American liberals may demand an end to excessive violence against Latinx migrants and refugees . . . but they rarely locate immigration and border policies within broader systemic forces. A long arc of dirty colonial coups, capitalist trade agreements extracting land and labor, climate change, and enforced oppression is the primary driver of displacement from Mexico and Central America. Migration is a predictable consequence of these displacements, yet today the US is fortifying its border against the very people impacted by its own policies. Analyzing the border as part of historic and contemporary imperial relations . . . forces a shift from notions of charity and humanitarianism to restitution, reparations, and responsibility. —Harsha Walia
Border and Rule Footnote 1That sovereign nation-states have the right to exclude most nonmembers is largely assumed in both popular political discourse and mainstream political and legal theory; Joseph Carens has aptly dubbed this “the conventional moral view on immigration.”Footnote 2 The ubiquity of this view means that it is often treated as obvious rather than argued for,Footnote 3 but the political thinkers who do argue for it often stress its deep normative import, portraying a nation's control over its borders as indispensable to collective self-determination and so as constituting a core pillar of democratic political sovereignty. Accordingly, as E. Tendayi Achiume suggests, both “the governing law and the dominant ethics that underpin it” view the barring of outsiders as “not only permissible but even righteous as a matter of sovereign self-determination.”Footnote 4
The conventional view has remained hegemonic in the face of strong philosophical criticism.Footnote 5 Yet emerging realities are now raising pressing questions about states’ broad discretion over immigration, as well as the understanding of sovereignty to which it is conceptually bound.Footnote 6 Foremost among these new realitiesFootnote 7 is the increasingly consequential phenomenon of climate-related displacement and migration. Although the links between climate change and human movement are complex and context dependent,Footnote 8 studies suggest that climate change already centrally contributes to the displacement of tens of millions of people each year,Footnote 9 and is likely to contribute to the displacement of many millions more in the coming decades.Footnote 10 The repercussions of this dynamic have not yet been adequately integrated into the wider political theory literature,Footnote 11 but several normative theorists of mobility and migration have begun to articulate its potential import for immigration ethics.Footnote 12 The argument I develop here adds to this growing body of literature by probing the limits of the conventional view—as well as some of its critical counterparts—in dealing with certain instances of climate-related displacement and migration. Specifically, I will attempt to show that many climate migrants are owed admission as reparation for injustice, and that the character of this injustice raises broader challenges for the conventional view.
In making this argument, I build on another conviction that is widely held in political theory (even by proponents of the conventional view)—namely, that states do not have an equally broad right to exclude those whose displacement they have precipitated. This idea also has intuitive appeal in mainstream political discourse. For instance, in response to Joe Biden and Kamala Harris threatening Central American migrants with removal under the Trump-era Title 42 expulsion (which bypassed due process for asylum seekers under the pretext of “public health”), Congresswoman Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez recently asserted that “we can't help set someone's house on fire and then blame them for fleeing.”Footnote 13
Ocasio-Cortez's statement, which made national headlines and was shared widely across social media, pointed specifically to the U.S. history of economic and political destabilization in Central America and did not discuss climate change. However, the Central American Dry Corridor (encompassing parts of Guatemala, El Salvador, Nicaragua, and Honduras)Footnote 14 from which many of today's asylum seekers and “irregular migrants” originate is highly vulnerable to climate impacts.Footnote 15 In 2020 alone, the region “experienced more than one and a half million new displacements driven by disasters”Footnote 16 such as hurricanes and landslides, with roughly the same number of people again facing urgent food insecurity as a result of prolonged drought and crop failure.Footnote 17 It is well documented that these impacts have led to increased cross-border migration; for example, an internal report by the U.S. Customs and Border Protection agency found that “the overwhelming factor behind the recent record migration from Guatemala was a crop shortage that left citizens impoverished and starving”Footnote 18 after a record five-year drought. Furthermore, the literature on climate justice stresses that vulnerability to climate change is inextricable from and consistently compounds the historical harms of colonialism and imperialism to which Congresswoman Ocasio-Cortez refersFootnote 19 (in some instances even rendering her fire metaphor tragically literal). Given the outsized contribution of the United States to global heating, attention to the climate-driven dimension of migration should considerably strengthen her basic point.
Below, I expand on the idea that we cannot set someone's house on fire and then punish them for fleeing, by exploring the ethics of climate-related displacement and migration from the Dry Corridor to the United States. While the conventional view assumes that such state-sponsored “arson” is relatively rare, I argue that an investigation into the roots of climate-related migration from this region will show it to be the norm, suggesting the need for a different framing. The basic structure of the argument is as follows: After a few brief notes concerning scope and methodology, I begin by considering how influential proponents of the conventional view such as Michael Walzer, Christopher Wellman, and David Miller attempt to ground states’ right to exclude migrants. I then weigh the merits of several climate-centered challenges to this view. Next, I explore how the harms of U.S. policy continue to decisively shape migration from the Dry Corridor to the United States, suggesting more extensive reparative duties toward a greater proportion of these claimants than is ordinarily supposed. After briefly considering and responding to potential objections, I conclude by gesturing toward some of the wider implications of this argument, contending that the character of the injustices involved and the scope and scale of the requisite reparative response raise deeper questions about the adequacy of the conventional view.
