Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T16:00:07.106Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

‘The friend-making table’: variety and the definition of friendship in Plutarch’s Table Talk

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 July 2023

N. Bryant Kirkland*
Affiliation:
University of California, Los Angeles
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Plutarch’s Table Talk asserts the ‘friend-making’ (φιλοποιός) character of the symposium seemingly unproblematically (612D, 621C). Yet it is not entirely clear how readers are to understand the dynamics of social variety in the work, or how its presentation of friendship relates to Plutarch’s formal pronouncements elsewhere on the subject. This article explores connections between Table Talk and aspects of On Having Many Friends and How to Tell a Flatterer from a Friend. It also considers some ideas around poikilia in Plutarch in connection to discussions of complexity and simplicity in Table Talk, as a window onto the work’s presentation of amicable variety. I argue that social variety is often the implicit target in discussions of party pragmatics and gastronomic variety. Unlike the moral essays, Table Talk ultimately endorses a broad conceptualization of friendship’s and variety’s value, inviting readers to rethink Plutarchan ideas for the sympotic context.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

I. Introduction

In recent years the tendency to view Plutarch’s Table Talk (Quaestiones conuiuales) as an unsystematic mass, best quarried for random bits of lore, has been challenged by studies that show the text to be an engaging and coherent structure in its own right.Footnote 1 Far from being an off-putting miscellany, the work is increasingly recognized as inviting readers into its ‘social ποικιλία’ as fellow interlocutors, prompting them to engage with a range of topics across its variegated content.Footnote 2 Still, questions concerning the work’s purposes and effects persist, including its connections to other parts of Plutarch’s corpus. This article explores some implications of Table Talk’s assertion of the symposium’s ‘friend-making’ (φιλοποιός) capacity, programmatically announced at the work’s start (1 praef., 612D), along two related lines of inquiry. One concerns how readers are to interpret Table Talk’s presentation of amity in relation to Plutarch’s ideas on friendship expressed elsewhere. Table Talk appears to valorize the very poluphilia and loose amity against which Plutarch warns in such works as On Having Many Friends, and readers are accordingly invited to situate Plutarch’s presentation of sympotic friendship in relation to his formal disquisitions on the topic. Related to the work’s amicable variety is the question of how to interpret Table Talk’s idea of variety more generally. After all, poikilia can carry ambiguous connotations, and so it is worth asking how Table Talk represents its own brand of multiplicity. Is social poikilia good poikilia, and if so, why? How do positive and negative ideas of variety converge in the symposium? Speculations about the benefits of variousness appear directly and indirectly in Table Talk, and I aim to show how the text ‘thinks’ by analogy about variety and companionship as intertwined, even in discussions which on the surface concern the pragmatics of party-giving or gastronomic variation.

By conjuring connections between social and intellectual variety, Table Talk evokes topics that Plutarch contemplates in other works and thereby affords readers the chance for comparative consideration across his corpus.Footnote 3 Such comparison inspires readers to the very mode of flexible thinking encouraged by Table Talk’s dynamic of group discussion.Footnote 4 Plutarch, too, as author of other works becomes an implicit interlocutor, as it were, in dialogue with the ‘Plutarch’ of Table Talk, a text in which he also appears as a character.Footnote 5 Recall of and occasional tension between aspects of Table Talk and Plutarch’s wider corpus complicate any easy sense of his authority and intensify the need for engagement by the reader, who is encouraged to parse the ways in which Plutarchan ideas might apply in different genres or contexts.

In what follows I discuss (section II) interpretive issues raised by Table Talk’s foregrounding of the symposium’s friend-making capacity, including some connections to notions of variety in Plutarch. I then turn (section III) to close readings of specific portions of Table Talk that either explicitly or implicitly consider friendship or variety, with some attention to ways in which these scenes interact with notions expressed in other Plutarch texts. I conclude with a discussion (section IV) of how the role of the ‘shadow’ articulates Table Talk’s broad notion of sociality. I argue that while sympotic sociality evokes ambiguities from Plutarch’s corpus on the topics of both friendship and variety, Table Talk ultimately offers a more open-ended, flexible idea of friendship than that endorsed by Plutarch’s treatises. The work’s expansive ethics of amity helps to define the nature of the Plutarchan symposium. Table Talk’s tendency towards undogmatic, unresolved answers is in part enabled by a fluid notion of sociality, in which intellectual variety echoes and implicitly reinforces the value of social poikilia.

