Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T23:54:01.694Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

HIGHER INDEPENDENCE

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 April 2022

VERA FISCHER
Affiliation:
INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA KOLINGASSE 14-16, 1090WIEN, AUSTRIAE-mail:[email protected]
DIANA CAROLINA MONTOYA*
Affiliation:
INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA KOLINGASSE 14-16, 1090WIEN, AUSTRIAE-mail:[email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We study higher analogues of the classical independence number on $\omega $ . For $\kappa $ regular uncountable, we denote by $i(\kappa )$ the minimal size of a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family. We establish ZFC relations between $i(\kappa )$ and the standard higher analogues of some of the classical cardinal characteristics, e.g., $\mathfrak {r}(\kappa )\leq \mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ and $\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )\leq \mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ . For $\kappa $ measurable, assuming that $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ we construct a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family which remains maximal after the $\kappa $ -support product of $\lambda $ many copies of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing. Thus, we show the consistency of $\kappa ^{+}=\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )=\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )<2^{\kappa }$ . We conclude the paper with interesting open questions and discuss difficulties regarding other natural approaches to higher independence.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

A family $\mathcal {A}$ contained in $[\omega ]^{\omega }$ is said to be independent if for every two finite disjoint subfamilies $\mathcal {B}$ and $\mathcal {C}$ the set $\bigcap \mathcal {B}\backslash \bigcup \mathcal {C}$ is infinite. We refer to such sets as Boolean combinations. The least size of a maximal (under inclusion) independent family is denoted $\mathfrak {i}$ . For an excellent introduction to the subject of cardinal characteristics of the continuum and definition of various characteristics we refer the reader to [Reference Blass, Foreman and Kanamori2].

The past decade has seen an increased volume of work regarding natural higher analogues for uncountable cardinals $\kappa $ of the classical cardinal characteristics. However, even though we already have a comparatively rich literature in this area there is very little known about analogues of the notion of independence. Even in the classical, countable setting, the independence number, and the notion of independence in general, do not seem to be that well-studied. Among the many open questions surrounding independence are the consistency of $\text {cof}(\mathfrak {i})=\omega $ and the consistency of $\mathfrak {i}<\mathfrak {a}$ . A difficulty in the study of the higher independence number is the fact that it is not a priori clear what the natural generalization of the classical independence number should be. Given an uncountable cardinal $\kappa $ Footnote 1 one may consider subfamilies $\mathcal {A}$ of $[\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ which have the property that every Boolean combination generated by strictly less than $\kappa $ many elements of $\mathcal {A}$ is unbounded. That is, one may require that for every two disjoint subfamilies $\mathcal {B}$ and $\mathcal {C}$ of $\mathcal {A}$ , such that $|\mathcal {B}|<\kappa $ and $|\mathcal {C}|<\kappa $ , the Boolean combination $\bigcap \mathcal {B}\backslash \bigcup \mathcal {C}$ is unbounded. We refer to such families as strongly independent. A major problem presenting itself in the study of this notion of strong independence on $\kappa $ is the very existence of maximal, under inclusion, strongly independent families. Results regarding these families, together with a number of interesting open questions are included in the last section of the paper. An earlier study of the notion of strong independence can be found in [Reference Kunnen20], where it is shown that the existence of a maximal strongly $\omega _{1}$ -independent family is equiconsistent with the existence of a measurable.

A more restrictive, but fruitful, approach towards the generalization of the classical notion of independence is the requirement that for a given family $\mathcal {A}\subseteq [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ the finitely generated Boolean combinations are unbounded. That is, given a family $\mathcal {A}\subseteq [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ we say that $\mathcal {A}$ is $\kappa $ -independent if for every two disjoint finite subfamilies $\mathcal {B}$ and $\mathcal {C}$ contained in $\mathcal {A}$ , the set $\bigcap \mathcal {B}\backslash \bigcup \mathcal {C}$ is unbounded.Footnote 2 The existence of a maximal under inclusion $\kappa $ -independent family is provided by the Axiom of Choice and thus given an uncountable regular cardinal $\kappa $ , one can define the higher independence number, denoted $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ , to be the minimal size of a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family. A standard diagonalization argument going over all Boolean combinations, shows that $\kappa ^{+}\leq \mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ . Classical examples of independent families of cardinality $2^{\omega }$ do generalize into the uncountable and provide the existence of $\kappa $ -independent families and so of maximal $\kappa $ -independent families of cardinality $2^{\kappa }$ (see Lemma 2.4). An example of a strongly $\kappa $ -independent family of cardinality $2^{\kappa }$ , under some additional hypothesis on $\kappa $ , is provided in Lemma 10.2.

One of the main breakthroughs in the study of the classical independence number is the consistency of $\mathfrak {i}<\mathfrak {u}$ , established in 1992 by Shelah (see [Reference Shelah22]). The consistency proof carries a somewhat hidden construction of a Sacks indestructible maximal independent family, that is a maximal independent family which remains maximal after the countable support product and countable support iterations of Sacks forcing. A tree version of Shelah’s poset, known as party forcing, has been used in [Reference Chodounsky, Grebik and Fischer7] to establish the consistency of $\mathfrak {i}=\mathfrak {f}<\mathfrak {u}$ , where $\mathfrak {f}$ is the free sequences number.Footnote 3 For recent studies on Sacks indestructible, co-analytic maximal independent families see [Reference Brendle, Fischer and Khomskii5], as well as [Reference Bergfalk, Fischer and Switzer1, Reference Cruz-Chapital, Fischer, Guzman and Supina9, Reference Switzer23]. In this paper, we prove:

Theorem. Let $\kappa $ be a measurable cardinal and let $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ . Then there is a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family which remains maximal after the $\kappa $ -support product of $\lambda $ -many copies of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing.

The existence of this indestructible maximal $\kappa $ -independent family is closely related to the properties of a normal measure $\mathcal {U}$ on $\kappa $ . With the indestructible family $\mathcal {A}$ , we associate a $\kappa ^{+}$ -complete filter $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ which is properly contained in $\mathcal {U}$ and its elements meet every Boolean combination on an unbounded set. The properties of this filter capture to a great extent the indestructibility of the associated independent family.

For readers familiar with the countable setting, we will draw a more detailed comparison. As developed originally in the work of Shelah [Reference Shelah22] and later analyzed for example in [Reference Chodounsky, Grebik and Fischer7], an independent family which is maximal in a strong sense and whose density filter (a similarly to $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ associated filter) is selective (which means both a P-set and Q-set) is indestructible by countable support products and iterations of Sacks forcing. While $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is a $\kappa $ -P-set, in the sense that every subfamily of cardinality $\leq \kappa $ has a pseudo-intersection in the filter (see Definition 5.4 and Lemma 5.5), the role of the Q-set property from the countable setting is taken by the fact that for every ground model strictly increasing function in $^{\kappa }\kappa $ there is a set in the filter whose enumeration function grows faster than the given function (see Lemma 5.6 and Corollary 5.7).Footnote 4 In both, the countable and the uncountable setting a strengthening of the maximality of the corresponding maximal independent family plays an important role. In the countable setting this strengthening is known as dense maximality, a property which originally appears in [Reference Goldstern and Shelah16]. The $\kappa $ -maximal independent family which we construct is densely maximal in a similar sense (see Definition 6.1). Moreover we make an explicit use of an equivalent characterisation of dense maximality given in Lemma 6.2, characterization which plays a key role in our main theorem. An analogue to the countable setting of the overall approach, which we take in this paper can be found in the more recent studies [Reference Bergfalk, Fischer and Switzer1, Reference Cruz-Chapital, Fischer, Guzman and Supina9, Reference Switzer23]. Note that an analogue of the equivalent characterization given in Lemma 6.2 implicitly appears in [Reference Shelah22].

Finally, the existence of a $\kappa $ -mad family, which remains maximal after an arbitrarily long $\kappa $ -supported product of $\kappa $ -Sacks reals is a straightforward generalization of the classical case. Moreover, if $\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+}$ then $\mathfrak {a}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+}$ (see [Reference Blass, Hyttinen and Zhang3, Reference Raghavan and Shelah21]). Thus our result leads to the following statement:

Theorem. Let $\kappa $ be a measurable cardinal and $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ . Then there is a cardinal preserving generic extension in which

$$ \begin{align*}\mathfrak{a}(\kappa)=\mathfrak{d}(\kappa)=\mathfrak{r}(\kappa)=\mathfrak{i}(\kappa)=\kappa^{+}<2^{\kappa}.\end{align*} $$

One of the very interesting open questions regarding the classical independence number is the consistency of $\mathfrak {i}<\mathfrak {a}$ . As a very partial result towards this question we obtain the following:

Corollary. Let $\kappa $ be regular uncountable. If $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+}$ then $\mathfrak {a}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+}$ .

1.1 Structure of the paper

In Section 2 we define a notion of independence at $\kappa $ , for $\kappa $ arbitrary infinite cardinal and define the cardinal number $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ for $\kappa $ regular uncountable. In Section 3, given a measurable cardinal $\kappa $ , witnessed by a normal measure $\mathcal {U}$ and working under the hypothesis that $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ , we define a $\kappa ^{+}$ closed poset $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ which adjoins a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family, which we denote $\mathcal {A}_{G}$ .Footnote 5 In Section 4 we study the properties of an ideal on $\kappa $ , to which we refer as density ideal and denote $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ , which is contained in the dual ideal of $\mathcal {U}$ and which naturally captures crucial properties of the independent family $\mathcal {A}_{G}$ . In Section 5.1, we show that the dual filter of this ideal, denoted $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ is a $\kappa $ -P-set. In Section 6 we show that the family $\mathcal {A}_{G}$ is densely maximal in a natural sense and characterize dense maximality in terms of properties of the density ideal. Section 7 introduces the concepts of preprocessed conditions and outer hulls necessary for the proofs in the last section. In Section 8 we prove our main theorem, by showing that the densely maximal $\kappa $ -independent family $\mathcal {A}_{G}$ remains maximal after the $\kappa $ -support product of $\lambda $ many copies of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing. We conclude the paper with some open questions and an appendix, discussing the notion of strong independence.

2 The higher independence number

In the following we set to define a higher analogue of the notion of independent families on $\omega $ for the special case in which the Boolean combinations are finitely generated.

Definition 2.1. Let $\kappa $ be a regular uncountable cardinal and let $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ be the set of all finite partial functions with domain included in $\mathcal {A}$ and range the set $\{0,1\}$ . For each $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ let $\mathcal {A}^{h}=\bigcap \{\mathcal {A}^{h(A)}:A\in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(h)\}$ where $\mathcal {A}^{h(A)}=A$ if $h(A)=0$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h(A)}=\kappa \backslash A$ if $h(A)=1$ . We refer to sets of the form $\mathcal {A}^{h}$ as Boolean combinations.

With this we can state the definition of $\kappa $ -independence. For a discussion of the most general definition in which the Boolean combinations are generated by arbitrarily large subfamilies of the given family, see [Reference Fischer and Eskew10].

Definition 2.2.

  1. (1) A family $\mathcal {A}\subseteq [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ is said to be $\kappa $ -independent if for each $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ the set $\mathcal {A}^{h}$ is unbounded. It is said to be a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family if it is $\kappa $ -independent and maximal under inclusion.

  2. (2) The least size of a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family is denoted $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ .

Remark 2.3. For $\kappa =\omega $ the above notions coincide with the classical notions of independence on $[\omega ]^{\omega }$ and $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )=\mathfrak {i}$ , where $\mathfrak {i}$ is the classical independence number.

Lemma 2.4. Let $\kappa $ be a regular infinite cardinal. Then

  1. (1) Every $\kappa $ -independent family is contained in a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family.

  2. (2) $\kappa ^{+}\leq \mathfrak {r}(\kappa )\leq \mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ .

  3. (3) There is a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family of cardinality $2^{\kappa }$ .

  4. (4) $\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )\leq \mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ .

Proof Since the increasing union of a collection of $\kappa $ -independent families is $\kappa $ -independent, by the Axiom of Choice every $\kappa $ -independent family is contained in a maximal one. Note that if $\mathcal {A}$ is a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family, then the set of Boolean combinations $\{\mathcal {A}^{h}: h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})\}$ is not split and so $\mathfrak {r}(\kappa )\leq |\mathcal {A}|$ . For a construction of a $\kappa $ -independent family of cardinality $2^{\kappa }$ , see [Reference Geschke14, Theorem 4.2]. Finally, the proof that $\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )\leq \mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ follows closely the proof of the classical case, i.e., $\mathfrak {d}\leq \mathfrak {i}$ (see [Reference Halbeisen18]).

One of the most interesting open questions, regarding the classical cardinal characteristics is the consistency of $\mathfrak {i}<\mathfrak {a}$ . By the last item of the above theorem and the fact that if $\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+}$ implies that $\mathfrak {a}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+}$ (see [Reference Blass, Hyttinen and Zhang3, Reference Raghavan and Shelah21]), we obtain the following:

Corollary 2.5. Let $\kappa $ be a regular uncountable cardinal. Then if $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+}$ then $\mathfrak {a}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+}$ .

3 Adjoining a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family

In this section, we provide a partial order which adjoins a maximal $\kappa $ -independent family, a family which we will later show to be indestructible by products of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing.

Let $\kappa $ be a measurable cardinal and $\mathcal {U}$ a normal measure on $\kappa $ .

Definition 3.1. Let $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ be the poset of all pairs $(\mathcal {A},A)$ where $\mathcal {A}$ is a $\kappa $ -independent family of cardinality $\kappa $ and $A\in \mathcal {U}$ has the property that $\forall h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ the set $\mathcal {A}^{h}\cap A$ is unbounded. The extension relation is defined as follows: $(\mathcal {A}_{1},A_{1})\leq (\mathcal {A}_{0},A_{0})$ if and only if $\mathcal {A}_{1}\supseteq \mathcal {A}_{0}$ and $A_{1}\subseteq ^{*} A_{0}$ .Footnote 6

Lemma 3.2. Assume $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ . Then $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ is $\kappa ^{+}$ -closed and $\kappa ^{++}\mathrm{{-}cc}$ .

Proof. Let $\{(\mathcal {A}_{i},A_{i})\}_{i\in \kappa }$ be a decreasing sequence in $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ . We can assume that $\{A_{i}\}_{i\in \kappa }$ is strictly decreasing, i.e., for each $i>j$ we have $A_{j}\subseteq A_{i}$ . Then $\mathcal {A}=\bigcup _{i\in \kappa }\mathcal {A}_{i}$ is an independent family of cardinality $\kappa $ and the diagonal intersection $A^{\prime }=\Delta _{i\in \kappa }A_{i}\in \mathcal {U}$ .

