic has what we refer to as the de Bruijn property: it satisfies a recursion of the form $b_{t+n} = b_t + f(b_{t+1},\dots,b_{t+n-1})$ . In a sequence with the de Bruijn property the $n$ -long words $0v$ and $1v$ must be followed by different bits. Of course, not every coin toss sequence has the de Bruijn property. The sequential edit, defined below, of a coin toss sequence $C_i$ is obtained in a left-to-right bit-by-bit manner and adheres as closely as possible to $C_i$ , changes being made only when forced by the desire to respect the de Bruijn property. On the other hand, the shotgun edit, also defined below, of a sequence $C_i$ is a naive imitation of a sequential edit. In a sense and circumstances to be made precise, by the combination of Theorems 2 and 4, with high probability, these two produce the same output.

3.1. Sequential editing

We begin with an $n+t$ long bit sequence

\begin{equation*} C_{0}, C_1, \dots, C_{t+n-1}. \end{equation*}

The new bit sequence of the same length,

\begin{equation*} b_{0}, b_1, \dots, b_{t+n-1}, \end{equation*}

is produced by following two rules:

  1. Rule 1:

    \begin{equation*} b_i = C_i, 0 \le i \le n-1; \end{equation*}
  2. Rule 2: For $i\ge 0$ determine bit $b_{i+n}$ by first asking if the feedback logic bit $f(b_{i+1},\dots,b_{i+n-1})$ has been previously defined; if so, set $b_{i+n}$ accordingly:

    \begin{equation*} b_{i+n} = b_{i} \oplus f(b_{i+1},\dots,b_{i+n-1}); \end{equation*}
    otherwise, define (and remember) the feedback logic bit in such a way that $b_{i+n}$ and $C_{i+n}$ agree.

Here, we give some terminology and indexing practice. We say that the sequence $b$ is obtained from the coin toss sequence $C$ by sequential editing. Each time a $b_{i+n}$ has freedom – because the necessary feedback bit has not yet been set – we set the feedback bit so that $b_{i+n}=C_{i+n}$ ; but at any time the bit $b_{i+n}$ ‘has no choice’, we assign it the forced value. Such a time $i$ is a time of a potential edit; if it turns out (by chance) that $b_{i+n}$ and $C_{i+n}$ agree, then no actual edit has taken place; if it is forced to take $b_{i+n}$ equal to $\overline{C_{i+n}}$ then an actual edit has taken place, and we label the time of this actual edit as $i$ rather than $i+n$ . The sequence $b$ obtained by this process always has the de Bruijn property. In terms of the de Bruijn graph with all vertices resolved, a potential edit occurs at time $i$ when $e_{i}$ , the edge from $v_{i}$ to $v_{i+1}$ , is going in to a vertex $v=v_{i+1}$ where $f(v)$ , the resolution of that vertex, is already known, so that the successor edge, $e_{i+1}=\pi _f(e_i)$ is determined — this is equivalent to determining $b_{i+n}$ , the rightmost bit of $e_{i+1}$ .

3.2. Shotgun editing

Now we define a second, generally different, way to edit the coin toss sequence $C_i$ to produce a sequence $a_i$ . We call this the shotgun edit. Unlike $b_i$ obtained by sequential editing, the sequence $a_i$ obtained by shotgun editing may not have the de Bruijn property.

The symbols $I$ , $J$ , $I_k$ , $J_k$ denote intervals of integers contained in the $(n+t)$ -long interval $[0,1,2,\dots,t+n-1]$ . We use $\ell (I)$ and $r(I)$ to denote the left- and right- endpoints of the interval $I$ . A binary sequence

(9) \begin{equation} C_{0},C_1, \dots, C_{t+n-1}, \end{equation}

has an $m$ -long repeat at $(I,J)$ if $\ell (I)\lt \ell (J)$ , $|I|=m=|J|$ and the two ordered $m$ -tuples $(C_i\;:\;i\in I)$ and $(C_j\;:\;j\in J)$ are equal. We say that (9) has a leftmost Footnote 4 $m$ -long repeat at $(I,J)$ if, in addition, either $\ell (I)=0$ or

\begin{equation*} C_{\ell (I)-1} \neq C_{\ell (J)-1}. \end{equation*}

This given, the shotgun edit of coin toss (9) is readily defined: make a list $(I_1,J_1),(I_2,J_2),\dots$ of all the leftmost $n$ -long repeats found in (9). Let

\begin{equation*} a_i = \begin {cases} \overline {C_i} & \textit {if} i=r(J_k) \textit {some} k\\[5pt] C_i & \textit {otherwise.} \end {cases} \end{equation*}

3.3. Zero and first generation words

Let

\begin{equation*} C_{0},C_1, \dots, C_{t+n-1}, \end{equation*}

be a coin toss sequence whose leftmost $n$ -tuple repeats occur at $(I_1,J_1),(I_2,J_2),\dots$ . The zero-generation words of length $h$ are simply words of the form:

\begin{equation*} (C_i,C_{i+1},\dots,C_{i+h-1}). \end{equation*}

A first-generation word is a zero-generation word with exactly one bit complemented, with the index of the complemented bit required to be $r(J_k)$ for some $k$ :

\begin{equation*} (C_i,C_{i+1},\dots,\overline {C_{i+j}}, \dots, C_{i+h-1}), i+j = r(J_k). \end{equation*}

3.4. The good event $G_{(t)}$

We always consider $n$ to be understood, but sometimes we will not want to emphasise the role of $t$ , hence writing $G \equiv{G_{(t)}}$ . Henceforth we shall always assume that $t$ is at most $N=2^n$ , since we are interested in cycle lengths for permutations on a set of size $N$ . Let

\begin{equation*} C_{0},C_1, \dots, C_{t+n-1}, \end{equation*}

be a length $n+t$ coin toss sequence whose leftmost $n$ -repeats occur at $(I_1,J_1),(I_2,J_2),\dots$ . Then the good event $G_{(t)}$ is defined to be the conjunction of these six conditions:

  1. (a) neither the initial $n$ -long word of the coin toss sequence, nor any of its $1$ -offsFootnote 5 is repeated (probability of failure $O(tn/N)$ );

  2. (b) all intersections of the form $I_k\cap J_{k^{\prime }}$ are empty (probability of failure $O(t^3n/N^2+tn^3/N)$ );

  3. (c) the sets $I_1,I_2,\dots$ are pairwise disjoint; likewise $J_1,J_2,\dots$ (probability of failure $O(t^2n^2/N^2+t^3n/N^2+tn^3/N)$ );

  4. (d) no first-generation word of length $n-1$ equals a zero-generation word of length $n-1$ , or another first-generation word of length $n-1$ (probability of failure $O(t^4n^2/N^3+t^3n^3/N^2+tn^3/N)$ );

  5. (e) for every leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeat $(I,J)$ we have

    \begin{equation*} r(J_k)\notin I \cup J \cup \{\ell (I)-1,\ell (J)-1\}, \end{equation*}
    for all $k$ (probability of failure $O(t^3n/N^2+t^2n^2/N^2+tn^3/N)$ );
  6. (f) there is no $(2n-1)$ -repeat (probability of failure $O(t^2/N^2)$ ).

The indicated probabilities of failure will be proven below in Theorem 4. First, though, we will prove a theorem that explains why $G$ is called the ‘good event’.

Theorem 2. If the coin toss sequence

\begin{equation*} C_{0},C_1, \dots, C_{t+n-1}, \end{equation*}

belongs to the good event $G$ , then

Conclusion 1. The sequentially edited sequence $b_i$ and the shotgun edited sequence $a_i$ agree; and

Conclusion 2. The sequentially edited sequence $b_i$ and the coin toss sequence have their leftmost $(n-1)$ repeats at exactly the same positions.

These conclusions, along with Theorem 4 in the next subsection, will provide substantial control of the prevalence of $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats

Proof of Conclusion 1. Assume, to the contrary, that the $a$ and $b$ sequences differ; let $i$ be the first position of disagreement:

\begin{equation*} a_j = b_j, j\lt i;\; a_i\ne b_i. \end{equation*}

There are two possibilities: (1) $a_i\neq b_i$ and $b_i=C_i$ ; or (2) $a_i\neq b_i$ and $a_i=C_i$ .

Case (1). Since $a_i\neq C_i$ we have $i=r(J_k)$ for some $k$ , and there is a leftmost $n$ -repeat in the $C$ sequence at $(I_k,J_k)$ . But $a_j=C_j$ for $j\in I_k$ (condition(b)); and $a_j=C_j$ for $j\in J_k\setminus \{i\}$ (condition (c)). Hence $b_j=a_j=C_j$ for $j \in I_k\cup J_k\setminus \{i\}$ . But $b_i\neq a_i \neq C_i$ , so in fact the $b$ -sequence itself has an $n$ -repeat at $(I_k,J_k)$ . But the $b$ -sequence has the de Bruijn property, and so the $(I_k,J_k)$ repeat can be backed up $d=\ell (I_k)\gt 0$ steps to reveal

\begin{equation*} (b_0,\dots,b_{n-1}) = (b_{i-d-n+1},\dots,b_{i-d}). (d=\ell (I_k)\gt 0). \end{equation*}

Since $i-d\lt i$ ,

\begin{equation*} (a_0,\dots,a_{n-1}) = (a_{i-d-n+1},\dots,a_{i-d}), \end{equation*}

so in fact

(10) \begin{equation} (C_0,\dots,C_{n-1}) = (a_{i-d-n+1},\dots,a_{i-d}). \end{equation}

The word on the right side of the last equality is either a zero-generation or a first-generation word; either case contradicts condition (a).

Case (2). Because $i$ is a sequential edit point, ( $b_i\neq C_i$ ), it must be that the $(n-1)$ -long word $(b_{i-n+1},\dots, b_{i-1})$ is appearing for a second or later time, say

\begin{equation*} (b_{\ell -n+1},\dots, b_{\ell -1}) = (b_{i-n+1},\dots, b_{i-1}), \ell \lt i. \end{equation*}

We must have $b_{\ell }=C_{\ell }$ , since no sequential editing took place at time $\ell$ . (The relevant bit of the feedback logic had not yet been determined.) We know that $b_i\neq b_{\ell }$ , else the $b$ -sequence contains an $n$ -repeat which, as was explained in Case (1), backs up to yield the contradictory (10). So, $C_i\neq b_i \neq b_{\ell } = C_{\ell }$ ; that is, $C_i=C_{\ell }$ and

\begin{equation*} (b_{\ell -n+1},\dots, b_{\ell -1}, C_{\ell }) = (b_{i-n+1},\dots, b_{i-1}, C_i), \ell \lt i. \end{equation*}

Because $i$ is the first point at which the $b$ and $a$ sequences disagree,

(11) \begin{equation} (a_{\ell -n+1},\dots, a_{\ell -1}, C_{\ell }) = (a_{i-n+1},\dots, a_{i-1}, C_i), \ell \lt i. \end{equation}

Suppose (for the sake of a contradiction) that none of the $a$ bits appearing on either side of this last Equation (11) was edited by the shotgun process. Then we have

(12) \begin{equation} (C_{\ell -n+1},\dots, C_{\ell -1}, C_{\ell }) = (C_{i-n+1},\dots, C_{i-1}, C_i), \ell \lt i. \end{equation}

We have thus discovered an $n$ -long repeat in the coin toss sequence, but it might not be a leftmost $n$ -long repeat. So, we look left to determine the least $m\ge 1$ such that either $\ell -n+1-m\lt 0$ (i.e., you’ve gone ‘off the board’) or the run of equalities is broken:

\begin{equation*} C_{\ell -n+1-m} \neq C_{i-n+1-m}. \end{equation*}

One of these two will happen for $m\lt n$ or else the $C$ -sequence is found to contain a $2n$ -repeat, contradicting assumption (f). But then we have found a leftmost $n$ -repeat in the $C$ -sequence beginning at $\ell -n+1-m+1$ and $i-n+1-m+1$ ; shotgun editing would consequently modify the $C$ -bit at position $i-n+1-m+1+n-1=i-m+1$ . Since

\begin{equation*} i-n+1 \lt i-m+1 \le i, \end{equation*}

we have found that one of the $C$ -bits on the right side of equation (12), namely the one whose index is $i-m+1$ , is changed by shotgun editing, contrary to our earlier supposition that none of the $a$ bits appearing on either side of the equality (11) was edited by the shotgun process.

By condition (c), every $n$ -long word in the $a$ sequence either is a zero-generation word (matches exactly the corresponding $C$ -bits) or is a first-generation word (matches the corresponding $C$ -bits with exactly one change). Thus, at least one of the $n$ -long words appearing in (11) is a first-generation word, and this contradicts condition (d).

Proof of Conclusion 2. We will make use of the $a$ and $b$ sequences being equal. Suppose we have a leftmost $(n-1)$ repeat in the coin toss sequence,

(13) \begin{equation} C_{i+j} = C_{\ell +j}, 0\le j\lt (n-1);\; \textit{and}\; i=0 \;\textit{or } C_{i-1} \neq C_{\ell -1}. \end{equation}

By condition (e), none of these $2n$ bits (or $2n-2$ in case $i=0$ ) can be edited by the shotgun edit. Hence, we have a leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeat at the same place in the $a$ sequence, whence also the $b$ sequence.

On the other hand, suppose we have a leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeat in the $a$ sequence,

(14) \begin{equation} (a_i, a_{i+1}, \dots, a_{i+n-2}) = (a_\ell, a_{\ell +1}, \dots, a_{\ell +n-2}), \end{equation}

and

\begin{equation*} i=0, \quad \textit{or}\quad a_{i-1} \neq a_{\ell -1}. \end{equation*}

If

\begin{equation*} (a_{i},\dots,a_{i+n-2}) \neq (C_{i},\dots,C_{i+n-2}). \end{equation*}

then $(a_{i},\dots,a_{i+n-2})$ is a first-generation word of length $n-1$ which equals the first- or zero-generation word $(a_{\ell },\dots,a_{\ell +n-2})$ , which is forbidden by condition (d). So,

(15) \begin{equation} (a_{i},\dots,a_{i+n-2}) = (C_{i},\dots,C_{i+n-2}). \end{equation}

Similarly,

(16) \begin{equation} (a_{\ell },\dots,a_{\ell +n-2}) = (C_{\ell },\dots,C_{\ell +n-2}). \end{equation}

Altogether by (14),(15),(16) we have

(17) \begin{equation} (C_{i},\dots,C_{i+n-2}) = (C_{\ell },\dots,C_{\ell +n-2}). \end{equation}

If $i=0$ , then the last is a leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeat in the $C$ sequence, as asserted. So, to conclude, suppose for the sake of a contradiction that $i\gt 0$ and that $C_{i-1}= C_{\ell -1}$ . Then, we have an $n$ -long repeat

\begin{equation*} (C_{i-1},\dots,C_{i+n-2}) = (C_{\ell -1},\dots,C_{\ell +n-2}). \end{equation*}

Sliding left for $m$ steps, we will encounter a leftmost $n$ -repeat in the coin toss sequence

\begin{equation*} (C_{i-1-m},\dots,C_{i+n-2-m}) = (C_{\ell -1-m},\dots,C_{\ell +n-2-m}), \end{equation*}

with $0\le m\lt n-1$ by condition (f). But in such a case $a_{\ell +n-2-m} \neq C_{\ell +n-2-m}$ by the definition of shotgun editing. However, for $0\le m\lt n-1$

\begin{equation*} \ell \le \ell +n-2-m \le \ell +n-2, \end{equation*}

and by (16) $a_{\ell +n-2-m} = C_{\ell +n-2-m}$ The supposition that $i\gt 0$ and that $C_{i-1}= C_{\ell -1}$ has been contradicted, and so (17) is, indeed, a leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeat as needed.

3.5. Probability

In this section we bound the probability of failure of any one of the conditions (a)–(f) appearing in Theorem 2. Let $S$ be a set of relations, each of the form $C_i=C_j$ or $C_i \neq C_j$ with $i\lt j$ . We assume always that $S$ has at most one relation for a given $(i,j)$ ; that is, we don’t allow both $C_i=C_j$ and $C_i \neq C_j$ . What is the probability that a coin toss sequence $C$ will satisfy such a set of relations? The desired probability is $2^{-|S|}$ provided the graph associated with $S$ is cycle free. The graph we have in mind here is $(V,E)$ where $V$ is the set $0,1,2,\dots$ and $E$ is the set of pairs $\{i,j\}$ such that at least one (and by convention exactly one) of the relations $C_i=C_j$ or $C_i \neq C_j$ belongs to $S$ .

