Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T11:07:41.698Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Pronouns beyond phi-features: the speaker–addressee relation in Japanese pronouns and its implications for formal pronouns

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 November 2024

Elizabeth Ritter
Affiliation:
University of Calgary
Martina Wiltschko*
Affiliation:
ICREA and Universitat Pompeu Fabra
*
Corresponding author: Martina Wiltschko; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Greenberg’s Universal 42 states that all languages have pronominal categories involving at least three persons and two numbers. However, this characterization fails to capture the properties of pronouns in Japanese, which are not bundles of person, number and gender features (so-called phi-features); rather, they contain sociolinguistic information about the interlocutors. We propose that these properties are structurally determined. Following Ritter and Wiltschko, we assume that the highest layer of structure in nominals is interactional structure. As for phi-features, we adopt the standard assumption that they are represented internal to the determiner phrase (DP). We propose that the distinctive properties of Japanese pronouns follow from the hypothesis that they spell out elements of the interactional structure and not the DP. We show that the lack of phi-features in Japanese pronouns correlates with other properties of this language’s grammar. Support for this analysis comes from languages where pronouns with phi-features can optionally be used to encode formality (e.g. German and French). We propose that in these languages, formal pronouns originate within the DP but are interpreted in the interactional structure. Finally, we suggest that this analysis may extend to imposters and vocatives in that they may also be interpreted in the interactional structure.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. What is a Pronoun?

It is a widely held assumption that all languages have pronouns, as reflected in Greenberg’s (Reference Greenberg and Greenberg1966:96) Universal 42, reproduced in (1).

Within the generative approach, which we adopt here, pronouns are conceived of as bundles of person, number and (in some languages) gender features (so-called phi-features). These features determine the paradigmatic organization of pronouns. Given this approach, it is tempting to equate the content of first- and second-person phi-features with the interactional roles of speaker and addressee, respectively (Harley and Ritter Reference Harley and Ritter2002). However, evidence from the Japanese language indicates that this seemingly straightforward equivalence is not warranted.

The goal of this paper is to demonstrate that Japanese pronouns bear the interactional roles of speaker and addressee but lack phi-features and that the separation of interactional roles from phi-features is structurally conditioned. Phi-based pronouns are typically analyzed as instantiating functional categories internal to the determiner phrase (DP) (Abney Reference Abney1987, Déchaine and Wiltschko Reference Déchaine and Wiltschko2002, Ritter Reference Ritter1995). We argue that Japanese pronouns instantiate syntactic categories above the DP that realize interactional content, including speaker and addressee roles. To support this claim, we discuss the well-known observation that Japanese pronouns lack the paradigmatic contrasts typical of phi-based pronouns. As Kuroda (Reference Kuroda1965:105) explains, ‘[i]n English grammar, as opposed to Japanese, one can easily point out formal (i.e. syntactico-morphological) characteristics of the personal pronouns. If we review some of these formal characteristics, we can see that there is nothing corresponding to them in the case of the Japanese so-called personal pronouns.’ Instead, Japanese pronouns are characterized by rich sociolinguistic information. For example, Takubo (Reference Takubo, Jacobsen and Takubo2020:689) notes that ‘Japanese counterparts to “pronouns” such as watasi ‘I,’ anata ‘you,’ kare ‘he,’ kanozyo ‘she,’ etc., form an open class, and new additions to this class are always possible.’ To see this, consider representative examples in (2).

The rich inventory of singular pronouns suggests that they consist of more than phi-features. This is further supported by another well-known fact about Japanese pronouns mentioned by Takubo (Reference Takubo, Jacobsen and Takubo2020:690), namely that they ‘cannot be freely used in conversational discourse … [and u]nlike English, the use of second person [pro]nouns to refer to the addressee in Japanese is usually considered impolite and restricted only to individuals who are close to the speaker.’ This is illustrated in (3).Footnote 1

A recent development in the architecture of the nominal spine makes a simple structural analysis available. According to Ritter and Wiltschko (Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2019), nominals include a layer of structure dedicated to encoding aspects of the interaction between the speaker and the addressee (i.e. interactional structure). We argue that Japanese pronouns spell out this interactional structure, and hence, we refer to them as interactional pronouns. Interactional pronouns contrast with paradigmatic pronouns, the term we use for pronouns consisting of bundles of phi-features that form closed paradigms.

This paper is organized as follows: In Section 2, we present our assumptions regarding the structure of nominals. In Section 3, we propose that aspects of the socially constructed relationship between speaker and addressee are part of the interactional structure, and we develop our analysis of Japanese pronouns as intrinsically interactional. In Section 4, we extend our analysis to the formality distinction attested in languages with paradigmatic pronouns. In Section 5, we compare our analysis to that of Portner et al. (Reference Portner, Pak and Zanuttini2019). Section 6 concludes the article.

2. The Interactional Structure of Nominals

Our point of departure is the assumption that nominals and clauses have a parallel structure. This idea goes back to Chomsky (Reference Chomsky, Roderick and Peter1970) and has been widely assumed ( e.g. Abney Reference Abney1987, Grimshaw Reference Grimshaw, Coopmans, Martin and Grimshaw2000).

The focus of the present paper is the set of categories that relate the proposition or referent to the conversational interaction and, hence, go beyond propositional or referential content. That such categories are part of the functional structure associated with clauses was first proposed in the seminal paper by Speas and Tenny (Reference Speas, Tenny and Di Sciullo2003). They argue that the propositional structure of a clause is dominated by an articulated speech act phrase (SAP). Evidence for this layer of structure comes from a variety of empirical phenomena, including agreement with the speaker and addressee (Miyagawa Reference Miyagawa2009, Zu Reference Zu, Aparicio, Flinn, Franich, Pietraszko and Vardomskaya2015, Reference Zu2018), confirmational particles (Haegeman Reference Haegeman2014, Wiltschko and Heim Reference Wiltschko, Heim, Kaltenböck, Keizer and Lohmann2016) and response markers (Krifka Reference Krifka and Snider2013). Similarly, it has been proposed that there are functional categories in the nominal domain that relate the referent to the conversational interaction: Hill (Reference Hill2007, Reference Hill2013) proposes that vocative nominals are associated with a layer of structure above the DP, (her vocative phrase [VocP]) to account for the fact that vocative nominals have different properties from bare nouns or DPs (cf. Espinal Reference Espinal, Sonnenhauser and Hanna2013).

Given the parallelism between clausal and nominal structure, the existence of a nominal layer responsible for regulating nominal reference in interaction is expected on conceptual grounds. The proposal for a clausal interactional structure that most straightforwardly extends to nominals is that of Wiltschko (Reference Wiltschko2021), as demonstrated by Ritter and Wiltschko (Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2019). They argue that the same interactional categories can account for the semantic and distributional differences between personal and impersonal pronouns, on the one hand, and different types of vocatives, on the other. Here we offer an analysis of Japanese interactional pronouns and demonstrate that they also require nominal interactional structure. In the remainder of this section, we introduce properties of Wiltschko’s (Reference Wiltschko2021) Interactional Spine Hypothesis that are relevant to our analysis.

According to the Interactional Spine Hypothesis, clauses contain another set of functional categories that compose the interactional structure. These consist of a Resp(onse)P and two grounding phrases, GroundSpkrP and GroundAdrP. Following Ritter and Wiltschko (Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2019), we assume that the nominal interactional structure contains the same layers, as illustrated in (4). The Interactional Spine Hypothesis is an extension of Wiltschko’s (Reference Wiltschko2014) Universal Spine Hypothesis. According to the latter, specific functional categories are instantiations of universal functions that are present in both the nominal and clausal spine. For example, DP and tense phrase (TP) both instantiate the anchoring function, which is the process of anchoring the event or the individual to the utterance context. The labels GroundP and RespP represent the universal, category-neutral interactional functions grounding and responding, and we assume that there are nominal and clausal versions of these functions as well.

In the clausal spine, RespP signals whether the sentence functions as an initiating or reacting move. In the nominal spine, RespP serves the same function and hosts attention-getting particles, such as hey (Ritter and Wiltschko Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2019). Because it plays no role in the typology of nominals developed here, we abstract away from this category.

In (4), GroundSpkrP and GroundAdrP constitute the syntactic representation of the interlocutors and their knowledge states (i.e. their grounds). As schematized in (5), the specifier of these phrases is assigned an interactional role by the respective head: the argument in Spec,GroundSpkrP is assigned the role of the holder of speaker’s ground and the argument in Spec,GroundAdrP is assigned the role of the holder of addressee’s ground. These correspond to the traditional speech act roles, speaker and addressee.

The terms speaker and addressee, as we use them here, refer to interactional roles rather than syntactic features. Thus, like thematic roles, they do not participate in any syntactic agreement relation.

In the nominal spine, GroundSpkrP encodes the speaker’s commitment to the identity of the discourse referent, that is, the knowledge the speaker has about the referent. GroundAdrP encodes what the speaker assumes the addressee knows about the discourse referent and about the relationship between the interlocutors. For example, speakers often know different names, titles and descriptions for a given individual, but the choice they make when referring to that individual depends on their addressee, as shown in (6) and (7).

Although the interactional structure has no overt content in the examples in (6) and (7), the structure in (5) predicts that it can be overtly realized. In the next section, we show that this is the case for Japanese pronouns.

3. Japanese Pronouns as Interactional Pronouns

In this section, we develop our proposal regarding the syntactic structure of interactional pronouns. We show that it provides a new solution to a long-standing problem in the grammar of Japanese. That is, it has long been observed that Japanese pronouns do not behave like paradigmatic pronouns in two respects: They lack phi-features, and they are laden with fine-grained sociolinguistic content. We show how an analysis of Japanese pronouns as intrinsically interactional accounts for both properties. In Section 3.1, we review previous treatments that seek to account for these distinctive properties of Japanese pronouns and point out their limitations. We then show that nominal interactional structure accounts for the presence of interactional content (Section 3.2), and the lack of phi-features (Section 3.3). In Section 3.4, we explore the difference in interpretation between person, number, and gender when realized as formal phi-features and as open-class interactional content.