Now, for each $i\in \kappa $ , let $\{h_{i,j}\}_{j\in \kappa }$ enumerate $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Recursively we will define a set $A^{\prime \prime }=\{k_{i,l,m}\}_{l,m<i; i<\kappa }$ which is a pseudo-intersection of $\{A_{i}\}_{i\in \kappa }$ and which meets every Boolean combination $\mathcal {A}^{h}$ for $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ on an unbounded set. Then $A=A^{\prime }\cup A^{\prime \prime }$ is an element of $\mathcal {U}$ and $(\mathcal {A},A)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ is a common extension of $\{(\mathcal {A}_{i},A_{i})\}_{i\in \kappa }$ .

3.1 Construction of $A^{\prime \prime }$

At step i pick $k_{i,m,l}\in A_{i}\cap \mathcal {A}_{i}^{h_{m,l}}$ for each $m,l<i$ . Then in particular $k_{i,m,l}\in A_{m}$ for each $m\leq i$ and $k_{i,m,l}\in \mathcal {A}_{m}^{h_{m,l}}$ for each $m,l < i$ . Take $A^{\prime \prime }=\{k_{i,m,l}\}_{m,l<i;i<\kappa }$ . Then $A^{\prime \prime }$ meets every Boolean combination on an unbounded set and is a pseudo-intersection. Fix $\gamma \in \kappa $ . Then for all $\xi $ such that $\xi>\gamma $ and all $m,l<\xi $ we have that $k_{\xi ,l,m}\in A_{\xi }\subseteq A_{\gamma }$ . Thus $A^{\prime \prime }\backslash A_{\gamma }\subseteq \{k_{\xi ,l,m}\}_{\xi <\gamma; l,m<\xi }$ , which is a bounded set.

The poset has the $\kappa ^{++}$ -cc, because $|\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}|=\kappa ^{+}$ . Indeed, $\Big |\big [[\kappa ]^{\kappa }\big ]^{\kappa }\Big |=\kappa ^{+}$ .⊣

Lemma 3.3. If $(\mathcal {A},A)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ , then there is $B\notin \mathcal {A}$ such that $B\subseteq A$ and $(\mathcal {A}\cup \{B\},A)\leq (\mathcal {A},A)$ .

Proof Let $\{h_{i}\}_{i\in \kappa }$ be a fixed enumeration of $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Since $\mathcal {A}^{h_{0}}\cap A$ is unbounded, we can find distinct $k_{0,0}$ , $k_{0,1}$ in $\mathcal {A}^{h_{0}}\cap A$ . Suppose we have defined $\{k_{i,j}: i\in \gamma , j\in 2\}$ distinct. Since $\mathcal {A}^{h_{\gamma }}\cap A$ is unbounded, we can find distinct $k_{\gamma ,0}, k_{\gamma ,1}$ in $(\mathcal {A}^{h_{\gamma }}\cap A)\backslash \{k_{i,j}: i\in \gamma , j\in 2\}$ . Finally, take $B=\{k_{i,0}\}_{i\in \kappa }$ . Clearly $B\subseteq A$ and $\mathcal {A}\cup \{B\}$ is independent. To verify the latter note that for each $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ there are unboundedly many $h_{i}\supseteq h$ . Then for unboundedly many $i\in \kappa $ , $k_{i,0}\in \mathcal {A}^{h_{i}}\cap B\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\cap B$ and $k_{i,1}\in \mathcal {A}^{h_{i}}\backslash B\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash B$ .

Corollary 3.4. Let G be $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter. Then $\mathcal {A}_{G}=\bigcup \{\mathcal {A}: \exists A\in \mathcal {U} \text { with }(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ is a $\kappa $ -maximal independent family.

Proof Suppose $X\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }\setminus \mathcal {A}_{G}$ and $\mathcal {A}_{G}\cup \{X\}$ is independent. Take $(\mathcal {A},A)\in G$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}(\mathcal{A},A)\Vdash "\mathcal{A}_{G}\cup\{X\}\text{ is independent and }X\notin \mathcal{A}_{G}."\end{align*} $$

Since $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ is $\kappa ^{+}$ -closed, the set X belongs to the ground model. Now, if for each $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ the intersections $\mathcal {A}^{h}\cap X\cap A$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h}\cap A\cap X^{c}$ are unbounded, then $(\mathcal {A}\cup \{X\},A)\leq (\mathcal {A},A)$ and

$$ \begin{align*}(\mathcal{A}\cup\{X\},A)\Vdash "X\in\mathcal{A}_{G},\!\text{"}\end{align*} $$

which is a contradiction. Therefore there is $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that either $\mathcal {A}^{h}\cap A\cap X$ or $\mathcal {A}^{h}\cap A\cap X^{c}$ is bounded. However, by Lemma 3.3, there is $B\notin \mathcal {A}$ such that $B\subseteq A$ and $(\mathcal {A}\cup \{B\},A)\leq (\mathcal {A},A)$ . But then,

$$ \begin{align*}(\mathcal{A}\cup\{B\},A)\Vdash "\exists h\in\operatorname{\mathrm{FF}}_{<\omega,\kappa}(\mathcal{A}_{G})\text{ such that }\mathcal{A}^{h}_{G}\cap X\text{ or }\mathcal{A}^{h}_{G}\setminus X \text{ is bounded}."\end{align*} $$

Therefore $(\mathcal {A}\cup \{B\}, A)\Vdash "\mathcal {A}_{G}\cup \{X\}\text { is not independent},\text{"}$ which is a contradiction.

Remark 3.5. Given a measurable cardinal $\kappa $ and a normal measure $\mathcal {U}$ on $\kappa $ , whenever $\mathcal {A}=\mathcal {A}_{G}$ is the generic maximal $\kappa $ -independent family given by a $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter G, we will say that $\mathcal {A}$ is $\mathcal {U}$ -supported.

4 The density ideal

The density ideal (see [Reference Fischer and Montoya11]) plays an important role in describing the properties of maximal independent families on $\omega $ . A higher analogue of this notion will play an equally important role in the study of maximal $\kappa $ -independent families indestructible by $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing.

Definition 4.1. Let $\mathcal {A}$ be a $\mathcal {U}$ -supported independent family. The density ideal $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is the ideal of all $X\in \mathcal {U}^{*}$ , where $\mathcal {U}^{*}$ is the dual ideal of $\mathcal {U}$ , such that $\forall h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ there is $h^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap X=\emptyset $ .

Lemma 4.2.

  1. (1) If $\mathcal {A}$ be an independent family, then $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega , \kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is an ideal.

  2. (2) If $\mathcal {A}_{0},\mathcal {A}_{1}$ are independent families such that $\mathcal {A}_{0}\subseteq \mathcal {A}_{1}$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{0})\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{1})$ .

Proof To prove item $(1)$ above consider any $X_{0}$ and $X_{1}$ in $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Fix any $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Then there is $h_{0}\supseteq h$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h_{0}}\cap X_{0}=\emptyset $ and there is $h_{1}\supseteq h_{0}$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}\cap X_{1}=\emptyset $ . But then $h_{1}\supseteq h$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}\cap (X_{0}\cup X_{1})=\emptyset $ . Clearly, $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is closed under subsets and thus $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is an ideal.

To prove item $(2)$ consider any $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{0})$ . Let $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{1})$ . Then $h^{\prime }=h\upharpoonright \mathcal {A}_{0}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{0})$ and by hypothesis there is $h_{0}$ in $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{0})$ extending $h^{\prime }$ such that $\mathcal {A}_{0}^{h_{0}}\cap X=\emptyset $ . Let $h_{1}=h_{0}\cup h\upharpoonright (\mathcal {A}_{1}\backslash \mathcal {A}_{0})$ . Then $\mathcal {A}_{1}^{h_{1}}\cap X\subseteq \mathcal {A}_{0}^{h_{0}}\cap X$ and so $\mathcal {A}_{1}^{h_{1}}\cap X=\emptyset $ .

Remark 4.3. Note that $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is not necessarily $\kappa $ -complete.

Lemma 4.4. $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P_{\mathcal {U}}}}\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})=\bigcup \{\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}):\exists A (\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ .

Proof To see $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}}\bigcup \{\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}):\exists A(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ consider any $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter G. In $V[G]$ we have $\mathcal {A}_{G}=\bigcup \{\mathcal {A}:\exists A(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ . Now for all $(\mathcal {A},A)\in G$ , by Lemma 4.2(2), $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ . Therefore $\bigcup \{\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}):\exists A(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ .

The fact that $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P_{\mathcal {U}}}}\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})\subseteq \bigcup \{\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}):\exists \mathcal {A} (\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ follows from the $\kappa ^{+}$ -closure of $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ . Consider any $p=(\mathcal {A},A)\in G$ and a $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -name $\dot {X}$ for a subset of $\kappa $ such that $p\Vdash \dot {X}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ . Fix $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Then

$$ \begin{align*}p\Vdash\exists h^{\prime}\in\operatorname{\mathrm{FF}}_{<\omega,\kappa}(\mathcal{A}_{G})(h\subseteq h^{\prime}\text{ and }\mathcal{A}_{G}^{h^{\prime}}\cap X=\emptyset).\end{align*} $$

Thus there is $(\mathcal {A}^{\prime },A^{\prime })\leq (\mathcal {A},A)$ such that $h^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}^{\prime })$ , $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap X=\emptyset $ . Proceed inductively to construct a decreasing sequence $\{(\mathcal {A}_{i},A_{i})\}_{i\in \kappa }$ of conditions below p such that if $\mathcal {A}_{\kappa }=\bigcup _{i\in \kappa }\mathcal {A}_{i}$ then for all $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{\kappa })$ there is $h^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{\kappa })$ extending h and such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap X=\emptyset $ . Thus $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{\kappa })$ . By the $\kappa ^{+}$ -closure of $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ , there is $p^{\prime }=(\mathcal {B},B)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ which is an extension of all $(\mathcal {A}_{i},A_{i})$ . Thus $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {B})$ , $p^{\prime }\leq p$ and

$$ \begin{align*}p^{\prime}\Vdash \dot{X}\in \bigcup\{\operatorname{\mathrm{id}}_{<\omega,\kappa}(\mathcal{A}): \exists A(\mathcal{A},A)\in G\}.\\[-40pt] \end{align*} $$

Lemma 4.5. Let $(\mathcal {A},A)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ and let $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Then $(\mathcal {A},A\backslash X)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ .

Proof It is sufficient to show that for each $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ the set $\mathcal {A}^{h}\cap (A\backslash X)$ is unbounded. Fix $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Since $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ there is $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ , $h^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ extending h such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap X=\emptyset $ . Thus $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\subseteq \kappa \backslash X$ . However

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{A}^{h^{\prime}}\cap A=(\mathcal{A}^{h^{\prime}}\cap A\cap X)\cup (\mathcal{A}^{h^{\prime}}\cap A\cap X^{c}).\end{align*} $$

Thus $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A=\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap X^{c}$ is unbounded. Therefore $(\mathcal {A},A\backslash X)$ is a condition.

Corollary 4.6. Let G be a $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter. Then in $V[G]$ the density ideal $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ is generated by $\{\kappa \backslash A:\exists \mathcal {A}(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ . That is

$$ \begin{align*}\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_{\mathcal{U}}}\operatorname{\mathrm{id}}_{<\omega,\kappa}(\mathcal{A}_{G})=\langle\{\kappa\backslash A:\exists \mathcal{A}(\mathcal{A},A)\in G\}{\rangle}.\end{align*} $$

Proof Let G be a $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter. By Lemma 4.4, $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})=\bigcup \{\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}):\exists A(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ . Let $\mathcal {I}_{G}$ be the ideal generated by $\{\kappa \backslash A:\exists \mathcal {A}(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ .

First we will show that $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})\subseteq \mathcal {I}_{G}$ . Let $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ . Thus there is $(\mathcal {A},A)\in G$ such that $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . However the set $D_{X}=\{(\mathcal {B},B)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}: X\cap B=\emptyset \}$ is dense below $(\mathcal {A},A)$ (indeed, if $(\mathcal {B},B)\leq (\mathcal {A},A)$ then $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {B})$ and by Lemma 4.5 $(\mathcal {B},B\backslash X)\leq (\mathcal {B},B)$ ) and so there is $(\mathcal {B},B)\in G$ such that $X\cap B=\emptyset $ . That is $X\subseteq \kappa \backslash B$ and so $X\in \mathcal {I}_{G}$ .

To show that $\mathcal {I}_{G}\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ , consider any $X\in \mathcal {I}_{G}$ . Then there is a finite set of conditions $\{(\mathcal {A}_{i},A_{i})\}_{i\in n}$ in G such that $X\subseteq \bigcup _{i\in n}\kappa \backslash A_{i}=\kappa \backslash \bigcap _{i\in n}A_{i}$ . Note that $(\mathcal {B},B)\in G$ , where $(\mathcal {B},B)=(\bigcup _{i\in n} \mathcal {A}_{i}, \bigcap _{i\in n} A_{i})$ . Thus $X\subseteq \kappa \backslash B$ . Fix any $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ . Then there is $(\mathcal {C},C)\in G$ such that $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {C})$ . Take $(\mathcal {E},E)\in G$ which is a common extension of $(\mathcal {B},B)$ and $(\mathcal {C},C)$ . Then $(\mathcal {E}, E)\leq (\mathcal {C}, B)$ and so in particular $(\mathcal {C},B)\in G$ . However the set $H_{B}=\{(\mathcal {C}^{\prime },C^{\prime }):\exists Y\in \mathcal {C}^{\prime }(Y\subseteq B)\}$ is dense below $(\mathcal {C},B)$ (apply Lemma 3.3) and so there is $(\mathcal {C}^{\prime },C^{\prime })\in G$ such that for some $Y\in \mathcal {C}^{\prime }$ , $Y\subseteq B$ . Then $h^{\prime }=h\cup \{(Y,0)\}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ and $\mathcal {A}_{G}^{h^{\prime }}\cap X=\emptyset $ . Thus $X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ .

5 The density filter

Of particular interest for our investigations will be the dual filter of the density ideal. Note that the density filter plays an important role in the original work of [Reference Shelah22] on the relative consistency of $\mathfrak {i}<\mathfrak {u}$ , from which the existence of a Sacks indestructible maximal independent family can be extracted (see also [Reference Fischer and Montoya11]).

Remark 5.1. Let G be $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic, let $\mathcal {F}_{G}=\{A:\exists \mathcal {A}\text { such that }(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ , and let $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ be the dual filter of $\operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ . By Corollary 4.6, $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega , G}(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ is generated by $\mathcal {F}_{G}$ .

Lemma 5.2. Let $(\mathcal {A},A)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ , $Y\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ and $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Then there is $h^{*}\supseteq h$ in $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ and $B\subseteq A$ such that $(\mathcal {A},B)\leq (\mathcal {A},A)$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h^{*}}\cap B$ is contained either in Y, or in $\kappa \backslash Y$ .