Brief Notes on Rhetorical Strategy and Terminology
The argument laid out below is deliberately limited in several respects. First, I do not directly defend the free movement of displaced or dispossessed people on the grounds of universal principles, although I am sympathetic to such arguments. Instead, I aim to demonstrate that even if we rhetorically accept the conventional view's tenets, attending to the harms driving actual instances of climate migration will greatly weaken some receiving states’ claims to justifiable exclusion. Critics of immigration restriction might worry that this argument concedes too much to the status quo. However, as discussed further below, there are good reasons to begin with this type of contextual approach. More abstract arguments for the rights of climate refugees based on self-determination,Footnote 20 common ownership of the Earth,Footnote 21 or a human right to a livable localeFootnote 22 may be well grounded, but they may also be less compelling for many audiences than an account that foregrounds the relevant harms visited by a particular receiving state upon particular migrants. Furthermore, the normative conclusions we draw about specific cases can also point beyond themselves, even if they are not always fully generalizable.
A second sort of argument that I am not pursuing here—again for reasons discussed further below—concerns the expansion of existing legal frameworks such as the 1951 Refugee Convention or the creation of new legal mechanisms to cover climate refugees.Footnote 23 Rather, I aim to make a straightforward normative argument concerning what is owed to any person whose cross-border migration is substantially driven by the harmful impacts of climate change. I use the phrase “climate migrants” to refer to such persons, including but not exclusively referring to those whose indisputably climate-forced movement and inability to return (for instance, residents of inundated island states) make them akin to refugees in the framework of existing international law. I agree with Carol Farbotko that climate migration should be understood as “a complex nexus of economic, social, cultural and political—as well as environmental—factors that contribute to mobility associated with climate change.”Footnote 24 Indeed, I will argue that the phenomenon of climate migration can only be properly understood in this way, and that it is largely incomprehensible when isolated from its structural and historical context.
Finally, the present discussion pertains only to receiving states’ responsibility toward cross-border climate migrants. This, of course, does not obviate responsibilities toward internal migrants. The majority of climate migration is currently internal,Footnote 25 and this migration too raises pressing questions, such as who should foot the bill for internal resettlement aid. Nonetheless, the core issue at stake in this article is the legitimacy of national immigration restrictions that aim to bar climate migrants from entry. Given the increasing political salience of this question,Footnote 26 I have chosen to focus on it here.
Characterizing the Conventional View
Despite meaningful disagreements among various liberal nationalist and communitarian defenses of the right to exclude, they share certain core commitments that together can be said to constitute the conventional view.Footnote 27 Most centrally, proponents of the conventional view defend a relatively broad right of states to decide who can enter their territories and who will be granted membership to their political communities. Accordingly, they see admission of most migrants and refugees as a matter of humanitarian “mutual aid” or charity rather than of justice. They will often concede that states may have special, stronger obligations toward claimants whose displacement has been caused by a receiving state. However, they necessarily view such cases as exceptional rather than the norm. Let us briefly unpack each of these tenets in turn.
