Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T00:06:05.315Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Is Deliberation an Antidote to Extreme Partisan Polarization? Reflections on “America in One Room”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 July 2021

JAMES FISHKIN*
Affiliation:
Stanford University, United States
ALICE SIU*
Affiliation:
Stanford University, United States
LARRY DIAMOND*
Affiliation:
Stanford University, United States
NORMAN BRADBURN*
Affiliation:
University of Chicago, United States
*
James Fishkin, Janet M. Peck Chair in International Communication and Professor of Communication and Political Science (by courtesy) and Director, Center for Deliberative Democracy, Stanford University and Department of Communication, Stanford University, United States, [email protected].
Alice Siu, Associate Director, Center for Deliberative Democracy, Stanford University, United States, [email protected].
Larry Diamond, Senior Fellow at the Freeman Spogli Institute for International Studies, Senior Fellow at the Hoover Institution, Professor, by courtesy, of Political Science and Sociology, Stanford University, United States, [email protected].
Norman Bradburn, Senior Fellow at NORC at the University of Chicago, and the Tiffany and Margaret Blake Distinguished Service Professor Emeritus in the faculties of the University of Chicago’s Irving B. Harris Graduate School of Public Policy Studies, Department of Psychology, Booth School of Business and the College at the University of Chicago, United States, [email protected].
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper is positioned at the intersection of two literatures: partisan polarization and deliberative democracy. It analyzes results from a national field experiment in which more than 500 registered voters were brought together from around the country to deliberate in depth over a long weekend on five major issues facing the country. A pre–post control group was also asked the same questions. The deliberators showed large, depolarizing changes in their policy attitudes and large decreases in affective polarization. The paper develops the rationale for hypotheses explaining these decreases and contrasts them with a literature that would have expected the opposite. The paper briefly concludes with a discussion of how elements of this “antidote” can be scaled.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Political Science Association

This paper stands at the intersection of two literatures—on partisan polarization and on democratic deliberation—that have not had much connection with one another. If readers find some of the results surprising, the authors have had the same reaction. In this paper we describe these results and our approach to explaining them.

Partisan Polarization

The United States is deeply divided along partisan lines. If representatives stray from the party line on any salient issues, they are pressured at the elite level by party “whips” and threatened at the mass level by activists with being “primaried” (Boatright Reference Boatright2014). At the mass level, scholars debate whether polarization on issues has been increasing (Abramowitz Reference Abramowitz2013; Reference Abramowitz2018; Campbell Reference Campbell2016; Fiorina Reference Fiorina and Abrams2009; Reference Fiorina2017; Hopkins and Sides Reference Hopkins and Sides2015), but on some salient issues, divisions along party lines seem increasingly intractable. Further, there is clear evidence that affective polarization has increased at the mass level and this gap in affect reinforces the divisions on substance (Iyengar et al. Reference Iyengar, Lelkes, Levendusky, Malhotra and Westwood2019; Iyengar and Krupenkin Reference Iyengar and Krupenkin2018; Iyengar, Sood, and Lelkes Reference Iyengar, Sood and Lelkes2012).

On at least some issues that deeply divide Americans, the lock-step choreography of party elites and mobilizable voters (undoubtedly with causal arrows in both directions—see Jacobs and Shapiro Reference Jacobs and Shapiro2000 and Lenz Reference Lenz2012) leads to policy deadlock. The continuing stasis endangers both process and outcome legitimacy (Hetherington and Rudolph Reference Hetherington and Rudolph2015).

The divisions are both substantive and affective. Social sorting has accompanied the political sorting of the two major parties, probably increasing the affective gap between them (Mason Reference Mason2014). Our division into competing political tribes has led to a tribalism of social separation. This, in turn, reinforces political polarization at the mass level and stalemate among policy elites. Affective polarization intensifies political distrust, further fueling the deadlock (Hetherington and Rudolph Reference Hetherington and Rudolph2015). Thus, we investigate both the substantive differences on specific policies and affective polarization as measured by feeling thermometer ratings (see Iyengar et al. Reference Iyengar, Lelkes, Levendusky, Malhotra and Westwood2019 for an overview).

Empirical Study of Public Deliberation

Over the last three decades, a large literature on “deliberative democracy” has developed both in normative theory and empirical social science (for an overview see Bächtiger et al. Reference Bächtiger, Dryzek, Mansbridge and Warren2018). As Goodin argues, “deliberation consists in the weighing of reasons for and against a course of action” (Goodin Reference Goodin, Fishkin and Laslett2003, 54). But this weighing presumes certain social conditions: “deliberation requires ‘weighing’ competing arguments for policies or candidates in a context of mutually civil and diverse discussion in which people can decide on the merits of arguments with good information” (Fishkin and Mansbridge Reference Fishkin and Mansbridge2017, 8; see also Bächtiger et al. Reference Bächtiger, Dryzek, Mansbridge and Warren2018, 2 for a similar definition).

Broadly sketched, deliberative democracy work has moved from representatives to citizens and from normative theory to the empirical study of deliberation (or the lack of it) by the mass public. While most empirical applications were initially in western democracies, interest in deliberative democracy has engaged many countries, including developing countries (Chirawurah et al. Reference Chirawurah, Fishkin, Santuah, Siu, Bawah, Kranjac-Berisavljevic and Giles2019 and some authoritarian ones (He and Warren Reference He and Warren2011).

According to some theories of democracy, elected representatives ideally deliberate on the merits regardless of party (Bessette Reference Bessette1994; Burke [1774] Reference Burke1854). But party discipline gives representatives little opportunity to do so. The prime incentive for elected representatives is to win reelection. They tend to be more interested in winning the election than in winning the argument on the merits.

How about the mass public? Most citizens, most of the time, are not well informed about complex political issues. Such generalizations appear to hold, not only for the US but also for most modern, large-scale democracies (Delli Carpini and Keeter Reference Delli Carpini and Keeter1996, 89–92). Citizens in mass society seem to have incentives for “rational ignorance” (Downs Reference Downs1957). If an individual has one opinion in millions, it is unlikely to make a difference, so why pay attention to the complexities of most public issues? Perhaps as a by-product of other activities, an individual can pick up impressions of relevant information and draw inferences (Lupia Reference Lupia1994; Popkin Reference Popkin1991), but most people lack the time to consider issues in depth. The same argument applies to deliberation: If we do not have an effective incentive to acquire information about an issue, we will not want to spend time weighing the arguments for and against it. Rational ignorance and rational nondeliberation are both, at root, part of the same collective action problem for citizens in the large-scale nation-state.

However, such generalizations do not apply to every issue. On occasion, grand debates focus the attention of the public on some salient issue on which the public deliberates to some considerable degree. Perhaps these are the “constitutional moments” Bruce Ackerman identified in the history of the American Republic: the Founding, Reconstruction, the New Deal, or the Civil Rights movement (Ackerman Reference Ackerman1993). While these national discussions mostly preceded the development of modern public opinion research, in the case of civil rights there has been a dramatic shift in public opinion over several decades (Page and Shapiro Reference Page and Shapiro1992). On some issues the change can be more rapid (for same-sex marriage see Rosenfeld Reference Rosenfeld2017).

Generally, “everyday talk,” as Jane Mansbridge calls public discussion outside organized settings, can have deliberative qualities but is likely to be less deliberative—less focused on the weighing of competing arguments—than what could be achieved in organized settings (Mansbridge Reference Mansbridge and Macedo1999). Empirical studies of public discussion, as distinct from just public opinion, confirm this picture (Conover, Searing, and Crewe Reference Conover, Searing and Crewe2002).

In everyday talk, citizens are more likely to engage those from similar social locations and who share their political views (Huckfeldt, Mendez, and Osborne Reference Huckfeldt, Mendez and Osborn2004; Mutz Reference Mutz2002). They are also likely to consult congenial news sources and get information on social media from their political soulmates. Many will stay within their own “filter bubbles” with social media firms employing algorithms to keep their attention by giving them mostly what they seem to want (Pariser Reference Pariser2011; Sunstein Reference Sunstein2017). The explosion of choice has undermined one of the empirical premises of liberal-democratic theory: that liberty will lead to diversity in the airing of different points of view, which will help people think for themselves (or as J. S. Mill put it, achieve “individuality” (Mill [1859] Reference Mill1962). When people have too much choice, they may well choose the most congenial options and end up exposed to like-mindedness rather than the views they disagree with (Sunstein Reference Sunstein2009). After exercising choice, partisans may have little idea what people on the other side are thinking, just as viewers of MSNBC may have little idea what viewers of Fox News are really thinking (and vice versa).