II. Tabling friendship and variety

Plutarch situates Table Talk in a double framework of friendship. The work is addressed to Plutarch’s friend Sossius Senecio, well-known as the dedicatee of Progress in Virtue and the Parallel Lives.Footnote 6 Moreover, as Plutarch implies at the outset, the symposium is in part about making friends: ‘Letting what happens over wine fall into complete oblivion not only militates against the so-called friend-making character of the table but also has the most highly reputed of philosophers to bear witness against it’ (τὸ δ’ ὅλως ἀμνημονϵῖν τῶν ἐν οἴνῳ μὴ μόνον τῷ φιλοποιῷ λϵγομένῳ μάχϵσθαι τῆς τραπέζης, ἀλλὰ καὶ τῶν φιλοσόφων τοὺς ἐλλογιμωτάτους ἀντιμαρτυροῦντας ἔχϵιν, 612D).Footnote 7 Plutarch presents his text as an enactment of friendship: if retrospection underscores the filiating ends of the party, beyond its occurrence in real time, failure to recall the party’s conversations becomes an ethical lapse that disrespects the relationships produced at the friend-making table.Footnote 8 Plutarch therefore extends the actual symposium’s potential for friendship to the power of the text itself: the literary work structured around the symposium, by virtue of being dedicated to a friend, reinforces the friend-making premise of its intra-diegetic proceedings.

A few scenes in, Theon echoes Plutarch’s paratextual framing, stating the symposium’s τέλος (1.4, 621C):Footnote 9

τοῦτο δ’ ἦν φιλίας ἐπίτασιν ἢ γένϵσιν δι’ ἡδονῆς ἐνϵργάσασθαι τοῖς παροῦσιν. διαγωγὴ γάρ ἐστιν ἐν οἴνῳ τὸ συμπόσιον ϵἰς φιλίαν ὑπὸ χάριτος τϵλϵυτῶσα.

This [aim] was through pleasure to generate among those present the intensification of friendship, or to bring it into being. For the symposium is a passing of time over wine that through gracious goodwill results in friendship.

‘Intensification’ (ἐπίτασις) requires that those at table already be friends; but for those who are not, the evening may inspire new relationships.Footnote 10 Hence the original ‘friend-making’ quality of the table is also twofold: to confirm existing friendships and to generate new ones.

None of this may seem remarkable at first blush. And yet, the declaration of the symposium as friend-forming generates certain opacities. Presented as the apparent condition of the symposium and one of its overriding aims, friendship as a concept for philosophical analysis is in fact scarcely addressed in Table Talk and never as an explicit subject among the symposiasts.Footnote 11 By contrast, Plato and Xenophon, both programmatically cited at the start of Table Talk (612D), devote attention in their Symposium texts to ideas of philia (albeit in connection with erōs rather than with how symposia foster philia).Footnote 12 Xenophon’s Socrates, for instance, offers a robust definition of τὸ φιλϵῖσθαι (Symp. 8.18) as part of his discourse on desire (8.1–42) and the superiority of ‘friendship of soul’ (τὴν τῆς ψυχῆς φιλίαν) to ‘enjoyment of the body’ (τὴν τοῦ σώματος χρῆσιν, 8.28).Footnote 13 While Table Talk, for its part, clearly situates itself within this sympotic literary tradition, its generic affinities are hardly predetermining: indeed, scholars have noted many differences between the Platonic-Xenophontic symposium and Table Talk, including the latter’s unusual amalgamation of sympotic, zetetic and miscellanistic forms.Footnote 14 Although its early allusion to the subject of friendship may recall the general ethical focus of Socratic sympotic conversation, Table Talk’s internal conversations do not take up the subject directly or make entirely clear how the symposium forges friendship. Nonetheless, since friendship is a topic on which Plutarch comments in other works and one of long-standing philosophical vintage, the reader may be prompted to examine its contours in Table Talk.Footnote 15 Already one may wonder how, for instance, Table Talk imagines friend-making to occur if attendees are supposed ab initio to be friends.Footnote 16 This issue is compounded by the potential presence of ‘shadows’, guests of guests, and similarly by the extent to which agreement is expected at the symposium, inasmuch as harmony is presented in Plutarch’s friendship treatises as a key component of companionship.Footnote 17 In short, we may ask whether and how the symposium’s conditions on these and other aspects of amity differ from those that Plutarch presents elsewhere.