3.1. The problem of classifying Japanese pronouns

The claim that Japanese pronouns do not behave like paradigmatic pronouns is not new. Previous authors have analyzed them in one of two ways – as nouns or as a third unidentified nominal category. We now review the arguments against analyzing Japanese pronouns as paradigmatic and those for and against analyzing them as nouns. We then introduce a new solution that exploits nominal interactional structure.

3.1.1. An old problem

It is a well-documented observation that Japanese pronouns do not behave like paradigmatic pronouns. They do not form paradigmatic oppositions with contrasting phi-features (Hashimoto Reference Hashimoto1948, Kuroda Reference Kuroda1965, Wetzel Reference Wetzel, Bachnik and Quinn1994). Rather, they contain sociolinguistic content, such as register, the interlocutors’ genders, ages, relative social status, and other aspects of their relation to one another. Consequently, Japanese has a sizable inventory of such forms (Hirose Reference Hirose2000; Kondo Reference Kondo1990; Kuroda Reference Kuroda1965; Martin Reference Martin1988; Miller Reference Miller1967; Shibatani Reference Shibatani1990; Suzuki Reference Suzuki1976; Wetzel Reference Wetzel, Bachnik and Quinn1994). For example, Martin (Reference Martin1988:1076–1077) lists 22 different speaker-denoting pronouns.

Implicit in much of this literature is the assumption that the forms in question must be either nouns or pronouns. If so, it follows that if they are not pronouns, then they must be nouns. This is the conclusion drawn by Hashimoto (Reference Hashimoto1948) and Kuroda (Reference Kuroda1965). See also Neeleman and Szendrői Reference Neeleman and Szendrői2007. Kuroda offers an argument based on properties that Japanese third-person pronouns share with nouns: they can both be modified by adjectives, as in (8).

This argument assumes that adjectives are modifiers internal to the noun phrase (NP). Because adjectives can also modify pronouns, it follows that pronouns must also be nouns.

This reasoning is valid for adjectives that serve as direct modifiers, but not all adjectives are direct modifiers. It is well documented that an additional source of modification is indirect modification, which is assumed to derive from a higher relative clause (see Cinque Reference Cinque2010). Sproat and Shih (Reference Sproat, Shih, Georgopoulos and Ishihar1991) show that Japanese adjectives are indirect modifiers. Watanabe (Reference Watanabe2012), however, identifies two exceptions: adjectives of origin/nationality and material adjectives. These exceptional classes appear to modify nouns directly. Interestingly, they are constructed with -no, which suggests that these constructions are appositional. Evidence for this apposition analysis comes from the observation that adjectives of origin/nationality require the addition of jin ‘person’ when they modify pronouns, as in (9).Footnote 2

We conclude that the fact that pronouns can be modified by adjectives does not constitute evidence that pronouns are nouns because they can only be indirectly modified. In other words, adjectives that can serve as direct modifiers cannot directly modify pronouns. Rather, when such adjectives appear with pronouns, they modify a noun (jin ‘person’) that is in an appositional relation with the pronoun.

Another difference between Japanese pronouns and nouns has to do with demonstratives (Hinds Reference Hinds1971). Unlike nouns, pronouns cannot be preceded by demonstratives, as shown by the contrast between (10) and (11).

A third difference that pertains to the internal structure of the nominal constituent is that nouns can be possessed, but pronouns cannot. Consider the examples of possessed nouns in (12), where the possessor is marked with genitive -no.

The fact that Japanese pronouns cannot be possessed manifests itself in two ways. First, when kare/kanojo is used in a possessive construction, it can be analyzed as a noun meaning ‘boyfriend’/‘girlfriend’ but not as a third-person pronoun, as in (13).

Second, first- and second-person pronouns cannot be combined with a possessor, as in (14). We attribute this ungrammaticality to the fact that first- and second-person pronouns are never nouns.

Strikingly, whereas first- or second-person pronouns cannot be possessed, they can combine with a noun suffixed with -no, otherwise used as a genitive marker. In this context, the presence of -no gives rise to an appositive interpretation rather than a possessive one, as in (9) and (15).

We interpret these facts as evidence that pronouns are not nouns.

The hypothesis that pronouns and nouns belong to different categories is further corroborated by an interpretive difference discussed by Hinds (Reference Hinds1971:154). Bare pronouns and nouns have different number specifications. Bare pronouns necessarily denote a singular individual, and plural marking is obligatory when the denotation is nonsingular, as in (16) and (17). In contrast, bare nouns have general number (i.e., they can be interpreted as singular or plural); hence plural marking is optional, as in (18).

In sum, there is a consensus that Japanese pronouns are not paradigmatic pronouns and that they have some properties in common with nouns. Nevertheless, there is also evidence that they differ from nouns, suggesting that they belong to a distinct category. So, what is their category? Even researchers who recognize that they are neither nouns nor pronouns offer no answer. For example, Hinds (Reference Hinds1971) does not categorize Japanese pronouns at all, and Takubo (Reference Takubo, Jacobsen and Takubo2020) classifies them as personal nouns. He reasons that they are personal because they deictically refer to the speaker or addressee (unlike nouns) and that they are noun-like because they are open class (unlike paradigmatic pronouns). However, this analysis fails to capture the sociolinguistic content that determines their use conditions, further distinguishing them from common nouns.

3.1.2. A new solution

We now offer a new solution to the long-standing problem of classifying Japanese pronouns. We argue that they belong to a syntactically and semantically distinct class of pronouns, which we call interactional pronouns. We assume that differences in external distribution, internal composition, and interpretive content are structurally conditioned (see Borer Reference Borer2005). In what follows, we argue that interactional pronouns occupy the nominal interactional structure and, hence, differ from both paradigmatic pronouns, which occupy the functional structure, and nouns, which occupy the lexical structure, as in (19).

Recall from Section 2 that the interactional structure contains two grounding phrases that introduce the ground-holders. The postulation of these grounding phrases predicts the existence of speaker- and addressee-denoting interactional pronouns. We propose that Japanese first- and second-person pronouns occupy Spec,GroundSpkrP and Spec,GroundAdrP, respectively, and that they receive their interactional roles in these positions, as schematized in (20).

Thus, the defining property of interactional pronouns is that they are realizations of one of the specifiers in the interactional layer and that their functional structure (DP) is occupied by pro. As such, interactional pronouns differ from paradigmatic ones, which spell out the functional structure. Given that phi-features are generally absent in Japanese, we hypothesize that pro in (20) also lacks phi-features.

This proposal raises the question as to whether there are interactional pronouns for the third person. We propose that Japanese third-person pronouns are derived interactional pronouns. As is well-documented, kare and kanojo, the third-person pronouns in Japanese, are intrinsically nouns meaning ‘boyfriend’ and ‘girlfriend’, respectively.Footnote 3 Hence, we propose that kare and kanojo are inserted as the head of NP and subsequently move to the grounding layer where they function as pronouns, as in (21). More specifically, they move to Spec,GroundSpkr, but unlike speaker-denoting pronouns, they are not interpreted as the holder of the speaker’s ground but instead as the content of the speaker’s ground

Suggestive evidence that kare and kanojo in their pronominal use occupy Spec,GroundSpkr comes from Obana’s (Reference Obana2003:154) observation that ‘the referent person should be known at least to the speaker, that he/she should not be present at the time of interaction, and that social distances should not be recognized between speaker, listener and referent person.’ Thus, like other interactional pronouns, the use conditions for kare and kanojo are determined by social relations between the speaker and the referent.

Note that in Japanese, at least in some contexts, third-person nominals that denote humans show a similar sensitivity to the speaker–addressee relation. This is exemplified in (22).Footnote 4

When talking to the president about the president’s son, an honorific marker (-san in (22) must be used on musuko (’son’). This raises the question of whether all third-person nominals denoting humans may or must move to the grounding layer. We leave this possibility as a matter for future research.

3.2. Interactional properties

According to our proposal, intrinsic interactional pronouns are inserted into the interactional structure and consequently, their content is interactional. We now demonstrate that the properties of Japanese pronouns are consistent with our analysis.

3.2.1. Rich sociolinguistic content

The fact that Japanese pronouns express sociolinguistic content falls out straightforwardly from the hypothesis that they appear in the interactional structure. This is in line with a widespread assumption according to which different kinds of content are associated with different layers of structure: descriptive (open class) content is associated with the lexical layer (NP) and grammatical features (phi and definiteness) with the functional layer (DP). Japanese pronouns do not have content that falls neatly within either of these layers of structure; rather, their content reflects the properties of the interlocutors and the context of their interaction. In what follows, we review characterizations of interactional pronouns that make it clear that their content is neither descriptive nor grammatical. Hence, their interpretive properties are not compatible with a structural analysis, according to which they are either NPs or DPs. But they have precisely the type of content one would expect of GroundP pronouns.

First consider Kaiser et al.’s (Reference Kaiser, Ichikawa, Kobayashi and Yamamoto2013) description of different Japanese addressee-denoting pronouns:

[K]imi is an intimate sounding form of address for males or females by older men, or by boyfriends towards girlfriends. [O]mae is quite informal, used between men who grew up or went to school together. It is also used by parents to their sons. [K]isama, also common in comics, is used in such male bastions as the army, sports teams etc., to subordinates or equals; in ordinary life, if you address someone with kisama, it signals that you’re trying to pick a fight! […] [Anata] is taught to foreigners as equivalent to ‘you’, simply because it is the most neutral of the lot. However, Westerners are renowned in Japan for overusing anata, which still has strong connotations, namely: […] anata is used when the speaker/writer does not know what the social level of the person/s addressed is. […] [A]nata is also typically used by a woman to her husband or lover (although less so by the younger generation).

Kaiser et al. (Reference Kaiser, Ichikawa, Kobayashi and Yamamoto2013:372–374)

This quote suggests that Japanese pronouns encode information about the addressee (age, gender, and social status), the relation between the interlocutors (level of intimacy), and their context of use (register). Kaiser et al.’s description also makes it clear that different Japanese pronouns do not minimally contrast with one another and that their content cannot be reduced to grammatical phi-features. Thus, these properties support our view that Japanese pronouns are categorically different from paradigmatic pronouns.