Given the state of everyday talk, the revival of interest in deliberative democracy for the mass public has been driven by a new (and very old) idea: engage a random sample of the relevant population in a design for deliberation where people are effectively motivated to weigh competing arguments on the merits and get good information so as to come to considered judgments. Some theorists advocate this practice on epistemic grounds (Landemore Reference Landemore2013). We offer this approach for its contribution to public will-formation—clarifying the “will of the people” in a world of misinformation and propaganda.

These deliberating microcosms or “minipublics” have various designs. Some versions go all the way back to ancient Athens (Fishkin Reference Fishkin2018; Hansen Reference Hansen1991; Manin Reference Manin1997; Ober Reference Ober2008). Modern designs vary in the data collected before and after deliberation, in the design of the deliberative process itself, and in the methods of identifying and recruiting random samples (for the challenges of recruitment see Dennis et al. Reference Dennis, Carter, Tipler, Watts and Yang2020; Neblo et al. Reference Neblo, Esterling, Kennedy, David and Sokhey2010). Citizens Juries engage small samples, up to two dozen or so, who deliberate together and try to reach a consensus on recommendations (see Már and Gastil Reference Már and Gastil2019 for their application to ballot propositions in the “Citizens Initiative Review”). Consensus conferences screen volunteers to get 14 or so who self-select from large initial samples (Andersen and Jaeger Reference Andersen and Jaeger1999, 335). Citizens Assemblies gather somewhat larger groups (in British Columbia about 160) and meet for successive weekends, arriving at a recommendation (for British Columbia see Fournier et al. Reference Fournier, van der Kolk, Carty, Blais and Rose2011; Warren and Pearse Reference Warren and Pearse2008; for more recent citizens assemblies in Ireland see Farrell, Suiter, and Harris Reference Farrell, Suiter and Harris2018; Farrell et al. Reference Farrell, Suiter, Harris and Cunningham2019).

Deliberative Polling employs stratified random sampling, often with control groups and numbers of participants large enough so that both representativeness and opinion changes can be evaluated in a statistically meaningful way. Despite these differences, the basic idea that all these approaches share is a response to the limitations of deliberation by the mass public in natural settings. If instead of one opinion in millions, each participant has one opinion in a few hundred, or in a dozen (if the design involves many small groups meeting concurrently), then each participant has a more significant role in the proceedings. Participating in a minipublic rather than just as a member of the public at large recalibrates the scale of interaction so that each individual can plausibly feel more consequential. The process also provides easy access to vetted briefing materials with good information expressing competing sides of the argument. If the several hundred participants are randomly assigned to small groups, these are likely to offer the diversity of viewpoints that most people do not get in ordinary discussion or on social media. Two key features of any minipublic—recalibration of the scale of discussions so that each individual can have a meaningful role and effective engagement of the participants with balanced argumentation—address two of the key debilitations of everyday talk.

The “America in One Room” Deliberative Poll

This paper focuses on a deliberating microcosm of a certain design—Deliberative Polling. The basic idea is simple. Engage a stratified random sample of the relevant public in good conditions for deliberation about a topic. What would the public really think about an issue if it had the time and opportunity to consider it in depth with balanced and authoritative information, to discuss the pros and cons with diverse others in moderated small groups, to identify questions for panels of competing experts in plenary sessions, and then to come to a considered judgment as expressed in confidential questionnaires? Deliberative Polling has kinship with other methods for bridging civic divides. But unlike Citizens Assemblies, Citizens Juries, or Consensus Conferences, it makes no effort to arrive at a shared consensus or group decision on an issue. Thus, opinions can be studied at the individual level, free of social pressure to go along with the crowd. If a consensus emerges, it will be apparent from the data (the confidential questionnaires)—and it will be an expression of the group’s considered judgments.

Why bring the people together for discussion, rather than just provide information? First, when Deliberative Polls have disaggregated the treatment, there was little or no opinion change or evidence of deliberation for those who just received information (Farrar et al. Reference Farrar, Fishkin, Green, List, Luskin and Paluck2010; Sandefur et al. Reference Sandefur, Birdsall, Fishkin and Moyo2020). Second, in a highly partisan context, mere provision of information is likely to “backfire,” leading partisans to entrench their views rather than reconsider them (Chong and Druckman Reference Chong and Druckman2007; Nyhan and Reifler Reference Nyhan and Reifler2010). Third, our objective is to see what respondents would think about the issues under good conditions for considering them. Provision of balanced information is just one of those good conditions. In addition, deliberation requires that people use that good information to “weigh” competing arguments through civil and diverse discussion, enabling them to decide on the merits of arguments (Fishkin and Mansbridge Reference Fishkin and Mansbridge2017, 8). Both discussion and information are components of the treatment intended to stimulate the “weighing” of competing arguments (for the actual knowledge gains in this experiment see Table A6 in the online Appendix.)

In advance of the initial survey, an advisory committee reflecting different views on the selected topics vets the briefing materials for balance and accuracy. These materials serve as the initial basis for discussion when the sample is convened to deliberate. The participants discuss each issue with their peers in the small groups, considering the balanced arguments for and against each option.

The first stage of the process resembles a normal public opinion poll: participants are surveyed with a standardized instrument in advance of seeing or discussing any information from the project. In the second stage, the random sample is brought together to a single place for extensive face-to-face discussions, usually over a long weekend. They are randomly assigned to moderated small groups, and they attend plenary sessions where they can pose questions agreed in their small groups to panels of experts or decision makers with diverse views on a particular issue. At the end of the deliberations, participants take the same questionnaire as on first contact, plus added questions for evaluation. Whenever possible, a pre–post control group completes the same questionnaire but does not receive the briefing materials or participate in the discussions. In its full realization, the project is a national field experiment in deliberation.

America in One Room was a national experiment in public deliberation about the major issues facing the country in the period just preceding the 2020 presidential primary season. The event gathered a stratified random sample of 526 registered voters from around the country, recruited by NORC at the University of Chicago. (All but three completed the entire deliberation and the exit survey). A pre–post control group of 844 was also recruited by NORC and took essentially the same questionnaire but did not receive the briefing documents or engage in organized discussions. The registered voter samples for both the treatment and control groups were sourced from NORC’s probability-based and nationally representative AmeriSpeaks panel. The recruitment and representativeness of the treatment and control groups is discussed in Dennis et al. Reference Dennis, Carter, Tipler, Watts and Yang2020, in the NORC Methodological ReportFootnote 1 and in section 1 of the online appendix.

The deliberations revolved around five broad issue areas, largely selected from a previous NORC survey about the top issues the public hoped to see discussed in the presidential campaign:Footnote 2 immigration, the economy (including taxes), health care, the environment (including climate change), and foreign policy. Each policy domain discussed at the event included specific policy proposals (47 in all) under active discussion by presidential candidates (some Democrat, some Republican) or other policy makers. The printed briefing materials attempted to concisely present the strongest evidence-based arguments for and against each proposal, and they were also distilled into brief introductory issue videos shown to the participants. The materials were vetted by subject matter experts with opposing perspectives and the nonpartisan Advisory Committee.

The sample gathered in Dallas during September 19–22, 2019, arriving Thursday late afternoon and leaving Sunday after lunch. The agenda alternated small group discussions by issue area and plenary sessions, each lasting 90 minutes and running throughout the weekend. Each of the five issue domains was discussed both in small group discussions and in plenary sessions with experts responding to questions agreed in the small groups. Participants remained with the same small group (averaging about 13 persons) throughout the event, enabling them to get to know one another on a personal level over the course of the weekend. In the final questionnaire, completed just before departure, respondents were asked (as they had been in the predeliberation survey) to rate each specific policy proposal on a 0 to 10 scale, where 0 was “strongly oppose,” 10 was “strongly favor,” and 5 was the midpoint.Footnote 3 The control group took the same questionnaire within the same approximate period.

Of the 47 proposals, we classify 26 as instances of extreme partisan polarization between Republicans and Democrats. Our criteria are as follows:

  1. (a) At least 15% of each party takes the strongest possible position (0 or 10) at time 1, with these Democrats and Republicans at opposite poles on the proposal.

  2. (b) A majority of those party members who take a position at time 1 are on the same side of the scale as those taking the strongest positions in favor or against.