That sympotic gatherings are associated in Greek literature with anxieties about falsehood, flattery and parasitism, all bad ingredients for friendship, only adds to these considerations.Footnote 18 Plutarch’s description of the ‘so-called’ (λϵγομένῳ, 612D) friend-making capacity of the symposiastic table may hint at this lineage.Footnote 19 Theognidean verse, for instance, invoked by Plutarch in On Having Many Friends (96F), represents at various junctures anxieties about the changeability of one’s drinking companions; it famously encourages imitation of the octopus for maintaining a mutable, ‘dappled disposition’ (ποικίλον ἦθος) in relation to fellow symposiasts (Thgn. 213–18 W).Footnote 20 In How to Tell a Flatterer from a Friend, Plutarch notes that hosts give ear to false friends (ever quick to book dinners: 64F) as soon as the hand-washing water is presented (50D), quoting Eupolis’ Flatterers on ‘friends from saucepan to just after dessert’ (54B). Concerns over flattery and superficiality probably help to explain Plutarch’s dismissal, in On Having Many Friends, of the faddish belief that just because people have shared a drink once, they can be called friends (De amicorum multitudine 94A). Thus, if Table Talk’s opening reference to friendship is traditional, so are worries about the meaning of sympotic comity.

Anxiety about friendship’s legibility at the symposium, where wine can cloud judgement and potentially produce false fellow feeling, lies behind Plutarch’s brother Lamprias’ comments at Table Talk 7.10 (715F):

τὸν δὲ δὴ φόβον οὐδϵνὸς ἧττον ἐμποδὼν ὄντα βουλϵυομένοις ἐξϵλαύνϵι, καὶ πολλὰ τῶν ἄλλων παθῶν ἀφιλότιμα καὶ ἀγϵννῆ κατασβέννυσι, καὶ τὸ κακόηθϵς καὶ τὸ ὕπουλον ὥσπϵρ τινὰς διπλόας ἀναπτύσσϵι τῆς ψυχῆς, καὶ παντὸς ἤθους καὶ πάθους ποιϵῖ καταφάνϵιαν ἐν τοῖς λόγοις.

Wine drives away the anxiety which is no small hindrance to those who deliberate, and it quells many other unseemly and sordid emotions. It discloses the malice and deceit concealed in the folds of the soul, as it were, and in speech it makes transparent every part of character and emotion.

Here the promise of the Plutarchan symposium is that the gathering exposes, rather than helps to conceal, bad character.Footnote 21 Yet even as one acknowledges some rosiness in Table Talk’s pedestalling of friendship as the party’s operative end, the optimistic energies cannot shed the murkier inheritance of symposiastic vigilance, intimated in the concern over the hidden feelings wrapped in the ‘folds of the soul’.Footnote 22 The positive possibilities framed by Lamprias have the effect of underscoring the very anxieties about sympotic amity they appear intended to dispel. The dinner party, as a zone of varied voices and views in which distraction, disagreement and multifariousness may predominate, would in fact seem to constitute an ambiguous site for forging friendship.