In particular, if the graph of $S$ consists of the $n$ pairs $(i,j),(i+1,j+1),\dots,(i+n-1,\, j+n-1)$ the probability is $2^{-n}=1/N$ . This is quite clear if $I=\{i,\dots,i+n-1\}$ and $J=\{j,\dots,j+n-1\}$ are disjoint, since then the underlying graph has no vertex of degree 2. It is also true if $I$ and $J$ overlap, (of course $I\neq J$ ): every vertex of degree $2$ in the graph (i.e., every element of $I\cap J$ ) has one larger neighbour and one smaller neighbour. But a cycle would require at least one vertex with two smaller neighbours.

We will have frequent occasion below, in the proof of Theorem 4, to consider sets $S$ whose graphs are the union of two such $n$ -sets of pairs $(i_1,j_1)$ , $(i_1+1,j_1+1), \dots, (i_1+n-1,j_1+n-1)$ and $(i_2,j_2)$ , $(i_2+1,j_2+1), \dots$ $(i_2+n-1,j_2+n-1)$ . We begin with a lemma which shows that in many situations which arise in these proofs the probability in question is $1/N^2$ .

Lemma 3. Let $\mathcal{G}$ be the graph whose edges consist of two sets of pairs

\begin{equation*}(i_1,j_1),(i_1+1,j_1+1),\dots,(i_1+m_1-1,j_1+m_1-1).\end{equation*}

and

\begin{equation*}(i_2,j_2), (i_2+1,j_2+1),\dots,(i_2+m_2-1,j_2+m_2-1).\end{equation*}

Then $\mathcal{G}$ is cycle free if any one of the following three conditions holds, where we assume $i_1\lt j_1$ and $i_2\lt j_2$ :

  1. (i) $I_1\cap I_2 =\emptyset$

  2. (ii) $J_1\cap J_2 =\emptyset$

  3. (iii) $(I_1\cup I_2) \cap (J_1\cup J_2) = \emptyset$ and $j_2-i_2 \neq j_1-i_1$ .

Proof. If $I_1\cap I_2=\emptyset$ then no vertex has two neighbours larger than it. If $J_1\cap J_2=\emptyset$ then no vertex has two neighbours smaller than it. In case (iii), all edges out of $I_1\cup I_2$ go to $J_1\cup J_2$ , and vice versa. A cycle, if there is one, lies within the bipartite graph whose parts are $I_1\cup I_2$ and $J_1\cup J_2$ , and clearly the cycle must alternate edges between $(I_1,J_1)$ and $(I_2,J_2)$ types. If the cycle (of necessity even in length) uses $\ell$ edges of the first sort and $\ell$ of the second, then it has travelled $\ell \times (j_1-i_1)$ in one direction and $\ell \times (j_2-i_2)$ in the other. The last part of condition (iii) makes it impossible for the cycle to have returned to its starting point.

Theorem 4. Let $G$ be the good event. Then,

\begin{equation*} \mathbb {P}(G) \ge 1 - O\left (t^4n^2/N^3+t^3n^3/N^2+tn^3/N\right ). \end{equation*}

Proof. We shall show that the probability that a random coin toss sequence of length $t+n$ fails any one of the conditions (a) through (f) in the definition of $G$ is $O(t^4n^2/N^3+t^3n^3/N^2+tn^3/N)$ . (More explicitly, each will be shown to fail with the probability indicated in the definition of $G$ .) We invoke the above Lemma during the proof by citing Lemma (i), Lemma (ii) and Lemma (iii).

Condition (a): [neither the initial $n$ -long word of the coin toss sequence, nor any of its $1$ -offs, is repeated.] Consider first an exact repetition. There are $t-1$ places where the repeated sequence can start, and by earlier remarks the probability that the second sequence repeats the first is $1/N$ . The same argument applies to the $1$ -offs of the initial pattern, and we conclude that the probability for condition (a) to fail is less than $t(n+1)/N$ .

Condition (b): [all intersections $I_k\cap J_{k^{\prime }}$ are empty.] For $k=k^{\prime }$ we bound the probability of failure by $tn/N$ using the same technique as in case (a). Suppose that $I_1\cap J_2 \neq \emptyset$ . By the $k=k^{\prime }$ case of the proof we may assume $J_1$ disjoint from $I_1$ and to its right; and $I_2$ disjoint from $J_2$ and to its left. If $I_1\cap I_2=\emptyset$ then Lemma (i) yields the upper bound $O(t^3n/N^2)$ . If $J_1\cap J_2=\emptyset$ then Lemma (ii) yields $O(t^3n/N^2)$ . In the remaining case $I_1$ meets $I_2$ , $J_1$ meets $J_2$ , and $I_1$ meets $J_2$ . Thus the union $I_1\cup I_2\cup J_1\cup J_2$ is an interval, and a bound of $O(tn^3/N)$ results.

Condition (c): [the sets $I_1,I_2,\dots$ are pairwise disjoint; likewise $J_1,J_2,\dots$ .] We will prove the assertion regarding $I_1,I_2,\dots$ ; the other assertion is proven in an entirely similar manner. Suppose $I_1\cap I_2\neq \emptyset$ . We may assume $J_1\cap J_2\neq \emptyset$ ; otherwise Lemma (ii) implies an upper bound of $O(t^3n/N^2)$ . So now, both intersections $I_1\cap I_2$ and $J_1\cap J_2$ are nonempty. If any one of the four intersections $I_a\cap J_b$ is nonempty, then again the union $I_1\cup I_2\cup J_1 \cup J_2$ is an interval, and we have the upper bound $O(tn^3/N)$ . So assume $(I_1\cup I_2) \cap (J_1 \cup J_2) = \emptyset$ . Assume, for the sake of a contradiction, that $r(J_2)-r(I_2)=d=r(J_1)-r(I_1)$ . Then we have $I_1\neq I_2$ and $J_1\neq J_2$ . Without loss, let us say $I_1$ is left of $I_2$ and $J_1$ is left of $J_2$ . We have $C_{\ell (I_2)-1} \neq C_{\ell (J_2)-1}$ because $(I_2,J_2)$ is assumed to be a leftmost $n$ -repeat. Since $I_1$ is left of $I_2$ , $\ell (I_2)-1\in I_1$ ; but then $C_{\ell (I_2)-1} = C_{\ell (J_2)-1}$ , the contradiction. So, $r(J_2)-r(I_2)=d=r(J_1)-r(I_1)$ is untenable and now Lemma (iii) implies an upper bound of $O(t^2n^2/N^2)$ .

Condition (d): [no First-generation word of length $n-1$ equals a Zero-generation word of length $n-1$ , or another First-generation word of length $n-1$ ]. Suppose the first assertion is violated. Then we have, for some $i$ , some $d\gt 0$ and some $j\in \{i,i+1,\dots,i+n-2\}$ ,

(18) \begin{equation} C_{\ell }=C_{\ell +d}\; \textit{for}\; \ell \in \{i,i+1,\dots,i+n-2\}\setminus \{j\}, \textit{and}\; C_{j}\neq C_{j+d}, \end{equation}

with $r(J_k) \in \{j,j+d\}$ and with $(I_k,J_k)$ a leftmost $n$ -repeat. Let $I = \{i,i+1,\ldots,i+n-2\}$ and let $J = \{i+d,i+d+1,\ldots,i+d+n-2\}$ . If $I$ and $I_k$ are disjoint then using Lemma (i) the probability is bounded by $O(t^3 \, n/N^2)$ . So assume they intersect, so their union is an interval. Similarly we can assume, using Lemma (ii), that $J$ and $J_k$ also intersect so their union is another interval. If these two intervals intersect, forming another interval, we have a probability bound of $O(t \, n^3/N)$ . Otherwise $( I \cup I_k) \cap (J \cup J_k)$ is empty. If $r(J_k) - r(I_k) = d$ then $C_j = C_{j+d}$ , contradicting (18). So Lemma (iii) implies $O(t^2 \, n^2/N^2)$ for the probability. This gives an overall bound of $O(t \, n^3/N +t^2 \, n^2/N^2 +t^3 \,n/N^2)$ .

Next, suppose the second assertion of (d) is violated. Then we have, for some $i$ , some $d\gt 0$ and some $j_1,j_2\in \{i,i+1,\dots,i+n-2\}$ ,

(19) \begin{equation} (C_i, C_{i+1},\dots, \overline{C_{j_1}}, \dots, C_{i+n-2}) = (C_{i+d}, C_{i+d+1},\dots, \overline{C_{j_2+d}}, \dots, C_{i+d+n-2}), \end{equation}

with $j_1=r(J_1)$ , $j_2+d=r(J_2)$ and $(I_1,J_1), (I_2,J_2)$ leftmost $n$ -repeats. As reasoned before we have $I\cap J$ , $I_1\cap J_1$ and $I_2\cap J_2$ all empty with probability at least $1-O(tn^2/N)$ . It follows, from the sheer geometry of the situation, that $I\cap I_1=\emptyset$ . We may assume that $I_1\cap I_2=\emptyset$ , since (as proven in (c) above) the probability of failure is $O(t^3n/N^2+t^2n^2/N^2+tn^3/N)$ . We may assume that $I_1\cap I=\emptyset$ , for otherwise the union of $I_1$ and $I$ and $J_1$ is a connected interval, and then by reasoning as above a bound of $O( t^3n^3/N^2)$ results. We now have all three intersections $I\cap I_1$ , $I\cap I_2$ and $I_1\cap I_2$ being empty; and by an obvious embellishment of Lemma (i) the probability of the remaining case is $O( t^4n^2/N^3)$ .

Condition (e): [for every leftmost $(n-1)$ -repeat $(I,J)$ we have

\begin{equation*} r(J_k)\notin I \cup J \cup \{\ell (I)-1,\ell (J)-1\}, \end{equation*}

for all $k$ .] Say $I=\{i,i+1,\dots,i+n-2\}$ and $J=\{i+d,i+d+1,\dots,i+d+n-2\}$ . The probability that $I_k\cap J_k$ is not empty is $O(tn/N)$ , so assume $I_k\cap J_k=\emptyset$ . If $r(J_k) \in I\cup \{i-1\}$ , then, since $I_k$ lies entirely to the left of $J_k$ , $I_k\cap I=\emptyset$ . By Lemma (i) the probability of this is $O(t^3n/N^2)$ .

The probability that $I\cap J$ is not empty is $O(tn/N)$ , so assume both $I_k\cap J_k$ and $I\cap J$ are empty. The probability that $I_k\cap I$ is empty is, by Lemma (i), $O(t^3n/N^2)$ , so assume $I_k\cap I\neq \emptyset$ . If $I\cap J_k$ or $I_k\cap J$ is nonempty then $I_k\cup I \cup J_k \cup J$ is an interval, and the probability of this is $O(tn^3/N)$ . So, assume $(I\cup I_k) \cap (I_k\cup J) = \emptyset$ . If $r(J_k)-r(I_k)=r(J)-r(I)$ , then

\begin{align*} C_{\ell (I)-1} = C_{\ell (J)-1} & \quad \textit{by}\; \ell (I)-1 \in I_k \\[5pt] C_{\ell (I)-1} \neq C_{\ell (J)-1} & \quad \textit{by}\; (I,J)\; \textit{being a leftmost }\; (n-1)-\textit{repeat}, \end{align*}

an impossibility. So, $r(J_k)-r(I_k)\neq r(J)-r(I)$ and Lemma (iii) gives the bound $O(t^2n^2/N^2)$ for this final scenario.

Condition (f): [there is no $(2n-1)$ -repeat.] Easily, the failure probability is at most $2t^2/N^2$ .

3.6. Coin tossing versus paths in the de Bruijn graph

Theorem 5. Let $b_0,\dots,b_{t+n-1}$ be a bit string. Then, the probability that this string arose by the sequential editing of an $n+t$ long coin toss sequence is the same as the probability that it arose by choosing a logic $f\;:\;V^{n-1}\rightarrow V$ and starting position $(b_0,\dots,b_{n-1})$ each uniformly at random.

Proof. Without loss of generality we assume the given string has the de Bruijn property. (Else, the two probabilities are both zero.) First, let’s compute the probability that $b$ arose by sequential editing of a $(t+n)$ -long coin toss. The probability of the coin toss yielding $b_0,\dots,b_{n-1}$ is $(1/2)^n$ . Consider $b_i$ , with $i\ge n$ . If $(b_{i-n+1},\dots,b_{i-1})$ is equal to $(b_{j-n+1},\dots,b_{j-1})$ for some $j$ in the range $n\le j\lt i$ , then sequential editing says to let $b_i$ be what it ought to be: $b_{i-n}\oplus f(b_{i-n+1},\dots,b_{i-1})$ . In which case, it does not matter what value $C_i$ has. But if $i\ge n$ and $(b_{i-n+1},\dots,b_{i-1})$ has not been seen before (among $(n-1)$ -long words ending at a position greater then or equal to $n$ ), then $C_i$ must be equal to $b_i$ . (And, we remember henceforward the value of $f(b_{i-n+1},\dots,b_{i-1})$ is $b_i\oplus b_{i-n}$ .) Altogether, then, the probability that a length $t+n$ coin toss will yield a given sequence $b_0,b_1,\dots,b_{t+n-1}$ by sequential editing is $2^{-r}$ where

\begin{equation*} r = n-1+ \#\textit {distinct } (n-1)\textit {-long subwords ending at position } n-1 \textit { or later}. \end{equation*}

Now let’s compute the probability that $b$ arose by choosing a starting position and logic at random. Classify each position $i$ , $0\le i\le t+n-1$ , as Type I or Type II. The position is Type I if $i\ge n$ and the preceding $(n-1)$ long word $(b_{i-n+1},\dots,b_{i-1})$ is appearing for the first time in the $b$ -sequence. The position is Type II otherwise: either $i\lt n$ , or the preceding $(n-1)$ long word $(b_{i-n+1},\dots,b_{i-1})$ is appearing for the second or later time. It should be clear that the probability in question is

\begin{equation*} \left (\frac {1}{2}\right )^{n+\#\textit {Type I}}. \end{equation*}

The two probabilities just calculated agree.Footnote 6

3.7. Notation for paths starting at $k$ random $n$ -tuples

We now fix $k \ge 1$ and use the notation $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ to name $k$ random $n$ -tuples. Collectively, these $k$ edges of $D_{n-1}$ are denoted

(20) \begin{equation} \boldsymbol{{e}} = (e_1,e_2,\ldots,e_k) \in (\mathbb{F}_2^n)^k. \end{equation}

Picking a random feedback $f$ , and $k$ random $n$ -tuples, independent of $f$ , is equivalent to picking one element, uniformly at random from the space

(21) \begin{equation} S_{n,k} \;:\!=\; \{ (f,\boldsymbol{{e}})\,: \, \ f\;:\; \mathbb{F}_2^{n-1} \to \mathbb{F}_2, \boldsymbol{{e}} \in (\mathbb{F}_2^n)^k \}, \textrm{ with } |S_{n,k}|=2^{2^{n-1}+kn}. \end{equation}

The choice of $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ from $S_{n,k}$ determines $k$ infinite periodic sequences of edges: for $a=1$ to $k$ ,

(22) \begin{equation} {\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_a) \;:\!=\; (e_{a,0} e_{a,1} e_{a,2}\cdots ) \textit{ where } e_{a,0}=e_a, \textrm{ and for } i \ge 0, e_{a,i+1}= \pi _f(e_{a,i}). \end{equation}

For the sake of comparison with coin tossing, we often look at such paths only up to time $t$ (this is what motivated our terminology segment):

(23) \begin{equation} \textrm{ for } a=1 \textrm{ to } k, \ \ {\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_a,t) = (e_{a,0} e_{a,1} \cdots e_{a,t}). \end{equation}

3.8. $(k,t)$ -sequential editing

Now we will define a modification of the sequential editing process that was discussed earlier in Section 3.1. The reader should bear in mind our ultimate goal. We wish to study what happens when a feedback logic $f$ is chosen at random; $k$ different starting $n$ -tuples $e_1,\dots,e_k$ are chosen at random; and $k$ walks of length $t$ are generated, the first starting from $e_1$ and using the logic $f$ to continue for $t$ steps; the second starting from $e_2$ , etc. As in Section 3.1, we wish to generate these walks using $k(n+t)$ coin tosses, and we would like to have an analogue to Theorem 5 saying that our procedure for passing from the coin toss to the $k$ walks perfectly simulates the process of choosing a logic and starting points at random. The reader can almost certainly envision the natural way to achieve this, but we will write out the details.