The claim that states have a broad right to include or exclude as they see fit is justified on various grounds. Many justifications lean heavily upon the principles of democratic self-determination and free association; for example, Wellman suggests that the right to exclude requires only “three core premises: 1) Legitimate states are entitled to political self-determination, 2) freedom of association is an integral component of self-determination, and 3) freedom of association entitles one to not associate with others.”Footnote 28 Theorists making this sort of rights-based argument often draw an analogy between nation-states and clubs or other forms of voluntary organizations, which, as Walzer notes, “can regulate admissions but cannot bar withdrawals”Footnote 29 (the latter being unacceptably coercive). While the posited right to self-determination is sometimes taken to be sufficient to justify selective exclusion, proponents of border controls may also appeal to various consequentialist reasons for limiting entry or full membership. They posit states’ rights or duties to protect themselves against the dangers posed by unregulated immigration—dangers that ostensibly include the possible erosion of cultural cohesion or shared democratic values, threats to public safety or national security, the straining of welfare programs, and the loss of environmental integrity.Footnote 30
On this view, states may have a duty to take the interests of migrants into account and give appropriate reasons for exclusion, but they are not generally obligated to admit those who come or to extend citizenship and full privileges of membership to those who are admitted. If no comprehensive universal right to free movement is recognized, and if states have a right to admit or exclude largely as they see fit, then admission of the needy becomes primarily a matter of benevolence rather than of justice.Footnote 31 Miller, for instance, argues that we cannot completely ignore the interests of migrants in crafting immigration policy, but this “does not in general mean that we have obligations toward them, and especially not obligations of justice that in principle third parties can force us to discharge.”Footnote 32
Certain qualifications are acknowledged on the conventional view; in accordance with existing norms of international law, states are usually thought to have a shared responsibility toward persons who have no other form of state protection, such as refugees fleeing persecution or war.Footnote 33 These responsibilities are generally understood as broadly humanitarian in character.Footnote 34 Additionally, although they command considerably less attention in the literature, most defenders of the right to exclude concede that there may be special obligations in cases where a receiving state has helped to cause the displacement. For instance, Walzer suggests that we “may have obligations of the same sort that we have toward fellow nationals” toward “any group whom we have helped turn into refugees.”Footnote 35 Miller refers to such migrants as “particularity claimants”Footnote 36 because particular states may owe them admission due to past wrongs, and argues that in such cases admission to a state that contributed to a particularity claimant's displacement may be understood as “a form of reparation.”Footnote 37
However, although they acknowledge that some states may owe some groups entry and status as reparation for harm, advocates of the right to exclude generally regard such cases as exceptions to the rule of discretionary exclusion. Indeed, one could argue that they must understand such cases as exceptional in order to maintain the conventional view, lest the exception become the rule and upend the entire framework.
Climate-Centered Challenges to the Conventional View
In light of growing concern about climate-related displacement and migration, a number of political theorists and ethicists have argued that climate migrants should be excepted from discretionary exclusion. Nuances and partial overlap notwithstanding, these arguments generally fall into two categories: first, those making universal humanitarian claims for appropriate compensation to the displaced; and second, those making reparative claims concerning what specific states owe to the specific claimants whom they have harmed.
Several thinkers have made influential arguments for the expansion of the right to asylum or resettlement based on the universal rights of those displaced by climate change and the humanitarian duties of all states toward them. For instance, Clare Heyward and Jörgen Ödalen argue that residents of small island states like Tuvalu and the Maldives, who stand to lose not only their homes and livelihoods but “their membership of a self-governing political community,” should have a globally accepted right to settle in any state they choose.Footnote 38 Robyn Eckersley makes a similar case for states’ common but differentiated humanitarian responsibility to accept climate refugees.Footnote 39 Cara Nine goes slightly further, arguing that island nations permanently displaced by sea-level rise should be granted new sovereign territory, which would be provided by any existing states with territory to spare. These accounts largely set aside the question of specific causal responsibility for climate displacement, arguing instead for states’ shared responsibility (sometimes modulated by their differential ability) to compensate the dispossessed for their loss of political self-determination—though Nine parenthetically notes that “if we can establish that certain groups are to blame for the plight of the Tuvaluans, then the Tuvaluans will have additional grounds for claiming appropriate compensation, including possibly territorial rights, from the guilty parties.”Footnote 40
Other theorists focus more centrally on such reparative claims, contending that the presumption of displacement without blame wrongly lets polluting states off the hook by collectivizing responsibility. Sujatha Byravan and Sudhir Chella Rajan, for example, argue that those permanently displaced by sea-level rise (whom they deem “climate exiles”) should be granted immigration benefits “on the basis of the host countries’ historical greenhouse gas emissions.”Footnote 41 Rebecca Buxton agrees that permanent climate-related displacement resulting from “total territory loss” is a wrong requiring specific reparation by polluting states, but argues that reparations ideally ought to take the form of new territory for displaced groups rather than immigration rights alone (essentially proffering a reparative version of Nine's view).Footnote 42
Such reparative arguments represent an important challenge to liberal nationalists like Miller who tend to minimize receiving states’ causal or outcome responsibility for displacement. For example, in the conclusion of Strangers in Our Midst, Miller briefly acknowledges the worry that climate migration could challenge the conventional view. Although a “remote possibility,” he says,
we can imagine a future in which the effects of global warming and resource depletion make large parts of the Earth's surface uninhabitable, and then the searching question is whether the societies that have escaped relatively unscathed would have an obligation to admit refugees in numbers that would transform their own cultures and political institutions. . . . The correct answer is that the obligation to admit would in these circumstances be humanitarian in nature, not something that justice demands, which also implies that it would be a matter for the citizens of the receiving society to decide upon—they could not be forced to comply, either by the refugees themselves or by third parties.Footnote 43
To remain compatible with both his generally restrictive position on immigration and his acknowledgment of states’ special duties toward particularity claimants, Miller's thought experiment necessarily marginalizes the causal responsibility of those receiving societies for mass climate displacement. Reminders of that responsibility challenge the conventional view—not only in Miller's quasi-hypothetical future but also in the perilous present that climate migrants already face. The power of Ocasio-Cortez's appeal to the historical harms underlying northward migration from Central America must be understood in this real-world political context.