If interactional pronouns are not defined by a set of grammatical phi-features, then they need not constitute a closed class. The fact that different grammars of Japanese have different lists of interactional pronouns indicates that this is the case. Relatedly, the sociolinguistic content of interactional pronouns is subject to changing societal pressures that result in the need for frequent innovation in the inventory. Thus, we might expect interactional pronouns to change more rapidly than paradigmatic pronouns. It certainly seems to be the case that the use of Japanese pronouns changes relatively quickly. For example, the use of anata varies between older and younger speakers, according to Kaiser et al. (Reference Kaiser, Ichikawa, Kobayashi and Yamamoto2013).Footnote 5

Given that the use of interactional pronouns is sensitive to gender, one might ask whether this is a type of phi-feature. A first indication that the gender specification on interactional pronouns is not a phi-feature comes from the observation that it does not trigger agreement (see Section 3.3.1). Additionally, gender in interactional pronouns does not form a natural class with person and number. It is part of a set of restrictions that also includes age, status, and aspects of the relationship between the interlocutors. Moreover, the use of a given speaker- or addressee-denoting pronoun may be restricted not only by the age and gender of the referent but also by the age and gender of the other interlocutor. This is illustrated in Table 1, based on the description of addressee-denoting interactional pronouns in Kaiser et al. (Reference Kaiser, Ichikawa, Kobayashi and Yamamoto2013:372–374). The types of restrictions illustrated in Table 1 contrast with phi-feature-based restrictions on paradigmatic pronouns. We note that formal pronouns in languages like French and German, whose use is sensitive to age and social status, are exceptional in this respect, and hence, we analyze them as derived interactional pronouns (see Section 4).

Table 1 Restrictions on addressee-oriented interactional pronouns

3.2.2. Avoiding pronouns for reasons of politeness

Helmbrecht (Reference Helmbrecht, Dryer and Haspelmath2013) developed a linguistic typology based on the number of politeness distinctions in the inventory of second-person pronouns. This typology divides languages into four types: those with no distinctions, those with a binary distinction, those with multiple distinctions, and those that avoid pronouns ‘for reasons of politeness’. Interestingly, this fourth type (to which Japanese belongs) is qualitatively different from the first three: the classification is based on the pronouns’ conditions of use. We argue that this qualitative difference reflects the fact that the first three types of languages have paradigmatic pronouns, whereas the fourth type of language has interactional pronouns (McDonald Reference McDonald2021). It is their rich sociolinguistic content that leads to complex restrictions on their conditions of use. Consequently, avoiding pronouns might be the socially safest thing to do.

Japanese makes available two strategies for avoiding interactional pronouns: using titles, names, or kinship terms and using a zero pronoun (pro). With respect to the first strategy, all the descriptive grammars of Japanese point out that titles, names, and kinship terms are preferred over the forms we are calling interactional pronouns. According to Kaiser et al. (Reference Kaiser, Ichikawa, Kobayashi and Yamamoto2013:137): ‘Japanese pronouns are intimately tied up with hierarchy and levels of respect. For this reason, the use of personal pronouns is generally avoided in formal relationships and situations; instead, name (family name + suffix of personal address) is preferred’ (see also Akiyama and Akiyama Reference Akiyama and Akiyama1991). This is illustrated in (23).

This avoidance strategy is not restricted to second-person pronouns but affects the use of all pronouns. For example, in (24) the kinship term otoo-san (‘father’) substitutes for a first-person pronoun.

Thus, in Japanese, titles, names, and kinship terms form a natural class with pronouns because they are all interactional and have a similar syntactic distribution. In contrast, in languages with paradigmatic pronouns, the use of titles, names, and kinship terms in place of pronouns is highly marked and is known as the imposter use (Collins and Postal Reference Collins and Postal2012), as illustrated in (25).

We now turn to the second strategy for avoiding interactional pronouns, namely the use of a zero pronoun (pro). In Japanese pro can occur in both subject and object position, as in (26). It is compatible with any person and number specification, and its interpretation is determined by the discourse context

We note that in some languages, paradigmatic pronouns can also be replaced by pro (and in these languages pro is licensed by rich agreement; Rizzi Reference Rizzi1986). However, in such languages, the use of pro is not determined by politeness but rather by economy considerations. The difference in the use conditions for pro as an alternative to paradigmatic versus interactional pronouns is reflected in its frequency of use (see McCraw Reference McCraw2010, Travis Reference Travis2007 for data and discussion).

3.2.3. Intrinsic referentiality

Recall that first- and second-person interactional pronouns occupy Spec,GroundP where they receive the role of ground-holder. Since ground-holders are always interpreted relative to the current interaction, the bearers of these roles necessarily denote the current speaker or addressee and, consequently, must be referential. Hence, these interactional pronouns will always be referential. Evidence for the intrinsic referentiality of Japanese first- and second-person pronouns comes from the observation that they cannot be used as impersonal pronouns. Thus, they are unlike paradigmatic pronouns, which can be used either personally or impersonally (e.g. Jespersen Reference Jespersen1909, Kitagawa and Lehrer Reference Kitagawa and Lehrer1990, Malamud Reference Malamud2006). This is illustrated in (27) and (28): English you can be interpreted impersonally, but Japanese anata cannot.

Kitagawa and Lehrer (Reference Kitagawa and Lehrer1990) show that Japanese pro, like English you, can be interpreted either personally or impersonally, as in (29).

Kitagawa and Lehrer’s (Reference Kitagawa and Lehrer1990:756) explanation of this fact accords with our hypothesis ‘[I]n languages like Japanese […], the so-called (lexical) personal pronouns, especially those having to do with first-and 2nd persons, are too closely tied to the actual speech act context. They are simply too loaded with semantic and pragmatic information.’ The intrinsic referentiality of Japanese interactional pronouns provides an additional property that distinguishes them from common nouns. Common nouns are never intrinsically referential; rather they require functional superstructure to be interpreted referentially.

3.3. Absence of phi-based grammatical properties

Our hypothesis that interactional pronouns lack phi-features correctly predicts that they will not trigger grammatical operations based on phi-features. We now show that they do not trigger phi-feature agreement (Section 3.3.1) or induce phi-based blocking effects in long-distance anaphora (Section 3.3.2). Taken together, these facts invite the conclusion that phi-features are simply absent in the grammar of Japanese.

3.3.1. No phi-feature agreement

If Japanese interactional pronouns lack phi-features, it follows that they will not trigger phi-feature agreement. This is indeed the case. Neither verbs nor DP internal modifiers display phi-feature agreement with interactional pronouns (or any other nominal).

First, as shown in (30), there is no subject agreement for person or number on the verb.

Second, there is no DP internal number agreement on modifiers or specifiers. To see this, we consider nominal phrases where a pronoun functions as the specifier of a common noun. Unlike in English, there is no agreement between the pronoun and the common noun in Japanese. If the Japanese pronoun is marked with the plural marker -tachi, the noun is not also marked for plural, as shown by the contrast between (31a) and (31b). This differs from the equivalent construction in English, as shown in (32).

We interpret this as an indication that the Japanese plural marker -tachi is a modifying pluralizer in the sense of Wiltschko (Reference Wiltschko2008), and not a head feature (Section 3.4).

The absence of phi-agreement with interactional pronouns is not surprising, given that it is a characteristic found more generally in the language (Kuroda Reference Kuroda1992). This raises the question as to whether there is a necessary correlation between the absence of phi-agreement and the absence of phi-features on pronouns. In the next section, we argue that the answer is no, based on a comparison of Japanese and Mandarin.

3.3.2. No phi-based blocking effects in long-distance anaphora

Blocking effects in long-distance anaphora were first discussed for Mandarin, where the reflexive anaphor ziji can be locally or long-distance bound (Huang Reference Huang1984), as in (33a). Significantly, both potential antecedents in (33a) are third-person DPs (Zhangsan and Lisi), and ziji can be bound by either. Blocking effects occur when a first- or second-person pronoun is the more local antecedent. This is illustrated in (33b), where ziji cannot be bound by Zhangsan due to the presence of the intervening a first- or second-person pronoun.

Importantly, this blocking effect has been attributed to the presence of phi-features on Mandarin pronouns (Huang and Tang Reference Huang, Tang, Koster and Reuland1991,Tang Reference Tang1985, Reference Tang1989). On our approach, this would suggest that Mandarin has paradigmatic pronouns. This is indeed the case, as evidenced by the fact that they form a phi-based paradigm of the familiar type, as shown in Table 2.

Table 2 Chinese paradigmatic pronouns

As for Japanese, Aikawa (Reference Aikawa1993) showed that the reflexive anaphor zibun can be either locally or long-distance bound, as in (34a). Aikawa also shows that the presence of a first-person pronoun does not block long-distance binding: zibun can be co-referent with any of the antecedents in (34b). In this respect, Japanese differs from Mandarin.

We attribute the difference in blocking effects between Japanese and Mandarin to a difference in the pronouns: Japanese has interactional pronouns, which, by hypothesis, lack phi-features and, hence, do not induce blocking effects. In contrast, Mandarin pronouns are paradigmatic bundles of phi-features, and these phi-features induce the observed blocking effect.

Thus, a lack of phi-agreement does not necessarily imply a lack of phi-features on pronouns. However, we contend that when there are no phi-features on pronouns, phi-agreement is simply unavailable and that this is the case in Japanese.

3.4. When person, number, and gender are not phi-features

As we have seen, Japanese interactional pronouns have content pertaining to person, number, and gender, which is like the content expressed by phi-features. In this section, we address questions raised by this fact in light of our claim that Japanese pronouns lack phi-features.

3.4.1. Person

Interactional pronouns are assigned the roles of the speaker, addressee, or another referent that is part of the speaker’s ground. This approximates the content of grammatical person phi-features. We now identify three distributional differences that we attribute to the difference between person as an interactional role and person as a phi-feature.