The first $n+t$ coins are used exactly as in Section 3.1: Rule 1 is applied to the first $n$ coin tosses to yield starting point $e_1$ , and then Rule 2 is applied $t$ times to get the overlapping $n$ -tuples $e_1=e_{1,0}, e_{1,1}, \ldots, e_{1,t}$ that form the first walk. Equivalently, this segment is spelled out by the $(n+t)$ de Bruijn bits $b_0 \ldots b_{t+n-1}$ , and along the way, some feedback logic bits have been defined.

Then, for the next $n$ coin tosses, $C_i$ for $i=t+n$ to $i=t+2n-1$ inclusive, sequential editing is suspended; again Rule 1 is applied, to give

\begin{equation*} e_2 \;:\!=\; (b_{t+n},\ldots,b_{t+2n-1}) \;:\!=\; (C_{t+n},\ldots,C_{t+2n-1}), \end{equation*}

with no new feedback logic bits learned. Then, Rule 2 is applied for the next $t$ input bits, $C_i$ for $i=t+2n$ to $i=2t+2n-1$ to create the second walk of length $t$ , ${\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_2,t)$ — remembering of course those feedback logic bits that were learned during the creation of ${\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_1,t)$ , and (most likely) learning some new feedback logic bits in the process. (It might be the case that $e_2=e_1$ , or that $e_2$ appears in the first walk, in which case, we don’t learn any new feedback logic bits.) If $k\gt 2$ , we continue in a similar fashion, first suspending editing for time $n$ , during which time we learn no new feedback logic bits and we form $e_a \;:\!=\; (b_{(a-1)(t+n)},\ldots,b_{(a-1)t+an-1}) \;:\!=\; (C_{(a-1)(t+n)},\ldots,C_{(a-1)t+an-1})$ , then returning to Rule 2 for the next $t$ bits, to fill out ${\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_a,t)$ .

For $k,t \ge 1$ we define

(24) \begin{align} {{Q-EDIT_{k,t}}}\;:\;\{0,1\}^{k(n+t)} \;\;\;\to \;\;\; (\mathbb{F}_2^{t+n})^k \end{align}
(25) \begin{align} (C_0,C_1,\ldots,C_{k(n+t)-1}) \;\;\; \mapsto \;\;\; ({\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_1,t),\ldots,{\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_k,t) ) \end{align}

as given by the above procedure.

It may, or should, seem intuitively obvious that ${Q-EDIT_{k,t}}$ , applied to an input uniformly chosen from $ \{0,1\}^{k(n+t)}$ , induces the same distribution on the $k$ segments of length $t$ in (22), as does a uniform pick from $S_{n,k}$ and iteration of $\pi _f$ from each of $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ . We claim that the argument given in the proof of Theorem 5 can be adapted to show this.

3.9. The good event $G_{(k,t)}$ for $(k,t)$ -sequential editing

There are two different ways to produce $k$ walks each of length $t$ out of a sequence of $k(n+t)$ coin tosses. The first, with $t'=(k-1)n+kt$ playing the role of $t$ , is simple sequential edit, to determine a starting $n$ -tuple $e$ , and one path $e_0,e_1,\ldots,e_{t'}$ corresponding to $t'=(k-1)n+kt$ iterates of $\pi _f$ starting from $e$ . The good event, regarding this first procedure, is really $G \equiv G_{((k-1)n+kt)}$ . We can then cut the path of length $t'$ to produce $k$ paths of length $t$ ; see (31) to see the natural notation associated with such cutting. The second procedure is is to apply ${Q-EDIT_{k,t}}$ , defined in the previous section, to produce a $k$ -tuple of starting edges, $\boldsymbol{{e}}$ , and $k$ segments of length $t$ , as in (23). The good event, regarding this second procedure, to be called $G_{(k,t)}$ , is designed so that the two procedures agree. We simply take all of the demands of the good event for simple editing on $k(n+t)$ coins, and throw in additional requirements to ensure the suspensions of editing involved in the definition of ${Q-EDIT_{k,t}}$ . Informally, these additional requirements are that every $(n-1)$ tuple which appears at some time $j$ involved in suspension occurs at no other time $i$ in the coin toss sequence. Formally, given $n,k,t$ , the bad event $B$ is given by

(26) \begin{equation} B = \bigcup _{ i \in [0, k(n+t)-n+1]} \ \ \bigcup _{j \in \cup _{a=1}^{k-1} [a(n+t)-n+2,a(n+t)]} M_{ij}, \end{equation}

where the event $M_{ij} = \emptyset$ if $i=j$ , and otherwise

\begin{equation*} M_{ij} = \{d_\textit {HAMMING}(C_iC_{i+1}\cdots C_{i+n-2},C_jC_{j+1}\cdots C_{j+n-2}) \le 1 \}, \end{equation*}

and the good event is then

(27) \begin{equation} {G_{(k,t)}} = G_{((k-1)n+kt)} \setminus B. \end{equation}

Since a word of length $n-1$ has $n$ neighbours at Hamming distance 1 or less, ${\mathbb{P}}(M_{ij}) = n/2^{n-1}$ for $i \ne j$ , so that ${\mathbb{P}}(B) \le (n+t)k^2n^2 \times 2/N$ , for the sake of extending Theorem 4.

We now consider the following to have been proved; it is a single theorem, to give the extensions of Theorems 2 and 4 and 5, appropriate to $k,t$ sequential editing. Note that in the final conclusion of Theorem 6 we treat $k$ as fixed while $n,t \to \infty$ , so that $t$ and $kt$ are of the same order, and we take the assumption $t/\sqrt{N} \to \infty$ so that the three terms in the bound from Theorem 4 are covered by a single term.

Theorem 6.

  1. (i) The procedure ${Q-EDIT_{k,t}}$ , applied to a coin toss sequence

    \begin{equation*} (C_0,C_1,\ldots,C_{k(n+t)-1}), \end{equation*}
    chosen uniformly at random from $\{0,1\}^{k(n+t)}$ , yields $k$ segments of length $t$ , $({\operatorname{Seg}}(f,e_1,t),\ldots,{\operatorname{Seg}}(f,e_k,t) )$ with exactly the same distribution as obtained by a random feedback logic $f$ and $k$ starting $n$ -tuples, $\boldsymbol{{e}} = (e_1,\ldots,e_k)$ .
  2. (ii) The good event ${G_{(k,t)}} \subset \{0,1\}^{k(n+t)}$ , defined by (27) — which ultimately involves conditions (a) through (f) from Section 3.4, applied with $t'=(k-1)n+kt$ in the role of $t$ , is such that for every outcome in $G_{(k,t)}$ , the bit sequence $b_0b_1 \cdots b_{k(n+t)-1}$ (and the equivalent sequence of overlapping $n$ -tuples, $e_0e_1\cdots e_{(k-1)n+kt}$ ) formed by single sequential edit agrees with the shotgun edit of the $k(n+t)$ coins, and leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats have the same locations in $b_0b_1 \cdots b_{k(n+t)-1}$ and in $(C_0,C_1,\ldots,C_{k(n+t)-1})$ .

  3. (iii) Also, on the good event $G_{(k,t)}$ , the $k$ segments of length $t$ , produced by ${Q-EDIT_{k,t}}$ and notated as in (23) match exactly with $e_0\cdots e_t, e_{t+n}\cdots e_{2t+n}, \ldots, e_{(k-1)(t+n)} \cdots e_{(k-1)n+kt}$ , produced by cutting the output of the single sequential edit of $k(n+t)$ coins.

  4. (iv) Finally, if $t/\sqrt{N} \to \infty$ with $k$ fixed, then ${\mathbb{P}}({G_{(k,t)}}) \ge 1 - O(n^3 \, t^3/N^2)$ .

We summarise: there is an exact operation, sequential editing of $n+t$ coin tosses, which achieves the exact distribution of ${\textrm{Seg}}(f,e,t)$ , as induced by a uniform choice of $(f,e)$ from its $2^{2^{n-1}} 2^n$ possible values, followed by starting at $e$ and taking $t$ iterates of the permutation $\pi _f$ . There is a good event $G \equiv G_{t}$ , with ${\mathbb{P}}(G) \to 1$ provided that $t^3n^3/N^2 \to 0$ , for which the sequential edit agrees with the shotgun edit, and $v_i=v_j$ iff the coins have a leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeat at $(i,j)$ . This sequential edit can be used with $k(n+t)$ in place of $n+t$ , to create one long segment; there is the corresponding good event $G_{t^{\prime }}$ , $t^{\prime }=(k-1)n+kt$ . There is a second, distinct operation, ${Q-EDIT_{k,t}}$ , for editing $k(n+t)$ coin tosses, to yield the exact distribution of $k$ segments of length $t$ under a single logic $f$ and $k$ starting $n$ -tuples, $\boldsymbol{{e}} = (e_1,\ldots,e_k)$ ; that is, the distribution of $({\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_1,t),\ldots,{\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_k,t))$ as induced by a uniform choice of $(f,{\mathbb{E}\,})$ from its $2^{2^{n-1}} 2^{kn}$ possible values. And there is a corresponding good event ${G_{(k,t)}} \subset G_{t^{\prime }}$ , with

\begin{equation*} {\mathbb {P}}(G_{t^{\prime }} \setminus {G_{(k,t)}}) \le 2k^2n^2(n+t)/N, \end{equation*}

formed by adding the constraint that $i$ or $j \in \cup _{0 \le a \lt k} [a(n+t)-n+2,a(n+t)]$ implies that there is not an $(n-1)$ tuple repeat at $(i,j)$ . On the event $G_{(k,t)}$ , the $k$ -sequential edit agrees exactly with the cutting of ${\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_1,k(n+t)-n)$ .

Figure 1. An example, one segment of length 290, where there are three leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats, at (56,153), (120,260) and (135,175).

Figure 2. The same example: one segment of length 290, where there are three leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats, at locations (56,153), (120,260) and (135,175). Now, the locations are plotted in standard Cartesian coordinates.

Figure 3. Coloring. An example, with $k=3$ , $n=10,t=90$ . The same one segment of length 290, as in Figure 1, where there are three leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats, at (56,153), (120,260) and (135,175). Now the first segment is coloured red, the second yellow and the third blue.

Figure 4. Coloring and cutting; a succinct way to visualise both. The $k$ segments of length $t$ are still shown as they appear along the single segment of length $k(t+n)-n$ . We also show the $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ $t$ by $t$ squares where matches may occur between two differently coloured length $t$ segments. Note the repeat at (56,153) is a vertex coloured both red and yellow, hence orange. The repeat at (120,260) is a vertex coloured both yellow and blue, hence green. The vertex at (135,175) is coloured yellow twice - we could show it as an extra-saturated yellow but did not. The significance of the diagonals of the small squares is explained in Section 4.3.

3.10. A cutting example

We now illustrate some of the concepts just introduced, with an example and with Figures 1, 2, 3 and 4. Take $n=10,t=90,k=3$ . So, to generate $k=3$ segments of length $t=90$ , we start with $k(n+t)=300$ coin tosses, used to generate one segment of length $k(n+t)-n=290$ . When we have in mind a single segment of length $t$ , we will use a single subscript to label the edges, so that with $e=e_0$ , the segment is a list of $t+1$ edges

(28) \begin{equation} {\textrm{Seg}}(f,e,t)= e_0 e_1 \cdots e_t. \end{equation}

The coin tosses, indexed from $i=0$ to $i=299$ , are labelled $C_i$ , the de Bruijn bits formed by sequential edit are labelled $b_i$ , and the bits formed by shotgun edit are labelled $a_i$ . On the good event $G$ , we will have $a_i=b_i$ for all $i$ . The vertex $v_i$ is the $(n-1)$ - tuple of bits starting with $b_i$ , the edge $e_i$ is the $n$ -tuple of bits starting with $b_i$ and edge $e_i$ at time $i$ goes from vertex $v_{i}$ to $v_{i+1}$ :

\begin{equation*} v_{i} = b_{i}b_{i+1}\cdots b_{i+n-2}, \ e_i = b_{i}b_{i+1}\cdots b_{i+n-1}, \ e_i= (v_{i},v_{i+1}) . \end{equation*}

We also view the segment in (28) as a list of $t+2$ vertices, or as a list of $t+n$ bits, and abuse notation by writing equality, so that

(29) \begin{equation} {\textrm{Seg}}(f,e,t)= v_0 v_1 \cdots v_t v_{t+1}. \end{equation}
(30) \begin{equation} {\textrm{Seg}}(f,e,t)= b_0 b_1\cdots b_{n-1}b_n \cdots b_tb_{t+1}\cdots b_{t+n-1}. \end{equation}

Since we are particularly interested in leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats, we shall suppose that we are in the good event $G$ , and the leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats in the coin toss sequence are at (56,153), (120,260) and (135,175). Thanks to $G$ occurring, we know that all 291 edges $e_0$ to $e_{290}$ are distinct, and the only vertex repetitions are $v_{56}=v_{153}, v_{120}=v_{260}$ and $v_{135}=v_{175}$ . One way of indicating where these vertex repeats occur is to draw some auxiliary lines pointing to the locations, as in Figure 1. Figure 2 gives a two-dimensional (‘spatial’) view of the same situation.

When we cut the single long segment in (28) into $k=3$ segments, we use two indices; the first runs from 1 to $k$ , and the second runs from 0 to $t$ . Including the relation with (28), for Example 1, but with the labels $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ overloaded — since they also appear on the left side, naming the starting edges for the $k$ segments — this will give

\begin{equation*} \begin {array}{c@{\quad}c@{\quad}c@{\quad}c@{\quad}c} {\textrm {Seg}}(f,e_1,t) & = & e_{1,0}\cdots e_{1,90} & = & e_0\cdots e_{90} \\[5pt] {\textrm {Seg}}(f,e_2,t) & = & e_{2,0}\cdots e_{2,90} & = & e_{100}\cdots e_{190} \\[5pt] {\textrm {Seg}}(f,e_3,t) & = & e_{3,0}\cdots e_{3,90} & = & e_{200}\cdots e_{290}. \end {array} \end{equation*}

The same $k=3$ segments of length $t=90$ , presented as lists of vertices (which here are 9-tuples) are notated as

(31) \begin{equation} \begin{array}{c@{\quad}c@{\quad}c@{\quad}c@{\quad}c}{\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_1,t) & = & v_{1,0}v_{1,1}\cdots v_{1,90}v_{1,91} & = & v_0v_1\cdots v_{90}v_{91} \\[5pt] {\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_2,t) & = & v_{2,0}v_{2,1}\cdots v_{2,90}v_{2,91} & = & v_{100}v_{101}\cdots v_{190}v_{191} \\[5pt] {\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_3,t) & = & v_{3,0}v_{3,1}\cdots v_{3,90} v_{3,91} & = & v_{200}v_{201}\cdots v_{290}v_{291}. \end{array} \end{equation}

Collectively, these $k$ segments are given by a deterministic function of $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ , where $\boldsymbol{{e}}=(e_1,e_2,\ldots,e_k)$ names all $k$ starting points.

3.11. Coloring

Imagine the $k$ segments of length $t$ as pieces of (directed) yarn, with $k$ different ‘primary’ colours. Vertices that appear only once get the primary colour of the segment they come from; vertices that appear twice on the same segment might be visualised as having a more saturated version of the primary colour of that segment. The interesting case occurs when a vertex appears on two different segments; such a vertex, call it $v^{\#}$ , gets each of two primary colours — and its secondary colour shows which two segments this vertex lies on; for example imagine that the two strands are red and yellow, so that $v^{\#}$ is coloured orange. Figure 3 on page 31 and Figure 4 illustrate this colouring.

4. Toggling

To toggle a logic $ f\;:\;\mathbb{F}_2^{n-1} \to \mathbb{F}_2$ at a vertex $v \in \mathbb{F}_2^{n-1}$ is simply to get a new $f$ from the old, by changing the value at $v$ . This is called a ‘cross-join step’ and is studied extensively in the context of cycle joining algorithms to create a full cycle logic. Our interest in toggling is different: we have $k \ge 2$ segments induced by a logic $f$ and $k$ starting $n$ -tuples, $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ , and we want to choose $m$ different ‘toggle points’ in the role of $v$ , to get a nice family of $2^m$ related logics. All this is done in the interest of showing that the chance that $e_1$ and $e_2$ lie on the same cycle of $\pi _f$ is approximately one-half, for large $n$ , and more generally, that the chance $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ all lie on the same cycle is approximately $1/k$ , and even more, that the permutation $\pi _f$ , relativised to $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ , is approximately uniformly distributed over all $k!$ permutations. This introductory paragraph is intentionally short and vague; the full details use all of Sections 36. Section 4.1 gives a longer attempt at introduction, including Figure 5, showing the huge collection of candidate toggle vertices, using $k$ colours to help visualise the $k$ segments of interest.