Proof If there is $h^{\prime }$ extending h such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap Y$ is bounded, then $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A=^{*} \mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap (\kappa \backslash Y)$ and so for all $h^{\prime \prime }\supseteq h^{\prime }$ the set $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime \prime }}\cap A\cap (\kappa \backslash Y)$ is unbounded. Then take $B=(\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap (\kappa \backslash Y))\cup (A\backslash \mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }})$ . Then $B=^{*} A$ and so $B\in \mathcal {U}$ , $(\mathcal {A},B)$ is as desired.

If there is $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap (\kappa \backslash Y)$ is bounded, then $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A=^{*} \mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap Y$ and so for all $h^{\prime \prime }\supseteq h^{\prime }$ the set $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime \prime }}\cap A\cap Y$ is unbounded. Then take $B=(\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap Y)\cup (A\backslash \mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }})$ . Then $B=^{*} A$ and so $B\in \mathcal {U}$ , and the condition $(\mathcal {A},B)$ is as desired.

Suppose, none of the above two cases holds. Thus for every $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ , the sets $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap Y$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap A\cap (\kappa \backslash Y)$ are unbounded. Then each of the sets $B_{0}=(\mathcal {A}^{h}\cap A\cap Y)\cup (A\backslash \mathcal {A}^{h})$ and $B_{1}=(\mathcal {A}^{h}\cap A\cap (\kappa \backslash Y))\cup (A\backslash \mathcal {A}^{h})$ meets every Boolean combination $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}$ for $h^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ on an unbounded set. Thus if $A\backslash \mathcal {A}^{h}\in \mathcal {U}$ , both B and $B^{\prime }$ are as desired. Suppose $A\backslash \mathcal {A}^{h}\notin \mathcal {U}$ . Then $A\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}\in \mathcal {U}$ and so either $A\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}\cap Y$ or $A\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}\cap (\kappa \backslash Y)$ is in the normal measure. We can choose appropriately.

Corollary 5.3. Let $\mathcal {E}=\{Y,\kappa \backslash Y\}$ be a partition. Then the set of $(\mathcal {A},A)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ such that for each $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ there is $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ in $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ with the property that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}$ is either contained in Y, or in $\kappa \backslash Y$ is dense in $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ .

Proof Consider an arbitrary $(\mathcal {A},A)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ . Fix $h_{0}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Then there is $A_{0}\subseteq A$ such that $(\mathcal {A},A_{0})\leq (\mathcal {A},A)$ and there is $h_{1}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ extending $h_{0}$ and $B\subseteq A$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}\cap B$ is contained either in Y, or in $\kappa \backslash Y$ . However, by Lemma 3.3 there is $B_{0}\subseteq B$ such that $(\mathcal {A}\cup \{B_{0}\},B)\leq (\mathcal {A}, B)$ . Then extend $h_{1}$ to $h_{1}^{\prime }=h_{1}\cup \{(B_{0},0)\}$ and note that $h_{1}^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{1})$ , where $\mathcal {A}_{1}=\mathcal {A}\cup \{B_{0}\}$ , and that $\mathcal {A}_{1}^{h_{1}^{\prime }}$ is either contained in Y or in $\kappa \backslash Y$ . Proceed inductively and use the fact that $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ is $\kappa ^{+}$ -closed.

Definition 5.4. Let $\mathcal {F}\subseteq [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ . We say that $\mathcal {F}$ is a $\kappa \text {-P-set}$ if every $\mathcal {H}\subseteq \mathcal {F}$ of cardinality $\leq \kappa $ has a pseudo-intersection in $\mathcal {F}$ .

Lemma 5.5. Let G be a $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter. Then $\mathcal {F}_{G}$ is a $\kappa \mathrm{-P-}{set}$ .

Proof Suppose $\mathcal {F}_{G}$ is not a $\kappa \text {-P-set}$ . Thus there is $p\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}p\Vdash\exists\mathcal{H}\in[\mathcal{F}_{G}]^{\kappa}\text{ s.t. }\forall F\in\mathcal{F}_{G}\exists H\in\mathcal{H} (F\not\subseteq^{*} H).\end{align*} $$

Fix G a $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter such that $p\in G$ . Since $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ is $\kappa ^{+}$ -closed, we can find $\mathcal {H}^{\prime }=\{A_{i}\}_{i\in \kappa }$ in the ground model witnessing the above property. For each $i\in \kappa $ , let $\mathcal {A}_{i}$ be such that $(\mathcal {A}_{i}, A_{i})\in G$ . We can assume that $\tau =\{(\mathcal {A}_{i},A_{i})\}_{i\in \kappa }$ is decreasing and that $(\mathcal {A}_{0},A_{0})\leq p$ . Now, take $q=(\mathcal {A},A)$ in $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ to be a common lower bound of $\tau $ . Then $q\leq p$ and q forces that A is a pseudo-intersection of $\mathcal {H}^{\prime }$ , which is a contradiction.

5.1 Increasing functions and the density filter

In the countable setting a key feature of the Sacks indestructible maximal independent family appearing in [Reference Shelah22] is the fact that the associated density filter is a Q-set. The existence of sufficiently fast growing sets in $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega , \kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ , which we discuss in this section, will be of vital importance for our main result.

If $E\subseteq \kappa $ is an unbounded set and for each $\alpha \in \kappa $ let $s_{E}(\alpha )=\min \{\beta \in E: \beta>\alpha \}$ .

Lemma 5.6. Let $f\in V\cap {^{\kappa }\kappa }$ be a strictly increasing function and let $(\mathcal {A},A)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ . Then there is $A^{*}\subseteq A$ such that $(\mathcal {A},A^{*})\leq (\mathcal {A},A)$ and if $\{a(i)\}_{i<\kappa }$ is the increasing enumeration of $A^{*}$ then $f(a(i))<a(i+1)$ for all i.

Proof Let $C_{f}=\{\xi <\kappa : \forall \zeta <\xi (f(\zeta )<\xi )\}$ . Thus $C_{f}$ is a club and so $C_{f}\in \mathcal {U}$ . Then $E=A\cap C_{f}\in \mathcal {U}$ . Let $\{h_{i}\}_{i<\kappa }$ be an enumeration of the elements of $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that each element occurs unboundedly often. The set $A^{*}$ will be constructed as the union of an increasing sequence $\{B_{\xi }\}_{\xi <\kappa }$ of subsets of A.

Let $B_{0}=\emptyset $ . If $\mathcal {A}^{h_{0}}\cap E\neq \emptyset $ , let $a_{0}=\min \mathcal {A}^{h_{0}}\cap E$ . Otherwise, take $a_{0}=\min \mathcal {A}^{h_{0}}\cap A$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*}B_{1}=\{a_{0}\}\cup (E\cap s_{E}(f(a_{0})))\cup \{s_{E}(f(a_{0}))\}.\end{align*} $$

Suppose we have defined $B_{\xi }$ . If $(\mathcal {A}^{h_{\xi +1}}\cap E)\backslash (B_{\xi }\cup \{\sup B_{\xi }\})\neq \emptyset $ , let $a_{\xi +1}=\min ((\mathcal {A}^{h_{\xi +1}}\cap E)\backslash (B_{\xi }\cup \{\sup B_{\xi }\}))$ . Otherwise, let $a_{\xi +1}=\min \{a\in \mathcal {A}^{h_{\xi +1}}\cap A: a>\sup B_{\xi }\}$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*}B_{\xi+1}= B_{\xi}\cup\{a_{\xi+1}\}\cup (E\cap s_{E}(f(a_{\xi+1})))\cup\{s_{E}(f(a_{\xi}))\}.\end{align*} $$

Now, suppose $\xi $ is a limit and for all $\zeta <\xi $ , the set $B_{\zeta }$ has been defined. Take $B_{\xi }^{*}=\bigcup _{\zeta <\xi } B_{\zeta }$ . If $(\mathcal {A}^{h_{\xi }}\cap E)\backslash (B_{\xi }^{*}\cup \{\sup B_{\xi }^{*}\})\neq \emptyset $ , let $a_{\xi }=\min (\mathcal {A}^{h_{\xi }}\cap E)\backslash (B_{\xi }^{*}\cup \{\sup B_{\xi }^{*}\})\neq \emptyset $ . Otherwise, let $a_{\xi }=\min \{a\in \mathcal {A}^{h_{\xi }}\cap A: a>\sup B^{*}_{\xi }\}$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*}B_{\xi}=B_{\xi}^{*}\cup\{a_{\xi}\}\cup E\cap s_{E}(f(a_{\xi}))\cup\{s_{E}(f(a_{\xi}))\}.\end{align*} $$

Finally, take $A^{*}=\bigcup _{\xi <\kappa } B_{\xi }$ . Then $A^{*}$ meets every Boolean combination $\mathcal {A}^{h}$ of $\mathcal {A}$ on an unbounded set (witnessed by the $a_{\xi }$ ’s), $A^{*}\subseteq A$ and since $\{a_{\xi }\}_{\xi <\kappa }$ is unbounded in $\kappa $ and

$$ \begin{align*}E\cap s_{E}(f(a_{\xi}))\subseteq B_{\xi}\subseteq A^{*} \end{align*} $$

for each $\xi $ , we also have that $E\subseteq A^{*}$ . Let $b<a$ be elements of $A^{*}$ . If $a\in E$ , then by definition of $C_{f}$ we have that $f(b)<a$ . If $a\notin E$ and $a=a_{\xi +1}$ for some $\xi $ , then

$$ \begin{align*}a_{\xi} < f(a_{\xi})< s_{E}(f(a_{\xi}))< a_{\xi+1}\end{align*} $$

by construction. If $\xi $ is a limit, $a=a_{\xi }$ and $f(a_{\zeta })<s_{E}(f(a_{\zeta }))<a_{\xi }$ for each $\zeta <\xi $ again by construction. Since $b=a_{\zeta }$ for some $\zeta <\xi $ , $f(b)<a$ .

The following corollary will play an important role in the main result of the paper.

Corollary 5.7. Let G be $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic, $f\in V\cap {^{\kappa }\kappa }$ be strictly increasing. Then there is $A\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega , \kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ such that if $\{a(i)\}_{i\in \kappa }$ is the increasing enumeration of A then $f(a(i))<a(i+1)$ for all $i \in \kappa $ .

Proof Since $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega , \kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ is generated by $\mathcal {F}_{G}$ (the set of second coordinated of elements of the generic filter G) we may use the previous lemma and get the result.

Indeed, this is a standard density argument: Let $D_{f}$ be the set of all $(\mathcal {A},A)\in \mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ such that if $\{a(i)\}_{i<\kappa }$ is the enumeration function of A then $f(a(i))< a(i+1)$ for all $i<\kappa $ . By Lemma 5.6 the set $D_{f}$ is dense. Thus, $G\cap D_{f}\neq \emptyset $ and so there is $(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\cap D_{f}$ . But, by definition of the set $\mathcal {F}_{G}$ , we have that $A\in \mathcal {F}_{G}$ (see also Remark 5.1), and by the same remark $A\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ . Since $(\mathcal {A}, A)\in D_{f}$ , we obtain that $f(a(i))<a(i+1)$ .

6 Dense maximality

The notion of densely maximal independent families on $\omega $ appears for the first time in [Reference Goldstern and Shelah16]. Moreover, the maximal independent family constructed in [Reference Shelah22] which becomes a witness to $\mathfrak {i}=\aleph _{1}$ in the model of [Reference Shelah22, Theorem 3.1] is densely maximal. A similar notion will play a vital role for our considerations:

Definition 6.1. An independent family $\mathcal {A}$ is said to be densely maximal if for every $X\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }\backslash \mathcal {A}$ and every $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ there is $h^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ extending h such that either $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap X=\emptyset $ or $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap (\kappa \backslash X)=\emptyset $ .

The following characterization of dense maximality on $\omega $ appears implicitly in the proof of [Reference Shelah22, Theorem 3.1]. This characterization will be the main tool in showing that a specially designed normal measure supported $\kappa $ -maximal independent family preserves its maximality after forcing with a large product of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing.

Lemma 6.2. Let $\mathcal {A}$ be an independent family. Then $\mathcal {A}$ is densely maximal if and only if

$(\ast )\ \forall h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}) \forall X\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ either there is $B\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X\subseteq B$ , or there is $h^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X$ .

Proof Suppose $\mathcal {A}$ satisfies property $(\ast )$ . Let $X\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ , $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ and consider $Y=X\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}$ . Apply property $(*)$ . If there is $B\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X\subseteq B$ , then $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Then there is $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap (\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X)=\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\backslash X=\emptyset $ . If there is $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X$ , then $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap X=\emptyset $ . Thus $\mathcal {A}$ is densely maximal.

Now suppose $\mathcal {A}$ is densely maximal. Fix $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $X\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ . We will show that $\mathcal {A}$ satisfies property $(\ast )$ . Suppose, there is no $B\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X\subseteq B$ . Thus in particular $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X\notin \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ and so there is $h^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that for all $h^{\prime \prime }\supseteq h^{\prime }$ the set $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime \prime }}\cap (\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X)\neq \emptyset $ . If h and $h^{\prime }$ are incompatible as conditions in $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ , then $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap (\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X)=\emptyset $ , which is a contradiction. Therefore h and $h^{\prime }$ are compatible. Without loss of generality, $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ (otherwise pass to a common extension of h and $h^{\prime }$ ). Thus h has an extension, namely $h^{\prime }$ , such that for all $h^{\prime \prime }\supseteq h^{\prime }$ the set $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime \prime }}\backslash X$ is non-empty. Apply the fact that $\mathcal {A}$ is densely maximal to $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}$ and X. Thus, there is $h^{\prime \prime }\supseteq h^{\prime }$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime \prime }}\cap X=\emptyset $ . Therefore $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime \prime }}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\backslash X\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X$ , which completes the proof of property $(\ast )$ .

Lemma 6.3. Let G be $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic. Then in $V_{0}=V[G]$ the family $\mathcal {A}_{G}:=\bigcup \{\mathcal {A}:\exists A(\mathcal {A},A)\in G\}$ is densely maximal.

Proof It is sufficient to show that $\mathcal {A}_{G}$ satisfies property $(\ast )$ from Lemma 6.2. Thus, fix h and X as in $(\ast )$ . Suppose there is no $B\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ such that $\mathcal {A}_{G}^{h}\backslash X\subseteq B$ . Then, in particular $\mathcal {A}_{G}^{h}\backslash X\notin \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ and so there is $h_{0}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ such that for all $h_{1}\supseteq h_{0}$ the set $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}\cap (\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X)\neq \emptyset $ (by definition of the density ideal). Consider the partition

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{E}=\{\mathcal{A}^{h}\backslash X, \kappa\backslash (\mathcal{A}^{h}\backslash X)\}\end{align*} $$

and the set $\mathcal {A}^{h_{0}}$ . By Corollary 5.3 there is $h_{1}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A}_{G})$ extending $h_{0}$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}$ is contained in one element of $\mathcal {E}$ . However, if $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}\subseteq \kappa \backslash (\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X)$ , then $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}\cap (\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X)=\emptyset $ , which is a contradiction to the choice of $h_{0}$ . Thus $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X$ and so $\mathcal {A}^{h_{1}}\cap X=\emptyset $ .