The first difference concerns impersonal pronouns. As a phi-feature, person need not be semantically interpreted.Footnote 6 In contrast, addressee-denoting interactional pronouns are inherently referential and cannot be used impersonally (see Section 3.2.3).

The second difference has to do with the use of pronouns in self-talk. Holmberg (Reference Holmberg, Zwart and de Vries2010) observes that when people talk to themselves, they can use either first- or second-person pronouns, as in (35).

Crucially, Japanese pronouns behave differently in the context of self-talk, as shown in (36). Although first-person pronouns are always possible, second-person pronouns are only felicitous if the individual is talking to an externalized image of themselves, for example, their reflection in a mirror.

We follow Ritter and Wiltschko (Reference Ritter, Wiltschko, Hernández and Plyley2021) in assuming that I-centered and you-centered self-talk are qualitatively different: when using the first-person pronoun, the speaker is thinking out loud and there is no addressee; when using the second-person pronoun, the speaker is having a conversation with themselves, and hence, they are treating themselves as an addressee. The Japanese pattern reveals that there is a difference in the role one adopts when talking to oneself with or without an externalized version of oneself. When looking in a mirror, an individual uses you-centered self-talk to address their mirror image, and consequently, the self-talking individual assumes the speaker role with the mirror image as the addressee. When there is no mirror, the self-talking individual using you-centred self-talk imagines a disembodied voice talking to them, and hence, they hold the addressee role (Gacea Reference Gacea, Pitteloud and Keeling2019:34; see also Ackema and Neeleman Reference Ackema and Neeleman2018). When a disembodied voice is the speaker, what is lacking is knowledge about the social relation between the speaker and the addressee. However, for the felicitous use of a Japanese second-person pronoun, this is precisely what is required. In contrast, paradigmatic pronouns with grammatical person do not have sociolinguistic requirements of this type.

One final consideration concerns the lack of clusivity in Japanese pronouns. Clusivity refers to a distinction between two types of first-person plural pronouns: inclusive first-person pronouns denote groups containing the speaker and the addressee(s), whereas exclusive first-person pronouns denote groups containing the speaker and others but crucially not the addressee(s). Following Ritter and Wiltschko (Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2019), we assume that this distinction is restricted to languages with person phi-features. This is because the combination of two binary person phi-features ([±1] and [±2]) gives rise to a four-way person distinction, as in Table 3.

Table 3 Person features

If this is the case, then the reason why Japanese has no clusivity distinction is that interactional pronouns receive their interpretation from the roles assigned to the specifier positions of the two GroundPs. Given the inventory of interactional roles, a dedicated inclusive interactional pronoun that simultaneously denotes the speaker and addressee may not be possible.Footnote 7

In Section 3.1.2, we proposed that third-person interactional pronouns are derived from nouns via movement into the specifier position of GroundSpkrP and that this movement gives rise to their interpretation as the content of the speaker’s ground. In this respect, they differ from paradigmatic third-person pronouns, which derive their interpretation from their person feature specification, [-1,-2]. Consequently, all interactional pronouns receive their person interpretation from their interactional roles, which they receive in the interactional structure.

3.4.2. Number

We now turn to the question as to how a number interpretation obtains in interactional pronouns in the absence of a number phi-feature. As discussed in Section 3.3.1, Japanese pronouns can be marked for plural via the suffix -tachi. We analyze -tachi as an associative plural marker syntactically realized as a modifier. As is typical of associative plural markers, -tachi can attach to proper names, and when it does, it triggers a group interpretation with the named individual as the focal member. The same associative interpretation applies to -tachi when it is suffixed to first- and second-person pronouns, with the speaker or addressee serving as the focal member. Interestingly, -tachi can also be suffixed to common nouns denoting humans. Nakanishi and Tomioka (Reference Nakanishi and Tomioka2004) demonstrate that even in this use -tachi has an associative interpretation. Thus, a plural interpretation is possible in the absence of a phi-feature, namely via a group-denoting associative plural marker.

The analysis of -tachi as a modifying pluralizer is consistent with the fact that -tachi does not trigger agreement (see Section 3.3.1). According to Wiltschko (Reference Wiltschko2008), modifying features do not trigger syntactic relations, including agreement. Additionally, Wiltschko argues that heads are obligatory while modifiers are optional and that this constitutes a diagnostic for modifying plural markers. Interestingly, -tachi is only optional when it occurs on nouns (see Section 3.1.1). In the absence of plural marking, nouns have general number and can be interpreted as either singular or plural. However, when pronouns and proper names are unmarked, they are interpreted as singular, and -tachi is obligatory for a plural interpretation. We attribute the contrast between common nouns, on the one hand, and pronouns and names, on the other, to their referential properties. Although common nouns are nonreferential predicates and are therefore number-neutral, pronouns and names are referential expressions and are therefore number-specific. Pronouns and names denote unique, singular individuals. Consequently, for them to be interpreted as plural requires explicit plural marking.

In sum, the distribution of -tachi is consistent with our hypothesis that Japanese pronouns do not contain phi-features. The fact that Japanese plural pronouns have plural markers is not evidence to the contrary: a plural interpretation is possible through other means, and in Japanese this obtains via the modifying associative plural marker.

3.4.3. Gender

We now show that information about gender in Japanese pronouns comes about in two ways. For third-person pronouns, gender is due to their lexical content, and for first- and second-person pronouns, a gendered interpretation is due to the use of backgrounded stereotypes about gender roles (McCready Reference McCready2019:110).

We adopt McCready’s analysis of the apparent gender specification of Japanese first- and second-person pronouns and briefly review her analysis here. McCready argues that Japanese pronouns lack gender content of any kind. It follows that they lack a gender phi-feature. Rather, based on her analysis, their gendered interpretation arises from expressive predication (in the sense of Potts Reference Potts2007). As part of their lexical denotation, they contain a predicate which gives rise to non-truth-conditional, not-at-issue meaning. For example, the first-person pronoun watashi is specified as ‘reserved’, and the second-person pronoun ore is specified as ‘rough’. McCready argues that these expressive predicates are stereotypically associated with specific genders: ‘reserved’ with female and ‘rough’ with male, and that this is how the gendered interpretation comes about. Evidence for this analysis stems from apparent gender mismatches, which are quite common for these forms. For example, ore is typically used by males as per the stereotypical association of ‘rough’. However, women frequently use ore, especially in-group (see McCready Reference McCready2019, Miyazaki Reference Miyazaki, Okamoto and Smith2004, Okamoto and Shibamoto Smith Reference Okamoto and Smith2016). As for watashi, the mismatches show an interesting interaction with formality. When a female speaker uses watashi, she can do so in both formal and informal contexts, but when a male speaker uses watashi, it is restricted to formal contexts. McCready attributes this difference to sociocultural norms, according to which being reserved is generally required in formal but not in informal contexts. Consequently, males and females can use watashi in a formal context. However, in informal contexts the use of watashi is determined by gender stereotypes. Females are stereotypically required to be reserved, but males are required to be the opposite. Hence, the use of watashi in informal contexts is expected for females but odd for males. These facts of Japanese pronoun usage demonstrate that a gendered interpretation can come about in the absence of phi-features.

3.5. Interim summary

We have now argued that Japanese has interactional pronouns. They differ from paradigmatic pronouns in their content: paradigmatic pronouns have grammatical phi-features, while interactional pronouns have sociolinguistic content. Additionally, they also differ from nouns in their syntactic distribution. Nouns can be directly modified by an adjective or specified by a demonstrative or possessor, whereas pronouns cannot. Furthermore, nouns differ from pronouns in terms of their number interpretation. Although bare nouns are interpreted as either singular or plural (i.e. general number), bare pronouns are necessarily singular. When a plural interpretation is intended, pronouns must be marked for plural. According to our analysis, Japanese pronouns behave neither like paradigmatic pronouns nor like nouns because they are neither. Rather, they instantiate a third type of nominal, namely interactional pronouns. As such they are intrinsically referential and loaded with sociolinguistic content, which is why they are often avoided for reasons of politeness. Moreover, as interactional pronouns, which are inserted directly in the interactional structure, they lack phi-features. This lack of phi-features, however, does not imply that interactional pronouns cannot encode similar content (i.e. person, number, and gender), but they must do so in different ways.

The existence of intrinsic interactional pronouns raises the question of whether the interactional structure could also be occupied as a result of movement from within the functional structure. If so, then we expect there to be pronouns with both phi-features and sociolinguistic content. In what follows, we argue that this is a promising way of analyzing formal pronouns of the T–V type.

4. Reanalyzing Formal Pronouns as Derived Interactional Pronouns

One of the core characteristics of interactional pronouns is their sensitivity to the identity of the interlocutors and the relation between them. This is reminiscent of formality distinctions in paradigmatic pronouns used for addressees in languages like French and German. So, are formal pronouns in these languages interactional or paradigmatic? In this section, we develop an analysis according to which paradigmatic pronouns can be recycled as interactional pronouns. In other words, they are derived interactional pronouns, as schematized in (37).

Recycling is a movement operation in which a given form is inserted in one position, where it receives an interpretation, and is subsequently moved into a higher position, where it receives a new interpretation (Mezhevich Reference Mezhevich2008). The new interpretation is determined by the interpretive content of this higher position. Thus, recycling differs from canonical syntactic movement in that the interpretive content of the moved form is reinterpreted in a higher position.Footnote 8

4.1. Formality in French pronouns

The French pronominal paradigm contains a second-person formal pronoun (vous), and significantly, this pronoun is identical to the second-person plural form. We propose that formal vous is derived via recycling of the second-person plural pronoun. That is, vous is first inserted DP internally with second-person plural phi-features. If it remains in this position, it receives its unmarked interpretation. When vous is used as a formal pronoun, it moves to the interactional structure, where it receives a marked formal interpretation. Hence, we assume that formal vous is interpreted in two different structural positions, as schematized in (38).