These two criteria combine to identify extreme partisan polarization because those taking the strongest positions are balanced at the two poles, Republicans on one side, Democrats at the other. The majority support on either side is also symmetrical. A majority of Republicans are on one side and a majority of Democrats are on the other.Footnote 4

Do issues of extreme partisan polarization depolarize when subjected to certain kinds of public deliberation? What do we mean by depolarization? How do movements by members of a given party relate to movements by members of the other party (assuming something like the US context with two major parties). These two questions suggest two kinds of depolarization:

  1. (a) One-sided depolarization: when the majority of members of a given party are on one side of the partisan divide and a majority of members of the other party are on the other side, one-sided depolarization occurs if the mean position of the members of one party moves toward the midpoint or crosses it, whereas the mean position of the members of the other party shows no significant movement toward the midpoint.

  2. (b) Two-sided depolarization: when the majority of members of a given party are on one side of the partisan divide and a majority of members of the other party are on the other side, two-sided depolarization occurs if the means of both parties move closer together on the scale or if they move to the same side of the scale.

In other words, if the partisans of only one party moderate toward the midpoint then it is one-sided depolarization. But if the partisans of both parties move toward each other it is two-sided depolarization.

Suppose that after deliberating, members of one party, say Republicans, move their mean position from opposition to support for a proposal while Democrats intensify their degree of support. In that case, partisans of the two parties might not end up closer together in their mean position (because Democrats moved further in their support than Republicans did in developing support). Nevertheless, in this hypothetical situation, we consider the two parties ending up on the same side of the issue to be sufficient to constitute depolarization. The mean positions of the two sides no longer disagree about whether a proposal should be supported or opposed. They only disagree on how strongly to support or oppose it. Thus we can speak of two forms of depolarization: changing distance (so that the two parties end up closer in their mean positions on the 0 to 10 scale) and changing sides (so that the two parties end up on the same side of an issue).

Research Questions

The literature offers a basis for contrasting expectations about what is likely to happen when discussion takes place across party lines on issues where the two parties are highly polarized. What will be the effect on issue-based polarization among party members and, in particular, among party members taking the strongest possible positions at opposite ends of the scale? In addition, what is the influence on affective polarization? The increasing dislike that supporters of the two parties feel for each other has evidently intensified our state of deadlock and division (Hetherington and Rudolph Reference Hetherington and Rudolph2015). The growing literature on affective polarization shows that it is distinct from issue-based polarization (Iyengar et al. Reference Iyengar, Lelkes, Levendusky, Malhotra and Westwood2019). We can distill these topics into a series of research questions and hypotheses.

Research Question 1: On issues of extreme partisan polarization, will cross-party discussion lead to more or less polarization on those issues?

When members of opposing parties discuss issues that are highly polarized along partisan lines, will partisan-based polarization on the issues increase or decrease? In other words, will the mean positions of each party move farther away from each other or closer together?

Consider two arguments predicting increased polarization from cross-party discussion on issues that are already highly polarized. The first expects that partisanship will fuel “directional” or “partisan”-motivated reasoning. As Taber and Lodge found, partisans “counterargue the contrary arguments and uncritically accept supporting arguments, evidence of a disconfirmation bias.” Also, by seeking out supporting arguments they will tend to exhibit confirmation bias (Taber and Lodge Reference Taber and Lodge2006, 755). These patterns are both part of directional motivated reasoning to support positions they are already invested in (Kunda Reference Kunda1990). Such processes are thus likely to push party members to more extreme positions on each side of the polarized divide (Druckman Reference Druckman2012; Leeper and Slothuus Reference Leeper and Slothuus2014; Levendusky, Druckman, and McClain Reference Levendusky, Druckman and Mclain2016). Even mere exposure to information one disagrees with often “backfires” in a partisan context, increasing disagreement (Chong and Druckman Reference Chong and Druckman2007; Nyhan and Reifler Reference Nyhan and Reifler2010).

Sunstein’s “law of group polarization” provides a second argument that discussion is likely to increase polarization, especially on issues that already exhibit deep divisions. Building on earlier work with small groups, he and his collaborators identify two causal factors supporting increased polarization—the “imbalance in the argument pool” and a “social comparison effect” (Sunstein Reference Sunstein2002; Reference Sunstein2009). More recently he has generalized the problem from juries and jury-like settings to the condition of the citizen in mass society (Sunstein Reference Sunstein2017). Republicans live in one social world, Democrats in another. Because of partisan selectivity, the bias in our social media “news feeds” and the algorithms in our “filter bubbles,” partisans are especially likely to get a strong imbalance in the argument pool (Pariser Reference Pariser2011; Sunstein Reference Sunstein2009). Weighing those unbalanced arguments, they are likely to move toward a more polarized position in the direction supported by the imbalance. Further, the social comparison effect (as they compare their views to those of their friends, associates, and fellow partisans; Asch Reference Asch1955) will, in effect, create bandwagon effects (Goidel and Shields Reference Goidel and Shields1994), a spiral of silence (Noelle-Neumann Reference Noelle-Neumann1984 ), and added pressure to move to the extreme of the side they were already on.

These arguments apply most clearly to unstructured everyday talk and cross-party encounters in natural settings. However, the deliberative minipublic investigated here, the Deliberative Poll, designs very different conditions for cross-partisan engagement on the issues. We expect that it will decrease rather than increase polarization because it supports different expectations about both motivated reasoning and the law of group polarization.

As Kunda first hypothesized, there are two kinds of “motivated reasoning”—“directional” and “accuracy based” (Kunda Reference Kunda1990). The argument that discussion will increase partisan polarization on issues that are already polarized relies on directional-motivated reasoning. But if an experimental treatment could encourage the second kind of motivated reasoning—accuracy-based—then reasoning on the merits would likely result. Further, if on issues of partisan polarization, people have arrived at positions without seriously considering (or even encountering) arguments on the other side, then we might well expect accuracy-based reasoning to reduce partisan polarization by overcoming the legacy of previously one-sided reasoning. The expectation here is not that deliberation will always depolarize but that it will likely depolarize on issues where participants begin the exercise with high levels of partisan polarization.

Kunda concluded that subjects were motivated to be accurate when they “expected to be evaluated, expected to justify their judgments, expected their judgments to be made public or expected their evaluations to affect the evaluated person’s life” (Kunda Reference Kunda1990, 481). When people think their views will matter, and when they have to share the reasons supporting their views, they become more attentive to accuracy goals.

These are precisely the motivations that the Deliberative Poll is designed to foster. The task of the small groups is to discuss the arguments for and against each policy proposal and then formulate group questions for the balanced panels of competing experts in the plenary sessions, all so that the participants can come to their own, individually considered judgments. The design also allows groups to submit additional questions to neutral fact checkers who reply during the deliberations. Thus, it encourages the small groups to seek and weigh relevant information and come to their individual considered judgments.

A parallel argument can be made about how the Deliberative Poll blunts the directional force of Sunstein’s “law of group polarization” (Sunstein Reference Sunstein2009, 55–57). The design engages the small group discussions with balanced materials, presenting pros and cons for each proposal. On each proposal, the moderators of the small group discussions attempt to cover the agenda of competing arguments in the briefing materials and to solicit added arguments from the randomly assigned members. Moderators are trained not to give any hint of their own views (Siu and Stanisevski Reference Siu, Stanisevski, Nabatchi, Gastil, Weiksner and Leighninger2012).Footnote 5 The plenary sessions are also balanced, featuring experts representing alternative views. These design features should minimize the problem of imbalances in the argument pool. As for the social comparison effect, the participants only express their final judgments in confidential questionnaires. The moderators encourage the participants to consider, and give voice to, arguments on either side without ever having to express their final decision. There is no “show of hands” or other voting on the proposals. Thus, the social pressures to go along with the crowd should be blunted.

The Deliberative Poll can thus be expected to blunt the dynamics of both directional-motivated reasoning and imbalanced argumentation, dynamics that might otherwise increase polarization (Grönlund, Herne, and Setälä Reference Kimmo, Herne and Setälä2015). But blunting the dynamics toward more polarization is not the same as depolarizing. Balanced argumentation might be expected to produce no aggregate net change (see Barabas Reference Barabas2004, 695). Why would the process actually depolarize on issues of high partisan polarization? Our expectation is that partisans have developed their views going into the deliberations on the basis of one-sided argumentation, without ever having taken seriously, or perhaps even having considered, the arguments on the other side of the partisan divide. If the design of the treatment can stimulate accuracy-based motivation and get them engaged thoughtfully with the other side, partisan participants are likely to adjust and move in the direction of the other party.