7 Preprocessed conditions and outer hulls

In this section we introduce the notions of preprocessed conditions and outer hulls for the special case of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing and its products. Note that both of these notions play a key role in Shelah’s proof of $\mathfrak {i}<\mathfrak {u}$ from [Reference Shelah22]: preprocessed conditions appear in [Reference Shelah22, Claim 1.11], while outer hulls appear in proof of [Reference Shelah22, Theorem 3.1] (page 440 of the article). Throughout this section we work under the assumption of GCH (at least $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ and $2^{<\kappa }=\kappa $ ) and $\kappa $ measurable. Thus in particular $\kappa $ is strongly inaccessible. We will work with the generalization of Sacks forcing and its products to the uncountable, both of which were first studied by Kanamori [Reference Kanamori19].

Recall that $p \subseteq 2^{< \kappa }$ is a tree if it is closed under initial segments. That is, $u \in p$ and $v \subseteq u$ imply $v \in p$ . Whenever p is a tree, $t,r\in p$ , and t is a proper initial segment or equal to r, we write $t\unlhd r$ and $r\unrhd t$ . A node $u\in p$ splits in p if both $u^{\frown } 0$ and $u^{\frown } 1$ belong to p. Given a tree p, we denote by $\text {split}(p)$ the set of splitting nodes of p.

Definition 7.1. For a strongly inaccessible $\kappa $ , the $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing, denoted $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ , is the poset consisting of sub-trees p of $2^{<\kappa }$ such that:

  1. (1) for each $u \in p$ there is $t \in p$ such that $u\unlhd t$ and t splits in p (t is said to be a splitting extension of u);

  2. (2) for any $\alpha < \kappa $ , if $(u_{\beta }: \beta < \alpha )$ is a sequence of nodes in p such that $\beta < \gamma < \alpha \to u_{\beta } \subseteq u_{\gamma }$ , then $\bigcup \{u_{\beta }: \beta < \alpha \} \in p$ ;

  3. (3) if $\delta < \kappa $ is a limit ordinal, $u \in 2^{\delta }$ , and for arbitrarily large $\beta < \delta $ the node $u \restriction \beta $ splits in p, then u splits in p.

The extension relation on $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ is defined by $p \leq q$ if and only if $p \subseteq q$ .

As in the countable case we define the $\operatorname {\mathrm {stem}}(p)$ where p is a condition in $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ as the unique splitting node that is comparable with all elements in p. By recursion on $\kappa $ define:

Definition 7.2 (The $\alpha $ -th splitting level of p).

Given $p \in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ let

  • $\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{0} (p) = \operatorname {\mathrm {stem}}(p)$ ,

  • $\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha +1}(p) = \{ \operatorname {\mathrm {stem}}(p_{u^{\frown } i}) : u \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(p)$ and $i \in 2 \}$ ,

  • for $\delta <\kappa $ is a limit ordinal, $\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\delta }(p)= \{s \in p: s \text { is a limit of nodes in } \bigcup _{\alpha < \delta } \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(p)\} $ .

We refer to $\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(p)$ as the $\alpha $ -th splitting level of p. Moreover for $t\in \text {split}(p)$ , let $\operatorname {\mathrm {sl}}(t,p)= \alpha $ where $t\in \text {split}_{\alpha }(p)$ .

Using this splitting levels we define the fusion orderings $\leq _{\alpha }$ on $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ : Given q and p in $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ let $q \leq _{\alpha } p$ if and only if $q \leq p$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(p)= \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q)$ .

Definition 7.3. A fusion sequence $(p_{\alpha }: \alpha < \kappa ) \subseteq \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ is sequence of conditions in $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ such that $p_{\alpha +1} \leq _{\alpha } p_{\alpha }$ for all $\alpha <\kappa $ and whenever $\delta < \kappa $ is a limit, then $p_{\delta } \leq _{\alpha } p_{\alpha }$ for all $\alpha < \delta $ .

For any regular uncountable cardinal $\lambda $ we denote by $\mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ the $\kappa $ -support product of $\lambda $ many copies of $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ . Moreover:

Definition 7.4 (Product fusion, Definition 1.7 in [Reference Kanamori19]).

  • If $(p_{\alpha }: \alpha < \beta ) \subseteq \mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ , we define a condition $p = \bigwedge _{\alpha < \beta } p_{\alpha }$ with $\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p) = \bigcup _{\alpha < \beta } \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p_{\alpha })$ and for every $\gamma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p)$ , $p(\gamma )= \bigcap \{ p_{\alpha }(\gamma ): \gamma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p_{\alpha })\}$ . Note that in the case $p \restriction \gamma \notin \mathbb {S}^{\gamma }_{\kappa }$ for $\gamma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p)$ or $\lvert \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p) \lvert> \kappa $ then p is left undefined.

  • If $p,q \in \mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ , $\alpha < \kappa $ and $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(q)$ with $\lvert F \lvert \leq \kappa $ , we say $p \leq _{F, \alpha } q$ if and only if $p \leq q$ and for every $\beta \in F$ , $p(\beta ) \leq _{\alpha } q(\beta )$ .

Lemma 7.5 (Generalized fusion [Reference Kanamori19]).

Suppose $(p_{\alpha } : \alpha < \kappa )\subseteq \mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ and $ F_{\alpha } \subseteq \lambda $ have the following properties:

  1. (1) $p_{\alpha +1} \leq _{F_{\alpha },\alpha } p_{\alpha }$ and $p_{\delta } = \bigwedge _{\alpha < \delta } p_{\alpha }$ when $\delta $ is a limit ordinal $< \!\kappa $ .

  2. (2) $\lvert F_{\alpha } \lvert < \kappa $ , $F_{\alpha } \subseteq F_{\alpha +1}$ , $F_{\delta } = \bigcup _{\alpha < \delta } F_{\alpha }$ for limit $\delta < \kappa $ and $\bigcup _{\alpha < \kappa } F_{\alpha } = \bigcup _{\alpha < \kappa } \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p_{\alpha })$ .

Then $p = \bigwedge _{\alpha < \kappa } p_{\alpha } \in \mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ and we refer to $(p_{\alpha }, F_{\alpha } : \alpha < \kappa )$ as a generalized fusion sequence.

In the following, we fix some notation:

Definition 7.6.

  • Given a condition $p \in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ , $\alpha < \kappa $ and $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ so that $\lvert F \lvert < \kappa $ let $\Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)=\prod _{i\in F}\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(p(i))$ . That is

    $$ \begin{align*}\Lambda^{F}_{\alpha}(p) = \{ \bar{\sigma} = (\sigma_{i})_{i \in F} : \sigma_{i} \in \operatorname{\mathrm{split}}_{\alpha}(p(i))\}.\end{align*} $$
  • For all $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ let $p_{\bar {\sigma }}\leq p$ be defined as follows: $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)=\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p_{\bar {\sigma }})$ and

    $$ \begin{align*}p_{\bar{\sigma}}(i) = \begin{cases} (p(i))_{ \sigma_{i}}, & \text{if } i \in F, \\ p(i), & \text{otherwise. } \end{cases} \end{align*} $$
  • Given $h \in {^{F}2}$ and $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ , let $p^{h}_{\bar {\sigma }}$ be defined as follows: $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p^{h}_{\bar {\sigma }})=\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ and

    $$ \begin{align*}p^{h}_{\bar{\sigma}}(i) = \begin{cases} (p(i))_{ \sigma_{i}^{\smallfrown} h(i)}, & \text{if } i \in F, \\ p(i), & \text{otherwise. } \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

7.1 Preprocessed conditions

The following notion of begin preprocessed for a condition can be seen for example in [Reference Shelah22, Lemma 1.11]. Given a name for a real $\tau $ and a condition p in an appropriate partial order, in particular the poset $Q_{\mathcal {I}}$ from [Reference Shelah22], Sacks forcing, or Miller partition forcing (see for definition for example [Reference Guzmán, Hrŭsák and Téllez17]), the notion provides a sufficiently good ground model approximation of $\tau $ realized by a condition q stronger than p.

We adapt the notion in the context of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing and its products.

Definition 7.7.

  1. (1) Let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ -name for a subset of $\kappa $ . We say that $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ is preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ if for all $\alpha \in \kappa $ and all $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(p)$ there is $x_{t}\in {^{\alpha } 2}$ such that $p_{t}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha =\check {x}_{t}$ .

  2. (2)
    1. (a) Let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ name for a subset of $\kappa $ , $p \in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ and $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ with $\lvert F \lvert < \kappa $ . We say that $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ is preprocessed for the pair $(F,\dot {X})$ if for all $\alpha <\kappa $ and all $\bar {\sigma }\in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F}(p)$ there are $F^{\prime } \supseteq F$ , such that $F^{\prime } \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p)$ and $\lvert F^{\prime }\lvert < \kappa $ , $\bar {\tau }_{\bar {\sigma }} \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F^{\prime }}(p)$ , and $x_{\bar {\sigma }}\in {^{\alpha } 2}$ such that $\bar {\sigma } \sqsubseteq \bar {\tau }_{\bar {\sigma }}$ and $p_{\bar {\tau }_{\bar {\sigma }}}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha =\check {x}_{\bar {\sigma }}$ .Footnote 7

    2. (b) We say that a condition $p \in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ is preprocessed for the name $\dot {X}$ if for all $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p)$ such that $\lvert F \lvert < \kappa $ , p is preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, F)$ .

Remark 7.8.

  1. (1) Note that if $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ is preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ , then for each $\alpha \in \kappa $ there is $Y_{\alpha }\subseteq {^{\alpha } 2}$ such that $p\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha \in \check {Y}_{\alpha }$ . Indeed, take $Y_{\alpha } =\bigcup \{x_{t}:t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(p)\}$ where $x_{t}$ is defined as in the definition above.

  2. (2) Similarly, if $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ is preprocessed for $(F,\dot {X})$ (F like above), then for each $\alpha <\kappa $ there is $Y_{\alpha }\subseteq {^{\alpha } 2}$ such that $p\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha \in \check {Y}_{\alpha }$ . Just take $Y_{\alpha } = \bigcup \{ x_{\bar {\sigma }}:\bar {\sigma }\in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p) \}$ where $x_{\bar {\sigma }}$ is defined as above.

Lemma 7.9.

  1. (1) Let $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ and let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ -name for a subset of $\kappa $ . Then there is $q\leq p$ such that q is preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ .

  2. (2) Let $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ and let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ -name for a subset of $\kappa $ . Then, for all $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ with $\lvert F\lvert < \kappa $ and $\gamma <\kappa $ there is $q\leq _{F, \gamma } p$ such that q is preprocessed for $(F,\dot {X})$ .

Proof $(1)$ We build a fusion sequence $\langle q_{\alpha }:\alpha <\kappa \rangle $ below p such that for all $\alpha>0$ and all $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha })$ there is $x_{t}\in {^{\alpha } 2}$ such that $(q_{\alpha })_{t}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha =\check {x}_{t}$ . Start with $q_{0}=p$ . Consider $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{0}(p)$ , i.e., $t=\operatorname {\mathrm {stem}}(p)$ . For each $i\in \{0,1\}$ there is $w_{t,i}\leq p_{t^{\smallfrown } i}$ and $x(t,i)\in \{0,1\}$ such that $w_{t,i}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}(0)=\check {x}(t,i)$ . Note that $\text {stem}(w_{t,i})\unrhd \operatorname {\mathrm {stem}}(p_{t^{\smallfrown } i})\unrhd t^{\smallfrown } i$ . Define $q_{1}= w^{0}_{t,0}\cup w^{0}_{t,1}$ . Then $q_{1}\leq _{0} q_{0}$ and for all $s\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{1}(q_{1})$ there is $x_{s}\in {^{1}2}$ such that $(q_{1})_{s}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright 1=\check {x}_{s}$ . Indeed, if $s\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{1}(q_{1})$ then $s\unrhd t^{\smallfrown } i$ for $i\in \{0,1\}$ and so $(q_{1})_{s}=w_{t,i}$ . Thus $(q_{1})_{s}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright 1= x_{s}$ where $x_{s}=(0,x(s,i))$ .

Now, suppose $q_{\alpha }$ has been defined and $\forall t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha })$ there is $x_{t}\in {^{\alpha } 2}$ such that $(q_{\alpha })_{t}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha =\check {x}_{t}$ . For each $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha })$ and each $i\in \{0,1\}$ find $w_{t,i}\leq (q_{\alpha })_{t^{\smallfrown } i}$ and $x(t,i)\in \{0,1\}$ such that $w^{\alpha }_{t,i}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}(\alpha )=\check {x}(t,i)$ . Then, take $q_{\alpha +1}=\bigcup \{w_{t,i}: t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha }), i\in \{0,1\}\}$ . Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha +1})=\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha })$ and so $q_{\alpha +1}\leq _{\alpha } q_{\alpha }$ . Moreover, for all $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha +1}(q_{\alpha +1})$ there is $x_{t}\in {^{\alpha +1} 2}$ such that $(q_{\alpha +1})_{t}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha +1 =\check {x}_{t}$ . Indeed. Fix $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha +1}(q_{\alpha +1})$ . Thus $r^{\smallfrown } i\unlhd t$ for some $r\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha +1})=\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha })$ for some $i\in \{0,1\}$ . By Inductive Hypothesis $(q_{\alpha })_{r}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha =\check {x}_{r}$ for some $x_{r}\in {^{\alpha } 2}$ . However $t\unrhd r^{\smallfrown } i$ and so $(q_{\alpha +1})_{t}=w_{r,i}\leq (q_{\alpha })_{r^{\smallfrown } i}\leq (q_{\alpha })_{r}$ . Thus, $(q_{\alpha +1})_{t}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha =\check {x}_{r}\text { and }\chi _{\dot {X}}(\alpha )=\check {x}(r,i)$ . That is $(q_{\alpha +1})_{t}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha +1 =\check {x}_{t}$ where $x_{t}=x_{r}\cup \{(\alpha , x(r,i))\}$ .