Recycling does not affect the grammatical features of the pronoun, but it does affect its interpretation, resulting in an apparent mismatch: It can be used to refer to either a singular or a plural addressee to signal formality. This differs from previous analyses of the T–V distinction, according to which formal pronouns have a morpho-syntactic honorific feature (e.g. Ackema and Neeleman Reference Ackema and Neeleman2018). Such analyses raise the question as to why this feature does not trigger agreement on the verb as phi-features do. There cannot be a general constraint against honorific agreement, as there are languages (for example, Maithili) with dedicated honorific paradigmatic pronouns that trigger honorific agreement on the verb (Kumari, Reference Kumari2023).

We now address the question as to how plurality can be reinterpreted as formality. Consider first what happens when there is no recycling and the plural feature is interpreted in the usual way. In this case, there are two or more addressees, each of which has their own knowledge state (i.e. their individual grounds). Thus, the common ground shared by the addressees is the intersection of the individual grounds of each member of the set. The ground to be considered is the knowledge the speaker assumes all addressees share. To see this, consider Figure 1, which represents a conversational interaction between three interlocutors. The speaker knows propositions p, q, and r, Addressee 1 knows q and r, and Addressee 2 knows only r. These constitute their respective grounds. The intersection of these grounds is r, and this is their common ground. This means that in the presence of multiple addressees, the content of the common ground shrinks, as it only includes knowledge shared between the speaker and all addressees.

Figure 1 Common ground between speaker and two addressees.

We now turn to the formal use of vous. We assume that vous is always first inserted in a DP internal position. This assumption is motivated by the fact that formal vous – like plural vous – triggers second-person plural agreement on the verb, as in (39).

Because agreement is a grammatical operation targeting phi-features, and phi-features are, by hypothesis, associated with functional categories, it follows that pronouns that have phi-features must originate in the functional structure. As for the interpretation of formal vous, we propose that the plural feature has its usual interpretive effect, regardless of how many actual addressees there are. In the absence of a plural addressee, the plural feature signals the presence of a hypothetical generic addressee whose knowledge state consists of the set of propositions that constitute general knowledge (G). Thus, in a formal context the common ground is reduced to general knowledge, as in Figure 2.

Figure 2 Common ground between speaker and formal addressee.

Introducing a generic addressee is intended to capture the intuition that, when the speaker is in a formal relationship with the addressee, the speaker’s contribution to the conversation is such that they only take into consideration what would be known by everyone. On this view, the speaker might be aware of things that the actual addressee knows (e.g. q in Figure 2), but the use of vous signals that the speaker does not engage with this knowledge, either because the addressee is of higher social status or because of the formal discourse context.

An anonymous reviewer points out that according to their intuition, polite forms can be used to discuss the exact same knowledge state of the actual addressee as the informal ones, including knowledge that only that addressee may possess. We agree with this observation; however, we do not think that this is a counterargument to our claim. Specifically, our analysis seeks to capture the fact that with the use of the formal pronoun, the speaker signals politeness, where politeness can be understood from the classic pragmatic perspective that puts the notion of face-saving at center stage. That is, by introducing a generic addressee by grammatical means (plural and/or third-person phi-features), the grammar encodes that the speaker does not directly access (and hence does not impose on) the addressee’s knowledge state. Mismatches between grammatical form and real-world knowledge in the way the reviewer points out are, in fact, expected just as they are in other grammatical domains (e.g. gender).

4.2. Formality in German pronouns

We now turn to German, where the third-person plural pronoun (sie) functions as the addressee-denoting formal pronoun. We argue that the German formal Sie is derived via recycling of the third-person plural pronoun. We assume that the interpretation of plural in the interactional layer proceeds as in French: It introduces a generic addressee. We further assume that third-person has the phi-feature specification [-1,-2], which does not correspond to the interactional role in Spec,GroundAdrP. The question we have to address now is how [-1,-2] is interpreted in the interactional structure.

We begin by considering what happens when there is no recycling, and [-1,-2] is interpreted in the usual way, namely as a third-person individual who is not a participant in the interaction. We assume that the common ground represents the knowledge state of the interlocutors but does not contain any information about what non-interlocutors know. Hence, the set of propositions that a particular non-interlocutor knows does not enter into the calculation of the common ground.

Turning now to the contribution of the grammatical person features in the formal use of Sie, we propose that the third-person specification contributes to its recycled interpretation: [-1,-2] introduces a non-participant, whose knowledge state does not enter into the calculation of the common ground. In other words, the third-person specification of Sie indicates that the actual addressee is treated like a non-participant; the speaker makes no assumptions about their knowledge state. This is the way a third-person is always interpreted, and in Figure 3, we represent this as an opaque ground, which does not intersect with that of the speaker or the addressee. As with vous, the plural specification introduces a generic addressee with general knowledge (G).

Figure 3 No common ground between the speaker and formal addressee.

The recycling analysis raises the question of whether it is possible to treat a singular non-participant pronoun ([-1,-2,-plural]) as an actual addressee without simultaneously introducing a generic addressee. In other words, can a third-person singular pronoun be recycled with the result that the actual addressee is represented as a non-participant, as in Figure 4. We argue that this was the case in earlier stages of German, where a singular third-person pronoun was used as a formal pronoun (see Simon Reference Simon, Taavitsainen and Jucker2003).

Figure 4 No common ground between the speaker and nonparticipant.

Taken together, the facts about the use of Sie and er to refer to the addressee indicate that the third-person specification signals a discrepancy in status between speaker and addressee: In both cases, the speaker does not consider the knowledge state of the current addressee. The difference between Sie and er lies in the number feature: The specification [+plural] introduces the generic addressee, whereas the specification [-plural] does not.

Finally, like French vous, German Sie always triggers the same agreement on the verb, whether it is used as the unmarked third-person plural pronoun or as the marked formal pronoun, as in (40).

Given the analyses we have just developed for French vous and German Sie (and er), the question arises as to whether the analytical difference affects the context of the use of these two types of formal pronouns. A more precise characterization of what counts as a formal context will have to be developed to answer this question, and a systematic sociolinguistic study is required. This goes beyond the scope of the present paper.

4.3. Typological consequences

We have now argued that paradigmatic pronouns, like interactional ones, can be realized in the interactional layer. We depart from previous analyses in that we do not assume a mismatch between the features and interpretation of formal pronouns. Both the plural and third-person specifications are interpreted literally: the former introduces an additional addressee (i.e., the generic addressee), and the latter treats the actual addressee as a non-participant for the purpose of constructing the common ground.

Our approach, which makes a novel distinction between paradigmatic pronouns and interactional pronouns, offers new insights into the typological facts of formality distinctions in second-person pronouns documented by Helmbrecht (Reference Helmbrecht, Dryer and Haspelmath2013). Languages that he classifies as avoiding the use of pronouns have interactional pronouns. In these languages, the information about social relations encoded in interactional pronouns is complex and nuanced, and speakers avoid using them to minimize the risk of a social faux pas. The operation of recycling that gives rise to formal pronouns in T–V languages is a complex operation that is not necessary for well-formedness and thus marked.

In a T–V language, there are also contexts in which speakers prefer to avoid using formal pronouns, for example, when the social relation is unclear. However, unlike the languages that Helmbrecht characterizes as avoiding the use of pronouns, strategies to avoid pronouns in T–V languages are much more involved, in that they require paraphrasing as impersonal or passives, for example. As we have seen, Japanese allows for either pro drop or the use of titles instead.

Because recycling is a marked option, this analysis correctly predicts that languages with formality distinctions of this type will constitute a minority among languages with paradigmatic pronouns. Furthermore, it correctly predicts that the greater the number of recycled pronominal forms, the more marked (and less common) the system will be. Hence systems with two degrees of formality (like French and contemporary German) should be more frequent than systems with three degrees. As illustrated in Table 4, these typological predictions are indeed borne out.

Table 4 Typology of degrees of formality in pronominal systems (Helmbrecht Reference Helmbrecht, Dryer and Haspelmath2013)

Our analysis focuses not on the number of formality distinctions but rather on their source: Formality can be introduced via intrinsic interactional pronouns or recycled paradigmatic pronouns. Everything else being equal, we might expect to find languages where a two-way distinction is derived not by recycling a pronoun but by inserting an interactional pronoun directly into the interactional structure. Thus, there is no reason why paradigmatic and interactional pronouns could not coexist in a single language.

In this context, an anonymous reviewer points out that the Dutch formal pronoun u might be a candidate for an interactional pronoun that coexists with a set of paradigmatic pronouns. This pronoun presents an interesting challenge as it appears to differ from both intrinsic interactional pronouns and recycled ones. Specifically, it differs from vous and Sie in that it is not homophonous with a paradigmatic pronoun. However, u triggers phi-agreement on the verb; in this respect, it differs from intrinsic interactional pronouns. This combination of properties suggests that u is a pronoun with obligatorily recycled phi-features. One possible explanation for the obligatoriness of recycling in the case of u is diachronic in nature. Specifically, according to Etymologisch woordenboek ven het Nederlands, u derives from uwe edelheid ‘Your Nobleness’, which was used in writing and abbreviated as ‘UE’. This may have eventually led to the current pronunciation. If so, then u, in fact, derives from an imposter, like Spanish usted. (See Collins and Ordóñez Reference Collins and Ordóñez2021 for an analysis of Spanish usted as an imposter and see Section 4.4 for a discussion of imposters.)

If u is obligatorily recycled, then its syntactic structure necessarily includes an interactional layer. This analysis of the formal pronoun u correctly predicts two differences between u and the regular paradigmatic second-person pronoun. First, u has no weak counterpart, whereas the regular paradigmatic second-person pronoun has both a strong and a weak form (jij and je). Second, u cannot be used as an impersonal pronoun, whereas je, the weak form of the paradigmatic second-person pronoun, can. We attribute both differences to the obligatory presence of interactional structure as part of u. According to Ritter and Wiltschko (Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2019), this layer is present in Dutch strong pronouns and missing in weak ones. Moreover, they argue that when a second-person pronoun contains an interactional structure, its reference is restricted to the current addressee, and hence, it is incompatible with an impersonal interpretation, as in (41).

Thus, formal pronouns can be derived in at least three ways: base-generated in the interactional layer, optionally moved into the interactional layer, or obligatorily moved into the interactional layer.