Uneasiness about sympotic friendship is moreover connected to another worry that bears on Table Talk and its representation of friend-making: namely, Plutarch’s ideas of variegation (poikilia) and multitude, concepts linked to both the kinds and number of people Plutarch thinks one should know. It may at first appear that a positive sense of variety applies to the symposium, much as positive valuations of the concept may describe variegated visual and literary phenomena.Footnote 23 Certainly, there is little surprise in discovering Plutarch’s repeated emphasis on variety in Table Talk.Footnote 24 He refers, for instance, to a ‘miscellaneous’ gathering (παντοδαπούς, 615D), a characterization that recurs in describing Callistratus’ tendency to ‘imitate Cimon among the ancients by giving pleasurable parties for many and diverse guests’ (ἐμιμϵῖτο τῶν παλαιῶν τὸν Κίμωνα πολλοὺς καὶ παντοδαποὺς ἑστιῶν ἡδέως, 667D). Plutarch’s mention of ‘highly diverse fare’ (αἱ τράπϵζαι ποικιλώτατοι, 667E) echoes this emphasis on social diversity. The poikilistic quality of Table Talk is also foregrounded in the recherché etymology Plutarch provides for skolion, moving in a ‘complicated and twisting’ (ποικίλον καὶ πολυκαμπές, 615C) manner, requiring many guests to contribute.Footnote 25

All the same, the very things (versatility, variety) figured as positive features, if not acclaimed virtues, of the diverse Table Talk might prompt thought of more ominous forms of versatility and variety. Recall that Plutarch uses the language of variety when characterizing the flatterer and false friend, notable in connection to the variegated symposium and its premise of friendship. The many-sided flatterer is ‘neither simple nor one’ (οὐχ ἁπλοῦς οὐδ’ ϵἷς, De adulatore et amico 52B) but ‘manifold and dappled’ (παντοδαπός … καὶ ποικίλος), a faker who ‘rearranges and reshapes himself’ (ῥυθμίζϵι καὶ σχηματίζϵι) as if composed of ‘some mouldable matter’ (ὥσπϵρ ὕλην τινά, 51C).Footnote 26 Relatedly, having a multitude of friends signifies an unstable and multifarious soul (De amicorum multitudine 97A–B):

As natural philosophers say of the shapeless, colourless substance and matter that are the underlying basis of everything, which of itself turns into everything, and is now fire, now liquid, then gas and then solid again, so in fact will there need to be, for the possession of many friends, an underlying basis of soul that is highly sensitive, multiform, supple and easily moved to change (πολυπαθῆ καὶ πολύτροπον καὶ ὑγρὰν καὶ ῥᾳδίαν μϵταβάλλϵιν).

If one’s character is multiple, the sameness (96E–F) sought in friendship will manifest in an unfortunate multiplicity of attachment.Footnote 27 The distractions of poluphilia hinder a deep sense of connection (95B), lead to absurd overcommitment (95C–D) and produce troubling forms of inattention (ἀμϵλϵῖα, 95D), all relevant concerns in the potentially distracting sympotic context, filled with various guests and possibilities for poluphilia.

One might instinctively parse the foregoing as differences between a (negatively figured) sense of a person’s dispositional variety and a (more positively figured) sense of symposiastic variety. But this would be to obscure the ways in which Plutarch himself, including in the above passage on poluphilia, blurs distinctions between internal and external, or between what one might call ethical poikilia, character that exhibits a variety of forms, and seemingly more innocuous forms of outward variety.Footnote 28 Plutarch at times links the aesthetic properties of things one encounters with the shaping of character, positing permeability between artefact and ēthos. In How to Study Poetry, for instance, he elaborates some of the ways in which uncritical engagement with literature can affect character. Plutarch at one point summons the octopus when conveying poetry’s potentially perilous variety (De audiendis poetis 15B–C):

‘Bad things lie within the head of the octopus; good dwells there also’ (πουλύποδος κϵφαλῇ ἔνι μὲν κακὸν ἐν δὲ καὶ ἐσθλόν) … Likewise, in the art of poetry, there is much that is pleasurable and nourishing for a young man’s mind, but equally as much that is disturbing and delusive if he listens to it without proper instruction.

The variety inherent to poetic content demands vigilance. At another point, Plutarch explicitly links poikilia with poetry’s capacity for deceitful, emotional persuasiveness (De audiendis poetis 25D):

ἄνϵυ δὲ τοῦ ἀληθοῦς μάλιστα μὲν ἡ ποιητικὴ τῷ ποικίλῳ χρῆται καὶ πολυτρόπῳ. τὸ γὰρ ἐμπαθὲς καὶ παράλογον καὶ ἀπροσδόκητον, ᾧ πλϵίστη μὲν ἔκπληξις ἕπϵται πλϵίστη δὲ χάρις, αἱ μϵταβολαὶ παρέχουσι τοῖς μύθοις· τὸ δ’ ἁπλοῦν ἀπαθὲς καὶ ἄμυθον.