It remains to consider the limit case. Suppose $\langle q_{\beta }:\beta <\alpha \rangle $ have been defined and for all $\beta <\alpha $ and all $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\beta }(q_{\beta })$ there is $x_{t}\in {^{\beta } 2}$ such that $(q_{\beta })_{t}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \beta =\check {x}_{t}$ . Then take $q_{\alpha }=\land _{\beta <\alpha } q_{\beta }$ . Note that if $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha })$ then there is $\{\eta _{\xi }:\xi <\alpha \}$ unbounded in $\alpha $ such that $t\upharpoonright \eta _{\xi }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\xi }(q_{\xi })$ and so by inductive hypothesis for some $x_{t\upharpoonright \eta _{\xi }}\in {^{\xi } 2}$ we have $(q_{\xi })_{t\upharpoonright \eta _{\xi }}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \xi =\check {x}_{t\upharpoonright \eta _{\xi }}$ . Then for $x_{t}=\bigcup \{x_{t\upharpoonright \eta _{\xi }}:\xi <\alpha \}$ we have $(q_{\alpha })_{t}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha =\check {x}_{t}$ .

$(2)$ The argument for the product runs similarly as the above case: Let $p \in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ , $\gamma < \kappa $ and $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ so that $\lvert F \lvert < \kappa $ . We shall define a fusion sequence $\langle q_{\alpha }, F_{\alpha }: \alpha <\kappa \rangle \subseteq \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ below p, ordinals $(\eta _{\alpha }: \alpha < \kappa )$ and bijections $g_{\alpha }: F_{\alpha } \to \eta _{\alpha }$ such that for all $\alpha <\kappa $ :

  1. (1) $q_{\alpha +1} \leq _{F_{\alpha }, \gamma + \alpha } q_{\alpha }$ .

  2. (2) $\eta _{\alpha } \geq \alpha $ .

  3. (3) For all $\alpha < \alpha ^{\prime }<\kappa $ , $g_{\alpha } \subseteq g_{\alpha ^{\prime }}$ and for limit ordinals $\delta < \kappa g_{\delta } = \bigcup _{\alpha < \delta } g_{\alpha }$ .

  4. (4) For all ${\bar {\sigma }}\in \Lambda _{\gamma + \alpha }^{F_{\alpha }}(q_{\alpha }) $ there is $x_{\bar {\sigma }}\in {^{\alpha } 2}$ such that $(q_{\alpha +1})_{\bar {\sigma }}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha =\check {x}_{\bar {\sigma }}$ .

Since similar arguments will be used in the upcoming results we give the proof in full detail. Start with $q_{0} = p$ and $F_{0}= F$ , in order to arrange that $q_{\alpha +1} \leq _{F_{\alpha }, \gamma + \alpha } q_{\alpha }$ start the following construction at some indecomposable ordinal $\alpha>\gamma $ (otherwise for all ordinals $\beta < \alpha $ , $\beta +\alpha = \alpha $ and so, at $\alpha $ we would just get $q_{\alpha +1} \leq _{F_{\alpha },\alpha } q_{\alpha }$ ) and letting $q_{\beta } = p$ for all $\beta <\alpha $ . At limit stages $\delta <\kappa $ the construction of $q_{\delta }$ and $F_{\delta }$ is determined by the conditions in Definition 7.4. Let $\eta _{\delta } = \sup _{\alpha <\delta } \eta _{\alpha }$ and $g_{\delta }$ as above.

Finally for the successor case, suppose $q_{\alpha }$ , $\eta _{\alpha }$ , $g_{\alpha }$ , and $F_{\alpha }$ have been defined. Fix an enumeration $\{\gamma _{l}=(\bar {\sigma }_{l}, h_{l}): l< \rho \}$ of all pairs of the form $(\bar {\sigma }, h)$ such that $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda _{\sigma }^{F_{\alpha }}(q_{\alpha })$ and $h \in {^{F_{\alpha }}2}$ . Note that the ordinals $\rho $ is $<\kappa $ .

Inductively, we will construct a sequence $\{r^{\alpha }_{l}:l<\rho \}$ of conditions below $q_{\alpha }$ satisfying:

  1. (1) $r^{\alpha }_{0} = q_{\alpha }$ ,

  2. (2) $r^{\alpha }_{l+1} \leq _{F_{\alpha },\gamma +\alpha } r^{\alpha }_{l}$ ,

  3. (3) $(r^{\alpha }_{l+1})_{\bar {\sigma }_{l}}^{h_{l}}$ forces a value $\check {x}(\alpha ,l)$ for $\chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha $ ,

  4. (4) For l limit ordinal $r^{\alpha }_{l} = \bigwedge _{k< l} r^{\alpha }_{k}$ .

It is enough to explain how the successor step is built: Suppose that we have constructed $r^{\alpha }_{l}$ satisfying the conditions above and consider the pair $\gamma _{l} =(\bar {\sigma }, h)$ , then find a condition $w_{l} \leq (r_{l})_{\bar {\sigma }}^{h}$ forcing a value $x(\bar {\sigma },l)$ for $\chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright \alpha $ . Note that $w_{l}$ is clearly not a condition that satisfies (2), so we build $r^{\alpha }_{l+1}$ as follows: $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(r^{\alpha }_{l+1})=\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(w_{l})$ and

$$ \begin{align*}& r^{\alpha}_{l+1}(i)\\ &\quad = \begin{cases} (w_{l}(i)) \cup \{ (q_{\alpha}(i))_{\tau {}^{\frown} j}: \tau \in \operatorname{\mathrm{split}}_{\alpha} (r_{l}(i)) \setminus \sigma_{i} \text{ or } j= 1-h(i) \}, & \text{if } i \in F_{\alpha}, \\ w_{l}(i), & \text{otherwise. } \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

Note that this is now a condition satisfying the properties above. Put $q_{\alpha +1}= \bigwedge _{l< \rho } r^{\alpha }_{l} F_{\alpha +1}=F_{\alpha }\cup \{\min (\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(q_{\alpha +1})\backslash F_{\alpha })\}$ , $\eta _{\alpha +1} = \eta _{\alpha } +1$ , and $g_{\alpha +1} = g_{\alpha } \cup \{(\min (\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(q_{\alpha +1})\backslash F_{\alpha }), \eta _{\alpha })\}$ .

In order to finish the proof, we check that the condition q is indeed preprocessed for $(F, \dot {X})$ . Fix $\alpha < \kappa $ and $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F}(q)$ . First, extend $\bar {\sigma }$ to a sequence $\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }= \bar {\sigma }^{\frown } \bar {\rho }_{0}$ in $\Lambda _{\alpha }^{F_{\alpha }}(q)$ by adding a fix tail $\bar {\rho }_{0}$ of splitting nodes in $q(i)$ at level $\alpha $ for each $i \in F_{\alpha } \backslash F$ .

Since $q \leq _{\alpha , F_{\alpha }} q_{\alpha }$ we get that $\Lambda _{\alpha }^{F_{\alpha }}(q)= \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F_{\alpha }}(q_{\alpha })$ and so $\bar {\sigma }^{\prime } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F_{\alpha }}(q_{\alpha })$ and we can use the fusion properties to get that there is an $x_{\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }} \in {^{\alpha } 2}$ such that $(q_{\alpha +1})_{\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }} \Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright (\alpha ) = \check {x}_{\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }}$ , so we finally use that the condition $q_{\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }} \leq (q_{\alpha +1})_{\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }}$ to get that $(q)_{\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }} \Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}}\upharpoonright (\alpha ) = \check {x}_{\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }}$ as we wanted.

Corollary 7.10. Let $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ and let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ -name for a subset of $\kappa $ , then we can find $q \leq p$ such that q is preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ .

Proof Recall first that there are $\kappa $ -many sets $G \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(p)$ so that $\lvert G \lvert < \kappa $ , so let $(G_{\beta }: \beta <\kappa )$ be an enumeration of them. We can use build a fusion sequence $(q_{\alpha }, F_{\alpha })$ below p such that for all $\alpha < \kappa $ , $q_{\alpha + 1}$ is preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, G_{\alpha })$ .

Start with $q_{0} = p$ and $F_{0} = G_{0}$ . The limit step is built as usual and it is left to explain how the successor case is constructed: Suppose we have already defined $q_{\alpha }$ and $F_{\alpha }$ , then we use the lemma above for $\dot {X}$ , $q_{\alpha }$ , and $F_{\alpha }$ to get a condition $r \leq _{\alpha , F_{\alpha }} q_{\alpha }$ that is preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, G_{\alpha })$ . Define then $q_{\alpha +1} =r$ and $F_{\alpha +1} = F_{\alpha } \cup G_{\alpha }$ .

We claim that the fusion q of the sequence defined above is preprocessed for all $G_{\alpha }$ ’s: Indeed, if $\alpha $ is fixed we know that $q_{\alpha +1}$ is preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, G_{\alpha })$ , then it is enough to notice that since $q \leq _{\alpha +1, F_{\alpha +1}} q_{\alpha +1}$ , then q is also preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, G_{\alpha })$ .

7.2 Outer hull

Below, we introduce the notion of an outer hull, making explicit some well-known techniques. In the consistency proof of $\mathfrak {i}<\mathfrak {u}$ from [Reference Shelah22], outer hulls appear on page 440. Other more recent applications of the notion can be found for example in [Reference Guzmán, Hrŭsák and Téllez17].

Definition 7.11.

  • Let $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ and let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ -name for a subset of $\kappa $ . For each $t\in \text {split}_{\alpha }(p)$ , we refer to the set $Y_{t}=\{\beta \in \kappa : p_{t}\not \Vdash \check {\beta }\notin \dot {X}\}$ , as the outer hull of $\dot {X}$ below $p_{t}$ . Moreover, if $q_{t,\beta }\leq p_{t}$ and $q_{t,\beta }\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ , we say that $q_{t,\beta }$ is a witness for $\beta \in Y_{t}$ .

  • Let $p\in \mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ and let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ -name for a subset of $\kappa $ . For all $\alpha < \kappa $ , $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ such that $\lvert F \lvert < \kappa $ and $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ we refer to the set $Y_{\bar {\sigma }}=\{\beta \in \kappa : p_{\bar {\sigma }}\not \Vdash \check {\beta }\notin \dot {X}\}$ , as the outer hull of $\dot {X}$ below $p_{\bar {\sigma }}$ . Moreover, if $q_{\bar {\sigma },\beta }\leq p_{\bar {\sigma }}$ and $q_{\bar {\sigma },\beta }\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ , we say that $q_{\bar {\sigma },\beta }$ is a witness for $\beta \in Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ .

Remark 7.12. Let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ -name for a subset of $\kappa $ . Suppose $Y_{t}$ is the outer hull of $\dot {X}$ below $p_{t}$ . If $p_{t}\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ , then $p_{t}$ is a witness to $\beta \in Y_{t}$ and so $p_{t}\Vdash \dot {X}\subseteq \check {Y}_{t}$ . Analogously for $\mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ and $Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ .

We proceed with the following lemma.

Lemma 7.13.

  1. (1) Let $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ be preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ and for each $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)$ let $Y_{t}$ be the outer hull of $\dot {X}$ below $p_{t}$ . Then for each $\alpha < \kappa $ , $t\in \text {split}_{\alpha }(p)$ and $\beta \in Y_{t}$ there is an $r(t,\beta )\in p$ such that t is an initial segment of $r(t,\beta )$ and $p_{r(t,\beta )}\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ . Moreover, for each $t\in \text {split}(p)$ and each $\beta \in Y_{t}$ there is $r=r(t,\beta )\in \text {split}_{\beta }(p)$ such that $p_{r}\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ .

  2. (2) Let $p\in \mathbb {S}^{\lambda }_{\kappa }$ be preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, F)$ (where $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ and $\lvert F\lvert < \kappa $ ) and for each $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ let $Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ be the outer hull of $\dot {X}$ below $p_{\bar {\sigma }}$ . Then for each $\alpha < \kappa $ , $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ , $\beta \in Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ , and $i \in F$ there are $F^{\prime } \supseteq F$ , $\lvert F^{\prime } \lvert <\kappa $ , and $\bar {\tau }^{\prime } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F^{\prime }}(p)$ such that if $\bar {\tau }^{\prime }=(r_{i}(\bar {\sigma }, \beta ) : i \in F^{\prime })$ then $r_{i}(\bar {\sigma },\beta )\in p(i)$ such that $\sigma _{i}$ is an initial segment of $r_{i}(\bar {\sigma },\beta )$ for all $i \in F$ and $p_{\bar {\tau }^{\prime }}\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ . Moreover, for each $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ , $\beta \in Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ , and $i \in F$ there are $F^{\prime } \supseteq F$ , $\lvert F^{\prime } \lvert <\kappa $ , and $\bar {\tau }^{\prime } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F^{\prime }}(p)$ such that if $\bar {\tau }=(r_{i}(\bar {\sigma }, \beta ) : i \in F^{\prime })$ where $r_{i}=r_{i}(\bar {\sigma },\beta )\in \text {split}_{\beta }(p)(i)$ for all $i\in F$ , then $p_{\bar {\tau }^{\prime }}\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ .

Proof $(1)$ Fix $\alpha ,t$ and $\beta \in Y_{t}$ . Then there is $q \leq p_{t}$ such that $q\Vdash \beta \in \dot {X}$ . Take any $r= r(t, \beta )\in \text {split}_{\beta }(q)$ . Note that $t\unlhd r$ and there is $\beta ^{\prime }\geq \beta $ such that $r\in \text {split}_{\beta ^{\prime }}(p)$ . On the other hand, because p is preprocessed we can use Lemma 7.9 to find $x_{r} \subseteq {^{\alpha ^{\prime }} 2}$ such that $p_{r}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}} \upharpoonright \beta ^{\prime } = \check {x}_{r}$ . Since $q_{r}\leq p_{r}$ we must have that $ \check {x}_{t}(\beta )=1$ . Thus $p_{r}\Vdash \beta \in \dot {X}$ .

Moreover, if $r^{*}\unlhd r$ and $r^{*}\in \text {split}_{\beta +1}(p)$ then already $p_{r^{*}}\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ . Indeed, since p is preprocessed there is an $x_{r^{*}} \in {^{\beta } 2}$ so that $p_{r^{*}} \Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}} \upharpoonright _{\beta +1} \in \check {x}_{r^{*}}$ , thus $p_{r}$ forces a value for $\chi _{\dot {X}}(\beta )$ which has to be 1 because $q_{r} \leq q,p_{r}$ and so $p_{r} \Vdash \check {\beta } \in \dot {X}$ . In particular, if $\beta \leq \operatorname {\mathrm {sl}}(t,p)$ then in fact $p_{t}\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}$ .