Limits of the Normative Literature on Climate Migration
While it demonstrates the importance of acknowledging reparative duties, the example of migration from Central America to the United States also demonstrates several important limits of the extant literature concerning reparative justice for climate migrants.
Humanitarian and reparative accounts alike have tended to focus on persons or groups who have been indisputably and irreversibly displaced by climate impacts alone. In practice, this means limiting the discussion to displacement from small island states and analogous cases of near-total inundation, excluding migrants like those from the Dry Corridor. It is understandable that many normative theories of climate migration privilege cases that effectively isolate the role of climate change in displacement. However, these clear-cut instances represent a relatively small subset of the overall body of cases of current and projected future climate-related displacement and migration; the empirical literature suggests that most climate migration does and will occur in contexts where the state is not existentially threatened by sea-level riseFootnote 44 and where the relationship between climate impacts and migration outcomes is modulated by a variety of nonclimatic factors.
The complexity that these cases introduce might seem to make our task as normative theorists more difficult and leave our arguments more vulnerable to critique. Miller, for instance, charges those who theorize responsibility for climate harms in the context of global inequality with “trying to advance a wider egalitarian agenda under the guise of a mechanism for tackling global warming.”Footnote 45 Nonetheless, we cannot bracket these cases without unreasonably restricting the scope of the argument and disqualifying the large bulk of climate migrants from appropriate redress. As Jamie Draper has recently argued, theorists of climate migration will instead have to reject “untenable monocausal assumptions about the relationship between climate change and displacement”Footnote 46 and argue for a more realistically complex view if they wish to properly account for this larger and more broadly representative set of cases.
Philosophers tend to be uncomfortable with such messy complexity, but social scientists widely accept that even apparently nonanthropogenic disasters are never purely “natural.”Footnote 47 Take, for instance, the 2010 earthquake near Port-au-Prince, Haiti, which killed tens or hundreds of thousands of HaitiansFootnote 48 and displaced as many as 1.5 million more.Footnote 49 By contrast, when an earthquake of similar magnitude struck the San Francisco Bay area in 1989, it killed sixty-three people.Footnote 50 We cannot account for the discrepancy if we look only at the force of the earthquakes’ shocks. Nor can we account for most climate migration based only on changes in temperature, precipitation, or sea level; it is impossible to get a conceptual grasp on the phenomenon without considering the real-world contexts within which such migration takes place.Footnote 51
In addition to excluding much climate-related migration from consideration, the reluctance of normative theorists to grapple with these real-world complexities prevents them from effectively challenging the idealized image of the international order that structures and constrains the conversation. As Sarah Fine observes, “The contemporary philosophical debate [concerning immigration] is conducted in relatively sanitized discourse” that improperly brackets highly relevant features of the real world.Footnote 52 For example, Fine points out that Miller's defense of border controls in an ideal nonracist world is illegitimately applied to the actual world of thoroughly racialized immigration policies.Footnote 53 More generally, she argues that if we are starting from “the world as it is,” as Miller claims to do,
then we are starting from a world in which existing territorial borders and population distributions have come about in a variety of complex ways, many of which have included extensive injustices, such as those involved in colonialism, slave trading, wars of aggression, ethnic cleansing and land seizures. The list is long. But Miller's animating idea of benign, discrete national communities stretching into the past and future allows him to brush over those kinds of facts about the world.Footnote 54
Ernesto Rosen Velásquez shows that similar methodological concerns apply to the restrictionist arguments of Christopher Wellman and Stephen Macedo.Footnote 55
The normative theories of climate migration discussed in the previous section challenge aspects of the conventional view by emphasizing polluting states’ responsibilities toward climate migrants, but they generally do not call these broader idealizing assumptions into question. This tendency, too, is understandable, given the complexity of proving the contemporary relevance of historical harms like colonialism or the reality of systemic neocolonial exploitation when attempting to develop a general theory of migration justice.Footnote 56 An interlocutor can simply counter, as Miller does to Thomas Pogge when discussing global poverty, that linking historical injustices to present-day conditions “would require taking specific cases and showing the causal mechanisms at work, rather than relying on broad brush assertions.”Footnote 57
However understandable it may be, the reluctance to take up this challenge has problematic consequences. For instance, most extant accounts attribute causal or outcome responsibility for climate change solely based on states’ greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions,Footnote 58 without considering their role in advancing or impeding global climate policy or the various other ways in which they have contributed unequally to the climate crisis. As I have argued elsewhere, a focus on emissions in the absence of historical and structural context leads philosophers to produce “myopic treatments of responsibility for climate change,”Footnote 59 thereby ceding crucial ground to partisans of the conventional view.