Therefore, we hypothesize the following:

H1 On issues of extreme partisan polarization, deliberation with an appropriate design will depolarize substantive differences between the parties.

This depolarization can be one-sided, with just one set of party members moving toward the midpoint (or past it). Or, it can be two-sided, with the means of both parties moving closer toward each other (or to the same side of the midpoint on that issue).

This hypothesis is formulated in terms of party members for the two main parties. Consider now not just party members in general but those party members who take the strongest position at either end of the scale. Should we also expect them to depolarize?

We might expect them to be the least likely to depolarize. Their previous thinking has already pushed them as far as possible to the limits of the scale. Their partisan loyalties have likely supported motivated reasoning and imbalanced argumentation in their natural environments. Of all the partisans on either side, it seems we should expect them to be the most dug in (see Wojcieszak Reference Wojcieszak2011, 605, who found the extremes becoming even more so on a battery of questions).

Still, there is another perspective. If the design of the treatment stimulates accuracy-based motivated reasoning and balanced argumentation, those initially taking the strongest positions on the scale could also be susceptible to change. The very fact that in their natural environments they have arrived at such polarized positions may suggest they have been least exposed previously to serious engagement with the other side of the partisan divide. At least on these issues of high partisanship, they may be fully as susceptible to depolarization as those taking more moderate positions. This idea suggests the next hypothesis:

H2 On issues of extreme partisan polarization, deliberation with an appropriate design will depolarize substantive differences among those members of each party who took the most polarized positions before deliberation.

“Most polarized” refers to those taking a position of 0 or 10 on an issue that satisfies our criteria for extreme partisan polarization. Again, this depolarization could encompass just the proponents on one side or it could be two-sided so that the means of the two groups who take maximum positions at either side of an issue move closer together (or move to the same side).

Now let us turn to affective polarization. Will the same pattern hold?

Research Question 2: On issues of extreme partisan polarization, will cross-party discussion lead to more or less affective polarization?

It could be argued that cross-party discussion on issues of partisan polarization will likely exacerbate affective divisions between the parties by triggering the dynamics of in-group/out-group identity that increase hostility toward the out-group (the other party; Tajfel Reference Tajfel1981). Stimulating outrage across the partisan divide has become a major part of our political culture in traditional media, social media, and campaign advertising (Berry and Soberieraj Reference Berry and Sobieraj2014; Mutz Reference Mutz2015).

However, the same deliberative design that we believe fosters accuracy-based motivated reasoning and balanced argumentation can also be expected to reduce affect. A line of research about contact across deep divisions indicates that under certain conditions, “contact yields liking,” or decreased affective polarization. Not just any contact but contact satisfying certain conditions. Going back to pioneering work by Allport (Reference Allport1954), a design that fosters “equal status between groups, common goals, cooperation and institutional support” (Pettigrew and Tropp Reference Pettigrew and Tropp2011, 75–6) for the importance of the interactions will likely lead the two groups to a reduction in prejudice. These four conditions are not all essential, but in meta-analyses they were held to work best in combination (Hewstone and Swart Reference Hewstone and Swart2011; Pettigrew and Tropp Reference Pettigrew and Tropp2006; Reference Pettigrew and Tropp2011).

The deliberative design employed in “America in One Room” intentionally fosters equal status, emphasizing that everyone’s opinion counts and deserves to be listened to. It encourages the participants to cooperate together to consider competing arguments and come to their own informed conclusions. It engages the participants in a common effort to develop and pose questions of greatest concern for presentation on behalf of their group in the plenary sessions. And, it offers institutional support for these efforts, while the evident media interest in the event added to the sense of informal support for the project.

The contact hypothesis has not previously been applied to the Deliberative Poll treatment for the question of change in affect. However, it has been applied to changes in policy attitudes affecting the Roma in Bulgaria and the Aboriginals in Australia. In those projects the dependent variables were policy proposals affecting the minority groups (more favorable treatment of the Roma or the Aboriginals; Kim, Fishkin, and Luskin Reference Kim, Fishkin and Luskin2018). In Northern Ireland, the Deliberative Poll influenced community perceptions (Protestants and Catholics each viewed the other community as more “trustworthy” and “open to reason” (Luskin et al. Reference Luskin, O’Flynn, Fishkin and Russell2014). Other organized discussions provide support for the contact hypothesis in cases of extreme group division such as between Israelis and Palestinians (Maoz Reference Maoz2000).

On this basis we hypothesize the following:

H3: On issues of extreme partisan polarization, deliberation among members of different parties conducted with an appropriate design will reduce affective polarization.

Following deliberation, partisans’ thermometer ratings for the opposite party will increase or the gap between thermometer ratings for one’s own party and the opposing one will diminish. The group discussions, moderated to ensure mutual respect and a context of equality, combined with the common task of formulating questions for the competing experts will lower the temperature of the heated partisan divisions and change the way the in-group feels about the out-group.

This hypothesis applies generally to people who identify with one party or the other. What of those who take the strongest positions on either side of the partisan divide? Will affective polarization attenuate among them as well? In theory, the psychology of in-group/out-group division should be even stronger for those who take the strongest positions, so one might expect them to be less susceptible to the contact hypothesis. On the other hand, they might be the very people who have had less contact, or at least less contact under constructive conditions, with members of the other party. Hence, we might expect the contact hypothesis to come into play for them as well:

H4: On issues of extreme partisan polarization, deliberation among members of different parties conducted with the appropriate design will reduce affective polarization among those in both parties initially taking the most polarized positions on the issues.

What Happened?

Again, 26 of the 47 policy proposals fit our criteria for extreme partisan polarization. The magnitude of the depolarizing changes on such contentious issues deserves attention. The results for all 26 proposals are in Tables 15.

Table 1. Immigration

Note: *p < 0.05, ** p < 0.01, *** p < 0.000.

Table 2. Environment

Note: *p < 0.05, ** p < 0.01, *** p < 0.000.

Table 3. Economy and Taxes

Note: *p < 0.05, **p < 0.01, ***p < 0.000.

Table 4. Health Care

Note: *p < 0.05, ** p < 0.01, *** p < 0.000.

Table 5. Foreign Policy

Note: *p < 0.05, ** p < 0.01, *** p < 0.000.

Table 1 shows the opinion changes by party for the five polarized proposals on immigration. For each question, the table shows the means before and after deliberation for Democrats and Republicans overall and for the most polarized (those Democrats and Republicans answering either 0 or 10 before deliberation). In almost every case, the changes are statistically significant not only for the treatment group but also in the difference-in-difference analyses that include the control group. The control group showed very little substantive change between T1 and T2. Comparisons to the control group are presented in the online Appendix (Table A3). These changes are for party members. We observe similar changes when the “lean Republicans” are included with the Republicans and the “lean Democrats” are included with the Democrats. Those results are in the online Appendix (Table A4).

Immigration

On immigration, all five of the proposals exhibiting extreme partisan polarization produced massive changes with deliberation. For example, on question 2a “Reduce the number of refugees allowed to resettle in the US,” 65% of Republicans initially supported this proposal (mean 7.05 on the 0 to 10 scale). This support dropped 31 points to 34% (mean 4.72) after deliberation. On the Democrat side, opposition to this proposal increased significantly from 58% (mean of 3.3) to 75% (2.39), an increase of 17 points. The mean position of Republicans who initially took the most polarized position (in favor) went from 10 to 6.49, whereas the mean position for Democrats who initially took the most polarized position in opposition went from 0 to 0.725. Republicans and Democrats and those taking the most polarized positions moved significantly closer together as shown in the last column of Table 1. This pattern applies to all five immigration proposals.

Another highly contested proposal on immigration was the proposal to continue DACA (the Deferred Action for Childhood Arrivals program). Among Republicans, only 36% (mean 4.64) supported this proposal before deliberation. After deliberation, Republican support rose 25 points to 61% (mean 6.11). Support among Democrats also increased from the initially high level of 89% (mean 8.74) to 95% (mean 9.25). The mean position of Republicans who initially took the strongest position in opposition went from 0 to 3.667, whereas Democrats who initially took the strongest position in favor moved only slightly from it (to 9.787). Overall, Republicans and Democrats not only moved closer together but also moved to the same side of the issue, as Republicans changed from opposition to support for DACA.