$(2)$ In the same way, fix now $\alpha , F$ and $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F}(p)$ . Then there is $q \leq p_{\bar {\sigma }}$ such that $q\Vdash \beta \in \dot {X}$ . For all $i \in F$ take any $r_{i}= r_{i}(\bar {\sigma }, \beta )\in \text {split}_{\beta }(q(i))$ . Note that $\sigma _{i}\unlhd r_{i}$ for all $i \in F$ . We can find $\beta ^{\prime }\geq \beta $ such that $r_{i} \in \text {split}_{\beta ^{\prime }}(p(i))$ uniformly for all $i \in F$ . Hence if $\bar {\tau }=(r_{i}(\bar {\sigma }, \beta ) : i \in F)$ , by Lemma 7.9 there are $F^{\prime } \supseteq F$ , $\bar {\tau }^{\prime } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F^{\prime }}(p)$ , and $x_{\bar {\tau }^{\prime }} \in {^{\beta ^{\prime }} 2}$ such that $p_{\bar {\tau }^{\prime }}\Vdash \chi _{\dot {X}} \upharpoonright \beta ^{\prime } = \check {x}_{\bar {\tau }}$ . Let $y= \chi _{\dot {X}} \upharpoonright \beta ^{\prime }$ . Since $q_{\bar {\tau }^{\prime }}\leq p_{\bar {\tau }^{\prime }}$ we must have that $ y(\beta )=1$ . Thus $p_{\bar {\tau }^{\prime }}\Vdash \beta \in \dot {X}$ . The argument for the moreover part is the same as for part (1).

Definition 7.14. For $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ and $F\in [\text {supp}(p)]^{<\kappa }$ , let $\Lambda (F)=\bigcup _{\alpha <\kappa }\Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }$ . For $\bar {\sigma }$ and $\bar {\tau }$ in $\Lambda (F)$ we say that $\bar {\tau }\unlhd \bar {\sigma }$ if and only if for each $i\in F(\bar {\tau }(i)\unlhd \bar {\sigma }(i))$ .

Corollary 7.15.

  1. (1) Let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ -name for an infinite subset of $\kappa $ . If $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ is preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ , $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)$ , and $Y_{t}$ is the outer hull of $\dot {X}$ below $p_{t}$ , then

    $$ \begin{align*} \hspace{-2pc} Y_{t}=\{\beta< \kappa:\exists r\in \text{split}(p)\text{ such that } t\unlhd r \text{ and }p_{r}\Vdash\check{\beta}\in\dot{X}\}.\end{align*} $$
  2. (2) Let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ -name for an infinite subset of $\kappa $ . If $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ is preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, F\in [\text {supp}(p)]^{<\kappa })$ and $\bar {\sigma }\in \Lambda (F)$ , then

    $$ \begin{align*}\hspace{-2.6pc}Y_{\bar{\sigma}}=\{\beta\in\kappa:\exists \bar{\tau}\in \Lambda(F^{\prime}) \text{ for } F^{\prime} \supseteq F, \lvert F^{\prime}\lvert <\kappa \text{ such that } \bar{\sigma}\sqsubseteq \bar{\tau} \text{ and }p_{\bar{\tau}}\Vdash\check{\beta}\in\dot{X}\}.\end{align*} $$

8 $\kappa $ -Sacks indestructibility

In this section we set out to obtain our main result, namely the relative consistency of $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )<2^{\kappa }$ . For this we start with a measurable cardinal $\kappa $ and a normal measure $\mathcal {U}$ on $\kappa $ . Using the forcing notion $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ we adjoin a $\mathcal {U}$ -supported $\kappa $ -maximal independent family, which by Lemma 6.3 is densely maximal. A key feature of our proof is Lemma 6.2 which gives an equivalent characterisation of dense maximality via the property $(\ast )$ of the same lemma. In fact, to show that $\mathcal {A}=\mathcal {A}_{G}$ for a $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter G remains maximal after forcing with a large product of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing, we show that the property $(\ast )$ is preserved. With other words, we show that in the final generic extension a $\kappa $ -independent family which we adjoin via forcing at an initial step of the construction satisfies property $(\ast )$ . Note that in difference with the original work of Shelah [Reference Shelah22], we are only interested in products of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing and not iterations.

Theorem 8.1 (GCH).

Let $\kappa $ be a measurable cardinal, let $\mathcal {U}$ be a normal measure on $\kappa $ , and let G be $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ -generic filter over the ground model $V_{0}$ . Let $\mathcal {A}=\mathcal {A}_{G}$ and $V=V_{0}[G]$ . Then

$$ \begin{align*}V^{\mathbb{S}_{\kappa}}\vDash\mathcal{A}\text{ is a densely maximal independent family}.\end{align*} $$

Proof Note that GCH holds in V and $\kappa $ is inaccessible in V. By Lemma 6.3 the family $\mathcal {A}$ is densely maximal in V. To prove that $(\mathcal {A}\text { is densely maximal})^{V^{\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }}}$ we will show that in $V^{\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }}$ , property $(*)$ of $\mathcal {A}$ from Lemma 6.2 holds. More precisely, we will show that in $V^{\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }}$ for each $X\subseteq \kappa $ and each $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $X\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ property $(*)_{X,h}$ holds, where

$(*)_{X,h}$ either $\exists B\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X\subseteq B$ or there is $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash X$ .

Suppose not. Thus, there are $X\subseteq \kappa $ , $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $X\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ and $\lnot (*)_{X,h}$ . That is,

$$ \begin{align*}V^{\mathbb{S}_{\kappa}}\vDash X\subseteq\mathcal{A}^{h}\land \mathcal{A}^{h}\backslash X\notin\operatorname{\mathrm{id}}_{<\omega,\kappa}(\mathcal{A})\land\forall h^{\prime}\supseteq h(\mathcal{A}^{h^{\prime}}\cap X\neq\emptyset).\end{align*} $$

Let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ -name for X in V and let $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }$ force the above. By Lemma 7.9 we can assume that p is preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ and by Corollary 7.15 that for each $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)$ for the outer hull $Y_{t}$ of $\dot {X}$ below $p_{t}$ is of the form $Y_{t}=\{\beta < \kappa :\exists r\in \text {split}(p)\text { such that }t\unlhd r\text { or }r\unlhd t\text { and }p_{r}\Vdash \check {\beta }\in \dot {X}\}$ .

Claim 8.2. Let $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)$ . Then $Y_{t}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ .

Proof Let $m\in Y_{t}$ . Thus there is $q_{t,m}\leq p_{t}$ such that $q_{t,m}\Vdash \check {m}\in \dot {X}$ . But $p_{t}\Vdash \dot {X}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ and so m must be an element of $\mathcal {A}^{h}$ .

We will make use of the following function $H\in {^{\kappa }\kappa }\cap V$ . Given $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)$ and $\beta \in Y_{t}$ , let $r(t,\beta )$ be a witness to $\beta \in Y_{t}$ such that t is comparable with $r(t,\beta )$ and $r(t,\beta )$ is of least splitting level. Then define

$$ \begin{align*}H(\gamma)=\sup\{\gamma+1\}\cup\{\operatorname{\mathrm{sl}}(r(t,\beta)): t\in\text{split}_{\gamma}(p), \beta\leq \gamma \},\end{align*} $$

where if $r(t,\beta )$ is not defined, i.e., $\beta \notin Y_{t}$ , then we take $\operatorname {\mathrm {sl}}(r(t,\beta ))=0$ .

Fix $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)$ . Since $Y_{t}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ , by the dense maximality of $\mathcal {A}$ in V either there is $B\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash Y_{t}\subseteq B$ or there is $h^{\prime }\supseteq h$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash Y_{t}$ . In the latter case, $\mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap Y_{t}=\emptyset $ and since $p\Vdash \dot {X}\subseteq \check {Y}_{t}$ , we obtain that $p\Vdash \mathcal {A}^{h^{\prime }}\cap \dot {X}=\emptyset $ , contrary to the choice of p. Thus, we can assume that $\forall t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)\exists B_{t}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash Y_{t}\subseteq B_{t}$ , $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash Y_{t}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . But then $Y_{t}\cup \kappa \backslash \mathcal {A}^{h}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Now, since $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is a $\kappa $ -p-set, there is $C\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $C\subseteq ^{*} Y_{t}\cup \kappa \backslash \mathcal {A}^{h}$ for each $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)$ . Thus in particular, $C\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}\subseteq ^{*} Y_{t}$ for all $t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}(p)$ and so we can find a function $f\in V\cap {^{\kappa }\kappa }$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\forall \alpha\in\kappa \,\,\forall t\in\text{split}_{\alpha+1}(p) \,\,(C\cap\mathcal{A}^{h})\backslash Y_{t}\subseteq f(\alpha).\end{align*} $$

Equivalently, for each $\alpha \in \kappa $ ,

$$ \begin{align*}(C\cap\mathcal{A}^{h})\backslash f(\alpha)\subseteq \bigcap_{t\in\operatorname{\mathrm{split}}_{\alpha+1}(p)}Y_{t}.\end{align*} $$

Moreover, we can assume that $H(\alpha )+1 < f(\alpha )$ and that f is strictly increasing.

Now, we use Corollary 5.7 for the strictly increasing function $f^{2}=f\circ f$ , i.e., the composition of f with itself. Then there is a set $C^{*}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\forall \alpha \in C^{*}\forall \gamma \in \alpha \cap C^{*} (f^{2}(\gamma )<\alpha )$ . Now, let $C^{\prime }=C \cap C^{*} \cap (f(1),\kappa )$ . Thus $C^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Let $\{k(\alpha ): \alpha <\kappa \}$ be an increasing enumeration of $C^{\prime } \cap \mathcal {A}^{h}$ . Since $C^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ the latter set is indeed unbounded in $\kappa $ . Recursively, we will define a fusion sequence $\tau =\langle q_{\alpha }:\alpha \in \kappa \rangle $ below p such that:

  1. (1) $q_{\alpha +1} \leq _{\alpha } q_{\alpha }$ .

  2. (2) $q_{\alpha +1} \Vdash k(\alpha ) \in \dot {X}$ .

  3. (3) If q is the fusion of $\tau $ then $q\Vdash C^{\prime }\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}\subseteq \dot {X}$ .

But then, since $q\Vdash \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash \dot {X}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash C^{\prime }$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash C^{\prime }\subseteq \kappa \backslash C^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ , we obtain that $q\Vdash \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash \dot {X}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ , which is again a contradiction to the choice of p.

Here is the construction of $\tau $ . Start with $q_{0} =p$ and at limits take intersections. Consider $k(0)$ and put $r = \operatorname {\mathrm {stem}}(p)$ . Since

$$ \begin{align*}(C\cap\mathcal{A}^{h})\backslash f(0)\subseteq \bigcap_{t\in\text{split}_{1}(p)} Y_{t},\end{align*} $$

for each $j \in \{0,1\}$ and p is preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ there is $r_{j}(t,k(0))\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{H(k(0))}(p)$ such that $p_{r_{j}(t,k(0))}\Vdash \check {k}(0)\in \dot {X}$ . Let $q_{1}=\bigcup \{p_{r_{j}(t,k(0))}: t\in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{1}(p) , j \in \{0,1\}\}$ . Thus $q_{1}\leq _{0} q_{0}$ as we wanted.

For completeness we present the construction of the next step: take $k(1)$ and $t \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{1}(q_{1})$ . Note that $\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{1}(q_{1})= \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\delta }(p)$ for some $1 \leq \delta \leq H(k(0))\leq f(k(0))$ and since $f^{2}(k(0)) < k(1)$ and $C \backslash Y_{r} \subseteq f(f(k(0)))$ for all $r \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{f(k(0))+1}(p)$ , we obtain $k(1) \in Y_{r}$ for all $r \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{f(k(0))+1}(p)$ . Using the fact that p is preprocessed and repeating the argument above, find for each $j \in \{0,1\}$ an extension $r_{j}(t,k(1))\leq p_{t^{\frown } j}$ such that $r_{j}(t,k(1)) \Vdash k(1) \in \dot {X}$ . Let $q_{2} = \bigcup \{r_{j}(t,k(1)): t \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{1}(q_{1}) \wedge j \in \{0,1\} \}$ . Then $q_{2}$ is a condition, $q_{2} \leq _{1} q_{1}$ , and $q_{2} \Vdash k(1) \in \dot {X}$ .

In general, suppose we have constructed $q_{\alpha }$ and consider $k(\alpha )$ , and $t \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha })$ , then there is $\delta \geq \alpha $ so that $t \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\delta } (p)$ and $\delta \leq H(k(\alpha ))$ . Again, since $f^{2}(k(\alpha )) < k(\alpha +1)$ and $C \backslash Y_{r} \subseteq f(f(k(\alpha )))$ for all $r \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{f(k(\alpha ))+1}(p)$ we get that $k(\alpha ) \in Y_{t}$ , so again use that p is preprocessed and repeat the argument above to find conditions $r_{j}(t,k(\alpha )) \leq p_{t^{\smallfrown } j}$ forcing $r_{j}(t,k(\alpha )) \Vdash k(\alpha ) \in \dot {X} j \in \{0,1\}$ . Put $q_{\alpha +1} = \bigcup \{r_{j}(t,k(\alpha )): t \in \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha }) \wedge j \in \{0,1\} \}$ . Then $q_{\alpha +1}$ is a condition, $q_{\alpha +1} \leq _{\alpha } q_{\alpha }$ , and $q_{\alpha +1} \Vdash k(\alpha ) \in \dot {X}$ .

Theorem 8.3. The generic maximal independent family adjoined by $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ over a model $V_{0}$ of GCH remains maximal after the $\kappa $ -support product $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ .

Proof The idea for this proof is not much different than the one for the successor step; however, the fusion argument has to be handled more carefully. We give now an outline with the most important details. As in the case above start with a densely maximal independent family $\mathcal {A}$ in $V=V^{\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}}$ . To prove that

$$ \begin{align*}(\mathcal{A}\text{ is densely maximal independent family})^{V^{\mathbb{S}_{\kappa}^{\lambda}}},\end{align*} $$

we will show that in $V^{\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }}$ , property $(*)$ from Lemma 6.2 holds for the family $\mathcal {A}$ . Specifically, we show that in $V^{\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }}$ for each $X\subseteq \kappa $ and each $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $X\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ property $(*)_{X,h}$ holds, where $(*)_{X,h}$ states:

$$ \begin{align*}& \text{either }\exists B\in\operatorname{\mathrm{id}}_{<\omega,\kappa}(\mathcal{A})\text{ such that }\mathcal{A}^{h}\backslash X\subseteq B \\ & \quad\text{ or there is }h^{\prime}\supseteq h\text{ such that }\mathcal{A}^{h^{\prime}}\subseteq\mathcal{A}^{h}\backslash X.\end{align*} $$

Suppose not. Thus, there are $X\subseteq \kappa $ , $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $X\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ and $\lnot (*)_{X,h}$ . That is,

$$ \begin{align*}V^{\mathbb{S}_{\kappa}^{\lambda}}\vDash X\subseteq\mathcal{A}^{h}\land \mathcal{A}^{h}\backslash X\notin\operatorname{\mathrm{id}}_{<\omega,\kappa}(\mathcal{A})\land\forall h^{\prime}\supseteq h(\mathcal{A}^{h^{\prime}}\cap X\neq\emptyset).\end{align*} $$

Let $\dot {X}$ be an $\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ -name for X in V and let $p\in \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ force the above. Passing to a stronger condition if necessary we can assume that p is preprocessed for $\dot {X}$ . Now, for every $\alpha < \kappa $ and all $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ such that $\lvert F \lvert < \kappa $ consider the set $\Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ . This is a set of size $<\!\kappa $ because $\lvert \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(p(i)) \lvert \leq 2^{\lvert \alpha \lvert }$ and $\lvert F \lvert < \kappa $ . Also, $\{\Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p): \alpha <\kappa \wedge F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p) \wedge \lvert F \lvert < \kappa \}$ has size $\kappa $ and so does its union.