In general, isolating climate migration from its broader sociopolitical context and sanitizing the dynamics of that context through theoretical abstraction allow proponents of the conventional view to minimize claims of justice and narrow the pool of particularity claimants. A closer examination of real-world cases of climate migration can help to bring these issues into clearer focus, underlining the need for a more integrative and less idealized approach to reparative justice for climate migrants.
A Dry Corridor Drenched in Blood
I have suggested that a more realistic account of receiving states’ responsibilities toward climate migrants would need to look at the specificities and complex histories of particular cases, and that doing so may disrupt the dominant debates about migration in various ways. Miller may argue that we need to examine specific cases “rather than relying on broad brush assertions,” but he says this only to dismiss the idea that present-day harms are often the result of historical injustices and structural imperatives and that this should be reflected in normative theory; he does not actually examine specific cases and the causal mechanisms at work or explore their connections with climate change and migration. Once we descend from the heights of philosophical abstraction and examine the deep entwinement of imperial history and climate vulnerability in particular instances, the conventional view's assumptions about the exceptional character of particularity claims may become harder to justify.
To see why, let us briefly consider the case of contemporary climate migrants attempting to reach the United States from the Dry Corridor. In considering the case of these migrants, the question is: To what extent does the United States, as a receiving state, bear responsibility for causing climate migration from this region, thereby creating a body of particularity claimants toward whom it would have more stringent obligations of justice according to the conventional view? Below, I answer this question in two parts, beginning with a partial analysis of responsibility for climate change and then turning to an abridged integrationist account of social, political, and economic vulnerability to climate impacts.
In weighing U.S. responsibility for climate change, the most obvious factor—and the one on which most reparative accounts exclusively focus—is GHG emissions. This is reasonably straightforward to quantify; while home to a bit over 4 percent of the global population, the United States has emitted approximately a quarter of all historical anthropogenic GHG emissions.Footnote 60 By contrast, El Salvador and Nicaragua have each contributed just .01 percent of historical GHG emissions; Honduras is responsible for .02 percent, and Guatemala .03 percent.Footnote 61 This causal disparity is not merely historical; per capita emissions in the United States today are still roughly fifteen times higher than in any of these Central American countries.Footnote 62
However, emissions and consumption are only the most visible part of the proverbial iceberg. In determining the full causal responsibility of the United States for climate change, we would have to consider numerous other factors. We would need, for instance, to examine the political role of the United States in undermining, delaying, and watering down attempts to address climate change at the international level.Footnote 63 We would also need to consider that even as Democratic presidents pledged meaningful climate action, the United States has dramatically expanded its own exploitation of fossil fuelsFootnote 64 and increased financing for international fossil fuel production through the Export–Import Bank.Footnote 65 Finally, in addition to the direct role of the U.S. government in stymieing climate action, we would also want to account for the role played by U.S.-based multinationals such as ExxonMobil and Koch Industries, which are heavily subsidized by U.S. taxpayers and have spent billions of dollarsFootnote 66 to successfully thwart climate action.Footnote 67
This close relationship between the U.S. state apparatus and U.S.-based segments of fossil fuel capital (recently exemplified in striking fashion by former Exxon CEO Rex Tillerson's appointment as secretary of state in the Trump administration) also raises the broader question of the role of the United States in expanding the reach and enforcing the norms of global capitalism, which is increasingly recognized as a central driver of climate change and environmental destruction more generally. If, as a number of contemporary critical theorists argue, the United States as global hegemon has helped to impose an unsustainable and carbon-intensive model of production, consumption, and governance upon the world—with capitalist “carbon democracy” and its “imperial mode of living” in the North premised upon extractivism and superexploitation in the SouthFootnote 68—this, too, would be relevant to our evaluation of causal responsibility for climate forcings of migration.
With respect to causal responsibility for the current state of the climate, the role of the United States is already looking quite substantial. However, we still have an incomplete picture of causal responsibility for climate migration from the Dry Corridor because we cannot neatly separate direct climatic drivers from the broader social conditions that create displacement and motivate climate migration. The White House's own 2021 report on climate change and migration acknowledges that political and economic context largely determines whether people ultimately migrate in response to climate impacts.Footnote 69 An appropriate normative account of Central American climate migration must likewise recognize that while climate change is ultimately pushing people in the Dry Corridor to migrate, this motivation is inextricable from the precarity of their daily existence and the lack of safe and viable alternatives to cross-border migration.
Philosophers such as Miller and Wellman explicitly assume that such precarity—constituted by a mix of poverty, lack of government infrastructure, incapacity of disaster response adaptation measures, preponderance of violence and conflict, and so on—is generally the responsibility of the sending countries themselves.Footnote 70 But a closer examination of actual cases may often show otherwise.