A third immigration topic was perhaps the most intensely contested of the polarized proposals: “Undocumented immigrants should be forced to return to their home countries before applying to legally come back to the US to live and work permanently.” Before deliberation support for this proposal among Republicans was at 79% (with a mean of 7.9). After deliberation it dropped in half to 40% (a mean of 5.32). Democratic opposition to the proposal increased with deliberation, from 63% (mean 3.3) before deliberation to 78% (mean 2.44) after. For partisans initially taking the strongest positions, Republican mean support dropped substantially from 10 to 6.62, whereas Democrats’ opposition softened only slightly (from 0 to 0.87).

The sample did not have any undocumented immigrants because it included only registered voters. But many participants had family or acquaintances who were undocumented, and these perspectives were part of the discussion. While every effort was made to provide a balance of perspectives in the briefing materials and the plenary sessions, the opinions shifted markedly in a direction more sympathetic to the plight of the undocumented as well as of refugees and immigrants more generally. On all five immigration issues, Republicans and Democrats ended up significantly closer together even when the movement was mostly one-sided, as can be seen in the last column of Table 1. In two cases, (DACA and visas for low-income workers) Republicans moved so far that they ended on the same side as the Democrats, changing from opposition to support

Environment

Six environmental proposals satisfied our criteria for extreme partisan polarization. These mostly focused on climate change, but energy independence was also discussed. The changes for the environment proposals can be found in Table 2. Consider “The US should commit to the 2014 Paris Agreement to combat climate change.” Support among Democrats began very high and stayed high: 89% (a mean of 8.9) before deliberation and 91% (a mean of 9.06) after deliberation. Republicans, on the other hand, greatly decreased their opposition. They went from 56% opposed (mean of 3.7) to only 40% opposed (mean 4.54). For those taking the strongest positions on either side, Democrats’ support declined slightly (from a mean of 10 to 9.61), whereas Republicans’ opposition softened more substantially (from 0 to 2.27)

Overall, three of the six polarized issues on the environment saw two-sided depolarization, as documented in the last column in Table 2. In addition, the proposal for “Moving beyond the Paris agreement” experienced one-sided depolarization. Finally, all six of the proposals showed two-sided depolarization among those beginning with the most polarized positions.

The Economy and Taxes

Seven economic proposals exhibited extreme partisan polarization. Several of these were progressive proposals that lost support from the Democrats after deliberation. Democrats expressed concerns about the expense of some proposals in light of the national debt and they also moved in response to geographically diverse concerns about imposing a national policy (like a $15 minimum wage) that did not account for local variation.

The most dramatic drop was on “The government should fund a bond for each child born that will accumulate in value until the child turns 18 to then become usable for higher education or other essentials for a start in life.” This so-called “Baby Bonds” proposal was a centerpiece in the campaign of a Democratic presidential candidate.Footnote 6

The Baby Bonds proposal was initially supported by 62% of Democrats (mean 6.82), but this support plummeted by two thirds to 21% after deliberation (mean 3.51). Republican support started low (15%, mean of 2.68) and dropped lower (5%, mean of 1.35). Even Democrats who took the strongest position declined sharply in support (from a mean of 10 to 4.56). Republicans who took the strongest position barely warmed in their opposition (from 0 to 0.39).

Another ambitious proposal was to “increase the federal minimum wage from $7.25 an hour to $15/hour.” Democratic support for this proposal dropped 23 points from 82% (mean of 8.31) to 59% (mean of 6.34). Republican opposition increased from 63% (mean of 3.26) to 71% (mean of 2.57). While Republican opposition increased, Democratic support dropped much more. Thus, Republicans and Democrats ended up closer together. As for those taking the strongest positions, Democrats who started out at 10 in support went down substantially to a mean of 7.21. Republicans who started out at 0 in opposition went up only slightly to 0.96.

Of the seven economic proposals, five produced two-sided depolarization between Republicans and Democrats. Among those starting with the strongest positions, all seven proposals showed two-sided depolarization.

Health Care

Five health care proposals fit the criteria for extreme partisan polarization. Some were strongly supported by Republicans (and opposed by Democrats) and others strongly supported by Democrats (and opposed by Republicans). Consider “The Affordable Care Act should be repealed.” Support for this proposal to eliminate “Obamacare” was initially at 69% among Republicans (mean of 7.52). After deliberation, it dropped 21 points among Republicans to 48% (mean of 5.72). Democrats were strongly opposed both before and after (76% opposed, mean of 1.87 before deliberation; 80% opposed, mean of 1.84 afterwards). Republicans taking the strongest position in support moved much more, from a mean of 10 to 7.35. Democrats taking the strongest position in opposition moved only slightly, from 0 to 0.78. Before deliberation, 48% of Republicans took the strongest position in support of eliminating the ACA, whereas after, only 22% did. Before deliberation, 58% of Democrats took the strongest position in opposition to this proposal; afterwards it dropped to 50%.

Consider now a Democratic-leaning health care proposal, “Medicare for All”: that “People should be automatically enrolled in a more generous version of Medicare.” This started high among Democrats (70% support, mean of 7.39), but dropped 14 points to 56% after deliberation (mean of 6.41). Republicans opposed this both before and after (63% to 66%, mean of 3.04). Democrats who initially took the strongest position in favor moderated their views appreciably, going from a mean of 10 to 7.76. Republicans who took the strongest position in opposition moderated a bit, from 0 to 1.147.

Of the five polarized proposals on health care, three showed two-sided and one (Medicare for All) showed one-sided depolarization. In that case, the Democrats moved in a more moderate direction toward the midpoint but the Republicans did not.

Foreign Policy

Only three foreign policy proposals fit our criteria for extreme partisan polarization. The two most contentious were the Iran Nuclear Agreement and the Trans-Pacific Partnership (TPP).

On “The US should recommit to the Iran Nuclear Agreement,” Republican opposition dropped by a third, from 63% (mean of 3.09) to 41% (mean of 4.52). Democratic support increased slightly from 78% (mean of 7.93) to 83% (mean of 8.5). For those with the strongest views on the scale, Republican opposition decreased a lot, from a mean of 0 to 2.79, whereas Democratic support decreased only slightly, from 10 to 9.46.

On the proposal “The US should rejoin the Trans-Pacific Partnership, a trading agreement between 12 countries excluding China,” Democrats started high (66% with a mean of 7.16) and went dramatically higher (88% with a mean of 8.56). In other words, Democratic support increased by a third. Meanwhile, Republicans rose even more dramatically from 23% (mean of 4.24) to 62% (mean of 6.15), an increase of 39 points. Republicans transformed from a mean position of opposition to one of support. This was thus a classic instance in which the depolarizing effect of deliberation resulted in both sets of partisans supporting the same policy. Democrats who took the strongest possible position in support declined only slightly (from 10 to 9.66). Republicans who took the strongest possible position in opposition flipped over the midpoint (going from 0 to 5.05)—one of the two biggest changes in average support among the strongest advocates of any position in our Deliberative Poll.Footnote 7 Opposition to the TPP collapsed with deliberation, and support for international cooperation on this and other items increased dramatically. While the gap between Republicans and Democrats on the scale decreased, the change was not statistically significant because as Republicans moved from opposition to support, Democrats moved to even stronger support. Since Republicans changed sides on this issue, it was two-sided depolarization as noted earlier.

Overview of Issue-Based Results

Overall, there were 26 proposals that fit our criteria for partisan-based polarization. Table 6 provides a simple scorecard of results for the effect of deliberation.

Republican and Democratic partisans moved closer on 22 out of the 26 proposals. In 19, the movements were statistically significant.Footnote 8 The 19 includes one case, the TPP, where the decline in distance between Republicans and Democrats was not significant, but only because the two parties ended up on the same side of the issue after each moved to statistically significant degrees. Republicans moved or depolarized so much that they crossed the midpoint to the same side as the Democrats, and 21 of the 26 items showed depolarization by one party and not the other. As noted earlier, both parties showed some equally large movements in a depolarizing direction.Footnote 9

Table 6. Issue-Based Depolarization

Among partisans of each party who initially took the strongest possible positions, in either support or opposition, there was two-sided depolarization on all 26 highly polarized proposals. When difference-in-difference analyses are included, 20 out of the 26 proposals are significant for partisansFootnote 10 and 26 out of 26 proposals remain significant for those starting at the polar ends of the scale (see the online appendix for the difference in difference analyses). These results support both hypotheses 1 and 2.