Similarly to Claim 8.2 we obtain:

Claim 8.4. For all $\alpha < \kappa $ and $F \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p)$ such that $\lvert F \lvert <\kappa $ , if $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ then $Y_{\bar {\sigma }}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}$ .

Before proceeding with construction of a fusion sequence, which will lead to the desired contradiction, we need to define one more auxiliary object, namely the function H defined below. Whenever $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha }(p)$ and $\beta \in Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ , let $r(\bar {\sigma },\beta )$ be a witness to $\beta \in Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ such that for each $i \in F $ the stem of the condition $r(\bar {\sigma },\beta )(i)$ is of minimal height. Define $H\in {^{\kappa }\kappa }\cap V$ as follows:

$$ \begin{align*}H(\gamma) & =\sup\{\gamma+1\} \\& \quad\cup\{\operatorname{\mathrm{sl}}(\operatorname{\mathrm{stem}}(r(\bar{\sigma},\beta))): \bar{\sigma} \in \Lambda_{\gamma}^{F}(p), \beta\leq \gamma, F\subseteq \operatorname{\mathrm{supp}}(p)\cap \gamma \text{ and } \lvert F \lvert <\kappa \}.\end{align*} $$

Again, following the argument for the single step, we can assume that for all $\alpha <\kappa $ and all $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F}(p)$ there exists $B_{\bar {\sigma }}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash Y_{\bar {\sigma }} \subseteq B_{\bar {\sigma }}$ , $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash Y_{\bar {\sigma }}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . But then $Y_{\bar {\sigma }}\cup \kappa \backslash \mathcal {A}^{h}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Now, since $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is a $\kappa $ -p-set, there is $C\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $C\subseteq ^{*} Y_{\bar {\sigma }}\cup \kappa \backslash \mathcal {A}^{h}$ for each $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F}$ . Thus in particular, $C\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}\subseteq Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ for each $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda _{\alpha }^{F}(p)$ and so we can find a function $f\in V\cap {^{\kappa }\kappa }$ such that,

$$ \begin{align*}\forall \alpha\in\kappa \,\,\forall F \subseteq \operatorname{\mathrm{supp}}(p) \,\,\forall \bar{\sigma} \in \Lambda^{F}_{\alpha+1}(p) \,\,(\lvert F \lvert <\kappa \to C\cap (\mathcal{A}^{h}\backslash Y_{\bar{\sigma}} )\subseteq f(\alpha)).\end{align*} $$

Thus, for each $\alpha \in \kappa $ , $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F}_{\alpha +1}(p)$ , and $\beta \in C\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}$ , if $\beta>f(\alpha )$ then $\beta \in Y_{\bar {\sigma }}$ . Moreover, we can assume that f is strictly increasing, that $H(\alpha )\leq f(\alpha )$ and $\alpha +2<f(\alpha )$ for all $\alpha \in \kappa $ .

By Corollary 5.7, there is $C^{*}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ such that $\forall \alpha \in C^{*}\forall \gamma \in \alpha \cap C^{*} (f^{2}(\gamma )<\alpha )$ . Now, let $C^{\prime }=C \cap C^{*} \cap (f(0),\kappa )$ . Thus $C^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ . Let $\{k(\alpha ): \alpha \in \kappa \}$ be an increasing enumeration of $C^{\prime } \cap \mathcal {A}^{h}$ . Since $C^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ the latter set is indeed unbounded in $\kappa $ . Recursively, we will define a fusion sequence $\tau =\langle q_{\alpha }, F_{\alpha }:\alpha \in \kappa \rangle \subseteq \mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$ below p, ordinals $(\eta _{\alpha }: \alpha < \kappa )$ , and bijections $g_{\alpha }: F_{\alpha } \to \eta _{\alpha }$ such that for all $\alpha <\kappa $ :

  1. (1) $q_{\alpha +1} \leq _{F_{\alpha },\alpha } q_{\alpha }.$ .

  2. (2) $\eta _{\alpha } \geq \alpha $

  3. (3) For all $\alpha < \alpha ^{\prime }<\kappa $ , $g_{\alpha } \subseteq g_{\alpha ^{\prime }}$ , and for limit ordinals $\delta < \kappa g_{\delta } = \bigcup _{\alpha < \delta } g_{\alpha }$ .

  4. (4) $q_{\alpha +1} \Vdash k(\alpha ) \in \dot {X}$ .

Now, if q is the fusion of $\tau $ then $q\Vdash C^{\prime }\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}\subseteq \dot {X}$ . But then, since $q\Vdash \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash \dot {X}\subseteq \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash C^{\prime }$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash C^{\prime }\subseteq \omega \backslash C^{\prime }\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ , we obtain that $q\Vdash \mathcal {A}^{h}\backslash \dot {X}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ , contradicting the choice of p.

We proceed with the recursive construction of $\tau $ . Start with $q_{0} = p$ , $F_{0}= \min (\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p))$ , $\eta _{0} = 0$ , and $g_{0}= \emptyset $ . At limit stages $\delta <\kappa $ the construction of $q_{\delta }$ and $F_{\delta }$ it is already been determined so that the conditions in Definition 7.4 are fulfilled. Finally, let $\eta _{\delta } = \sup _{\alpha <\delta } \eta _{\alpha }$ and $g_{\delta }$ as above. Consider $k(0)$ and put $\bar {\sigma } = \langle \operatorname {\mathrm {stem}}(p(\min (\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(p))))\rangle $ . Since for all $\bar {\tau } \in \Lambda ^{F_{0}}_{1}(p)$ , $C \setminus Y_{\bar {\tau }} \subseteq f(0)$ , $k(0) \geq f(0)$ , and p is preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, F_{0})$ we have that $k(0) \in Y_{\bar {\tau }}$ for all $\bar {\tau } \in \Lambda ^{F_{0}}_{1}(p)$ and so, by Corollary 7.15 for each $h \in ^{F_{0}} 2$ there exists a set $F_{0}^{\prime } \supseteq F_{0}$ , a $\bar {\tau } \sqsupseteq \bar {\sigma }$ , and condition $r_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(0)) \leq p^{h}_{\bar {\tau }_{h}}$ such that $r_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(0)) \Vdash k(0) \in \dot {X}$ .

For completeness, we give a more detailed proof of the existence of the conditions $r_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(0))$ . Recall that $p^{h}_{\bar {\sigma }}$ is defined as follows:

$$ \begin{align*}p^{h}_{\bar{\sigma}}(i) = \begin{cases} (p(i))_{ \sigma_{i}^{\smallfrown} h(i)}, & \text{if } i \in F, \\ p(i), & \text{otherwise. } \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

There are sequences $\bar {\sigma }^{\prime }_{h} \in \Lambda ^{F_{0}}_{1}(p)$ such that $\bar {\sigma }_{h} \unlhd \bar {\sigma }^{\prime }_{h}$ where $\bar {\sigma }_{h}$ is such that $\sigma _{h}(i)= \sigma (i)^{\frown } h(i)$ for all $i \in F_{0}$ . Hence, using that p is preprocessed we can get a set $F_{0}^{\prime } \supseteq F_{0}$ such that $\lvert F_{0}^{\prime } \lvert < \kappa $ and sequences $\bar {\tau }_{h} \sqsupseteq \bar {\sigma }^{\prime }_{h}$ so that $p_{\bar {\tau }_{h}} \Vdash k(0) \in \dot {X}$ . Thus, take $r_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(0))=p_{\bar {\tau }_{h}}$ .

Then if $q_{1}= \bigcup \{ r_{h}(\bar {\sigma },k(0)) : h \in {^{F_{0}}} 2, \bar {\tau }_{h} \in \Lambda ^{F_{0}^{\prime }}_{0}(p) \}$ , $F_{1}= F_{0}^{\prime } \cup \{\min \{\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(q_{1}) \backslash F_{0}^{\prime }\}\}$ , $\eta _{1}= \eta _{0} +1$ , and $g_{1} = g_{0} \cup \{ (\min \{\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(q_{1}) \backslash F_{0}^{\prime }, \eta _{1})\}$ we have that $q_{1} \leq _{0,F_{0}^{\prime }} q_{0}\text { and }q_{1} \Vdash k(0) \in \dot {X}$ as we wanted.

In general, suppose we have constructed $q_{\alpha }$ , $F_{\alpha }$ , $\eta _{\alpha }$ , and $g_{\alpha }$ as desired. Consider $k(\alpha )$ and the set $\Lambda ^{F_{\alpha }}_{\alpha +1}(p_{\alpha })$ . Fix an enumeration $\{\gamma _{l} =(\bar {\sigma }_{l}, h_{l}): l< \rho \}$ of all pairs of the form $(\bar {\sigma }, h)$ such that $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda _{\alpha +1}^{F_{\alpha }}(q_{\alpha })$ and $h \in {^{F_{\alpha }}2}$ . Note that the ordinal $\rho $ is $< \kappa $ . Inductively, we will construct a sequence $\{r^{\alpha }_{l}:l<\rho \}$ of conditions below $q_{\alpha }$ satisfying:

  1. (1) $r^{\alpha }_{0} = q_{\alpha }$ .

  2. (2) $r^{\alpha }_{l+1} \leq _{\alpha , F_{\alpha }} r^{\alpha }_{l}$ .

  3. (3) $(r^{\alpha }_{l+1})_{\bar {\sigma }_{l}}^{h_{l}} \Vdash \check {k}(\alpha ) \in \dot {X}$ .

  4. (4) For l limit ordinal $r^{\alpha }_{l} = \bigwedge _{k< l} r^{\alpha }_{k}$ .

It is enough to explain how the successor step is built: Suppose then that we have constructed $r^{\alpha }_{l}$ satisfying the conditions above and consider the pair $\gamma _{l} =(\bar {\sigma }, h)$ . Notice that since $\lvert F_{\alpha } \lvert < \kappa $ for all $i \in F_{\alpha }$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha }(i)) \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {split}}_{\delta }(p(i))$ for some $\delta \leq H(k(\alpha ))$ . Also, since $f^{2}(k(\alpha )) < k(\alpha +1)$ and for all $\bar {\tau } \in \Lambda _{f(\alpha )+1}^{F_{\alpha }}(p)$ we have that $C \backslash Y_{\bar {\tau }} \subseteq f(f(k(\alpha )))$ , we obtain that $k(\alpha ) \in Y_{\bar {\tau }}$ for all $\bar {\tau } \in \Lambda _{f(\alpha )+1}^{F_{\alpha }}(p)$ . Thus, again we repeat the argument above using the fact that p is preprocessed for $(\dot {X}, F_{\alpha })$ and find a set $F_{\alpha }^{\prime } \supseteq F_{\alpha }$ , a sequence $\bar {\tau }_{h} \in \Lambda ^{F_{\alpha }^{\prime }}_{\alpha }(p)$ , and conditions $w_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(\alpha )) \leq p^{h}_{\bar {\tau }_{h}}$ forcing $w_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(\alpha )) \Vdash k(\alpha ) \in \dot {X}$ . Moreover, we can choose $w_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(\alpha ))$ so that $w_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(\alpha ))\leq (q_{\alpha })^{h}_{\bar {\tau }_{h}}$ . Note that $w_{h}(\bar {\tau }_{h},k(\alpha ))$ might not yet be a condition satisfying the condition (2). In order to fix this, we define $r^{\alpha }_{l+1}$ as follows: $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(r^{\alpha }_{l+1})=\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(w_{l})$ and

$$ \begin{align*} & r^{\alpha}_{l+1}(i) = \\ & \!\begin{cases} (w_{h}(\bar{\tau}_{h},k(\alpha))(i) \cup \{ (q_{\alpha}(i))_{\rho {}^{\frown} j}{:} \rho \in \operatorname{\mathrm{split}}_{\alpha} (r_{l}(i)) {\setminus} \sigma_{i} \text{ or } j= 1-h(i) \}, &\!\! \text{if } i \in F_{\alpha}^{\prime}, \\ w_{h}(\bar{\sigma},k(\alpha))(i), &\!\! \text{otherwise. } \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

Finally, let $q_{\alpha +1}= \bigwedge _{l< \rho } r^{\alpha }_{l}$ , $\eta _{\alpha +1} = \eta _{\alpha } +1$ , $F_{\alpha +1}=F_{\alpha }^{\prime }\cup \{\min (\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(q_{\alpha +1})\backslash F_{\alpha }^{\prime })\}$ , and $g_{\alpha +1} = g_{\alpha } \cup \{(\min (\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(q_{\alpha +1})\backslash F_{\alpha }^{\prime }), \eta _{\alpha })\}$ . The construction is now complete. Indeed, to see that $q_{\alpha +1} \Vdash \check {k}(\alpha ) \in \dot {X}$ notice that for all $\bar {\sigma } \in \Lambda ^{F_{\alpha }}_{\alpha }(q_{\alpha +1})$ and all $h \in {^{F_{\alpha }}} 2$ , $(q_{\alpha +1})^{h}_{\bar {\sigma }} \Vdash \check {k}(\alpha ) \in \dot {X}$ .

Remark 8.5. Note that $\kappa $ might cease to be measurable in $V^{\mathbb {S}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }}$ from the above theorem. For a preparation of the universe, which guarantees that $\kappa $ remains measurable see [Reference Friedman13].

9 Concluding remarks and questions

The use of the assumption $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ played a crucial role in our construction of a densely maximal $\kappa $ -independent family. Thus one may ask:

Question 9.1. Does ZFC imply the existence of a densely maximal $\kappa $ -independent families?

Even though we are able to show both that consistently $\mathfrak {i}_{f}(\kappa )=\kappa ^{+} < 2^{\kappa }$ and $\kappa ^{+}<\mathfrak {i}_{f}(\kappa )=2^{\kappa }$ , the currently available techniques seem to be insufficient to answer the following:

Question 9.2. Let $\kappa $ be a regular uncountable cardinal. Is it consistent that $\kappa ^{+}<\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )<2^{\kappa }$ ?