The assumption that Central American climate vulnerability, poverty, and instability are due to poor self-governance is a familiar one.Footnote 71 As Juan Gonzalez points out, it echoes the common pretexts given for U.S. interventions over the last century, where U.S. officials and media “told people back home the Latin Americans were incapable of responsible government,” while “critical details of how the dictators rose to power and terrorized their people with Washington's help, or how their regimes provided a ‘friendly’ business climate for North American firms, remained hidden deep in diplomatic correspondences.”Footnote 72 Gonzalez highlights this legacy of imperialism as a central driver of northward migration, which he characterizes as “the unintended harvest of the U.S. empire.”Footnote 73 Thus, in order to develop a more realistic picture of the responsibility of the United States for climate migration from the Dry Corridor, one must also take into account the relevant history of U.S. foreign policy in Central America.
The list of U.S. interventions in the region is long;Footnote 74 here, I can only briefly gesture toward a few of the relevant harms over the last century. These include U.S. invasions and occupations of all four Dry Corridor countries (and many others) during the early and mid-twentieth century, securing the rule of leaders friendly to U.S. corporate and financial interests. U.S.-backed strongmen like Jorge Ubico Castañeda in Guatemala, Maximiliano Hernández Martínez in El Salvador, Tiburcio Carías Andino in Honduras, and the Somoza family in Nicaragua crushed dissent, assassinated progressive rivals, and undermined attempts at national economic development while massively enriching themselves and their U.S. clients. Gonzalez points out that although these names are barely known in the United States, “to their countrymen, they represent lost decades so filled with horror and darkness that some nations are only now recovering.”Footnote 75
As the twentieth century progressed, U.S. strategy shifted somewhat; there were still military invasions and occupations where necessary, but more discreet interventions were preferred when possible.Footnote 76 Throughout the second half of the twentieth century, the CIA and its affiliates helped to overthrow or assassinate democratically elected presidents and revolutionary leaders throughout the Dry Corridor. In this period, the United States armed and funded numerous military juntas and installed corrupt right-wing dictators friendly to U.S. corporations such as the United Fruit Company (now Chiquita); meanwhile, death squads trained at the U.S.-run School of the Americas and armed and funded by the United States suppressed resistance, butchering and terrorizing hundreds of thousands of Salvadorians, Guatemalans, Nicaraguans, and Hondurans.Footnote 77 This situation, of course, caused a large northward exodus and created lasting destabilization and danger.
Since the turn of the twenty-first century, the United States has shifted toward “soft power” in the region;Footnote 78 however, it has hardly ceased interfering in Central American politics. In 2009, for example, the United States tacitly supported a military coup against Honduras's democratically elected president Manuel Zelaya,Footnote 79 conspiring through back channels to prevent his return to office and refusing to cut off aid to the junta.Footnote 80 As Belén Fernández shows, this coup “spawned a maelstrom of violence that terrorized ordinary Hondurans and forced caravans of migrants to flee the country.”Footnote 81 Since that coup, hundreds of labor and environmental activists have been murdered, including the well-known land defender Berta Cáceres (whose killers included two graduates of the infamous School of the Americas, subsequently renamed the Western Hemisphere Institute for Security Cooperation).Footnote 82 It is no coincidence that Nicaragua, Honduras, and Guatemala top Global Witness's rankings of murdered environmental activists per capita.Footnote 83
It is important to note that throughout this history, violent statecraft has gone hand in hand with exploitative and coercive economic and environmental policy. In the early twentieth century, U.S. invasions allowed the United States to reshape economic life in the region, facilitating massive land expropriation and the subsequent transformation of much of that land into monocropped plantationsFootnote 84 (a transformation that still has tremendous bearing upon contemporary climate vulnerability).Footnote 85 This symbiosis of overt and structural violence continued in the neoliberal era; it is often rather difficult to pass structural adjustment policies and austerity packages democratically, which is why they generally had to be imposed by force and terror throughout Latin America in the second half of the twentieth century.Footnote 86 But even when such overt coercion is absent, economic policies pushing privatization, export processing zones,Footnote 87 and free trade agreements exploit the structural imbalances of the global economy to benefit the United States and some local elites at the expense of everyday people and the environment in Central America.Footnote 88
Philosophers concerned with the ethics of immigration generally downplay the coercive character of these dynamics when debating which historical wrongs might be appropriately redressed through entry and status.Footnote 89 But as James Souter argues, we are owed a convincing argument for why “the effects of ‘destabilizing structural adjustment programs’”Footnote 90 should not be categorized as a wrong of this kind. When one examines the history of the Dry Corridor, one finds that the imposition of such policies by the United States (as well as by institutions like the World Bank and International Monetary Fund, over which the United States holds great influence) has undermined democratic control over fundamental aspects of social policy and slashed social safety nets,Footnote 91 facilitated large-scale land grabbing, and fed the rapid acceleration of resource extraction and environmental degradationFootnote 92—all of which have helped to make everyday life in the Dry Corridor precarious and sensitive to climate impacts.Footnote 93