4.4. The difference between kare-type pronouns and formal pronouns

In Section 3, we identified another type of derived interactional pronoun: Japanese kare and kanojo. These are third-person pronouns that derive from common nouns. When used as pronouns, most of their semantic content is removed, and all that remains is their gender. Importantly, since kare and kanojo are interpreted as third-person interactional pronouns, we analyze them as denoting the content rather than the holder of the ground. The similarities and differences between the two types of derived interactional pronouns are summarized in Table 5.

Table 5 Two types of derived interactional pronouns

There are two descriptive differences between formal pronouns and kare pronouns: (i) the source of the derived pronoun (pronoun or noun); and (ii) their interpretation in the interactional layer (ground-holder or ground content). These differences define two parameters of variation, and the question arises as to whether there is a correlation between them. In other words, are interactional pronouns that derive from paradigmatic pronouns necessarily interpreted as ground-holders? And are those that derive from nouns necessarily interpreted as ground content? We introduce evidence suggesting that the answer to both questions is no. First, we show that there are nouns that can be interpreted in the interactional structure as ground-holders. Second, we show that there are other types of functional items that can be interpreted as ground content.

There are two contexts where we find nouns that are interpreted in the interactional structure as ground-holders: vocatives and imposters. Consider first the vocatives in (42).

These examples illustrate different types of nominals that can serve as vocatives: proper names (42a), and bare common nouns (42b, 42c). Crucially, vocatives are not propositional arguments; they are terms of address. In the present analysis, this means that these nouns are interpreted as holders of the addressee’s ground.

Next, consider imposters, which are exemplified in (43).

Imposters are so called because they consist of a non-pronominal DP, which is exceptionally interpreted as an interlocutor. For example, in (43a), the present authors is interpreted as referring to the authors of the current text, and hence, could be replaced by we; similarly in (43b), this reporter is interpreted as referring to the speaker (or author) of the current utterance (or text) and could be replaced by I/me; and in (43c), Your Majesty refers to the King, who is also the current addressee, and thus could be replaced by you (barring social norms). Like vocatives, imposters contain a noun but are interpreted in the interactional structure as ground-holders. However, unlike vocatives, imposters also serve as propositional arguments. We can thus conclude that nouns can be (re-)interpreted as either ground content or as ground-holders.

Next, we turn to the question of whether functional items can be (re-)interpreted as ground content. Colasanti and Wiltschko (Reference Colasanti and Wiltschko2019) propose that spatial demonstrative determiners can be recycled in the interactional structure, like paradigmatic personal pronouns. They argue that in their discourse use, the English demonstratives this and that denote the ground content. To see this, consider the examples in (44).

The proximal form this in (44a) is recycled in the speaker’s ground and thus interpreted as a discourse referent that is novel in the sense that it is unfamiliar to the addressee. In contrast, the distal form that in (44b) is recycled in the addressee’s ground and thus interpreted as a discourse referent, which is familiar to both the speaker and addressee. This indicates that functional items, like nouns, can be (re-)interpreted as ground content as well as ground-holders.

We have now seen that the two parameters of variation (source category and interactional role) do not correlate. The resulting typology of derived interactional nominals is summarized in Table 6.

Table 6 Typology of derived interactional nominals

This section’s goal was to establish that the recycling mechanism we proposed for kare and kanojo is not specific to these third-person pronouns; it also captures the facts of formal second-person pronouns derived from paradigmatic ones, vocatives, imposters, and discourse demonstratives.

5. Why Nominal (Rather Than Clausal) Interactional Structure is the Locus of Formality

The postulation of nominal interactional structure is the linchpin of our account for the expression of formality in pronouns. We have looked at two qualitatively different types of pronouns, both of which require the presence of nominal interactional structure, albeit in different ways: Japanese interactional pronouns are directly associated with interactional structure, while formal pronouns of the T-V type are recycled into this position. As a result, the two types of pronouns differ. Our analysis departs from the one developed by Portner et al. (Reference Portner, Pak and Zanuttini2019), according to which formality is intrinsically associated with a functional category in the left periphery of the root clause (their cP). In this section, we point out some shortcomings of their proposal and argue that the postulation of nominal interactional structure provides the basis for an empirically more adequate analysis.

5.1. A unified analysis for politeness content

Portner et al.’s (Reference Portner, Pak and Zanuttini2019) analysis aims to unify two seemingly disparate empirical domains: (i) speech-style particles in Korean and (ii) the formality distinction in Italian second-person pronouns. Their goal is to understand a conundrum that these two phenomena present: Portner et al. claim that, on the one hand, both the particles and pronouns encode the same pragmatic information, but on the other hand, they differ in syntactic distribution. Specifically, both encode information pertaining to formality or politeness between the interlocutors, but Korean speech-style particles only occur in root clauses, whereas Italian second-person pronouns are not so restricted.

To account for these observations, Portner et al. propose that there is a functional category in the left periphery of the root clause, which they label cP (where c suggests context). They further propose that the specifier of cP hosts the interactional argument of addressee, whereas the head of cP contains information about the relation between the speaker and addressee. They implement this proposal with two grammatical features: (i) a multivalent feature expressing the relative status of the speaker and addressee ([S<A], [S≤A], [S=A], [S≥A], [S>A]) and (ii) a binary feature expressing the formality of the situation ([±formal]).

In their analysis, Korean speech-style particles are in the head of cP, and consequently, they can only occur in root clauses. This is because cP is not embeddable for reasons having to do with its semantics, that is, it denotes a performative relation. In contrast, Italian second-person pronouns appear inside the clause below cP but are interpreted in c (via binding). This accounts for the observation that these pronouns are not restricted to root clauses even though they seem to have the same politeness content as Korean speech-style particles. The politeness content in pronouns is associated with status features that are interpreted in c. For example, Italian Lei is specified as [status: S<A] while tu is specified as [status: S≥A]. Given the assumption that the content in the cP layer binds these pronouns, the formality and status of the utterance is set in c. In what follows, we point out some shortcomings of Portner et al.’s treatment of formal pronouns.

5.2. Problems with a unified analysis

We identify two problematic aspects that differentiate Portner et al.’s analysis from ours. First, they take the clausal projection c as the locus of formality and status for the entire utterance, and second, they represent formality and status as grammatical features with a limited set of values.

The assumption that the formality of the context and the status of the addressee are both set in c entails that there is a single setting of formality and status for the entire utterance. This incorrectly predicts that within a given sentence, we should not find instances of both formal and informal pronouns. For example, when talking to two addressees of different status it is possible to coordinate a formal with an informal pronoun, as shown in the German example in (45).

The problem with (45) is that the formality feature in c would be incompatible with one of the pronouns. This clash in formality is problematic for any analysis that entails a single setting for formality in a given utterance (see also Alok Reference Alok2020; Donovan and Palaz Reference Donovan and Palaz2022).

Next, we turn to problems with the assumption that formality and status are represented as grammatical features with a limited set of values. An immediate problem arises when considering a conversation between two interlocutors with different statuses, such as employer and employee. The status would be [employer > employee], and this is reflected in the fact that the formal pronoun is used. In German, the employee uses the formal pronoun to address the employer as expected by the specification as [S<A]. However, what is unexpected in this analysis is the fact that the same formal pronoun is also used by the employer to address the employee. In this case, the feature specification would be [S>A]. Note that this is true regardless of the formality of the context. Both interlocutors will always use formal pronouns, even when talking in an informal setting, such as a party, as in (46).

What the example in (46) demonstrates is that the feature specification of the formal pronoun cannot simply be [S<A], as it is also used when the opposite hierarchical relation holds. Similarly, it would not suffice to specify the pronoun (or context) as [+formal], as the use of a formal pronoun is not restricted to formal contexts. An anonymous reviewer suggests that the use of the same pronoun by the employer might simply indicate that they intend to be polite to the employee as well, and hence, they might express this with the same feature specification [S<A]. Evidence that this is not the case can be gleaned from differences in the forms of address they might use. For example, professors and students use formal pronouns in a university context. However, they differ in the form of vocatives that they use. Professors address their students using their last name and optionally a title (such as Herr). In contrast, students must address the Professor with their title (with or without the last name).

Another problem with the feature specification proposed in Portner et al. is that it cannot capture the qualitative difference between the formal pronouns of a T–V system and the open-ended pronoun inventory found in Japanese. A T–V system of the type discussed in Portner et al. is characterized by a dichotomy between an informal and a formal second-person pronoun. In contrast, as we have seen, the pronominal system of Japanese cannot be characterized in this way. Specifically, there are more than two second-person pronouns, each containing sociolinguistic information that goes well beyond status and formality. One would have to increase the inventory of available features to capture the Japanese forms. However, this still would not capture the other systematic differences between T-V pronouns and Japanese pronouns, such as the presence or absence of phi-agreement.

5.3. Why nominal interactional structure is needed

The problems for Portner et al.’s (Reference Portner, Pak and Zanuttini2019) analysis discussed here do not arise if one assumes that formality is encoded independently in each nominal. That is, if each nominal has an interactional layer, then each nominal has its own formality and status setting and is not dependent on clausal interactional structure for its interpretation. Furthermore, the assumption of a nominal interactional structure makes it possible to account for the qualitative difference between two types of pronouns with sociolinguistic content: intrinsic interactional pronouns of the Japanese type and interactional pronouns that are derived from paradigmatic ones. The interpretation of intrinsic interactional pronouns derives from their interactional role and not their feature content. Consequently, they form an open-ended class with nuanced sociolinguistic content. In contrast, the interpretation of derived interactional pronouns is constrained by their phi-feature content, which is recycled and reinterpreted in the interactional structure.

The proposal of nominal interactional structure, which is characterized not by phi-features but rather by interactional content, has implications well beyond the typology of formal pronouns. For example, we have seen that Japanese intrinsic interactional pronouns correlate with the absence of phi-features more generally. This correlation remains a coincidence in the analysis developed by Portner et al. but follows straightforwardly from ours. Similarly, our proposal immediately derives the fact that interactional pronouns cannot receive an impersonal interpretation, but paradigmatic pronouns can. This is something Portner et al. (Reference Portner, Pak and Zanuttini2019:27 Fn.25) observe but set aside.