Figure 5. Take $n=34$ , $N=2^n$ and $t=3 \times (n+N^{.6})-n$ . The expected number of leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats is about $\left(\substack{t \\[3pt] 2}\right)/N\doteq 501.4$ . The picture shows 500 ‘arrival’ points, giving the locations of repeats, plotted as for one segment of long length $t$ . In each $N^{.6}$ by $N^{.6}$ square, the expected number of points is $N^{.2}\doteq 111.4$ . The colour scheme is intended to be purple, green, blue across the top row, orange, yellow for the middle and red (magenta) for the bottom.

4.1. Big picture perspective: $k$ coloured segments, $m$ toggle points

We will have $k$ segments each of length $t=N^{.6}$ . The expected number of leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats within a single segment is about $\left(\substack{t \\[3pt] 2}\right)/N\doteq .5 N^{.2}$ . The expected number of repeats between two different given segments is about $t^2/ N = N^{.2}$ , so the expected number of repeats between two different segments, combined over all $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ choices for which two segments, is about $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right) \times N^{.2}$ . This is a huge number of repeats (each based on one vertex having a secondary colouring), and we intend to find $m$ such repeats, say at $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_m$ in narrowly constrained spatial positions. The goal is to show that, with high probability, for all $2^m$ choices of how to change $f$ by toggling the values of $f(v^{\#}_i)$ for $i \in I \subset \{1,2,\ldots,m\}$ , the same $m$ vertices will be picked out by the narrow two-dimensional spatial constraints.

In this section we present further figures intended to assist the reader’s intuition. We also give an algorithm which for a given logic $f$ and starting edges $e_i$ finds $m$ vertices $v^{\#}_1$ , …, $v^{\#}_m$ . These points—we call them toggle points—give rise to a family of $2^m$ functions. We also define (in Section 4.10) a process called relativisation which associates with $\pi _f$ in $S_N$ a permutation $\sigma$ in $S_k$ , $k$ being fixed and $N \to \infty$ . It will be shown that as $f$ varies over the $2^m$ functions in a ‘toggle class’, the resulting $\sigma ’s$ cover $S_k$ almost uniformly. In Section 5, it will be shown that this uniform coverage of $S_k$ (for each fixed $k$ ) is a sufficient condition to prove Theorem 1.

A critical issue is that the algorithm for choosing the toggle points must be such that, if the feedback $f$ is replaced by any one of the $2^m$ functions in the toggle class, the algorithm would find the same toggle points and the same class.Footnote 7 However this is not necessarily the case and the probability of success for the algorithm must be estimated; this leads to the definition of an event $H$ .

4.2. Toggling: The case $k=2$ and $m=1$

We show what can happen when we toggle one bit of a logic $f$ . We have two segments of length $t$ , which share a vertex $v^{\#}$ . Toggling changes the value of $f$ , only at $v^{\#}$ , and gives a new logic ${f^{*}}$ . Suppose that the segments under $f$ were red and yellow, and that $v^{\#}$ appears at position $i$ on the red segment, and position $j$ on the yellow segment. Overall, this repeat has spatial location $(i,j)$ and colour orange. Exactly one such repeat was visualised in Figures 2 and 3; it occurred with $(i,j)=(56,53)$ . The displacement is $i-j$ — we have a preferred sequence of colours, (derived from the rainbow ROY G. BIV) where red comes before yellow — hence the displacement is 3, rather than $-3$ , in this example.

4.3. Picking the ‘earliest’ toggle with a small displacement

Consider the case where we have $k=2$ segments and want to find a single vertex $v^{\#}$ via a recipe which, when applied to the segments under the toggled logic ${f^{*}}$ , still picks out the same vertex. A good recipe involves naming a small bound $d$ on the absolute displacement $|i-j|$ (thus staying close to the ‘diagonal’), and then picking the ‘earliest’ pair $(i,j)$ that satisfies the displacement bound. This was the key to overcoming the ‘fallacy’ described in Footnote 7.

The specific choice of how to define earliest is somewhat arbitrary; we will take smallest $(i+j)$ as the first criterion for earliest, with ties to be broken according to smallest value of $\max\!(i,j)$ — given that $i+j = i'+j'$ , this is equivalent to taking smallest absolute displacement for the tie-break criterion. For use in the case of $k$ colours and $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ colour pairs $\alpha =(a,b)$ , break further ties according to $\min\!(a,b)$ and then $\max\!(a,b)$ .

The logic $f$ , with value at $v^{\#}$ complemented, gives a new logic ${{f^{*}}}={\textrm{Toggle}}(f,\{v^{\#} \})$ , so that ${{f^{*}}}(v^{\#})=1-f(v^{\#})$ , while ${{f^{*}}}(v)=f(v) \ \ \forall v \ne v^{\#}$ . It is possible that changing the logic bit at $v^{\#}$ , will cause an earlier pair to become available as the location of a match between the two segments; so that the recipe for picking the earliest small displacement match, applied to ${f^{*}}$ , picks out a different vertex instead of $v^{\#}$ . In this case, the word toggle is very misleading: the overall operation (find $v^{\#}$ , then complement the logic at that vertex) is not an involution. Our programme is to specify a displacement bound $d$ that varies with $n$ , in such a way that 1) with high probability, at least one small displacement match can be found, and 2) with high probability, the vertex for the earliest small displacement match is the same in the logic ${{f^{*}}} ={\textrm{Toggle}}(f,\{v^{\#} \})$ at the vertex selected for $f$ . The example in Figure 8, viewed with any $d \ge 3$ , illustrates what might go wrong with respect to 2).

Figure 6. About 333 of the 500 occurrences of repeats from Figure 5, but now viewed as among $k=3$ segments of length $t=N^{.6}\doteq 1.38 \times 10^6$ . The $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ $t$ by $t$ above-diagonal squares from Figure 5 are superimposed, so the expected number of points is about $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right) \times N^{.2}\doteq 334.3$ . The approximately 167.1 repeats where both occurrences lie in the same segment, corresponding to the $k$ right triangles hugging the diagonal in Figure 5, are not shown. In Section 4.5 we discuss this picture, suggesting scaling for the axes, so that in each colour, the picture is approximately a standard (rate 1 per unit area) two-dimensional Poisson process. The colour scheme is intended to be purple, green, orange.

Figure 7. Toggling. An example with $t=90$ and displacement $d=3$ . The same repeat as shown in Figure 3 with location (56,153) and shown by the orange dot in Figure 4. When all $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ squares are superimposed, as in Figure 6, the spatial location becomes $(i,j)=(56,53)$ . Before the toggle, we have two segments of length $t=90$ ; after the toggle, the segments have length $t \pm d$ , that is, 93 and 87.

Figure 8. Toggling. This is a continuation of the example in Figure 7, with one repeat with location (56,153), shown by the orange dot in Figure 4. When all $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ squares are superimposed, as in Figure 6, the spatial location becomes $(i,j)=(56,53)$ . Now suppose there were an additional repeat, (which would have been shown by a red dot at (53,58) in Figure 4,) shown here in Figure 8 by the pair of red dots for $f$ . After the toggle at the orange vertex, vertex 53, along the segment that starts red and finishes yellow, is the same as vertex 55, along the segment that start yellow and finishes red. So, in the logic ${f^{*}}$ , we have two matches between the two segments: the original, at (56,53), shown by the orange dots, and a new one, at (53,55), shown by the red dots.

Recall, from Section 3, that $t$ is the length of our segments. To get high probability in 1), a necessary and sufficient condition is that

(32) \begin{equation} td/N \to \infty . \end{equation}

To get high probability in 2), a necessary and sufficient condition is that

(33) \begin{equation} d^2/N \to 0. \end{equation}

The argument that (33) suffices is somewhat delicate, akin to a stopping time argument; it is easier to prove — see (37) — that a sufficient condition is that

(34) \begin{equation} td^3/N^2 \to 0; \end{equation}

and then it will be easy to arrange for situations corresponding to pairs $(t,d)$ satisfying both (32) and (34).

4.4. Displacements caused by toggles

Suppose we have $k=3$ colours, as shown in Figure 9. There are three segments of length $t=90$ , with respect to $f$ . The segment with respect to $f$ , starting with $e_{1}$ , coloured red, has $v^{\#}_1$ in position 6 and $v^{\#}_2$ in position 35 — so the red segment, of length 90, is divided into an initial red path of length 6, followed by a red path of length 29, followed by a red path of length 55.

Figure 9. With starting edges $e_1,e_2,e_3$ , three segments under the logic $f$ are shown in the top part of the display; the red and yellow segments share a vertex $v^{\#}_1$ , coloured orange, early on, the red and blue segments share a vertex $v^{\#}_2$ , coloured purple, at a intermediate time, and the yellow and blue segments share a vertex $v^{\#}_3$ , coloured green, at a late time. We take ${{f^{*}}}={\textrm{Toggle}}(f,\{v^{\#}_1 \})$ and ${{f^{**}}}={\textrm{Toggle}}(f,\{v^{\#}_1,v^{\#}_2 \})$ to be the logics formed by toggling at $v^{\#}_1$ , and at both $v^{\#}_1$ and $v^{\#}_2$ . The middle part of the display shows the three segments under ${f^{*}}$ , and the bottom part of the display shows the three segments under ${f^{**}}$ .

The $f$ segment starting with $e_{2}$ , coloured yellow, has $v^{\#}_1$ in position 3 and $v^{\#}_3$ in position 75; hence, it is divided into yellow paths of lengths 3, 72, 15, in that order.

The $f$ segment starting with $e_{3}$ , coloured blue, has $v^{\#}_2$ in position 37 and $v^{\#}_3$ in position 71; hence, it is divided into blue paths of lengths 37, 34, 19, in that order.

Next, consider ${{f^{*}}} \;:\!=\; f$ , toggled at $v^{\#}_1$ . Its segment starting from $e_{1}$ has length 6 red followed by length (72 + 15) = 87, for a total length of 93. Its segment starting from $e_{2}$ has length 3 yellow, followed by length (29 + 55) = 84, for a total length of 87. The ${f^{*}}$ segment starting from $e_{3}$ is still length 90, all blue. More importantly, $v^{\#}_2$ has moved from position 35 on ${\textrm{Seg}}(f, e_1)$ to position 32 on ${\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_2)$ , and $v^{\#}_3$ has moved from position 75 on ${\textrm{Seg}}(f, e_2)$ to position 78 on ${\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_1)$ , so these have new positions under ${f^{*}}$ , i.e., have been displaced.

Now consider the full effect of changing from $f$ to ${f^{*}}$ , by toggling the logic at the bit $v^{\#}_1$ which appeared at positions $(i,j)=(i,i-d) = (6,3)$ , with $d=3$ , for the red and yellow segments: every red vertex later than 6 gets displaced by $-d$ , and every yellow vertex later than 3 gets displaced by $+d$ . If a match occurs at $(I,J)$ in the $f$ segments, and the colours involved are red, and some colour, call it $a$ , with $a$ not equal to yellow, then:

  • Case 1. Color $a$ comes after red, in the list of $k$ colours: the ordered colour pair is (red, $a)$ . The index $I\gt i$ belongs to a red vertex in position $I$ under the logic $f$ , and this vertex has position $I-d$ under the logic ${f^{*}}$ . So the point at $(I,J)$ moves to position $(I-d,J)$ .Footnote 8

  • Case 2. Color $a$ comes before red, in the list of $k$ colours; the colour pair is $(a,$ red). The index $J\gt i$ belongs to a red vertex, in position $J$ under the logic $f$ , but in position $J-d$ under the logic ${f^{*}}$ . So the point at $(I,J)$ moves to position $(I,J-d)$ .

If there is an orange match at $(I,J)$ for the $f$ segments, with $I\gt i$ and $J\gt j$ , this match will move to $(I-d,J+d)$ .

Similarly, a match between yellow, and some $a$ not equal to red, occurring at $(I,J)$ under the logic $f$ , moves to $(I+3,J)$ or $(I,J+3)$ under the logic ${f^{*}}$ , according to whether $a$ comes after or before yellow, in the list of all $k$ colours.

This effect can be seen in Figure 9: the orange dot is at (6,3) with displacement $d=3$ , the purple dot occurs at (35,37) under $f$ , but at (32,37) under ${f^{*}}$ and ${f^{**}}$ .

More cases can be seen in Figure 10.

Figure 10. Displacements caused by a single toggle. An example with $t=90$ , and three colours, red, yellow, and blue. Say the toggle is at $v^{\#}_2$ occurring at (red,blue) time $(35,40)$ , similar to the purple vertex at ( $35,37)$ in Figure 9, but with the displacement changed from −2 to −5, for the sake of being easier to see in the two-dimensional picture. We have thrown in several more matches between two different colours, at various earlier and later times, to show the resulting two-dimensional displacements. Red vertices at times greater than 35 have their time increased by 5, and blue vertices at times greater than 40 have their time decreased by 5. Two-dimensional match locations are indicated by a solid circle for the logic $f$ and an open circle for the logic ${f^{*}}$ .

4.5. The natural scale: by $1/\sqrt{N}$ for length, by $1/N$ for area

One gets an intuitive grasp of the process of spatial locations of places $(i,j)$ where two segments of different colours share a vertex, by looking at a picture such as that in Figure 6 — even though the axes are unlabelled.

One view would be that the square is $t$ by $t$ , with $n=34, N=2^n,t=N^{.6}$ , i.e., about 1.3 million by 1.3 million. The other natural view is that the square is about $t/\sqrt{N}$ by $t/\sqrt{N}$ , i.e., about 10.556 by 10.556, with area 111.43.

The latter point of view is natural, since at each $(i,j)$ , for each colour pair $(a,b)$ , $1 \le a \lt b \le k$ , with $\doteq$ to allow a small discrepancy for the failure of the good event, ${\mathbb{P}}($ an arrival Footnote 9 at $(i,j)$ in those colours) $ \;:\!=\;{\mathbb{P}}(v_{a,i}=v_{b,j}$ and $v_{a,i-1} \ne v_{b,j-1})$ $\doteq{\mathbb{P}}($ there is a leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeat at a specific locationFootnote 10 in the coin tossing sequence) $= 1/N$ . Hence, scaling length by $1/\sqrt{N}$ , so that area is scaled by $1/N$ , leads to

\begin{equation*} \text { the expected number of arrivals per unit area } =1. \end{equation*}

The picture in Figure 6, viewed as occurring on a 10.556 by 10.556 square, closely resembles a (standard, rate $1 \, dy \, dx$ ) two-dimensional Poisson process, in each secondary colour pair. And overall, ignoring colour, the picture resembles the rate $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right) \, dy \, dx$ Poisson process on the $t/ \sqrt{N}$ by $t/ \sqrt{N}$ square.

There are additional requirements for the Poisson process, beyond having intensity $1 \, dy \, dx$ . Namely, probabilistic independence for the counts in disjoint regions. We do have a good Poisson process approximation, for a combination of two reasons. First, the good event $G={G_{(k,t)}}$ from Theorem 6 gives a high-probability coupling (since $t=N^{.6}$ entails $t^3n^3/N^2 \to 0$ ) between coin tossing and the $k$ de Bruijn segments of length $t$ . Second, the Chen–Stein method, Theorem 3 of [Reference Arratia, Goldstein and Gordon6], gives a total variation distance upper bound (tending to zero since $t=N^{.6}$ entails $t^3n/N^2 \to 0$ ) between the process of indicators of leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats for coin tossing, and a process with the same intensity, but mutually independent coordinates.

We get our intuition from the Poisson process. But for our proofs, we will work directly with the discrete, dependent processes.

4.6. Controlled regions for $m$ successive potential toggle vertices

4.6.1. Quick motivation for the geometric progression

We will construct choice functions in (40), based on regions, defined in (36), which in turn are based on a geometric progression in (35). Here we give some motivation for this elaborate construction.

If we search for a single toggle point, in a thin and long rectangle along the diagonal, $\{ (i,j)\;:\;|i-j| \le d, 0\le i,j \le t \}$ , then, in the natural scale of Section 4.5, (and ignoring factors of $\sqrt{2}$ related to the 45 degree rotation, and of 2 for $\pm d$ ), the rectangle is $d_1 = d/\sqrt{N}$ by $w_1= \ t/\sqrt{N}$ . Condition (32) can be interpreted as meaning that the (natural scale) area, $d_1w_1$ , tends to infinity — so that with high probability, matches can be found in this rectangle, and condition (33) can similarly be interpreted as meaning that $d_1 \to 0$ , so that no matches will be found in the two-dimensional set, of area on the order of $d_1^2$ , of points within $\ell _\infty$ distance $d_1$ of the chosen location $(i,j)$ .