This is only a partial and extremely abbreviated account of the relevant dynamics in the region.Footnote 94 However, I hope that what has been said is sufficiently suggestive. My aim in laying out these various layers of harm is not to argue that the United States is solely responsible for producing climate migration in the Dry Corridor; there is certainly plenty of blame to go around,Footnote 95 and an exclusive focus on imperial harm can cover over local complexity and erase agency (including both that of resistance movements and that of local elites who perpetuate the racial dynamics of colonialism and oppress Indigenous peoples).Footnote 96
Given the great philosophical and empirical complexities involved, it is not clear exactly what portion of the responsibility for these migrants’ plight the United States owns; indeed, I will argue below that such calculations are ultimately impossible to make, suggesting the need for an alternative approach. Regardless, it should be clear that we cannot simply bracket the question, as many philosophers of migration do. It should further be clear that it does not make sense to solely blame the inhabitants of the Dry Corridor and their “ineffective” governments for the poverty, violence, and environmental degradation that have upended their lives. To do so, we would have to ignore the well-documented facts that the United States is the largest historical contributor to climate change and that these corrupt local leaders, murderous death squads, and opportunistic corporate actors have been consistently funded, trained, armed, and empowered by the United States for over a century, resulting in higher vulnerability to climate harms and fewer viable alternatives to cross-border migration. In this context it is clear that, as Seyla Benhabib argues, “Blaming the stranger is a way of reducing complexity and avoiding responsibility.”Footnote 97
The analysis offered above may not be generalizable to every sending or receiving country. But it does demonstrate that when we examine the realities of such migration, they may differ radically from the idealized picture painted by mainstream migration theory; at least in the case of the Dry Corridor, filling in the relevant context makes it extremely difficult to see the United States as a detached observer of its climate migrants’ misfortune. Because the United States has played a key role in causing the immiseration and displacement of these migrants, it seems that many are owed redress even according to the stated standards of the conventional view; as particularity claimants, many migrants would be owed admission and status. We might think that they deserve considerably more than that—Naomi Klein suggests that, beyond asylum and status, climate migrants are “owed kindness, compensation, and heartfelt apology”Footnote 98 from those who have helped to render their homes uninhabitable.
Objections
While I think the argument I have laid out is reasonably straightforward, there are several potential objections to consider.
One possible reply is that even if a state's past actions have contributed to climate migrants’ displacement, it is unfair to hold the present citizens of that state liable. The unfairness might be especially acute where the historical harms resulted from excusable ignorance, as is sometimes argued of pre-1990 GHG emissions.Footnote 99 There would indeed be cause for concern if I treated such emissions as a crime ex post facto and decreed that the descendants of emitters should be punished.Footnote 100 But I am not arguing for imposed immigration as retribution for past emissions; as Souter points out, even if migrants were not “highly beneficial to their states of asylum in economic, social and cultural terms . . . it would nevertheless be morally dubious to present the presence of human beings on one's territory as a form of punishment.”Footnote 101 Rather, climate migrants are persons to whom certain states and their citizens owe a debt, and this debt is incurred not only by those who directly and maliciously initiate harm but by all who benefit from and participate in ongoing structural injustice. As I explain below, the reparative program that stems from such injustice is not vulnerable to this objection of unfairness.
However, it might still be objected that even if a state's causal responsibility is acknowledged, its reparative duties toward climate migrants need not include granting entry and status. Wellman, for instance, asks why we would presume “that compensation must be paid in the currency of open borders” rather than, say, financial transfers.Footnote 102 It is worth taking this question seriously. I would not wish to suggest that granting entry and status to migrants is the only—or even the most efficient or important—form of reparation for the harms of climate change and imperial destabilization. There are numerous other obligations that responsible nations or their citizens may have toward those affected by climate change (such as to agitate for meaningful mitigation, massive financial and technological transfers, and the cessation of neocolonial resource exploitation),Footnote 103 some of which may be more effective at redressing its wrongs in some instances. Indeed, it is plausible that addressing the injustices of climate change through the liberalization of immigration alone could further harm sending countries and those without the means or mobility to migrate.Footnote 104
Nonetheless, given that some significant degree of climate-related displacement is now unavoidable, we are left with the question of what is owed to those who have been or will be uprooted by climate-related harms. Those harms may be “sufficiently severe to render proportionality unattainable”Footnote 105 when aiming for appropriate reparation—the status quo ante cannot be restored for those whose land and climate have been irreversibly degraded to the extent that their former ways of life have become impossible. Practically, in many such cases, entry and status will be the next best things to full restitution.