Affective Polarization

Whether deliberation influences affective polarization is a separate question. The dynamics of the two kinds of polarization are distinguishable (Iyengar et al. Reference Iyengar, Lelkes, Levendusky, Malhotra and Westwood2019). H3 hypothesized that with an appropriate design, deliberation between members of different parties will reduce affective polarization. We argued that the Deliberative Polling design satisfies the four criteria originally put forward by Allport and later supported by meta-analyses (Allport Reference Allport1954; Pettigrew and Tropp Reference Pettigrew and Tropp2006). Therefore, the contact hypothesis would support a reduction in affective polarization. Table 7 shows what happened for party members in general.

Affective polarization can be measured in at least two ways: thermometer ratings for the other party and the difference in thermometer ratings for one’s own party minus the other party (Iyengar et al. Reference Iyengar, Lelkes, Levendusky, Malhotra and Westwood2019). Both measures are pictured in Table 7 and the results are essentially the same. Partisans exhibited little change in their ratings of their own party but large and significant changes in their ratings of the other party. Democrats’ thermometer ratings of Republicans rose 13 points with deliberation. Republicans’ thermometer ratings of Democrats rose 14 points. As pictured in the table, the thermometer ratings for the control group were essentially unchanged. On either measure, our results support H3 for party members overall. These are large and significant effects by the standards of other experiments at depolarization (see Levendusky Reference Levendusky2018 for some imaginative efforts).

Table 7. Affective Polarization

What about affective polarization among those starting out with the most polarized views on the issues? Tables 8 and 9 show a stunning effect. The more often (across our 26 polarized issues) that partisans (both Democrats and Republicans) chose the extreme position (0 or 10) on the scale, the larger was the reduction in their affective polarization after deliberation. Democrats who chose the maximum position (for or against) on 11 or more of the 26 polarized questions increased their feeling thermometer toward Republicans by an average of 16 points. Republicans who offered extreme answers to 11 or more polarized questions increased their feeling thermometer toward Democrats by at least 17 points on average (and among the most frequent Republican maximalists, the average improvement in feeling toward Democrats was 24 points).

In other words, the more extreme were respondents’ issue positions before deliberation, the more their thermometer ratings toward members of the other party rose with deliberation. Thus, the contact hypothesis seemed to work, not just for party members in general but for members of each party who took the strongest positions before deliberation. These results support H4. By way of explanation, we speculate that those who took the most extreme issue positions on the scale at time 1, whether Republicans or Democrats, may have been even more isolated from serious contact with the other side than were party members in general.

Table 8. Extremity and Democrats’ Feelings toward Republicans

Note: Higher Score = Warmer Feeling; *p < 0.05, ** p < 0.01, *** p < 0.000; two-tailed test.

Table 9. Extremity and Republicans’ Feelings toward Democrats

Note: Higher Score = Warmer Feeling; *p < 0.05, ** p < 0.01, *** p < 0.000; two-tailed test.

Conclusion

These results from a national field experiment offer proof of concept that deliberation, with an appropriate design, can dramatically narrow differences between Republicans and Democrats on issues where they are initially deeply polarized. The Deliberative Poll seems to be at least one design that does this. Added research will show if there are others.Footnote 11

A critic might say that while this field experiment shows that the deliberative process can have a major effect, the effect is limited to so few people that it is hardly of any use. Can participation in such an organized design be scaled to larger populations? Dealing with the dual challenge of substantive and affective polarization would require many people outside the random sample to depolarize.

This limitation should be a prod to innovation. We can foster opportunities for many more people to deliberate. There is now a global community of researchers and practitioners experimenting with deliberative democracy (for a comprehensive compendium see Bächtiger et al. Reference Bächtiger, Dryzek, Mansbridge and Warren2018). Recent experiments have already productively introduced deliberative designs into the schools as a form of civic educationFootnote 12 and engaged minipublics in local public policy consultations. Deliberative designs have also been used for meetings between the public and elected representatives (Neblo, Esterling, and Lazer Reference Neblo, Esterling and David2018), for televising deliberations on key national issues, and for experimenting with the effect of exposure (via television or print) to the results of deliberating minipublics (Már and Gastil Reference Már and Gastil2019; Rasinski, Bradburn, and Lauen Reference Rasinski, Bradburn, Lauen, McCombs and Reynolds1999). Because of its cost effectiveness (foregoing the need to pay for transportation and hotels), online deliberation with video-based discussions enables a dramatic increase in the number of deliberating participants. Large numbers of video-based small group discussions can now be accommodated by an automated moderator, with a design to foster balanced, thoughtful discussion comparable to a Deliberative Poll (Fishkin et al. Reference Fishkin, Garg, Gelauff, Goel, Munagala, Sakshuwong, Siu and Yandamuri2019).

This technologically enlarged deliberation could be part of a wider-scale Deliberative Poll or a method of realizing the idea of Deliberation Day, a proposal to have very large numbers of small group discussions convened before a national election (Ackerman and Fishkin Reference Ackerman and Fishkin2004). Such a design realizes components of a “deliberative system” (Mansbridge et al. Reference Mansbridge, Bohman, Chambers, Christiano, Fung, Parkinson, Thompson, Parkinson and Mansbridge2012), to help exert more deliberative popular control (Fishkin Reference Fishkin2018, 199–210). What seems utopian in the form of face-to-face discussion (because of the prohibitive cost of bringing people physically together) might be made practical online. If the essential treatment is moderated, mutually respectful discussion among diverse others of competing arguments, supported by balanced information, then there is no need for the participants to be drawn in a random sample, so long as they are recruited at scale and assigned by algorithms to ensure diversity in each small group. Such wider-scale discussions would not be intended to represent the overall population, but they might help create a more thoughtful and substantive form of public opinion when brought to scale.

We can speculate more broadly. If deliberation supports accuracy-based rather than partisan-motivated reasoning and if it defuses affective polarization (via the contact hypothesis), then it would likely lessen receptiveness to partisan-motivated falsehoods. The sustained close interaction among diverse participants seems to open people’s minds and hearts, defusing the motivation to cling to falsehoods.

Our results suggest that the challenge now is to create a more-deliberative society, if aspirations for less-polarized public opinion and more mutually respectful citizenship are to be realized. We need more institutions that encourage evidence-based, thoughtful public discussion across our deep divisions. If one imagines “America in One Room” not as a minipublic but as an image of what needs to be brought to scale, one sees the potential for a deeper and more thoughtful democracy. Deliberation can engage citizens in choices that are based on more than partisan conformity, one-sided argumentation, or a mere impression of sound bites and headlines. Our findings suggest it is possible, at the level of mass public opinion, to build a democracy that transcends partisan deadlock. This field experiment is a pilot for imagining democratic possibilities.

SUPPLEMENTARY MATERIALS

To view supplementary material for this article, please visit http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0003055421000642.

DATA AVAILABILITY STATEMENT

Research documentation and data that support the findings of this study are openly available at the American Political Science Review Dataverse: https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/KJ8IH2.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the 2020 meetings of the American Association for Public Opinion Research and the 2020 meetings of the American Political Science Association. We would especially like to thank Henry Elkus and Sam Feinburg of Helena for their vision and collaboration. Michael Dennis, Jessica Carter, and their superb team at NORC at the University of Chicago were essential. Valentin Bolotnyy and Joshua Lerner offered insightful comments. Bruce Ackerman was especially noteworthy in helping to conceptualize the initial work. Dan Werner of “By the People Productions” played an essential role in executing the project. We would also like to acknowledge the support of the Helena Group Foundation and the advice and counsel of the distinguished Advisory Committee for America in One Room: Alexandra Rojas, Ben Ginsberg, Bill Galston, Bob Shrum, Bruce Ackerman, Eleanor Smeal, Irasema Coronado, Jane Mansbridge, Katherine Spillar, Kristen Clarke, Lanhee Chen, Luis Fraga, Norman Bradburn, Pete Peterson, and Peter Goldmark—and special thanks to research assistants: Erica Turret, Robbie Flatow, Caleb Young, Cornell Overfield, and Hannah Abelow.

FUNDING STATEMENT

This research was funded by the Helena Group Foundation.

CONFLICT OF INTEREST

The authors declare no ethical issues or conflicts of interest in this research.