Now in choosing $m$ toggle points, displacements caused by earlier toggles might change the search result, and we wish to make this unlikely. In more detail: as seen in Section 4.4, toggling a logic $f$ at a vertex $v^{\#}$ which appears on two different colours, at times $i,j$ with $|i-j| \le d$ causes displacements in the time indices of vertices occurring later on those segments, by amounts up to $d$ . Our $m$ potential toggle points, $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_m$ , are controlled so that on any segment, $v^{\#}_\ell$ is preceded by toggle points from among the $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_{\ell -1}$ . If the displacement caused by toggling at $v^{\#}_i$ is at most $d_i$ , then in choosing $v^{\#}_\ell$ , the accumulated displacements from previous toggles is at most $d_1+\cdots +d_{\ell -1}$ . By taking the $d_i$ in geometric progression, with large ratio $r^2$ , this accumulated displacement in the search for $v^{\#}_\ell$ is at most order of $d_{\ell -1}$ . The rectangle where we search for $v^{\#}_\ell$ is thin and long, $d_\ell$ by $w_\ell = r/d_\ell$ ; the length of its boundary is order of $w_\ell$ , so the area involved in points at a distance at most $d_{\ell -1} = d_\ell/r^2$ from the boundary is order of $1/r =o(1)$ . Hence with high probability, displaced indices have no effect.

4.6.2. The search regions

We divide the time interval $[0,t]$ into $m$ equal length pieces. On the earliest piece, with times in [0,t/m], we demand that we can find a match $(i,j)$ with $|i-j|$ very very very small, but no upper bound on $\max\!(i,j)$ other than $\max\!(i,j) \lt t/m$ . In the natural scale of Section 4.5 we are searching for matches in a very very very thin and very very long rectangle surrounding the diagonal line $i=j$ ; this rectangle has a large area. On the second piece, with times in $[t/m,2t/m]$ , we relax the notion of thin, expanding by a large factor $r^2$ , relax the notion of long, dividing by the factor $r^2$ , thus keeping the area constant. We continue this pair of geometric progressions, so the $m$ th region is a thin long rectangle — but still with the same area.

Here is a concrete way to accomplish the above, together with $t^3n^3/N^2 \to 0$ and with $k$ fixed. Let

\begin{equation*} t \;:\!=\; m \, N^{.6}, a \;:\!=\; N^{.1}, \text { so that } t/m = a \sqrt {N}. \end{equation*}

The last condition should be understood as ‘in the natural scale from Section 4.5, the $t$ by $t$ rectangle is $ma$ by $ma$ , and length $t/m$ for the discrete $i$ and $j$ corresponds to length $a$ ’. Let

\begin{equation*} r \;:\!=\; a^{1/(2m+1)}, \text { so that } r^{2m+1} = a, \end{equation*}

and, ignoring the factors of $\sqrt{2}$ involved in the 45 degree rotation, take the thin long rectangles to have shapes

(35) \begin{eqnarray} d_1 = \frac{1}{r^{2m}} & \textrm{ by } & w_1 = r^{2m+1} = (t/m)/\sqrt{N} \nonumber \\[5pt] d_2 = \frac{1}{r^{2m-2}} & \textrm{ by } & w_2 = r^{2m-1} \\[5pt] & \vdots & \nonumber \\[5pt] d_m = \frac{1}{r^2} & \textrm{ by } & w_m = r^{3} \nonumber \end{eqnarray}

Indexing by $\ell =1$ to $m$ , the $\ell$ th rectangle is $d_\ell \;:\!=\; r^{2\ell -2m-2}$ by $w_\ell \;:\!=\; r^{2m-2\ell +3}$ on the natural scale. Directly in terms of the discrete $i$ and $j$ , we define

(36) \begin{eqnarray}{\textit{Region}}_\ell =\left \{ (i,j)\;:\;\frac{|i-j|}{\sqrt{N}} \lt r^{2\ell -2m-2} \right . & \textrm{ and } & \\[5pt] \left . \frac{(\ell -1)t}{m} \le \min\!(i,j) \le \max\!(i,j) \le \frac{(\ell -1)t}{m} + \frac{t/m}{r^{2(\ell -1)}} \right \}, & & \nonumber \end{eqnarray}

so one checks that 1) as $\ell$ increases by 1, the thinness constraint relaxes by a factor of $r^2$ , while the width constraint becomes more severe by a factor of $r^2$ , so the area stays constant, 2) the first region, with $\ell =1$ , allows $i,j \in [0,t/m]$ and 3) the last region, with $\ell =m$ , has $|i-j|/\sqrt{N} \le 1/r^2 = o(1)$ as $n \to \infty$ .

Consider the possibility discussed in Section 4.3, where a toggle at a vertex appearing in two differently coloured segment enables a match within a single segment to become, after the toggle, an earlier match between two different segments. For each $\ell =1$ to $m$ , with the $(t,d)$ in (34) given by $t=w_\ell \sqrt{N}, d= d_\ell \sqrt{N}$ , the condition in (34) is indeed satisfied by our specific choice in (35). On the natural scale, and ignoring rotation, we are searching for a match in a $\delta = d_\ell$ by $W=w_\ell$ rectangle, thin and long, with $\delta \to 0$ and area $\delta W \to \infty$ . The condition (34), on the natural scale, means that $\delta ^3 W \to 0$ . It implies that, with high probability, we do not find a match between two differently coloured segments (at $(i,j)$ in the rectangle, with $|i-j|/\sqrt{N}\lt \delta$ ,) and simultaneously a nearby match within a single segment. Here, nearby means with both indices within distance $\delta \sqrt{N}$ from $i$ or $j$ . Now, the $\delta$ by $W$ rectangle can be covered by $W/\delta$ squares, each square of size $4 \delta$ by $4 \delta$ , and with each successive square being a translate, by $\delta$ , of the previous square. Ignoring constant factors,Footnote 11 the expected number of arrivals in one square is order of $\delta ^2$ , and the chance of two or more arrivals in that one square is order of $\delta ^4.$ Thus the expected number of squares with two or more arrivals is order of

(37) \begin{equation} W/\delta \times \delta ^4 \ = \delta ^3 W \ \ \ \to 0. \end{equation}

4.7. Definition of the choice functions

Write $V = \mathbb{F}_2^{n-1}$ for the set of vertices in $D_{n-1}$ , and write ‘null’ for a special value, not in $V$ , used to encode ‘undefined’. Recall that we write $\boldsymbol{{e}} = (e_1,\ldots,e_k)$ for the starting $n$ -tuples for $k$ segments, and $S_{n,k} = \{(f,\boldsymbol{{e}}) \}$ for the space in which we make a uniform choice of logic and starting edges. Also recall our notation (31) for vertices along the $k$ segments. Note that we have both $k$ segments and $k$ colours; these are different concepts, and ultimately, colours will be labelled according to the segment labels under $f$ — but on the soon to be defined ‘happy’ event $H$ , finding $v^{\#}_i$ on two different segments of $f$ will be equivalent to finding $v^{\#}_i$ on two different colours. To keep track of the colours, let

(38) \begin{equation} {\mathcal{A}} \;:\!=\; \{\alpha = (a,b)\;:\;1 \le a \lt b \le k \} \end{equation}

For $\ell =1$ to $m$ , we define

(39) \begin{equation} {\textrm{Candidates}}_\ell \;:\;S_{n,k} \to [0,t]^2 \times{\mathcal{A}} \end{equation}
\begin{equation*} {\textrm {Candidates}}_\ell (f,\boldsymbol{{e}}) = \{ (i,j,a,b)\;:\;(i,j) \in {\textit {Region}}_\ell \text { and } v_{a,i} = v_{b,j} \} \end{equation*}

where ${\textit{Region}}_\ell$ is defined by (36).

For $\ell =1$ to $m$ , we define

(40) \begin{equation} {\textit{Choice}}_\ell \;:\;S_{n,k} \to V \cup \{{\textit{null}} \}, \ \ {\textit{Choice}}_\ell (f,\boldsymbol{{e}}) = v^{\#}_\ell \textrm{ or else }{\textit{null}} \end{equation}

where the value is $\textit{null}$ if the set of candidates is empty, and otherwise, picking the first $(i,j,a,b)$ in ${\textrm{Candidates}}_\ell (f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ , $v^{\#}_\ell$ is the vertex with $v^{\#}_\ell =v_{a,i} = v_{b,j}$ . To be very careful, the order for first is the lex-first order on $(i+j, \max\!(i,j), a,b)$ .

4.8. The happy event $H = H(k,m,n)$

We now describe a subset of $S_{n,k}$ and refer to this subset as the happy event $H$ . One requirement for $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}}) \in H$ is that, for $\ell =1$ to $m$ , each of the values ${\textit{Choice}}_\ell (f,\boldsymbol{{e}}) \ne{\textit{null}}$ . Starting with such an $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ , the choice functions pick out a set of $m$ distinct vertices; call them $v^{\#}_1,\ldots, v^{\#}_m$ , and name the set, ${{V^{\#}}} = \{ v^{\#}_1,\ldots, v^{\#}_m \}$ — we will use this notation in (42) below.

Given a set of vertices, $U \subset V$ , we denote the logic $f$ toggled at the vertices in $U$ as ${\textrm{Toggle}}(f,U)$ , defined by

(41) \begin{equation} {\textrm{Toggle}}(f,U) \;:\!=\;{{f^{*}}}, \textrm{ where }{{f^{*}}}(v) = \left \{ \begin{array}{l@{\quad}l} 1-f(v) & \mbox{if $v \in U$} \\[5pt] f(v) & \mbox{if $v \in V \setminus U$} \end{array} \right . . \end{equation}

We define $H$ as follows:

(42) \begin{equation} H = \{ (f,\boldsymbol{{e}})\;:\;\forall \ U \subset{{V^{\#}}}, \textrm{ with }{{f^{*}}} ={\textrm{Toggle}}(f,U), v^{\#}_\ell ={\textit{Choice}}_\ell ({{f^{*}}},\boldsymbol{{e}}) \end{equation}
\begin{equation*} { \textit {and } \text {the segments }} {\textrm {Seg}}(f,e_i,t) \text { collectively have } k(t+1) \text { distinct edges} \}. \end{equation*}

Informally, $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ is in the happy event iff the $k$ segments involve no $n$ -repeats, and the choice recipes find $m$ potential toggle vertices, and all $2^m$ cousins ${f^{*}}$ , formed by toggling at a subset of those vertices, give rise to the same $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_m$ .

The definition above creates an equivalence relation on $H$ , in which all classes have size $2^m$ , and all $({{f^{*}}},\boldsymbol{{e}}) \in [(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})]$ share the same sequence $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_m$ . Using the calculations given in Section 4.6.1 one may show that for fixed $k,m$ , $|H|/|S_{n,k}| \to 1$ ; that it, that ${\mathbb{P}}(H) \to 1$ as $n \to \infty$ .

4.9. Definition and likelihood of an $\varepsilon$ -good schedule

Given $k$ , view $\mathcal{A}$ , defined by (38) as an alphabet of size

\begin{equation*} K \;:\!=\; \left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right). \end{equation*}

A schedule of length $m$ is a word $\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m \in{\mathcal{A}}^m$ . Given a schedule of length $m$ , and $m$ coin tosses $D_1,\ldots,D_m$ , for $i=1$ to $m$ define permutations in ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ by

\begin{equation*} \tau _i = \left \{ \begin {array}{l@{\quad}l} \text {the transposition } (a b) & \mbox {if $\alpha _i=(a,b)$ and $D_i=\text { heads }$} \\[5pt] \text { the identity } & \mbox {if $D_i=\text { tails }$} \end {array} \right ., \end{equation*}

and let $\tau = \tau (\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m,D_1,\ldots,D_m)$ be the product, with $\tau _1$ applied first,

(43) \begin{equation} \tau = \tau _m \circ \cdots \circ \tau _2 \circ \tau _1 \in{\mathcal{S}}_k. \end{equation}

Write $\sigma$ for an arbitrary permutation in ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ , and let

\begin{equation*} p_\sigma = p_\sigma (\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m) = {\mathbb {P}}(\tau = \sigma | \alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m ) \end{equation*}

be the conditional probability of getting $\sigma$ for the value of $\tau$ , given the schedule $\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m$ — these are values of the form $z/2^m$ with $z$ in $Z$ . The total variation distance to the uniform distribution on ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ is

\begin{equation*} {\textrm {Distance}}(\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m)={d_{\textit {TV}}}(\tau,\text {uniform}) = \frac {1}{2} \sum _\sigma \left | p_\sigma - \frac {1}{k!} \right |. \end{equation*}

Given $\varepsilon \gt 0$ , a schedule $\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m$ is $\varepsilon$ -good if ${\textrm{Distance}}(\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m) \lt \varepsilon$ .

Lemma 7. Given $k$ , and $\varepsilon \gt 0$ , there exists $m$ such that, for a random schedule of length $m$ , with all $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)^m$ equally likely,

(44) \begin{equation} {\mathbb{P}}( \alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m \textrm{ is } \varepsilon \textrm{-good}) \gt 1-\varepsilon . \end{equation}

Proof. There is a well-known bijection between ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ and the set $C_k \;:\!=\; [1] \times [2] \times \cdots \times [k]\;$ : given $c=(c_1,c_2,\ldots,c_k)$ with $1 \le c_i \le i$ , take

(45) \begin{equation} \sigma = (2 \ c_2) \circ \cdots \circ (k-1 \ c_{k-1}) \circ (k \ c_k), \end{equation}

where $(a \ b)$ denotes the transposition $(a \ b) \in{\mathcal{S}}_k$ if $a \ne b$ , and the identity map otherwise. (The corresponding algorithm, to generate uniformly distributed random permutations, is known as the ‘Fisher-Yates shuffle’ or ‘Knuth shuffle’.)

Now consider the particular word $w$ of length $K$ over the alphabet $\mathcal{A}$ defined in (38), given by

\begin{equation*} w= (1 \ 2) (1 \ 3) (2 \ 3) \cdots (k-2 \ k) (k-1 \ k). \end{equation*}

If we had $m=K$ and the schedule is $\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m=w$ , then ${\textrm{Distance}}(\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m) \le 1-2^{-K}$ , because for each $\sigma$ in (45), one assignment of the coin values $(D_1,\ldots,D_m)$ yields $\tau =\sigma$ , via the coins for the genuine transpositions among the $(i \ c_i)$ on the right side of (45) being heads, and all others coins being tails. When the word $w$ appears $\ell$ times inside a long word $\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m$ , we have, using a standard result,

\begin{equation*} {\textrm {Distance}}(\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m) \le \left ( 1-2^{-K}\right )^\ell . \end{equation*}

For historical interest, we note that similar results are in [Reference Diaconis11, Thm. 1, p. 23]; see also [Reference Diaconis and Shahshahani12]. In a very long random word $\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m$ , the number of occurrences of $w$ is random, with mean and variance roughly $m \ K^{-K}$ , so a sufficiently large $m$ guarantees that $\ell$ is sufficiently large, with high probability.

4.10. Relativized permutations

We will define ‘ $\pi _f$ relativized to $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ ’ to be a specific permutation in ${\mathcal{S}}_1 \cup \cdots{\mathcal{S}}_{k-1} \cup{\mathcal{S}}_k$ , where ${\mathcal{S}}_j$ denotes the set of all permutations on $\{1,2,\ldots,j\}$ . For use in Lemma 10, we need to allow for the possibility that $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ are not $k$ distinct $n$ -tuples.

Definition 8. Let $\pi$ be a permutation on a finite set $S$ , and let $\boldsymbol{{e}} = (e_1,\ldots,e_k) \in S^k$ . In case $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ are all distinct, write the full cycle notation for $\pi$ , erase all symbols not in $\{e_1,\ldots,e_k\}$ , and then relabel $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ as $1,\ldots,k$ . This yields the cycle notation for a permutation $\sigma = \sigma (\pi,\boldsymbol{{e}}) \in{\mathcal{S}}_k$ , and we call $\sigma$ $\pi$ relativized to $\boldsymbol{{e}}$ ’. In case $j \;:\!=\; | \{e_1,\ldots,e_k\}| \lt k$ , edit the list $(e_1,\ldots,e_k)$ by deleting repeats, from left to right, to get a new list $\boldsymbol{{e}}' =(e_1',\ldots,e_j') \in S^j$ , with no repeats. Now we take $\pi$ relativized to $\boldsymbol{{e}}$ ’ to be $ \sigma (\pi,\boldsymbol{{e}}') \in{\mathcal{S}}_j$ .