Further, even if more “efficient” reparative options are available in some instances, there is still something ethically perverse in a state's exclusion of migrants whose homes it has helped to destroy. Concerns about efficiency, as Souter notes, are often raised “without identifying what good is to be maximized, and in whose interests”;Footnote 106 in the context of reparation for wrongful displacement, such appeals to efficiency are germane only where admittance of some migrants would substantially and unavoidably undermine other claimants’ prospects for meaningful reparation. In my view, then, the most intuitive position to adopt is that everything possible should be done to end ongoing harms and to help people adapt to locked-in warming, and those compelled to migrate to the relative safety of a causally responsible receiving country must be granted entry and status.Footnote 107
From another perspective, some might object that this argument does not go far enough, and that many climate migrants are owed more than entry and status. For example, Buxton suggests that displaced communities should be granted new sovereign territory, which would “reestablish a sense of place for future generations” that immigration rights alone cannot do, and thus come closer to full reparation.Footnote 108 Others point out that full reparation also requires an explicit acknowledgment of and apology for the harm done. Such apologies can be empty gestures on their own, but when issued alongside full immigration rights they become more meaningful; in such a context, as Souter argues, the welcoming of migrants would function as “an inward-looking expression of contrition and apology, thereby acting as a form of satisfaction.”Footnote 109 Finally, Olúfémi O. Táíwò argues more radically that backward-looking views of reparation that primarily focus on the present effects of specific past harms are both unworkable and unnecessary, and that the appropriate response to structural injustices is a larger, forward-looking project of social transformation. Táíwò suggests that “climate justice and reparations are the same project,” the task of which is “quite literally, to remake the world” built by a global racial empire along more just lines.Footnote 110
I largely agree with these objections. In this situation, immigration rights are indeed “primarily remedial rather than fully reparatory,”Footnote 111 and cannot undo the loss of homes, communities, and ways of life. Likewise, true climate justice cannot be realized without abolishing the racialized structures of domination and exploitation that have fueled climate change and generated the dramatically unequal distribution of its harms. However, even if migration cannot substitute for the longer-term project of structural transformation, in the meantime it remains a vitally important lifeline for individual climate migrants.Footnote 112 Further, I believe my comparatively modest reparative argument is compatible with—and perhaps even a necessary component of—the more ambitious goals of full reparation and radical social transformation. While that larger project of constructive reparation is indeed forward looking, the proper recognition of past harms is indispensable for motivating it, and the fair treatment of climate migrants will be integral to any “just transition” worthy of the name.Footnote 113
Understanding my argument as facilitating the recognition of harm in the service of broader structural transformation may help to address a second version of the insufficiency objection. As noted at the start, my focus on specific contextual harms requires one to investigate the relevant historical facts and structural dynamics of particular cases, and as such the conclusions drawn are not immediately and fully generalizable. My argument may therefore appear both weaker and more difficult to make successfully than more immediately universalist appeals for border abolition. I will conclude by addressing this last objection more fully.
Conclusion
Rather than making broader arguments for open borders or border abolition based on human rights or universal principles in response to climate migration, I have pursued here a more modest line of critique, expanding upon the idea that even according to the conventional view you cannot set someone's house on fire and then blame them for fleeing. This intervention, as I have stressed, is intentionally bounded in scope; it requires us to consider who has set which particular houses on fire and then jailed or desiccated or drowned those fleeing the flames.
However, even when we confine our investigation to a particular context in this way, the scale of the arson we discover may raise broader questions about the conventional view; Benhabib suggests that such non-ideal explorations of actual examples may ultimately have “significant implications for…seminal question[s] in ideal democratic theory” such as “how to define and justify the boundaries of the demos.”Footnote 114 For example, while the liberal nationalist argument for border restriction requires that “nation-states must be represented as formally equal and sovereign,”Footnote 115 it should be clear from the account above that states in the Dry Corridor still cannot be said to have an equal, or even a minimally adequate, degree of sovereignty; decisions governing the most crucial aspects of their citizens’ life prospects, including whether much of their territory will be habitable by human beings in the coming decades, are too consistently made elsewhere. And if meaningful democratic self-determination—the basic principle that allegedly grounds a states’ right to exclude—is not generalizable in a warming world structured by border imperialism, then this highlights the need to further interrogate this fundamental ideological pillar of the modern nation-state form.
Furthermore, although the details are specific and important, the case I have discussed here is not unique in its general outlines; analogous stories can be told for many—perhaps most—other instances of climate migration. Migrants and advocates have already been telling these stories; if enough normative theorists care to listen and join them, the idealizing assumptions of the conventional view will become increasingly harder to justify, and the burden of justification may begin to shift. Rather than relying on broad brush assertions, we might then say, defenders of the right to exclude will have to demonstrate the actual instances in which such exclusion is warranted—where the processes are just, the institutions are legitimate, and the excluded are not wronged. Such cases, one suspects, may turn out to be the exception.