Importantly, we have argued that postulating nominal interactional structure makes it possible to have a representation of formality, status and politeness without recourse to grammatical formality and status features. Moreover, our approach allows for a straightforward analysis of other interactional phenomena, such as vocatives and terms of address. An analysis that treats the representation of interaction as an extension of the nominal constituent allows us to correlate the distinctive distributional properties of interactional nominals with their distinctive structural properties. We submit that such an analysis is more explanatorily adequate than an alternative that relies solely on a difference in nominal features.

6. Conclusion

We started this paper with a brief discussion of Greenberg’s (Reference Greenberg and Greenberg1966) Universal 42, according to which all languages have pronominal categories involving at least three persons and two numbers. We discussed empirical problems with this universal. One of these has to do with Japanese, where forms that are typically referred to as pronouns have rich sociolinguistic content and a very different distribution from phi-based pronouns in French and German. For this reason, Japanese pronouns are sometimes characterized as noun-like, although they do not have the same distribution as nouns either.

The core of this paper was devoted to developing an analysis that solves this conundrum. We argued that the so-called pronouns in Japanese are neither nouns nor paradigmatic pronouns; rather, they belong to another category of nominals that we call interactional pronouns. We proposed that interactional pronouns are structurally distinct from paradigmatic pronouns. Specifically, we argued that interactional pronouns are inserted in an interactional structure above the DP. This gives rise to a three-way distinction among nominal expressions, as summarized in (19) and repeated here in (47).

We extended this analysis to account for formality distinctions in languages with paradigmatic pronouns. We argued that formality distinctions in French and German pronouns are amenable to an analysis whereby the pronoun is inserted in the functional structure and recycled in the interactional structure, where its phi-features take on a new significance that can be exploited for sociolinguistic purposes. In this view then, formality is neither part of the phi-feature bundle of a pronominal paradigm, nor is it a dedicated feature within a pronominal paradigm. In this respect, our analysis is more parsimonious than that of Portner et al. (Reference Portner, Pak and Zanuttini2019), which assumes dedicated features for formality and status.

We now return to our original question and ask whether Greenberg’s Universal 42 is really universal. Our answer is yes and no. What appears to be universal is that all languages have nominal expressions that substitute for lexical noun phrases. However, if we are correct about the analysis of Japanese pronouns, then paradigmatic pronouns are not universal. But this raises the question of why all languages should have paradigmatic or interactional pronouns. Given that they do not constitute a natural class, why do we find one or the other (or possibly both) in all languages? The simple answer is that the architecture of nominals allows for the construction of such forms. In other words, given the complexity of the structure above the lexical layer, languages can construct noun substitutes in various ways.

Our proposal has significant implications to be explored in future research. First, consider the consequences of postulating pronouns that lack phi-features. One might ask whether there is a principled reason why a language might have intrinsic interactional pronouns rather than paradigmatic ones. We speculate that the answer might have to do with the absence of phi-features in the language. This is consistent with the fact that Japanese lacks overt phi-feature agreement and blocking effects in long-distance anaphora. Thus, it is not obvious that there is any evidence for phi-features elsewhere in the grammar. If it turns out that Japanese does indeed lack phi-features, then this would have significant consequences for syntactic theory more generally. For example, are there agree relations in a language without phi-features, and if so, how are they formed? Does the existence of interactional pronouns in a language point towards a more general tendency of the language to organize its grammar around interactional content? For example, is there an interactional equivalent to phi-based agreement relations? And if so, would this be restricted to languages without phi-features?

Another question that arises is which nominals include an interactional structure. Is there evidence that all referential nominals also include interactional structure? One possible reason why one might assume that this is the case has to do with the fact that at least some nominals are sensitive to the identity of the interlocutors and the context of use (e.g. kinship terms, titles, and names). Their sensitivity to context is reminiscent of the conditions of use we have observed for Japanese interactional pronouns. To see this, consider the examples in (48), which illustrate differences in the conditions of use for Mommy and the mother.

Mommy can only be used when referring to the mother of at least one of the interlocutors, whereas the mother is used when referring to the mother of someone other than the speaker or addressee.

On conceptual grounds, the presence of an interactional structure may be justified as it provides a locus for the context-sensitivity of such nominals. In this way, the interpretive content of interactional structure is reminiscent of a contextual variable that restricts the interpretation of quantified nominals, as in (49). In this example, the domain of quantification is restricted to a particular context, such as the graduate syntax class we are teaching. As a result, (49) does not mean that every student in the world got an A, but only those in our syntax class.

Adding a contextual variable to the representation of quantified nominals allows for a compositional analysis of the contextual restriction on the interpretation of this type of nominal. In the same way, adding an interactional structure may serve as the locus for the contextual restriction on the use of interactional nominals, which would permit a compositional analysis of the facts we considered here. We submit that an analysis of this type is more constrained than one that would consider these facts purely pragmatic.

Acknowledgments

The authors acknowledge Brittany MacDonald for many fruitful discussions of what we are now calling interactional pronouns, Kimiko Nakanishi and Carol Tenny for sharing their insights and knowledge of Japanese and Susanne Carroll and Anne Bertrand for helping us better understand the use of tu and vous in French. We are also grateful to the audience at the YYC Syntax Workshop on Pronouns, and the anonymous reviewers of this article for questions, comments and suggestions that significantly improved the content of this paper. This research was funded by SSHRC grant no. 435-2018-1011.

Footnotes

1 We use the glossing abbreviations listed in the Leipzig Glossing Rules (https://www.eva.mpg.de/lingua/resources/glossing-rules.php), as well as the following: frml = formal; ger = gerund; npst = non-past; pol = polite; rem = remote; sfp = sentence final particle; stat = stative.

2 We thank Kimiko Nakanishi, p.c. for providing these data.

3 An anonymous reviewer points out that the use of kare and kanojo as nouns is a recent innovation that developed from their use as third-person pronouns. We assume that synchronically they are in fact nouns and that this constitutes a case of degrammaticalization, in the sense of Lehmann (Reference Lehmann2015).

4 We are grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pointing out the significance of this observation, as well as for providing us with the data in (22).

5 See Yonezawa (Reference Yonezawa2021) for an illuminating discussion of the complex use conditions of anata.

6 The impersonal use of second-person paradigmatic pronouns is an instance of person not being semantically interpreted. On the impersonal use, second-person pronouns are not interpreted as referring to the current addressee. The possibility of remaining semantically uninterpreted is a general property of phi-features. Gender is not semantically interpreted on inanimate nouns and plural number is not semantically interpreted on pluralia tantum. Nevertheless, all phi-features are grammatically active as evidenced by the fact that they enter into the same agreement relations, regardless of whether they are semantically interpreted.

7 An anonymous reviewer suggests that inclusive interactional pronouns could be derived via movement of a pronoun from Spec,GroundSpkr into Spec,GroundAdr. Whether such pronouns exist and whether they are qualitatively different from paradigmatic inclusive pronouns is an empirical question that needs to be explored in future research.