On the happy event $H$ from (42), consider an equivalence class $[(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})]$ . We want to name a canonical choice of class leader, and since all $2^m$ elements $({{f^{*}}},\boldsymbol{{e}})$ in the class share the same $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_m$ , and differ only in the values of the ${f^{*}}$ at those vertices, the natural choice of leader is $(f_0,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ where

\begin{equation*} f_0(v^{\#}_1) = \cdots = f_0(v^{\#}_m) = 0. \end{equation*}

Finally, we can say what colours are: for $a=1$ to $k$ , the vertices along ${\textrm{Seg}}(f_0,e_a,t)$ have colour $a$ . Among the various $({{f^{*}}},\boldsymbol{{e}})$ in the equivalence class $[(f_0,\boldsymbol{{e}})]$ , except for the case ${{f^{*}}}=f_0$ , at least some of the $k$ segments start with one colour and end with another.

The schedule corresponding to the equivalence class $[(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})]$ is the word $\alpha _1 \alpha _2 \cdots \alpha _m$ where $\alpha _i = (a_i,b_i)$ where $1 \le a_i \lt b_i \le k$ and $v^{\#}_i$ appears on colours $a_i$ and $b_i$ , that is, $v^{\#}_i$ is a vertex of both ${\textrm{Seg}}(f_0,e_{a_i},t)$ and ${\textrm{Seg}}(f_0,e_{b_i},t)$ . We visualiseFootnote 12 $f(v^{\#}_i)=1$ as meaning that the strands of colours $a_i$ and $b_i$ are cut (at $v^{\#}_i$ ) and glued together to create a colour jump, as in Figs. 8 and 9.

For $a=1$ to $k$ , write ${e'}_a \;:\!=\;$ the final edge $e_{a,t}$ of ${\textrm{Seg}}(f_0,e_a,t)$ , so that, under the logic $f_0$ , ${\textrm{Seg}}(f_0,e_a,t)$ is a directed path (in colour $a$ ) from its female end $e_a$ to its male end ${e'}_a$ . Note that being in $H$ implies that the starting edges $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ are distinct, and the final edges ${e'}_1,\ldots,{e'}_k$ are distinct.

It is clear — from the relative timing of the appearances of the $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_m$ along the segments ${\textrm{Seg}}(f_0,e_a,t)$ — that under the logic ${f^{*}}$ , ${\textrm{Seg}}({{f^{*}}},e_a,t)$ is a directed path from its female end $e_a$ to its male end $e'_{\!\!g(a)}$ , where $g \equiv g({{f^{*}}})$ is the permutation in ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ given by

(46) \begin{equation} g = \tau _m \circ \cdots \circ \tau _2 \circ \tau _1 \in{\mathcal{S}}_k. \end{equation}
\begin{equation*} \tau _i = \left \{ \begin {array}{l@{\quad}l} \text {the transposition } (a b) & \mbox {if $\alpha _i=(a,b)$ and ${{f^{*}}}(v^{\#}_i)=1$ } \\[5pt] \text { the identity } & \mbox {if ${{f^{*}}}(v^{\#}_i)=0 $} \end {array} \right.\!\!, \end{equation*}

compare with (43).

Take the usual notation from Hall-style matching theory, and abbreviate the female ends as $\{1,2,\ldots,k\}$ and the male ends as $\{1',2',\ldots,k' \}$ . Then $f_0$ induces the matching from $\{1,2,\ldots,k\}$ to $\{1',2',\ldots,k' \}$ with $a \mapsto a'$ . Now the $k$ paths under $f_0$ starting from the male ends $\{1',2',\ldots,k' \}$ must eventually arrive at female ends $\{1,2,\ldots,k\}$ . Define the return matching $\hat{g}$ by $\hat{g}(a')=b$ if the path starting from the male end $a'$ first arrives at the female end $b$ . This return matching $\hat{g}$ is the same under all logics ${f^{*}}$ with $({{f^{*}}},\boldsymbol{{e}}) \in [(f_0,\boldsymbol{{e}})]$ .

Finally, for $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}}) \in H$ ,

(47) \begin{equation} \pi _f \textrm{ relativized to } \{e_1,\ldots,e_k\} = \hat{g} \circ g, \end{equation}

and of course, on each toggle class

\begin{equation*} {d_{\textit {TV}}}( \hat {g} \circ g, \text {uniform}({\mathcal {S}}_k)) = {d_{\textit {TV}}}( g, \text {uniform}({\mathcal {S}}_k)). \end{equation*}

With hindsight, we observe that the estimates of this section, and the previous Section 4.9, have enabled us to dodge a very difficult consideration of interlacement (of the $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ and $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_1$ ); see [Reference Arratia, Bollobás and Sorkin5] for a study of interlacement.

5. Sampling with $k$ starts, to prove poisson–Dirichlet convergence

5.1. Background, and notation, for flat random permutations

An overall reference for the following material and history is [Reference Arratia, Barbour and Tavaré3]. For a random permutation in ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ , with all $k!$ possible permutations equally likely, for j = 1,2,…, let

\begin{equation*} L_j \equiv L_j(k) \;:\!=\; \text {size of }j\text {-th longest cycle} \end{equation*}

with $L_j = 0$ if the permutation has fewer than $j$ cycles, so that always $L_1(k)+L_2(k)+\cdots = k$ . The notation $L_j \equiv L_j(k)$ means that we consider the two notations equivalent, so that we can use either, depending on whether or not we wish to emphasise the parameter $k$ . Write

(48) \begin{equation} {\boldsymbol{{L}}} \equiv{\boldsymbol{{L}}}(k) \;:\!=\; (L_1(k),L_2(k),\cdots ), \ {\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}} \equiv{\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}}(k) \;:\!=\; \frac{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}(k)}{k}, \end{equation}

so that ${\overline{L}}_i \equiv{\overline{L}}_i(k) \;:\!=\; L_i/k$ . We use notation analogous to the above, systematically: boldface gives a process, and overline specifies normalising, so that the sum of the components is 1.

This paragraph, summarising the convoluted history of the limit distribution for the length of the longest cycle, begins with Dickman’s 1930 study of the largest prime factor of a random integer. Dickman proved that for each fixed $u \ge 1$ , $\Psi (x,x^{1/u})/x \to \rho (u)$ , where $\Psi (x,y)$ counts the $y$ -smooth integers from 1 to $x$ . The function $\rho$ is characterised by $\rho (u)=0$ for $u\lt 0$ , $\rho (u)=1$ for $0 \le u \le 1$ and for all $u$ , $u \rho (u)=\int _{u-1}^u \rho (t) \ dt$ . In modern language, writing $P^+ = P^+(x)$ for the largest prime factor of an random integer chosen from 1 to $\lfloor x \rfloor$ , Dickman’s result is that

(49) \begin{equation} \frac{\log P^+}{\log x} \to ^d X_1, \textrm{ where }{\mathbb{P}}(X_1 \le 1/u) = \rho (u) \textrm{ for } u \ge 1. \end{equation}

Later work by Goncharov (1944) and Shepp and Lloyd (1966) showed the corresponding result for random permutations, that for every fixed $u \ge 1$ , ${\mathbb{P}}(L_1(k) \lt k/u) \to \rho (u)$ . In modern language this is

(50) \begin{equation} L_1(k)/k \to ^d X_1, \textrm{ where }{\mathbb{P}}(X_1 \le 1/u) = \rho (u) \textrm{ for } u \ge 1. \end{equation}

The random variable $X_1$ appearing in (49) and (50) is the first coordinate of the Poisson–Dirichlet process; the second coordinate corresponds to the second largest prime factor, or second largest cycle length, and so on. For primes, the joint limit was proved by Billingsley (1972) [Reference Billingsley9], and for permutations, the joint limit was discussed by Vershik and Shmidt (1977) and Kingman (1977). In these early studies, the Poisson–Dirichlet process appears as the limit, but not in a form easily recognisable as either (54) or (55). A fun exercise for the reader would be to prove that the distribution of $X_1$ , as given by the cumulative distribution function in (49), together with the integral equation characterising $\rho$ , is the same as the distribution of $X_1$ as given by its density, which is the special case $k=1$ of (54). See [Reference Arratia2] for more on the Poisson–Dirichlet in relation to prime factorizations and [Reference Arratia, Barbour and Tavaré4] for more on the Poisson–Dirichlet in relation to flat random permutations.

Returning to the process of longest cycle lengths in (48), the joint distribution is most easily understood by taking the cycles in ‘age order’. Let

(51) \begin{equation} A_j \equiv A_j(k) \;:\!=\; \textrm{size of }j\textrm{-th eldest cycle}. \end{equation}

Our notation convention has already told the reader that ${\boldsymbol{{A}}} \equiv{\boldsymbol{{A}}}(k) \;:\!=\; (A_1(k),A_2(k),\cdots )$ , and that ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}(k)={\boldsymbol{{A}}}(k)/k$ . Here, the notion of age comes from canonical cycle notation: 1 is written as the start of the first (eldest) cycle, whose length is $A_1$ , then the smallest $i$ not on this first cycle is the start of the second cycle, whose length is $A_2$ , and so on — with $A_j \;:\!=\; 0$ if the permutation has fewer than $j$ cycles.Footnote 13 It is easy to see that $A_1$ is uniformly distributed in $\{1,2,\ldots,k\}$ , and for each $j=1,2,\ldots$ , if there are at least $j$ cycles, then

\begin{equation*} A_j(k)\text { is uniformly distributed in } \{1,2,\ldots,k-(A_1+\cdots +A_{j-1})\}. \end{equation*}

This very easily leads to a description of the limit proportions: with $U,U_1,U_2,\ldots$ independent, uniformly distributed in (0,1),

(52) \begin{equation} {\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}} \;:\!=\; \frac{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}(k)}{k} \to ^d ( (1-U_1), U_1(1-U_2), U_1 U_2(1-U_3),\ldots\!). \end{equation}

We write $\to ^d$ to denote convergence in distribution, and we note that $U =^d 1-U$ , where $=^d$ denotes equality in distribution. The distribution of the process on the right side of (52) is named GEM, after Griffiths [Reference Griffiths18], Engen [Reference Engen15] and McCloskey [Reference McCloskey20]; its construction is popularly referred to as ‘stick breaking’ although stick breaking in general allows $U$ to take any distribution on (0,1), not just the uniform.

Convergence of processes, such as (52) and (56), and our Theorem 1 and Lemmas 9 and 10, are instances of convergence for stochastic processes with values in $\mathbb{R}^\infty$ , with the usual compact-open topology, and as such, convergence of processes is equivalent to convergence to the finite-dimensional-distributions, of the first $r$ coordinates, for each $r=1,2,\ldots$ .

Define

\begin{equation*} \Delta = \{(x_1,x_2,\dots \!) \in [0,1]^\infty \;:\;x_1+x_2+\cdots =1\}. \end{equation*}

The (usual subspace) topology on $\Delta$ is the same as the metric topology from the $\ell _1$ distance,

(53) \begin{equation} d( (x_1,x_2,\dots \!), (y_1,y_2,\dots \!) ) = \sum | x_i - y_i|, \end{equation}

We write $\rm{\small{ RANK}}$ for the function on $\Delta$ which sorts, with largest first. An example shows some of the subtlety of the preceeding considerations: let $\boldsymbol{{e}}_i \in \Delta$ be the $i^{th}$ standard basis vector — all zeros apart from a 1 in the $i^{th}$ coordinate, and let $\textbf{0}$ be the all zeros vector. Note that $\textbf{0} \in [0,1]^\infty \setminus \Delta$ , and in the larger space $[0,1]^\infty$ , $\boldsymbol{{e}}_n \to \textbf{0}$ . But for $i \ne j, d(\boldsymbol{{e}}_i,\boldsymbol{{e}}_j)=1$ , and the sequence $\boldsymbol{{e}}_1,\boldsymbol{{e}}_2,\ldots$ does not converge in $\Delta$ . The closure of $\Delta$ is the compact set $\overline{\Delta } = \{(x_1,x_2,\dots ) \in [0,1]^\infty \;:\;x_1+x_2+\cdots \le 1\}$ , and $\rm{{\small RANK}}$ is also definedFootnote 14 on $\overline{\Delta }$ ; note that $\textbf{0} \in \overline{\Delta }$ , and our $\boldsymbol{{e}}_n$ example shows that $\rm{{\small RANK}}$ is not continuous on $\overline{\Delta }$ . Donnelly and Joyce, [Reference Donnelly and Joyce13, Proposition 4], proved that $\rm{{\small RANK}}$ is continuous on $\Delta$ , observing that ‘…in parts of the literature some of these results seem already to have been assumed’.

By definition, a random $(X_1,X_2,\ldots\!) \in \Delta$ is the Poisson–Dirichlet process, or has the Poisson–Dirichlet distribution,Footnote 15 PD, if for each $k=1,2,\ldots$ , the joint density of the first $k$ coordinates is given by

(54) \begin{equation} f_k(x_1,x_2,\ldots,x_k) = \frac{1}{x_1x_2 \cdots x_k} \ \rho \left ( \frac{1-x_1-\cdots -x_k}{x_k} \right ) \end{equation}

on the region $x_1 \gt x_2 \gt \cdots \gt x_k \gt 0$ and $x_1+\cdots +x_k \lt 1$ , and zero elsewhere. The Poisson–Dirchlet process may be constructed from the GEM process, which appeared on the right side of (52), by sorting, with

(55) \begin{equation} (X_1,X_2,\ldots\!) =^d{\rm{{\small RANK}}}(( (1-U_1),U_1(1-U_2),U_1 U_2(1-U_3),\ldots\!) ). \end{equation}

For the process of largest cycle lengths in a random permutation, (48), the combination of the easy-to-see limit (52), and the continuity of RANK, and the characterisation (55) of the Poisson–Dirichlet distribution, proves that as $k \to \infty$ ,

(56) \begin{equation}{\overline{{\boldsymbol{{L}}}}}(k) \to ^d\textbf{X} \;:\!=\;(X_1,X_2,\ldots\!),\textrm{ with PD distribution}. \end{equation}

Our goal is to derive a new tool for proving the same PD convergence as in (56), but for non uniform permutations, such as those arising from a random FSR. It might benefit the reader to jump ahead a little, and read the statement of Lemma 10, and then the more technical Lemma 9, which has the meat of the argument used to prove Lemma 10. We have stated Lemma 9 in a fairly general form, hoping that it may be useful in the context of other combinatorial structures, and perhaps with limits other than the Poisson–Dirichlet.

5.2. The partition sampling lemma

Lemma 9. First, suppose that for each $N$ along a sequence of $N$ tending to $\infty$ we have a random set partition $\pi$ on $[N] \;:\!=\;\{1,2,\ldots,N\}$ . Let $M_j \equiv M_j(N)$ be the size of the $j$ -th largest block of $\pi$ , with $M_j \;:\!=\;0$ for $j$ greater than the number of blocks of $\pi$ , so that $M_1+M_2+\cdots = N$ . Let ${\boldsymbol{{M}}}(N)=(M_1(N),M_2(N),\ldots\!)$ and let ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}}(N)=M(N)/N$ .

Next, for each $k \ge 1$ , take an ordered sample of size $k$ , with replacement, from $[N]$ , with all $N^k$ possible outcomes equally likely. Such a sample picks out an ordered $($ by first appearance $)$ list of blocks of $\pi$ , say $\beta _1,\dots,\beta _r$ , with $r \le k$ . Let $C_j \equiv C_j(N,k)$ be the number of elements of the $k$ -sample landing in the block $\beta _j$ , with $C_j \;:\!=\; 0$ for $j\gt r$ , so that $C_1+C_2+\cdots = k$ . Let ${\boldsymbol{{C}}} \equiv{\boldsymbol{{C}}}(N,k) = (C_1,C_2,\ldots\!)$ .