The analogous question in the countable can be answered to the positive with the use of the so-called diagonalization filters (see [Reference Fischer and Shelah12]). A natural generalization of the notion of a diagonalization filter to the uncountable is given below:

Definition 9.3. Let $\mathcal {A}$ be a $\kappa $ -independent family. A $\kappa $ -complete filter $\mathcal {F}$ is said to be a $\kappa $ -diagonalization filter for $\mathcal {A}$ if $\forall F\in \mathcal {F}\forall h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})|F\cap \mathcal {A}^{h}|=\kappa $ and $\mathcal {F}$ is maximal with respect to the above property.

Moreover, as a straightforward generalization of the countable case (see [Reference Fischer and Shelah12]) one can show that:

Lemma 9.4 (See [Reference Fischer and Shelah12, Lemma 2]).

Suppose $\mathcal {A}$ is a $\kappa $ -independent family and $\mathcal {F}$ is a $\kappa $ -diagonalization filter for $\mathcal {A}$ . Let $\mathbb {M}^{\kappa }_{\mathcal {F}}$ be the generalized Mathias forcing relativized to the filter $\mathcal {F}$ .Footnote 8 Let G be an $\mathbb {M}^{\kappa }_{\mathcal {F}}$ -generic filter and let $x_{G}=\bigcup \{a:\exists A (a,A)\in G\}$ . Then $\mathcal {A}\cup \{x_{G}\}$ is $\kappa $ -independent and moreover for each $Y\in ([\kappa ]^{\kappa }\cap V)\backslash \mathcal {A}$ such that $\mathcal {A}\cup \{Y\}$ is $\kappa $ -independent, the family $\mathcal {A}\cup \{x_{G},Y\}$ is not $\kappa $ -independent.

Even though an appropriate iteration of posets of the above form would produce a positive answer to Question 9.2, the following remains open:

Question 9.5. Given a $\kappa $ -independent family $\mathcal {A}$ is there a $\kappa $ -diagonalization filter for $\mathcal {A}$ ? The co-bounded filter does satisfy the characterization property in Definition 9.3; however, the requirement for maximality is not straightforward to satisfy. Is there a large cardinal property which guarantees the existence of such maximal filter? Note that a diagonalization filter is never an ultrafilter.

Moreover of interest remain the following:

Question 9.6. Is it consistent that $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )<\mathfrak {a}(\kappa )$ ?

Clearly, if the above is consistent then in the corresponding model, $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )\geq \kappa ^{++}$ . One of the original questions, which motivated the work on this project is the evaluation of $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ in the model from [Reference Brooke-Taylor, Fischer, Friedman and Montoya6]. More precisely, we would like to know:

Question 9.7. Is it consistent that $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa ) < \mathfrak {u}(\kappa )?$

The consistency of $\mathfrak {r}<\mathfrak {i}$ holds in the Miller model. However, products of the generalized Miller poset $\mathbb {MI}_{\kappa }^{\mathcal {U}}$ , where $\mathcal {U}$ is a $\kappa $ -complete normal ultrafilter on $\kappa $ add $\kappa $ -Cohen reals (see [Reference Brendle, Brooke-Taylor, Friedman and Montoya4, Theorem 85]) and so increase $\mathfrak {r}(\kappa )$ . Even though $\mathbb {MI}_{\kappa }^{\mathcal {U}}$ has the generalized Laver property (see [Reference Brendle, Brooke-Taylor, Friedman and Montoya4, Proposition 81]), it is open if the generalized Laver property is preserved under $\kappa $ -support iterations. This leaves us with the following:

Question 9.8. Is it consistent that $\mathfrak {r}(\kappa )<\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ ?

10 Appendix: strong independence

Another approach towards finding a higher analogues of independence for a given uncountable cardinal $\kappa $ is to consider Boolean combinations generated by strictly less than $\kappa $ (not just finitely) many members of the family. More precisely one can give the following definition:

Definition 10.1. Let $\kappa $ be a regular uncountable cardinal, $\mathcal {A}\subseteq [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ of cardinality at least $\kappa $ .

  1. (1) Let $\operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\kappa ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ be the set of partial functions $h:\mathcal {A}\to \{0,1\}$ with domain of cardinality strictly below $\kappa $ and for $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\kappa ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ let $\mathcal {A}^{h}=\bigcap \{\mathcal {A}^{h(A)}: A\in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(h)\}$ where $\mathcal {A}^{h(A)}=A$ if $h(A)=0$ and $\mathcal {A}^{h(A)}=\kappa \backslash A$ if $h(A)=1$ .

  2. (2) The family $\mathcal {A}$ is said to be strongly $\kappa $ -independent if for every $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\kappa ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ the Boolean combination $\mathcal {A}^{h}$ is unbounded.

  3. (3) The family $\mathcal {A}$ is said to be maximal strongly $\kappa $ -independent if it is strongly $\kappa $ -independent and is not properly contained in another strongly $\kappa $ -independent family.

  4. (4) Suppose $\kappa $ is a regular uncountable cardinal for which maximal strongly $\kappa $ -independent families exist. With $\mathfrak {i}_{s}(\kappa )$ we denote the minimal size of a maximal strongly $\kappa $ -independent family.

Note that the increasing union of a countable sequence of strongly $\kappa $ -independent families is not necessarily strongly $\kappa $ -independent. Thus one cannot apply Zorn’s lemma to claim the existence of maximal strongly $\kappa $ -independent families. What we can say is the following:

Theorem 10.2. Let $\kappa $ be a regular uncountable cardinal.

  1. (1) For $\kappa $ strongly inaccessible, there is a strongly $\kappa $ -independent family of cardinality $2^{\kappa }$ .

  2. (2) If $\mathcal {A}$ is strongly $\kappa $ -independent and $|\mathcal {A}|<\mathfrak {r}(\kappa )$ then $\mathcal {A}$ is not maximal.

  3. (3) Suppose $\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )$ is such that for every $\gamma <\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )$ , $\gamma ^{<\kappa }<\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )$ . If $\mathcal {A}$ is strongly $\kappa $ -independent and $|\mathcal {A}|<\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )$ then $\mathcal {A}$ is not maximal.

Proof We will prove $(1)$ . Let $\mathcal {C}=\{(\gamma , A): \gamma <\kappa , A\subseteq \mathcal {P}(\gamma )\}$ . Given $X\subseteq \kappa $ define $\mathcal {Y}_{X}=\{(\gamma , A)\in \mathcal {C}: X\cap \gamma \in A\}$ . Then $\mathcal {Y}_{X}: X\subseteq \kappa \}$ is strongly $\kappa $ -independent. Indeed. Consider two disjoint subfamilies of $[\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ , each of size strictly smaller than $\kappa $ , say $\{X_{i}\}_{i\in I_{1}}$ and $\{Z_{j}\}_{j\in I_{2}}$ . Note that $(\gamma , A)\in \mathcal {X}=\bigcap _{i\in I_{1}} \mathcal {Y}_{X_{i}}\cap \bigcap _{j\in I_{2}}(\mathcal {C}\backslash \mathcal {Y}_{Z_{j}})$ if for all $i\in I_{1}$ , $X_{i}\cap A\in A$ and for all $j\in I_{2}$ , $Z_{j}\cap \gamma \notin A$ . However, there are unboundedly many $\gamma \in \kappa $ such that:

  • $X_{i}\cap \gamma \neq X_{i^{\prime }}\cap \gamma $ for $i\neq i^{\prime }$ both in $I_{1}$ ,

  • $Z_{j}\cap \gamma \neq Z_{j^{\prime }}\cap \gamma $ for $j\neq j^{\prime }$ both in $I_{2}$ , and

  • $X_{i}\cap \gamma \neq Z_{j}\cap \gamma $ for all $i\in I_{1}$ , $j\in I_{2}$ .

It remains to observe that for each such $\gamma $ , we have $(\gamma , A_{\gamma })\in \mathcal {X}$ , where $A_{\gamma }=\{X_{i}\cap \gamma :i\in I_{1}\}$ .

To see part $(2)$ note that if $|\mathcal {A}|<\mathfrak {r}(\kappa )$ , then the set $\{\mathcal {A}^{h}:h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {FF}}_{<\kappa ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})\}$ is split by some $X\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ and so $\mathcal {A}\cup \{X\}$ is strongly $\kappa $ -independent which properly contains $\mathcal {A}$ .

For a proof of part $(3)$ , see [Reference Brooke-Taylor, Fischer, Friedman and Montoya6, Proposition 27].

Corollary 10.3. Thus, if $\mathfrak {i}_{s}(\kappa )$ is defined, then $\kappa ^{+}\leq \mathfrak {i}_{s}(\kappa )\leq 2^{\kappa }$ . Moreover $\mathfrak {r}(\kappa )\leq \mathfrak {i}_{s}(\kappa )$ and if for every $\gamma <\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )$ , $\gamma ^{<\kappa }<\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )$ , then $\mathfrak {d}(\kappa )\leq \mathfrak {i}_{s}(\kappa )$ .

Question 10.4.

  1. (1) Is there a large cardinal property which implies the existence of a maximal strongly $\kappa $ -independent family?

  2. (2) Given a strongly $\kappa $ -independent family $\mathcal {A}$ , is there a large cardinal property which implies the existence of a $\kappa $ -diagonalization filter for $\mathcal {A}$ ?

  3. (3) Suppose $\mathfrak {i}_{s}(\kappa )$ is defined. A family which is strongly $\kappa $ -independent is $\kappa $ -independent. However a maximal strongly independent family is not necessarily maximal independent. Is there a ZFC relation between $\mathfrak {i}_{s}(\kappa )$ and $\mathfrak {i}(\kappa )$ ?

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank the anonymous referee for many helpful comments which significantly improved the quality of the manuscript. The authors would also like to thank the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) for the generous support through Grant Y1012-N35, as well as I4039 (Fischer) and T1100 (Montoya).

Footnotes

1 In the paper, we only study the case in which $\kappa $ is regular.

2 Clearly every strongly independent family is independent.

3 Partial orders and their tree versions often differ. Good example is given by the poset for adding an infinitely often equal real and its tree version. The former adds a Silver real and so kills all p-points (see [Reference Chodounsky and Guzmán8]), while the latter preserves p-points (see [Reference Goldstern, Judah and Shelah15]).

4 In the countable setting the filter in question is generated by a tower, see for example [Reference Brendle, Fischer and Khomskii5] and so the filter remains a P-set throughout an iteration of Sacks forcing. For our current argument, which only deals with products of $\kappa $ -Sacks forcing, the fact that $\operatorname {\mathrm {fil}}_{<\omega ,\kappa }(\mathcal {A})$ is a $\kappa $ -P-set is sufficient.

5 Using the normal measure $\mathcal {U}$ and the hypothesis $2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ one can alternatively use the properties of the poset $\mathbb {P}_{\mathcal {U}}$ to construct a family $\mathcal {A}$ having all essential properties of $\mathcal {A}_{G}$ using a transfinite recursion of length $\kappa ^{+}$ .

6 Throughout $A\subseteq ^{*} B$ means $|A\backslash B|<\kappa $ .

7 Here $\bar {\sigma } \sqsubseteq \bar {\tau }_{\bar {\sigma }}$ means for all $i \in F \sigma _{i}= \tau _{i}$ .

8 That is $\mathbb {M}^{\kappa }_{\mathcal {F}}$ consists of all pairs $(a,A)\in [\kappa ]^{<\kappa }\times \mathcal {F}$ such that $\sup a < \min A$ .

References

Bergfalk, J., Fischer, V., and Switzer, C., Projective well-orders and coanalytic witnesses. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 173 (2022), no. 8, p. 101135.Google Scholar
Blass, A., Cardinal characteristics of the continuum , Handbook of Set Theory (Foreman, M. and Kanamori, A., editors), Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 395489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blass, A., Hyttinen, T., and Zhang, Y., Mad families and their neighbours, preprint, http://www.math.lsa.umich.edu/~ablass/madfam.pdf.Google Scholar
Brendle, J., Brooke-Taylor, A., Friedman, S. D., and Montoya, D., Cichón’s diagram for uncountable cardinals . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 225 (2018), pp. 9591010.Google Scholar
Brendle, J., Fischer, V., and Khomskii, Y., Definable maximal independent families . Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 147 (2019), pp. 35473557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brooke-Taylor, A., Fischer, V., Friedman, S. D., and Montoya, D. C., Cardinal characteristics at κ is a small $u\left(\kappa \right)$ model. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 168 (2017), no. 1, pp. 3749.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chodounsky, D., Grebik, J., and Fischer, V., Free sequences in $\mathbf{\mathcal{P}}\hspace{-2pt}\left(\omega \right)\hspace{-2pt}/\mathrm{fin}$ . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 58 (2019), no. 7–8, pp. 10351051.Google Scholar
Chodounsky, D. and Guzmán, O., There are no P-points in silver extensions . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 232 (2019), no. 2, pp. 759773.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cruz-Chapital, J. A., Fischer, V., Guzman, O., and Supina, J., Partition forcing and maximal independent families, submitted.Google Scholar
Fischer, V. and Eskew, M., Strong independence and its spectrum, preprint, 2021. Available at https://arxiv.org/abs/2103.04063.Google Scholar
Fischer, V. and Montoya, D. C., Ideals of independence . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 58 (2019), pp. 767785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer, V. and Shelah, S., The spectrum of independence . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 58 (2019), no. 7–8, pp. 877884.Google Scholar
Friedman, S. D., Cardinal Characteristics of the Uncountable , Lecture Notes Series, Institute for Mathematics, Kurt Gödel Research Center, University of Vienna, 2014.Google Scholar
Geschke, S., Almost disjoint and independent families . RIMS Kokyuroku , vol. 1790 (2012), pp. 19.Google Scholar
Goldstern, M., Judah, H., and Shelah, S., Strong measure zero sets without Cohen reals, this Journal, vol. 58 (1993), no. 4, pp. 1323–1341.Google Scholar
Goldstern, M. and Shelah, S., Ramsey ultrafilters and the reaping number— $\mathrm{Con}\left(r<u\right)$ . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 49 (1990), no. 2, 121142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guzmán, O., Hrŭsák, M., and Téllez, O., Restricted MAD families, this Journal, vol. 85 (2020), no. 1, pp. 149–165.Google Scholar
Halbeisen, L., Combinatorial Set Theory. With a Gentle Introduction to Forcing , Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer, London, 2012.Google Scholar
Kanamori, A., Perfect-set forcing for uncountable cardinals . Annals of Mathematical Logic , vol. 19 (1980), pp. 97114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kunnen, K., Maximal σ-independent families . Fundamenta Mathematicae , vol. 117 (1983), no. 1, pp. 7580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raghavan, D. and Shelah, S., Two results on cardinal invariants at uncountable cardinals, In Proceedings of the 14th and 15th Asian Logic Conferences , pp. 129–138 (2019).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., $\mathrm{Con}\left(u>i\right)$ . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 31 (1992), no. 6, pp. 433443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Switzer, C., Selective independence and h-perfect tree forcing notions, preprint, 2022, arXiv:2202.12046.Google Scholar