But when it is split off from the truth, then above all does poetry make use of variety and a diversity of effects. Variations provide stories with emotional force, unlooked for and against our expectations, and with these variations come the greatest moments of astonishment and delight, whereas a simple narrative without variety is unemotional and not story-like.

Young readers must develop stability of character to withstand reading’s unpredictable motility. Nor are adults immune to variety: in On Affection for Offspring, Plutarch describes how humans grow to be ‘compounded of many viewpoints and serendipitous judgements’ (μιγνυμένη δόγματα καὶ κρίσϵις ἐπιθέτους) and their natures ‘become various’ (ποικίλη γέγονϵ, 493C). Finally, in On Having Many Friends, again after citing Theognis, Plutarch stresses that the octopus changes colour only externally; its alterations ‘lack depth’ (βάθος οὐκ ἔχουσιν, 96F). By contrast, the changes undertaken in adapting oneself to many friends are more consequential: ‘Friendships seek a complete likeness in character, emotion, word, practice and disposition’ (αἱ δὲ φιλίαι τὰ ἤθη ζητοῦσι συνϵξομοιοῦν καὶ τὰ πάθη καὶ τοὺς λόγους καὶ τὰ ἐπιτηδϵύματα καὶ τὰς διαθέσϵις, 97A). Poluphilia is a danger more coronary than cosmetic, as it were.

Returning, then, to the idea of sympotic friendship, one may be led to ask, upon recognizing how Plutarch moots the potential effects of various stimuli on character: what of listening in the context of the symposium? Are interlocutors not vulnerable to the parade of views on offer? How is the partygoer to withstand the possibly discombobulating conversational variety or the potential craftiness of a particular speaker? How should one maintain vigilance, amid bibulous repartee, sufficient to judge interlocutors’ character and suitability for friendship? In sum, although the idea of variety with reference to the symposium might seem positive, if not rudimentary, the surface poikilia and poluphilia of Table Talk become less anodyne when set in the context of Plutarch’s ideas elsewhere on character and friendship, variety and simplicity, external exposure and internal effect. Variety may be an aesthetic virtue, but it is not necessarily an ethical or social one.

As we shall see, Table Talk alludes to but also mollifies some of these concerns. Its discussions of social interactions and, in one exceptional case, of friendship directly (4 praef.) summon Plutarchan ideas of amity. Relatedly, its discussions of variety (social, gastronomic or otherwise) often only appear to concern the practical functioning of the symposium. For the engaged reader, conversations on variety and simplicity activate Plutarch’s wider moral universe, including his ideas on friendship. Certain discussions in Table Talk are thus potentially overdetermined in ways that make them about more than the pragmatics of conducting a party. Inasmuch as the text is populated by and intended for philosophers (8 praef., 716D–F), interlocutors and readers need not worry that they are being misled by shallow sophists.Footnote 29 But this also means that one should not write off apparently slight conversations as devoid of philosophical suggestiveness.

III. Reading the party

When Table Talk introduces the friend-making capacity of the dinner party, Plutarch’s readers, including Senecio, may believe they already have a sense of what friendship means from On Having Many Friends or How to Tell a Flatterer from a Friend. Although friendship is not directly taken up at length in its intra-diegetic party scenes, key topics from Plutarch’s friendship essays, including judgement, likeness and harmony, arise at various points in Table Talk.Footnote 30 Yet differences also emerge, helping readers to apprehend the nature of symposiastic friendship. The analogical potential of exchanges about seating arrangements, decoration or the fare on offer invites readers to compare seemingly superficial matters with deeper topics discussed in Plutarch’s corpus.Footnote 31 Plutarch hints at this analogical slippage himself (629D), as it is hard to maintain the putative distinction between narrowly ‘sympotic’ topics (συμποτικά) concerned with conducting the party and more expansive intellectual topics. Aspects of the former are inflected by the latter, and ‘both together’ (συναμφότϵρα) create the category of symposiastic discourse (συμποσιακά).