Finally, let ${\boldsymbol{{X}}} = (X_1,X_2,\ldots\!)$ be any random element of $\Delta$ , with $X_1 \ge X_2 \cdots \ge 0$ , and let ${\boldsymbol{{A}}}(k) \;:\!=\; (A_1(k),A_2(k),\cdots )$ be any random elements of $\mathbb{Z}_+^\infty$ for which $A_1(k)+A_2(k)+\cdots =k$ , and such that ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}(k) \;:\!=\;{\boldsymbol{{A}}}(k)/k$ has

(57) \begin{equation} \textrm{ as } k \to \infty, \ \ \ {\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}(k)) \to ^d{\boldsymbol{{X}}}. \end{equation}

Then, if for each fixed $k$ , as $N \to \infty$ , we have

(58) \begin{equation} {\boldsymbol{{C}}}(N,k) \to ^d{\boldsymbol{{A}}}(k), \end{equation}

it follows that

\begin{equation*} \text { as } N \to \infty, \ \ \ {\overline {{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}}(N) \to ^d {\boldsymbol{{X}}}. \end{equation*}

Proof. Here is an outline of our proof. We begin with an analysis of ‘sampling using $k$ probes’, leading to (61), which gets coordinatewise nearness, with exceptional probability O( $1/k)$ , uniformly over set partitions, which are indexed by $N$ . This is the crux of our proof; the remainder is similar to Donnelly and Joyce, [Reference Donnelly and Joyce13, Proposition 4], on the continuity of RANK. For an overview, with $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}$ defined in the following paragraph, and writing whp to mean ‘with high probability’, and $\doteq$ to mean ‘approximately equals, in $\ell _1$ ’:

\begin{equation*} {\boldsymbol{{X}}} \ (\text {by } 57) \doteq \textit {whp }\, {\rm {{\small RANK}}}({\overline {{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}) \ (\text {by } 58) = \textit {whp }\, {\rm {{\small RANK}}}({\overline {{\boldsymbol{{C}}}}}) = {\rm {{\small RANK}}}({\overline {{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}) \doteq \textit {whp }\, {\rm {{\small RANK}}}({\overline {{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}}) = {\overline {{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}}. \end{equation*}

Write the blocks of $\pi$ as $b_1,b_2,\ldots$ , listed in nonincreasing order of size, so that $M_i = |b_i|$ . Write $p_i \;:\!=\; M_i/N$ , so that ${\boldsymbol{{p}}} \;:\!=\; (p_1,p_2,\ldots\!) \equiv{\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}}$ is a random probability distribution on the positive integers. Let $D_j$ be the number of elements of the $k$ -sample in $b_j$ ; the lists $C_1,C_2,\ldots$ and $D_1,D_2,\ldots$ represent the same multiset, apart from rearrangement, so that

(59) \begin{equation} {\rm{{\small RANK}}}( (C_1,C_2,\ldots\!) ) ={\rm{{\small RANK}}}( (D_1,D_2,\ldots\!) ). \end{equation}

Write ${\boldsymbol{{D}}} \equiv{\boldsymbol{{D}}}(N,k) \;:\!=\; (D_1,D_2,\ldots\!)$ , and ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}} \equiv{\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}(N,k) \;:\!=\;{\boldsymbol{{D}}}/k$ , so that ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}=({\overline{D}}_1,{\overline{D}}_2,\ldots\!)$ and ${\overline{D}}_i = D_i/k$ .

Conditional on the value of $\boldsymbol{{p}}$ , the joint distribution of $(D_1,D_2,\ldots\!)$ is exactly Multinomial $(k,{\boldsymbol{{p}}})$ . We want to establish a form of uniformity for the convergence of ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}(k)$ to $\boldsymbol{{p}}$ . The first step is to recall the usual proof that for Binomial sampling, with a sample of size $k$ and true parameter $p \in [0,1]$ , the sample mean $\hat{p}$ converges to the true parameter $p$ — because the proof provides a quantitative bound. Specifically, Chebyshev’s inequality gets used, with

(60) \begin{align}{\mathbb{P}}( | \hat{p}-p | \ge \delta ) &={\mathbb{P}}( (\hat{p}-p)^2 \ge \delta ^2) \nonumber \\[5pt] & \le \frac{{\mathbb{E}\,} (\hat{p}-p)^2}{ \delta ^2} \nonumber \\[5pt] & = \frac{{\textrm{Var }} \hat{p}}{\delta ^2}\nonumber {}\\[5pt] & = \frac{p(1-p)}{k \delta ^2}\nonumber \\[5pt] & \le \frac{p}{k \delta ^2 }. \end{align}

In particular, conditional on any value for $\boldsymbol{{p}}$ , for $i=1,2,\ldots$ , with $p_i ={\overline{M}}_i = M_i(N)/N$ in the role of $p$ for (60),

\begin{equation*} {\mathbb {P}}(|{\overline {D}}_i-{\overline {M}}_i| \ge \delta \, | \, (p_1,p_2,\ldots\!)) \le \frac {p_i}{k \delta ^2 }. \end{equation*}

Hence, taking expectation to remove the conditioning on $\boldsymbol{{p}}$ , and then using $\sum _i p_i=1$ to analyse the union bound, we have a good event $G$ (proximity in $\ell _\infty$ ) whose complement

(61) \begin{equation} G^c \;:\!=\; ( \exists i, |{\overline{D}}_i-{\overline{M}}_i| \ge \delta ) \ \ \textrm{ has }{\mathbb{P}}(G^c) \le \frac{1}{k \delta ^2 }. \end{equation}

For ${\boldsymbol{{x}}} \in \Delta$ , $j \ge 1$ write $S_j({\boldsymbol{{x}}})$ for the sum of the $j$ largest coordinates of $\boldsymbol{{x}}$ . Obviously

(62) \begin{equation} \textrm{ for } \omega \in G, \ \ S_j({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}}) \ge S_j({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}) - j \, \delta . \end{equation}

Let $\varepsilon \gt 0$ be given and fixed for the remainder of this proof.

Let

(63) \begin{equation} R(j,\varepsilon ) \;:\!=\; \{{\boldsymbol{{y}}} = (y_1,y_2,\ldots\!) \in \Delta \;:\;{\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\boldsymbol{{y}}}) ={\boldsymbol{{x}}} =(x_1,x_2,\dots ) \textrm{ has } x_1+\cdots +x_j \gt 1-\varepsilon \}, \end{equation}

the set of points in $\Delta$ where some set of $j$ coordinates sums to more than $1-\varepsilon$ . Note that $R(j,\varepsilon )$ is invariant under permutations of the coordinates, including $\rm{{\small RANK}}$ . Since $\Delta = \cup _j R(j,\varepsilon )$ , and $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ from (57) is a random element of $\Delta$ , there exists $j=j(\varepsilon ) \ge 1$ , depending on the distribution of $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ , such that

(64) \begin{equation} {\mathbb{P}}({\boldsymbol{{X}}} \in R(j,\varepsilon )) \gt 1- \varepsilon ; \end{equation}

fix such a value for $j$ . [When used in Lemma 10, where the distribution of $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ is Poisson–Dirichlet, (55) can be used to show that the minimal such $j$ is asympotically $\log (1/\varepsilon )$ .]

Using the hypothesis (57), and observing that $R(j,\varepsilon )$ is an open set, (the open set part of the Portmanteau Theorem on weak convergence implies that) we can pick and fix a finite $k_0$ such that for all $k \ge k_0$ ,

(65) \begin{equation} {\mathbb{P}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}(k) \in R(j,\varepsilon )) \gt 1- \varepsilon . \end{equation}

Using the hypothesis (57) again, we can pick and fix a finite $k_1 \ge k_0$ such that for each $k \ge k_1$ , there exists a coupling (see Dudley [Reference Dudley14], Real Analysis and Probability, Corollary 11.6.4) such that the $\ell _1$ distance has

(66) \begin{equation} {\mathbb{P}}( d({\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}(k)),{\boldsymbol{{X}}} ) \ge \varepsilon ) \lt \varepsilon . \end{equation}

Next, intending to use (61) with $\varepsilon/j$ used in the role of $\delta$ , the upper bound is $1/(k \delta ^2) = j^2/(k \varepsilon ^2)$ . To have this upper bound be at most $\varepsilon$ , and also be able to apply (66), we take $k$ to be the maximum of $k_1$ and the ceiling of $ j^2/ \varepsilon ^3$ .

The value $k$ has been fixed, in the previous paragraph. Now, the convergence in hypothesis (58) involves the topologically discrete space $\mathbb{Z}_+^k$ , so the distributional convergence can be metrized by the total variation distance, hence there exists a finite $N_0(k)$ such that for all $N \ge N_0(k)$ , the total variation distance between distributions is at most $\varepsilon$ , and there exists a coupling with

\begin{equation*} {\mathbb {P}}( {\boldsymbol{{C}}}(N,k) \ne {\boldsymbol{{A}}}(k) ) \le \varepsilon . \end{equation*}

Of course this same coupling and exceptional event yields ${\mathbb{P}}({\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{C}}}}}) \ne{\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}) ) \le \varepsilon$ , and using also (65),

\begin{equation*} {\mathbb {P}}({\rm {{\small RANK}}}( {\overline {{\boldsymbol{{C}}}}}) = {\rm {{\small RANK}}}({\overline {{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}) \text { and } {\overline {{\boldsymbol{{C}}}}}(N,k) \in R(j,\varepsilon )) \gt 1-2 \varepsilon . \end{equation*}

But then (59), and the permutation invariance of $R(j,\varepsilon )$ converts the above into

(67) \begin{equation} {\mathbb{P}}({\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}) ={\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}}) \textrm{ and }{\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}(N,k) \in R(j,\varepsilon )) \gt 1-2 \varepsilon . \end{equation}

Next, observe that ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}(N,k) \in R(j,\varepsilon )$ and $G$ from (61) with $\delta = \varepsilon/j$ imply that, each of the $j$ indices $i$ for ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}(N,k) \in R(j,\varepsilon )$ has $|M_i - D_i| \lt \delta$ , so the sum of those $j$ coordinates of $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}$ is at least $S_j({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}) - j \, \delta = S_j({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}) - \varepsilon \gt 1 - 2 \varepsilon$ (as observed in (62))), and the sum of the other (outside the chosen $j$ ) coordinates of $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}$ is at most $2 \varepsilon$ , while the sum of the other (outside the chosen $j$ ) coordinates of $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}$ is at most $\varepsilon$ . Hence, the $\ell _1$ distance is at most $4 \varepsilon$ , accounted for by $j \delta = \varepsilon$ , from the $|M_i - D_i|$ with $i$ among the chosen $j$ , plus $2 \varepsilon + \varepsilon$ using $ |M_i - D_i| \le M_i + D_i$ on the other coordinates, outside the chosen $j$ . This result was that $d({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}},{\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}) \lt 4 \varepsilon$ . Now ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}} ={\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}})$ by construction, but due to sampling noise, maybe ${\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}} \ne{\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}})$ . However, since $\rm{{\small RANK}}$ is a contraction, we have $d({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}},{\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}})) \lt 4 \varepsilon$ .

Putting it all together, for any $N \ge N_0$ , the union of the exceptional events from (61) ( $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}$ near $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}$ , coordinatewise, with ${\mathbb{P}}(G^c) \le \varepsilon$ ), from (66) ( ${\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}})$ near $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ ), and from (67) ( $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}$ equals ${\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}})$ , in $R(j,\varepsilon )$ ) has probability at most $4 \varepsilon$ , and outside this exceptional event, $\overline{{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}$ is at most $4 \varepsilon$ away from ${\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{D}}}}}) ={\rm{{\small RANK}}}({\overline{{\boldsymbol{{A}}}}})$ , which in turn is at most $\varepsilon$ away from $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ . In summary, there are couplings so that

\begin{equation*} \forall N \ge N_0, \ {\mathbb {P}}( d({\overline {{\boldsymbol{{M}}}}},{\boldsymbol{{X}}}) \gt 5 \varepsilon ) \lt 4 \varepsilon . \end{equation*}

5.3. The permutation version of the sampling lemma

Lemma 10. Suppose that for a sequence of $N$ tending to $\infty$ we have a random permutation $\pi$ on $[N] \;:\!=\;\{1,2,\ldots,N\}$ . Let $M_j \equiv M_j(N)$ be the size of the $j$ -th largest cycle of $\pi$ , with $M_j \;:\!=\;0$ for $j$ greater than the number of cycles of $\pi$ , so that $M_1+M_2+\cdots = N$ .

Given $k \ge 1$ , take an ordered sample of size $k$ , with replacement, from $[N]$ , that is, $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ with all $N^k$ possible outcomes equally likely. Let $\sigma$ be $\pi$ relativised to $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ , as defined at the start of Section 4.10.

Now suppose that, for each fixed $k \ge 1$ ,

(68) \begin{equation} \forall \tau \in{\mathcal{S}}_k, \ \textrm{ as } N \to \infty, \ \ {\mathbb{P}}(\sigma = \tau ) \to 1/k! . \end{equation}

Then, as $N \to \infty$ ,

(69) \begin{equation} (M_1(N)/N,M_2(N)/N,\ldots\!) \to ^d{\boldsymbol{{X}}} =(X_1,X_2,\ldots\!), \end{equation}

where $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ has the Poisson–Dirichlet distribution, as in (55) and (56).

Proof. Take the processes ${\boldsymbol{{A}}}(k)$ of cycle lengths, in age order, as given by (51), for uniform random permutations in ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ , to serve as the random elements in the hypotheses (57) and (58) of Lemma 9. This requires using the Poisson–Dirichlet distribution, for $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ in (57).

Fix $k$ . Then (68) holding for each $\tau \in{\mathcal{S}}_k$ implies that the distribution of $\sigma$ is close, in total variation distance, to the uniform distribution on ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ . On the event, of probability $\frac{N-1}{N} \cdots \frac{N-(k-1)}{N} \to 1$ , that the $k$ -sample with replacement from the $N$ population has $k$ distinct elements, the counts $C(N,k)$ from Lemma 9 agree exactly with the cycle lengths in $\sigma$ . Hence hypothesis (68) implies the hypothesis (58).

6. Putting it all together: The Proof of Theorem 1

We now have established all the ingredients needed for our proof of Theorem 1. First, the conclusion (4) of Theorem 1 is exactly the conclusion (69) from Lemma 10.Footnote 16 To prove Theorem 1, it only remains to establish that the random FSR model (3) satisfies the hypothesis (68) of Lemma 10.

Fix $k$ for use in (68). The uniform choice of $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}}) \in S_{n,k}$ determines $\pi _f$ and the random sample $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ — for convenience in Lemma 10 we labelled the set $\mathbb{F}_2^n$ with the integers 1,2, $\ldots,N$ . Let an arbitrary $\varepsilon \gt 0$ be given. Fix $m = m(k,\varepsilon )$ as per Lemma 7, so that with high probability, a random schedule of length $m$ over the alphabet of size $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ is $\varepsilon$ -good.

We will take $t=N^{.6}$ , recalling that $N=2^n$ . By Theorem 6, for sufficiently large $n$ , on a good event $G_{(k,t)}$ of probability at least $1-\varepsilon$ , the two-dimensional process ${\boldsymbol{{X}}}^{(v)}$ of indicators of vertex repeats, in ${\textrm{Seg}}(f,e_1,k(t+n))$ , agrees with the two-dimensional process $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ of indicators of leftmost $(n-1)$ -tuple repeats for coin tossing; and cutting, to produce $\boldsymbol{{e}}$ and $k$ segments, causes no unwanted side effects. Then, by the Chen–Stein method as given by Theorem 3 of [Reference Arratia, Goldstein and Gordon6] (with a survey of applications to sequence repeats given by Section 5 of [Reference Arratia, Goldstein and Gordon7], and details for the sequence repeats problem given in (39)–(40) of [Reference Arratia, Martin, Reinert and Waterman8]), for sufficiently large $n$ the total variation distance between $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ and ${\boldsymbol{{X}}}'$ is at most $\varepsilon$ , where ${\boldsymbol{{X}}}'$ has the same marginals as $\boldsymbol{{X}}$ , but all coordinates mutually independent. Combined, the total variation distance between ${\boldsymbol{{X}}}^{(v)}$ and ${\boldsymbol{{X}}}'$ is arbitrarily small, at most $2 \varepsilon$ .

The indicator of the happy event $H$ is a functional of the process ${\boldsymbol{{X}}}^{(v)}$ , so we can approximate ${\mathbb{P}}(H)$ , with an additive error of at most $2 \varepsilon$ , by evaluating the same functional, applied to ${\boldsymbol{{X}}}'$ . The required estimates for this independent process are routine, via computations of the expected number of arrivals in various regions as in Section 4,Footnote 17 and we have already provided most of the details, in discussing (32) and (34). Additionally, one must check that the schedule resulting from use of (40) is close, in total variation distance, to the flat random choice in the hypothesis of Lemma 7; we omit the relatively easy details.