8 See Massam (Reference Massam2009) for an analysis that entails a similar movement operation for Niuean plural markers.

References

Abney, Stephen. 1987. The English noun phrase in its sentential aspect. Cambridge, MA: MIT, PhD dissertation.Google Scholar
Ackema, Peter & Neeleman, Ad. 2018. Features of person. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aikawa, Takako. 1993. Reflexivity in Japanese and LF-analysis of zibun-binding. Columbus, OH: The Ohio State University, PhD dissertation.Google Scholar
Akiyama, Nobuo and Akiyama, Carol. 1991. Japanese grammar. Hauppage, NY: Barron’s.Google Scholar
Alok, Deepak. 2020. Speaker and addressee in natural language: honorificity, indexicality and their interaction in Magahi. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University, PhD dissertation.Google Scholar
Borer, Hagit. 2005. In name only. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 1970. Remarks on nominalization. In Roderick, A. Jacobs and Peter, S. Rosenbaum, (eds.) Readings in English transformational grammar, 184221. Waltham, MA: Ginn.Google Scholar
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2010. The syntax of adjectives. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colasanti, Valentina and Wiltschko, Martina. 2019. Spatial and discourse deixis and the speech act structure of nominals. In Proceedings of the 2019 Annual Conference of the Canadian Linguistic Association. 114. Toronto: Canadian Linguistic Association. Accessed 6 July 2024. https://cla-acl.ca/pdfs/actes-2019/Colasanti-Wiltschko-CLA-2019.pdfGoogle Scholar
Collins, Chris and Postal, Paul Martin. 2012. Imposters: a study of pronominal agreement. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Chris and Ordóñez, Francisco. 2021. Spanish usted as an imposter. Probus. 33. 249269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Déchaine, Rose-Marie and Wiltschko, Martina. 2002. Decomposing pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry. 33(3). 409442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donovan, Michael and Palaz, Bilge. 2022. Formal values on pronouns are not bound by an operator. Unpublished manuscript. Newark, DE: University of Delaware.Google Scholar
Espinal, Maria Teresa. 2013. On the structure of vocatives. In Sonnenhauser, Barbara and Hanna, Patrizia Noel Aziz, (eds.), Vocative!, 109132. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Gacea, Alexandru O. 2019. Plato and the ‘internal dialogue’: an ancient answer for a new model of the self. In Pitteloud, Luca and Keeling, Evan, (eds.), Psychology and ontology in Plato, 3354. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenberg, Joseph H. 1966. Some universals of grammar with particular reference to the order of meaningful elements. In Greenberg, Joseph H., (ed.), Universals of language (2nd edition), 73113). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grimshaw, Jane. 2000. Locality and extended projection. In Coopmans, Peter, Martin, B.H. Everaert and Grimshaw, Jane, (eds.), Lexical specification and insertion, 115134. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haegeman, Liliane. 2014. West Flemish verb‐based discourse markers and the articulation of the speech act layer. Studia Linguistica. 68. 116139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harley, Heidi and Ritter, Elizabeth. 2002. Person and number in pronouns: a feature–geometric analysis. Language. 78(3). 482526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hasegawa, Nobuko. 1985. On the so-called ‘zero pronouns’ in Japanese. The Linguistic Review. 4(4). 289342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hashimoto, Shinkichi. 1948. Kokugohoo kenkyuu [Studies in Japanese grammar]. Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten.Google Scholar
Helmbrecht, Johannes. 2013. Politeness distinctions in pronouns. In Dryer, Matthew S. and Haspelmath, Martin, (eds.), The world atlas of language structures online. Leipzig: Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology.Google Scholar
Hill, Virginia. 2007. Vocatives and the pragmatics–syntax interface. Lingua. 117. 20772105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, Virginia. 2013. Vocatives: how syntax meets with pragmatics. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Hinds, John. 1971. Personal pronouns in Japanese. Glossa. 5(2). 146151.Google Scholar
Hirose, Yukio. 2000. Public and private self as two aspects of the speaker: a contrastive study of Japanese and English. Journal of Pragmatics. 32(11). 16231656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holmberg, Anders. 2010. Referring to yourself in self-talk. In Zwart, Jan-Wouter and de Vries, Mark, (eds.), Structure preserved: studies in syntax for Jan Koster, 185192. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huang, C-T. James, and Tang, C-C. Jane. 1991. The local nature of the long-distance reflexive in Chinese. In Koster, Jan and Reuland, Eric, (eds.), Long distance anaphora. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Huang, Yun-Hua. 1984. Reflexives in Chinese. Studies in English Literature and Linguistics. 10. 163188.Google Scholar
Inokuma, Sakumi. 2011. Syntax of personal pronouns and proper names and the notion of direct reference. Linguistic Research. 27. 6371.Google Scholar
Jespersen, Otto. 1909. A modern English grammar, vol. 7. London: George Allen.Google Scholar
Kaiser, Stefan, Ichikawa, Yasuko, Kobayashi, Noriko, and Yamamoto, Hilofumi. 2013. Japanese: a comprehensive grammar, 2nd edn. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitagawa, Chisato, and Lehrer, Adrienne. 1990. Impersonal uses of personal pronouns. Journal of Pragmatics. 14. 739759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kondo, Dorinne. 1990. Crafting selves: power, gender and discourses of identity in a Japanese workplace. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krifka, Manfred. 2013. Response particles as propositional anaphors. In Snider, Todd, (ed.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 23, 118. Washington, DC: Linguistic Society of America.Google Scholar
Kumari, Preeti. 2023. Honorificity agreement in Maithili: a meso-level comparison with Magahi and Bangla. Delhi: Indian Institute of Technology Delhi, PhD dissertation.Google Scholar
Kuroda, Sige-Yuki. 1965. Generative grammatical studies in the Japanese language. Cambridge, MA: MIT, PhD dissertation.Google Scholar
Kuroda, Sige-Yuki. 1992. Japanese syntax and semantics. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehmann, Christian, 2015. Thoughts on grammaticalization, 3rd edn. Berlin: Language Science Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malamud, Sophia A. 2006. Semantics and pragmatics of arbitrariness. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania, PhD dissertation.Google Scholar
Martin, Samuel E. 1988. A reference grammar of Japanese. Rutland, VT: Charles E. Tuttle.Google Scholar
Massam, Diane. 2009. On the separation and relatedness of classifiers, number, and individuation in Niuean. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory. 10(4). 669699.Google Scholar
McCraw, Mami. 2010. First-person singular pronouns in Japanese: how do they work in conversation? Albuquerque: University of New Mexico, PhD dissertation. https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/educ_llss_etds/26 (6 July 2024).Google Scholar
McCready, Elin. 2019The semantics and pragmatics of honorification: register and social meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDonald, Brittany. 2021. The interactional structure of nominals: an investigation of paranouns. Calgary: University of Calgary, MA thesis.Google Scholar
Mezhevich, Ilana. 2008. A feature-theoretic account of tense and aspect in Russian. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory. 26(2). 359401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Roy Andrew. 1967. The Japanese language. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Miyagawa, Shigeru. 2009. Why agree? Why move? Unifying agreement-based and discourse-configurational languages. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miyazaki, Ayumi. 2004. Japanese junior high school girls’ and boys’ first-person pronoun use and their social world. In Okamoto, Shigeko and Smith, Janet S. Shibamoto (eds.), Japanese language, gender, and ideology: Cultural models and real people, 256274. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakanishi, Kimiko and Tomioka, Satoshi. 2004. Japanese plurals are exceptional. Journal of East Asian Linguistics. 13(2). 113140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neeleman, Ad and Szendrői, Kriszta. 2007. Radical pro drop and the morphology of pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry. 38(4). 671714.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Obana, Yasuko. 2003. The use of kare/kanojo in Japanese society today. New Zealand Journal of Asian Studies. 5(1). 139155.Google Scholar
Okamoto, Shigeko and Smith, Janet S. Shibamoto. 2016. The social life of the Japanese language: cultural discourse and situated practice. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pan, Haihua. 2000. Why the blocking effect: Long-distance reflexives. In Cole, Peter, Hermon, Gabriella and Huang, C.-T. James (eds.), Syntax and semantics, vol. 33: Long distance reflexives, 279316. Bingley, UK: Emerald Group Publishing.Google Scholar
Philippa, Marlies and Debrabandere, Frans (2023). Etymologisch woordenboek van het Nederlands. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.Google Scholar
Portner, Paul, Pak, Miok, and Zanuttini, Raffaella. 2019. The speaker-addressee relation at the syntax-semantics interface. Language. 95(1). 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potts, Christopher. 2007. The expressive dimension. Theoretical Linguistics. 33(2). 165198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritter, Elizabeth. 1995. On the syntactic category of pronouns and agreementNatural Language & Linguistic Theory. 13(3). 405443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritter, Elizabeth and Wiltschko, Martina. 2019. Nominal speech act structure: Evidence from the structural deficiency of impersonal pronounsCanadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue canadienne de linguistique. 64(4). 709729.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritter, Elizabeth and Wiltschko, Martina. 2021. Grammar constrains the way we talk to ourselves. In Hernández, Angelica and Plyley, Chris, (eds.), Proceedings of the 2021 Annual Conference of the Canadian Linguistic Association. http://cla-acl.ca/ https://cla-acl.ca/pdfs/actes-2021/Ritter_and_Wiltschko-Grammar_constrains_the_way_we_talk_to_ourselves.pdfGoogle Scholar
Rizzi, Luigi. 1986. Null objects in Italian and the theory of proLinguistic Inquiry. 17(3). 501557.Google Scholar
Shibatani, Masayoshi. 1990. The languages of Japan. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Simon, Horst. 2003. From pragmatics to grammar: tracing the development of respect in the history of the German pronouns of address. In Taavitsainen, Irma and Jucker, Andreas H., (eds.), Diachronic perspectives on address term systems, 85124. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Speas, Margaret and Tenny, Carol. 2003. Configurational properties of point of view roles. In Di Sciullo, Anna Maria, (ed.), Asymmetry in grammar, 315344. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sproat, Richard and Shih, Chilin. 1991. The cross-linguistic distribution of adjective ordering restrictions. In Georgopoulos, Carol and Ishihar, Roberta, (eds.), Interdisciplinary approaches to language: essays in honor of S.-Y. Kuroda, 565593. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suzuki, Takao. 1976. Language and behavior in Japan: the conceptualization of personal relations. Japan Quarterly. 23(3). 255266.Google Scholar
Takubo, Yukinori. 2020. Nominal deixis in Japanese. In Jacobsen, Wesley and Takubo, Yukinori, (eds.), Handbook of Japanese semantics and pragmatics, 687732. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tang, C.-C. Jane. 1985. A study of reflexives in Chinese. Taiwan: National Taiwan Normal University, MA thesis.Google Scholar
Tang, C.-C. Jane. 1989. Chinese reflexives. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory. 7. 93121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Travis, Catherine E. 2007. Genre effects on subject expression in Spanish: priming in narrative and conversation. Language Variation & Change. 19(2). 101135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watanabe, Akira. 2012. Direct modification in Japanese. Linguistic Inquiry. 43(3). 504513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wetzel, Patricia J. 1994. A movable self: the linguistic indexing of uchi and soto. In Bachnik, Jane M. and Quinn, Charles J. Jr., (eds.), Situated meaning: inside and outside in Japanese self, society and language, 7387. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wiltschko, Martina. 2008. The syntax of non-inflectional plural marking. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory. 26(3). 639694.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiltschko, Martina. 2014. The universal structure of categories: towards a formal typology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiltschko, Martina. 2021. The grammar of interactional language. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiltschko, Martina and Heim, Johannes. 2016. The syntax of confirmationals: A neo-performative analysis. In Kaltenböck, Gunther, Keizer, Evelien and Lohmann, Arne, (eds.), Outside the clause: form and function of extra-clausal constituents, 305340. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yonezawa, Yoko. 2021. The mysterious address term anata ‘youin Japanese. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zu, Vera, 2015. Probing for conversation participants: the case of Jingpo. In Aparicio, Helena, Flinn, Gallagher, Franich, Kathryn, Pietraszko, Joanna and Vardomskaya, Tamara, (eds.), Proceedings of the Forty-ninth Annual Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 379389. Chicago: Chicago Linguistics Society.Google Scholar
Zu, Vera, 2018. Discourse participants and the structural representation of the context. New York: New York University, PhD dissertation.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1 Restrictions on addressee-oriented interactional pronouns

Figure 1

Table 2 Chinese paradigmatic pronouns

Figure 2

Table 3 Person features

Figure 3

Figure 1 Common ground between speaker and two addressees.

Figure 4

Figure 2 Common ground between speaker and formal addressee.

Figure 5

Figure 3 No common ground between the speaker and formal addressee.

Figure 6

Figure 4 No common ground between the speaker and nonparticipant.

Figure 7

Table 4 Typology of degrees of formality in pronominal systems (Helmbrecht 2013)

Figure 8

Table 5 Two types of derived interactional pronouns

Figure 9

Table 6 Typology of derived interactional nominals