ETHICAL STANDARDS

The authors declare that the human subjects research in this article was reviewed and approved by NORC at the University of Chicago and certificate numbers are provided in the appendix. The authors also affirm that this article adheres to the APSA’s Principles and Guidance on Human Subject Research.

Footnotes

1 The NORC methodological report is available at https://cdd.stanford.edu/mm/2019/10/NORC-Report-for-A1R-2019-Final.pdf.

3 “Strongly” referring to extremity on the scale and not “attitude strength” (Petty and Krosnick Reference Petty and Krosnick1995).

4 Party membership is based on the standard battery of party self-identification for the two major parties. Independents were asked whether they lean Republican or Democrat. Results for party members plus leaners are presented in the online appendix (Table A4).

5 For an evaluation of the moderators, see Table A4 in the online appendix. More than 90% of all participants (and separately of Republicans, Democrats, and Independents) disagreed strongly that “my moderator sometimes tried to influence the group with his or her own views.”

6 Senator Cory Booker. However, proposals were not identified with candidates (or parties) but presented in the briefings in nonpartisan terms so that participants could consider them on the merits.

7 The “baby bonds” proposal produced a comparable drop in average support (5.44) among the Democrats initially taking the strongest position.

8 Significance at least at the 0.05 level with two-tailed tests.

9 Table A7 in the online Appendix shows the contrasting results for the 21 nonpolarized items. In only five cases did they move significantly closer together.

10 This count includes the TPP question because the two parties moved to the same side.

11 Are the effects lasting? The answer is both no and yes. We focus on long-term effects in a separate paper. On the basis of follow-up waves with both the treatment and control groups, we see that some effects dissipate but others, such as voting intention near the time of the election more than a year later, show dramatic differences between the treatment and control group.