To summarise, we picked $k$ for use in Lemma 10, then fixed an arbitrary $\varepsilon \gt 0$ , then picked $m$ via Lemma 7.Footnote 18 For large $n$ , the process of vertex repeats among the $k$ segments of length $t$ is controlled, via comparison of ${{\boldsymbol{{X}}}^{(v)}},{\boldsymbol{{X}}},{{\boldsymbol{{X}}}'}$ , showing that most $(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})$ lie in $H$ , and furthermore, the event $H^* \equiv H^*(\varepsilon ) \subset H$ , that the chosen potential toggle vertices $v^{\#}_1,\ldots,v^{\#}_m$ pick out a $\varepsilon$ -good schedule, has ${\mathbb{P}}(H^*)\gt 1-4 \varepsilon$ . (Attributing $2 \varepsilon$ to ${d_{\textit{TV}}}({{\boldsymbol{{X}}}^{(v)}},{{\boldsymbol{{X}}}'})$ , $ \varepsilon$ to ${\mathbb{P}}(H^c)$ and $ \varepsilon$ to ${\mathbb{P}}(H \setminus H^*)$ .) Section 4.9 shows that, on $H^*$ , the settings of $f$ at its toggle vertices induce a nearly flat random matching between segment starts and ends, and (47) in Section 4.10 lifts this to show that $\pi _f$ relativised to $e_1,\ldots,e_k$ is a nearly flat random permutation in ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ . Thus the combination of Section 4.9 and 4.10 shows that, on $H^*$ , on each equivalence class $[(f,\boldsymbol{{e}})] \in H^*$ , the total variation distance to the uniform distribution on ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ is at most $\varepsilon$ . Hence, averaging over the classes in $H^*$ , and allowing distance 1 for the at most $4 \varepsilon$ of probability mass outside of $H^*$ , we get that for our fixed $k$ , for arbitrary $\varepsilon$ , for all sufficiently large $n$ , ${d_{\textit{TV}}}(\sigma,$ uniform $({\mathcal{S}}_k)) = \frac{1}{2} \sum _{\tau \in{\mathcal{S}}_k} |{\mathbb{P}}(\sigma = \tau ) - \frac{1}{k!}| \lt 5 \varepsilon$ , which establishes (68). This completes the proof.

Acknowledgments

We would like to acknowledge numerous helpful discussions with Danny Goldstein, Max Hankins and Jay-C Reyes. We are grateful to an anonymous and diligent referee.

Footnotes

1 A (stochastic) process is simply a collection of random variables, or, depending on one’s point of view, the joint distribution of that collection.

2 This same Poisson–Dirichlet process also gives the distributional limit for the process of scaled bit sizes of the prime factors of an integer chosen uniformly from 1 to $x$ , as $x$ goes to infinity. Here we write PD for PD $(1)$ , where, in general, GEM $(\theta )$ and PD $(\theta )$ for $\theta \gt 0$ are constructed using $U^{1/\theta }$ in place of $U$ , and the case $\theta =1/2$ gives the limits for the processes of sizes of largest components, in age order or strict size order, for random mappings, i.e., functions from $[n]$ to $[n]$ with all $n^n$ possibilities equally likely.

3 Since $U, U_1$ and $1-U_1$ all have the same distribution, uniform in $(0,1)$ .

4 This terminology means that the repeat cannot be extended on the left. The concept is standard in the literature, for example [Reference Aldous1] and [ Reference Arratia, Goldstein and Gordon7, p. 19].

5 I.e., words at Hamming distance 1, hence with our two-letter alphabet, words formed by complementing a single bit.

6 There are several interesting results in Maurer [Reference Maurer19] for cycles in de Bruijn graphs; one must be careful to think about the factor $2^{\pm r}$ in going back and forth between these estimates, and estimates for a random $\pi _f$ , corresponding to randomly resolved de Bruijn graphs.

7 Consider the simplest situation, $k=2$ and $m=1$ , where one is trying to prove (7) by showing that ${\mathbb{P}}(e_1,e_2$ lie on the same cycle) is approximately one half. Knowing that the segments starting from $e_1$ and $e_2$ have high probability of reaching a common vertex $v^{\#}$ , and that performing a cross-join step by toggling the logic $f$ at this $v^{\#}$ , to get a new logic ${f^{*}}$ , changes whether or not $e_1$ and $e_2$ lie on the same cycle, one might consider the proof complete. The fallacy is that this procedure does not pair up $f$ with ${f^{*}}$ , i.e., it need not be the case that $({{f^{*}}})^* = f$ , because the procedure used to find $v^{\#}$ (from $f$ , given $e_1,e_2$ ) might find a different $v$ when applied to ${f^{*}}$ . Overcoming this fallacy entails the study of displacements, starting in Sections 4.24.4.

8 More formally, the point at $(I,J)$ , labelled by the pair of colours ( $a$ ,red), in the coloured-spatial process of indicators of matches between segments under $f$ , corresponds to a point at $(I-d,J)$ in the coloured-spatial process for ${f^{*}}$ .

9 This jargon comes from queuing theory and Poisson arrival processes; we say there is an arrival at $(i,j)$ if the indicator indexed by $(i,j)$ takes the value 1, here indicating that there is an $(n-1)$ -tuple repeat.

10 The precise location doesn’t matter, but, using Section 3.10, the location is $(i_0,j_0)$ where $i_0 = i+(n+t)(a-1)$ and $j_0=j+(n+t)(b-1)$ .

11 such as $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)+k$ — for the intensity of arrivals in the superimposed process marking matches between two different colours or both within the same colour, and 16 — since a $4 \delta$ by $4 \delta$ square has area $16 \delta ^2$

12 This is a only a visualisation, and not a technical definition. Imagine $k$ strands of (directed) yarn, of different colours. They are all tangled up, but the start and end of each strand protrude from the tangle, so one has $2k$ protruding ends (one male, one female, in each colour). One only knows that inside the tangle, there are $m$ instances of two different coloured yarns being cut, and at each of these $m$ , both strands may be spliced back together in their original (no colour change) form, or else they may be cross-joined.

13 In contrast with permutations on $\{1,2,\ldots,N\}$ , similar to (51), where age order comes from the canonical cycle notation, for shift-register permutations $\pi _f$ , the oldest cycle is not the cycle containing the lex-first $n$ -tuple, $00\cdots 0$ . In fact, in a random FSR, the cycle starting from $00\cdots 0$ has exactly a one-half chance to have length 1. For permutations of a set lacking exchangeability, such as $\mathbb{F}_2^n$ , the notion of age order requires auxiliary randomisation: the oldest cycle is picked out by a random $n$ tuple; conditional on this cycle, with length $A_1\lt N$ , choose an $n$ tuple uniformly at random from the remaining $(N-A_1)$ $n$ -tuples not on the first cycle, to pick out the second oldest cycle, whose length is $A_2$ , and so on.

14 $\rm{{\small RANK}}$ is not defined on $[0,1]^\infty$ — for example ${\boldsymbol{{x}}} = (1/2,2/3,3/4,\ldots\!)$ does not have a largest coordinate.

15 This PD is PD(1); mathematical geneticists work with a family of distributions, PD( $\theta$ ), indexed by $\theta \in (0,\infty )$ .

16 There is a small shift of notation; in Section 5 we had to deal with both FSR permutations and flat random permutations. So in Section 5, instead of $\boldsymbol{{L}}$ for the process of largest FSR cycles lengths, $\boldsymbol{{M}}$ names the process of largest cycle lengths for an FSR permutation and $\boldsymbol{{L}}$ names the corresponding process for flat random permutations.

17 These arguments take two forms: 1) if the expected number of arrivals is small, specifically, less than $\delta$ , then the probability of (no arrivals) is large, specifically, greater than $1-\delta$ , and 2) if the expected number of arrivals is sufficiently large, specifically, some $\lambda \gt 1$ , and the indicators of arrivals are mutually independent, then the probability of (no arrivals) is small, specifically, at most $e^{-\lambda }$ . It is precisely the role of the Chen–Stein method to provide the required independence.

18 In a sense, Lemma 10 encapsulates a relation between an arbitrary $\varepsilon \gt 0$ , and $k$ , hiding the full programme: given $\varepsilon \gt 0$ to govern being close with high probability, pick a single $k$ large enough that the $k$ -sampled-and-relativized permutation being close to uniform in ${\mathcal{S}}_k$ would imply that the large cycle process for FSR permutation is close to the PD, then pick a single $m$ to work for this $k$ and $\varepsilon$ , then finally pick $n_0$ , the notion of sufficiently large $n$ , to work for this $k,m$ and $\varepsilon$ . The briefest summary is: given $\varepsilon$ , pick $k$ , then $m$ , then $n_0$ .

References

Aldous, D. (1989) Probability Approxiations via the Poisson Clumping Heuristic, Applied Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 77. Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arratia, R. A. (2002) On the amount of dependence in the prime factorization of a uniform random integer. In Contemporary Combinatorics, Vol. 10, Bolyai Soc. Math. Stud. János Bolyai Math. Soc., pp. 2991.Google Scholar
Arratia, R. A., Barbour, A. D. and Tavaré, S. (2003) Logarithmic Combinatorial Structures: a Probabilistic Approach. European Mathematical Society (EMS) Zurich.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arratia, R. A., Barbour, A. D. and Tavaré, S. (2006) A tale of three couplings: Poisson-Dirichlet and GEM approximations for random permutations. Combin. Probab. Comput. 15(1-2) 3162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arratia, R. A., Bollobás, B. and Sorkin, G. B. (2004) The interlace polynomial of a graph. J. Combin. Th. Ser. B. 92(2) 199233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arratia, R. A., Goldstein, L. M. and Gordon, L. I. (1989) Two moments suffice for Poisson approximation: the Chen-Stein method. Ann. Probab. 17(1) 925.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arratia, R. A., Goldstein, L. M. and Gordon, L. I. (1990) Poisson approximation and the Chen-Stein method. Stat. Sci. 5(4) 403434.Google Scholar
Arratia, R. A., Martin, D., Reinert, G. and Waterman, M. S. (2009) Poisson process approximation for sequence repeats, and sequencing by hybridization. J. Computat. Biol. 3(3) 425463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Billingsley, P. (1972) On the distribution of large prime divisors. Period. Math. Hung. 2(1-4) 283289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coppersmith, D., Rhoades, R. and VanderKam, J. Counting de Bruijn sequences as perturbations of linear recursions, to appear, https://arxiv.org/abs/1705.07835 Google Scholar
Diaconis, P. (1988) Group Representations in Probability and Statistics. Institute of Mathematical Studies.Google Scholar
Diaconis, P. and Shahshahani, M. (1981) Generating a random permutation with random transpositions. Z. Wahrsch. Verw. Gebiete 57(2) 159179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnelly, P. and Joyce, P. (1989) Continuity and weak convergence of ranked and size-biased permutations on the infinite simplex. Stochastic Process. Appl. 31(1) 89103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dudley, R. M. (2002) Real Analysis and Probability, Vol. 74. Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics . Cambridge University Press, Revised reprint of the 1989 original.Google Scholar
Engen, S. (1975) A note on the geometric series as a species frequency model. Biometrika 62(3) 697699.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Golomb, S. W. (1967) Shift Register Sequences. Holden Day, Inc. With portions co-authored by Lloyd R. Welch, Richard M. Goldstein, and Alfred W. Hales.Google Scholar
Golomb, S. W., Welch, L. R. and Goldstein, R. M. (1959) Cycles from Nonlinear Feedback Shift Registers, Progress Report. Jet Propulsion Laboratory, California Institute for Technology.Google Scholar
Griffiths, R. C. (1979) On the distribution of allele frequencies in a diffusion model. Theoret. Populat. Biol. 15(1) 140158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maurer, U. M. (1992) Asymptotically tight bounds on the number of cycles in generalized de Bruijn-Good graphs. Discr. Appl. Math. 37 421436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, J. W. (1965) A Model for the Distribution of Individuals by Species in An Environment, PhD thesis. Michigan State University. Google Scholar
Wolfram, S. and Golomb, S. (1932–2016) Available at https://writings.stephenwolfram.com/2016/05/solomon-golomb-19322016/.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. An example, one segment of length 290, where there are three leftmost $(n-1)$-tuple repeats, at (56,153), (120,260) and (135,175).

Figure 1

Figure 2. The same example: one segment of length 290, where there are three leftmost $(n-1)$-tuple repeats, at locations (56,153), (120,260) and (135,175). Now, the locations are plotted in standard Cartesian coordinates.

Figure 2

Figure 3. Coloring. An example, with $k=3$, $n=10,t=90$. The same one segment of length 290, as in Figure 1, where there are three leftmost $(n-1)$-tuple repeats, at (56,153), (120,260) and (135,175). Now the first segment is coloured red, the second yellow and the third blue.

Figure 3

Figure 4. Coloring and cutting; a succinct way to visualise both. The $k$ segments of length $t$ are still shown as they appear along the single segment of length $k(t+n)-n$. We also show the $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$$t$ by $t$ squares where matches may occur between two differently coloured length $t$ segments. Note the repeat at (56,153) is a vertex coloured both red and yellow, hence orange. The repeat at (120,260) is a vertex coloured both yellow and blue, hence green. The vertex at (135,175) is coloured yellow twice - we could show it as an extra-saturated yellow but did not. The significance of the diagonals of the small squares is explained in Section 4.3.

Figure 4

Figure 5. Take $n=34$, $N=2^n$ and $t=3 \times (n+N^{.6})-n$. The expected number of leftmost $(n-1)$-tuple repeats is about $\left(\substack{t \\[3pt] 2}\right)/N\doteq 501.4$. The picture shows 500 ‘arrival’ points, giving the locations of repeats, plotted as for one segment of long length $t$. In each $N^{.6}$ by $N^{.6}$ square, the expected number of points is $N^{.2}\doteq 111.4$. The colour scheme is intended to be purple, green, blue across the top row, orange, yellow for the middle and red (magenta) for the bottom.

Figure 5

Figure 6. About 333 of the 500 occurrences of repeats from Figure 5, but now viewed as among $k=3$ segments of length $t=N^{.6}\doteq 1.38 \times 10^6$. The $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$$t$ by $t$ above-diagonal squares from Figure 5 are superimposed, so the expected number of points is about $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right) \times N^{.2}\doteq 334.3$. The approximately 167.1 repeats where both occurrences lie in the same segment, corresponding to the $k$ right triangles hugging the diagonal in Figure 5, are not shown. In Section 4.5 we discuss this picture, suggesting scaling for the axes, so that in each colour, the picture is approximately a standard (rate 1 per unit area) two-dimensional Poisson process. The colour scheme is intended to be purple, green, orange.

Figure 6

Figure 7. Toggling. An example with $t=90$ and displacement $d=3$. The same repeat as shown in Figure 3 with location (56,153) and shown by the orange dot in Figure 4. When all $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ squares are superimposed, as in Figure 6, the spatial location becomes $(i,j)=(56,53)$. Before the toggle, we have two segments of length $t=90$; after the toggle, the segments have length $t \pm d$, that is, 93 and 87.

Figure 7

Figure 8. Toggling. This is a continuation of the example in Figure 7, with one repeat with location (56,153), shown by the orange dot in Figure 4. When all $\left(\substack{k \\[3pt] 2}\right)$ squares are superimposed, as in Figure 6, the spatial location becomes $(i,j)=(56,53)$. Now suppose there were an additional repeat, (which would have been shown by a red dot at (53,58) in Figure 4,) shown here in Figure 8 by the pair of red dots for $f$. After the toggle at the orange vertex, vertex 53, along the segment that starts red and finishes yellow, is the same as vertex 55, along the segment that start yellow and finishes red. So, in the logic ${f^{*}}$, we have two matches between the two segments: the original, at (56,53), shown by the orange dots, and a new one, at (53,55), shown by the red dots.

Figure 8

Figure 9. With starting edges $e_1,e_2,e_3$, three segments under the logic $f$ are shown in the top part of the display; the red and yellow segments share a vertex $v^{\#}_1$, coloured orange, early on, the red and blue segments share a vertex $v^{\#}_2$, coloured purple, at a intermediate time, and the yellow and blue segments share a vertex $v^{\#}_3$, coloured green, at a late time. We take ${{f^{*}}}={\textrm{Toggle}}(f,\{v^{\#}_1 \})$ and ${{f^{**}}}={\textrm{Toggle}}(f,\{v^{\#}_1,v^{\#}_2 \})$ to be the logics formed by toggling at $v^{\#}_1$, and at both $v^{\#}_1$ and $v^{\#}_2$. The middle part of the display shows the three segments under ${f^{*}}$, and the bottom part of the display shows the three segments under ${f^{**}}$.

Figure 9

Figure 10. Displacements caused by a single toggle. An example with $t=90$, and three colours, red, yellow, and blue. Say the toggle is at $v^{\#}_2$ occurring at (red,blue) time $(35,40)$, similar to the purple vertex at ($35,37)$ in Figure 9, but with the displacement changed from −2 to −5, for the sake of being easier to see in the two-dimensional picture. We have thrown in several more matches between two different colours, at various earlier and later times, to show the resulting two-dimensional displacements. Red vertices at times greater than 35 have their time increased by 5, and blue vertices at times greater than 40 have their time decreased by 5. Two-dimensional match locations are indicated by a solid circle for the logic $f$ and an open circle for the logic ${f^{*}}$.