References

REFERENCES

Abramowitz, Alan I. 2013. The Polarized Public? Why American Government is so Dysfunctional. New York: Pearson.Google Scholar
Abramowitz, Alan I. 2018. The Great Alignment: Race, Party Transformation, and the Rise of Donald Trump. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Ackerman, Bruce. 1993. We the People, Volume 1: Foundations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ackerman, Bruce, and Fishkin, James. 2004. Deliberation Day. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Andersen, Ida-Elisabeth, and Jaeger, Birgit. 1999. “Scenario Workshops and Consensus Conferences: Towards More Democratic Decision-Making.” Science and Public Policy 26 (5): 331–40.Google Scholar
Allport, Gordon W. 1954. The Nature of Prejudice. New York: Perseus Books.Google Scholar
Asch, Solomon E. 1955. “Opinions and Social Pressure.” Scientific American 193 (5): 31–5.Google Scholar
Bächtiger, Andre, Dryzek, John S., Mansbridge, Jane, and Warren, Mark E.. 2018. The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barabas, Jason. 2004. “How Deliberation Affects Policy Opinions.” The American Political Science Review 98 (4): 687701.Google Scholar
Berry, Jeffrey M., and Sobieraj, Sarah. 2014. The Outrage Industry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bessette, Joseph M. 1994 The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Boatright, Robert G. 2014. Getting Primaried: The Changing Politics of Congressional Primary Challenges. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Burke, Edmund. [1774] 1854. “Speech to the Electors of Bristol.” Reprinted in Vol 1, The Works of the Right Honourable Edmund Burke, 6 vols, 446–48. London: Henry G. Bohn.Google Scholar
Campbell, James E. 2016. Polarized: Making Sense of a Divided America. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Chirawurah, Dennis, Fishkin, James, Santuah, Niagia, Siu, Alice, Bawah, Ayaga, Kranjac-Berisavljevic, Gordana, and Giles, Kathleen. 2019. “Deliberation for Development: Ghana’s First Deliberative Poll.” Journal of Public Deliberation 15 (1): Article 3.Google Scholar
Chong, Dennis, and Druckman, James. 2007. “Framing Public Opinion in Competitive Democracies.” The American Political Science Review 101 (4): 637–55.Google Scholar
Conover, Pamela Johnston, Searing, Donald D., and Crewe, Ivor M.. 2002. “The Deliberative Potential of Political Discussion.” British Journal of Political Science 32 (1): 2162.Google Scholar
Delli Carpini, Michael, and Keeter, Scott. 1996. What Americans Know about Politics and Why it Matters. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Dennis, J. Michael, Carter, Jennifer, Tipler, Caroline, Watts, Mark, and Yang, Y. Michael. 2020. “Bringing a Representative Sample of Voters to ‘America in One Room’: Sampling & Recruitment.” Paper Presented at the meetings of the American Association of Public Opinion Research. https://cdd.stanford.edu/mm/2020/07/Dennis_AAPOR_A1R_SamplingRecruitment.pdf.Google Scholar
Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Druckman, James N. 2012. “The Politics Of Motivation.” Critical Review 24 (2): 199216.Google Scholar
Farrar, Cynthia, Fishkin, James, Green, Don, List, Christian, Luskin, Robert C., and Paluck, Elizabeth Levy. 2010. “Disaggregating Deliberation’s Effects.” British Journal of Political Science 40 (2): 333–47.Google Scholar
Farrell, David M., Suiter, Jane, and Harris, Clodagh. 2018. “‘Systematizing’ Constitutional Deliberation: The 2016–18 Citizens’ Assembly in Ireland.” Irish Political Studies 34 (1): 113–23.Google Scholar
Farrell, David M., Suiter, Jane, Harris, Clodagh, and Cunningham, Kevin. 2019. “The Effects of Mixed Membership in a Deliberative Forum: The Irish Constitutional Convention of 2012–2014.” Political Studies 68 (1): 5473.Google Scholar
Fiorina, Morris P., with Abrams, Samuel J.. 2009. Disconnect: The Breakdown of Representation in American Politics. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.Google Scholar
Fiorina, Morris P. 2017. Unstable Majorities: Polarization, Party Sorting and Political Stalemate. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution Press.Google Scholar
Fishkin, James. 2018. Democracy When the People Are Thinking. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fishkin, James S., and Mansbridge, Jane. 2017. “Introduction.” Daedalus 146 (3): 613.Google Scholar
Fishkin, James S., Siu, Alice, Diamond, Larry, and Bradburn, Norman. 2021. “Replication Data for: Is Deliberation an Antidote to Extreme Partisan Polarization? Reflections on ‘America in One Room.’” Harvard Dataverse. Dataset. https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/KJ8IH2.Google Scholar
Fishkin, James, Garg, Nikhil, Gelauff, Lodewijk, Goel, Ashish, Munagala, Kamesh, Sakshuwong, Sukolsak, Siu, Alice, and Yandamuri, Sravya. 2019. “Deliberative Democracy with the Online Deliberation Platform.” The 7th AAAI Conference on Human Computation and Crowdsourcing (HCOMP 2019): 1–2. https://www.humancomputation.com/2019/assets/papers/144.pdf.Google Scholar
Fournier, Patrick, van der Kolk, Henk, Carty, R. Kenneth, Blais, André, and Rose, Jonathan. 2011. When Citizens Decide: Lessons from Citizen Assemblies on Electoral Reform. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goodin, Robert E. 2003. “Democratic Deliberation Within.” In Debating Deliberative Democracy, eds. Fishkin, James and Laslett, Peter, 5479. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Goidel, Robert K., and Shields, Todd G.. 1994. “The Vanishing Marginals, the Bandwagon, and the Mass Media.” The Journal of Politics 56 (3): 802–10.Google Scholar
Kimmo, Grönlund, Herne, Kaisa, and Setälä, Maija. 2015. “Does Enclave Deliberation Polarize Opinions?Political Behavior 37: 9951020.Google Scholar
Hansen, Mogens Herman. 1991. The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
He, Baogang, and Warren, Mark E.. 2011. “Authoritarian Deliberation: The Deliberative Turn in Chinese Political Development.” Perspectives on Politics 9 (2): 269–89.Google Scholar
Hetherington, Marc J., and Rudolph, Thomas. 2015. Why Washington Won’t Work: Polarization, Political Trust and the Governing Crisis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hewstone, Miles, and Swart, Hermann. 2011. “Fifty-Odd Years of Inter-Group Contact: From Hypothesis to Integrated Theory.” British Journal of Social Psychology 50 (3): 374–86.Google Scholar
Hopkins, Daniel J., and Sides, John eds. 2015. Political Polarization in American Politics. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Huckfeldt, Robert, Mendez, Jeanette Morehouse, and Osborn, Tracy. 2004. “Disagreement, Ambivalence, and Engagement: The Political Consequences of Heterogeneous Networks.” Political Psychology 25 (1): 6595.Google Scholar
Iyengar, Shanto, Sood, Gaurav, and Lelkes, Yptach. 2012. “Affect, Not Ideology: A Social Identity Perspective on Polarization.” Public Opinion Quarterly 76 (3): 405–31.Google Scholar
Iyengar, Shanto, and Krupenkin, Masha. 2018. “The Strengthening of Partisan Affect.” Political Psychology 39 (S1): 201–18.Google Scholar
Iyengar, Shanto, Lelkes, Yptach, Levendusky, Mathew, Malhotra, Neil, and Westwood, Sean. 2019. “The Origins and Consequences of Affective Polarization in the United States.” Annual Review of Political Science 22: 129–46.Google Scholar
Jacobs, Lawrence R., and Shapiro, Robert Y.. 2000. Politicians Don’t Pander: Political Manipulation and the Loss of Democratic Responsiveness. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kim, Nuri, Fishkin, James, and Luskin, Robert C.. 2018. “Intergroup Contact in Deliberative Contexts: Evidence from Deliberative Polls.” Journal of Communication 68 (6): 1029–51.Google Scholar
Kunda, Ziva. 1990. “The Case for Motivated Reasoning.” Psychological Bulletin 108 (3): 480–98.Google Scholar
Landemore, Helene. 2013. Democratic Reason. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lenz, Gabriel S. 2012. Follow the Leader: How Voters Respond to Politicians’ Policies and Performance. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Leeper, Thomas J., and Slothuus, Rune. 2014. “Political Parties, Motivated Reasoning, and Public Opinion Formation.” Political Psychology 35: 129156.Google Scholar
Levendusky, Matthew S. 2018. “Americans, Not Partisans: Can Priming American National Identity Reduce Affective Polarization?The Journal of Politics 80 (1): 5970.Google Scholar
Levendusky, Matthew S., Druckman, James N., and Mclain, Audrey. 2016. “How Group Discussions Create Strong Attitudes and Strong Partisans.” Research & Politics 3 (2): 16.Google Scholar
Lupia, Arthur. 1994. “Shortcuts versus Encyclopedias: Information and Voting Behavior in California Insurance Reform Elections.” American Political Science Review 88 (1): 6376.Google Scholar
Luskin, Robert C., O’Flynn, Ian, Fishkin, James, and Russell, David. 2014. “Deliberating across Deep Divides.” Political Studies 62: 116–35.Google Scholar
Manin, Bernard. 1997. The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mansbridge, Jane. 1999. “Everyday Talk in the Deliberative System.” In Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement, ed. Macedo, Stephen, 211–42. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mansbridge, Jane, Bohman, James, Chambers, Simone, Christiano, Thomas, Fung, Archon, Parkinson, John, Thompson, Dennis F., et al. 2012. “A Systemic Approach to Deliberative Democracy.” In Deliberative Systems, eds. Parkinson, John and Mansbridge, Jane, 126. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Maoz, Ifat. 2000. “An Experiment in Peace: Reconciliation-Aimed Workshops of Jewish-Israeli and Palestinian Youth.” Journal of Peace Research 37 (6): 721–36.Google Scholar
Már, Kristinn, and Gastil, John. 2019. “Tracing the Boundaries of Motivated Reasoning: How Deliberative Minipublics Can Improve Voter Knowledge.” Political Psychology 41 (1): 107–27.Google Scholar
Mason, Lilliana. 2014. “‘I Disrespectfully Agree’: The Differential Effects of Partisan Sorting on Social and Issue Polarization.American Journal of Political Science 59 (1): 128145.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 1962. On Liberty. London: John Parker and Son; reprinted New York: New American Library.Google Scholar
Mutz, Diana C. 2002. “Cross-Cutting Social Networks: Testing Democratic Theory in Practice.” American Political Science Review 96 (1): 111–26.Google Scholar
Mutz, Diana C. 2015. In-Your-Face Politics: The Consequences of Uncivil Media. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Neblo, Michael A., Esterling, Kevin M., Kennedy, Ryan P., David, M. J. Lazer, and Sokhey, Anand E.. 2010. “Who Wants To Deliberate—And Why?American Political Science Review 104 (3): 566–83.Google Scholar
Neblo, Michael A., Esterling, Kevin M., and David, M. J. Lazer. 2018. Politics with the People: Building a Directly Representative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Noelle-Neumann, Elisabeth. 1984. “The Spiral of Silence: A Theory of Public Opinion.” Journal of Communication 24 (2): 4351.Google Scholar
Nyhan, Brendan, and Reifler, Jason. 2010. “When Corrections Fail: The Persistence of Political Misperceptions.” Political Behavior 32 (2): 303–30.Google Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 2008. Democracy and Knowledge: Innovation and Learning in Classical Athens. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Page, Benjamin, and Shapiro, Robert. 1992. The Rational Public: Fifty Years of Trends in Americans’ Policy Preferences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Pariser, Eli. 2011. The Filter Bubble. New York: The Penguin Group.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, Thomas F., and Tropp, Linda R.. 2006. “A Meta-Analytic Test of Intergroup Contact Theory.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 90 (5): 751–83.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, Thomas F., and Tropp, Linda R.. 2011. When Groups Meet: The Dynamics of Intergroup Contact. New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Petty, Richard E., and Krosnick, Jon A.. 1995. Attitude Strength: Antecedents and Consequences. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Popkin, Samuel L. 1991. The Reasoning Voter: Communication and Persuasion in Presidential Campaign. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Rasinski, K.A., Bradburn, N. M., and Lauen, D.. 1999. “The Effects of Media Coverage of the National Issues Convention on Citizen Attitudes and Opinions.” Chap. 8 in The Poll with a Human Face: National Issues Convention Experiment in Political Communications, eds. McCombs, Maxwell and Reynolds, Amy. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Rosenfeld, Michael J. 2017. “Moving a Mountain: The Extraordinary Trajectory of Same-Sex Marriage Approval in the United States.” Socius: Sociological Research for a Dynamic World 3: 122.Google Scholar
Sandefur, Justin, Birdsall, Nancy, Fishkin, James S., and Moyo, Mujubo. 2020. “Deliberative Democracy and the Resource Curse: A National Experiment in Tanzania.” Working Paper. https://cdd.stanford.edu/mm/2020/10/sandefur-cgdev-tanzania.pdf.Google Scholar
Siu, Alice, and Stanisevski, Dragan. 2012. “Deliberation in Multicultural Societies: Addressing Inequality, Exclusion and Marginalization.” Chap. 5 in Democracy in Motion: Evaluating the Practice and Impact of Deliberative Civic Engagement , eds. Nabatchi, Tina, Gastil, John, Weiksner, G. Michael, and Leighninger, Matt. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. 2002The Law of Group PolarizationThe Journal of Political Philosophy 10 (2): 175–95.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. 2009. Going to Extremes: How Like Minds Unite and Divide. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. 2017. # Republic: Divided Democracy in the Age of Social Media. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Taber, Charles S., and Lodge, Milton. 2006. “Motivated Skepticism in the Evaluation of Political Beliefs.” American Journal of Political Science 50 (3): 755–69.Google Scholar
Tajfel, Henri. 1981. Human Groups and Social Categories: Studies in Social Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, Mark E., and Pearse, Hilary eds. 2008. Designing Deliberative Democracy: The British Columbia Citizens Assembly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wojcieszak, Magdalena. 2011. “Deliberation and Attitude Polarization.” Journal of Communication 61 (4): 596617.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Immigration

Figure 1

Table 2. Environment

Figure 2

Table 3. Economy and Taxes

Figure 3

Table 4. Health Care

Figure 4

Table 5. Foreign Policy

Figure 5

Table 6. Issue-Based Depolarization

Figure 6

Table 7. Affective Polarization

Figure 7

Table 8. Extremity and Democrats’ Feelings toward Republicans

Figure 8

Table 9. Extremity and Republicans’ Feelings toward Democrats

Supplementary material: Link

Fishkin et al. Dataset

Link
Supplementary material: File

Fishkin et al. supplementary material

Fishkin et al. supplementary material

Download Fishkin et al. supplementary material(File)
File 81.9 KB
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.