i. Judging variety (Quaest. conv. 1.2, 3.1, 3.2)

As stated in On Having Many Friends, judgement is of the utmost importance (κυριώτατον ἡ κρίσις, 94Β) to the process of making friends. An idea of social judgement comes up early in Table Talk, too, in the work’s second question (1.2).Footnote 32 Specifically: should the host, having judged different personalities among the guests, decide the seating arrangements or leave them up to invitees? At first the language of judgement refers to the argumentative orbit, but considerations soon turn to the issue of judging character type, recalling ideas familiar from Plutarch’s friendship treatises.Footnote 33 Plutarch’s self-effacing recusatio at Quaest. conv. 1.2 may be read as a programmatic clue to interpreting a work often taken to be polyvocal rather than consistently authoritative or dogmatic.Footnote 34 Plutarch says of his own role (616F): ‘After these arguments [on whether the host or guests should decide the seating arrangements] had been put forth and the present company were demanding a judgement, I said that, since I had been picked as mediator, not judge, I would take the middle way’ (ἐπϵὶ δὲ καὶ ταῦτ’ ἐρρήθη καὶ τὴν κρίσιν ἀπῄτουν οἱ παρόντϵς, ἔφην ἐγὼ διαιτητὴς ᾑρημένος οὐ κριτὴς βαδιϵῖσθαι διὰ μέσου, 616F). He goes on to state that it is not hard to make distinctions among guests (οὐ λίαν χαλϵπὸν ϵἶναι δοκϵῖ τὸ πϵρὶ τὴν διάκρισιν, 617D), a view taken up by his grandfather Lamprias, whose proposal for seating arrangements will both echo and alter some ideas of judgement familiar from Plutarch’s treatises.Footnote 35

Guests, Lamprias says, should be arranged not by rank or prestige but for the purpose of pleasure (618A). The guiding force should be consideration ‘not of the worthiness of each person but the relation and harmony of each to each, as is the case with other things that are pooled together for a common purpose’ (οὔτϵ τὴν ἑνὸς ἑκάστου σκοπϵῖν ἀξίαν ἀλλὰ τὴν ἑτέρου πρὸς ἕτϵρον σχέσιν καὶ ἁρμονίαν, ὥσπϵρ ἄλλων τινῶν ϵἰς μίαν κοινωνίαν παραλαμβανομένων, 618A). Lamprias’ goal of harmony, however, results in an unexpected strategy: the placing together of temperamental opposites (618D–619A). On the one hand, Lamprias voices anxiety at the disorder (ἀταξία) that may arise at a party, leading to ‘other unspeakable horrors’ (κακοῖς ἄλλοις ἀμυθήτοις, 618C). Yet on the analogy of builders, painters and shipwrights, whose different materials are ‘combined and fitted together’ (συντϵθέντα καὶ συναρμοσθέντα) to produce ‘the unified work’ (τὸ κοινὸν ἔργον) possessing strength, beauty and utility (618B), the party should create harmony through difference. Therefore, seating rich with rich, young with young or ‘friend with friend’ (φίλῳ φίλον) is ‘static and ineffectual for the heightening and creation of goodwill’ (ἀκίνητος γὰρ αὕτη καὶ ἀργὴ πρὸς ϵὐνοίας ἐπίδοσιν ἢ γένϵσιν ἡ τάξις, 618E). Rather, it is better to seat ‘the mild-mannered with the grumpy, the young (who like to listen) with the aged (who like to talk), the reserved with the loudmouth, the quiet with the snappy’ (δυσκόλῳ δὲ πρᾶον ἀδολέσχῳ δὲ πρϵσβύτῃ φιλήκοον νϵανίσκον τῷ δ’ ἀλαζόνι τὸν ϵἴρωνα τῷ δ’ ὀργίλῳ τὸν σιωπηλόν, 618E).

The proposed configuration muddles the homology of temperament Plutarch elsewhere imagines as a precondition for friendship.Footnote 36 Whereas in On Having Many Friends, he rejects the idea that friendship can arise between people of ‘differing characters’ (ἤθϵσι διαφόροις) and ‘unlike feelings’ (πάθϵσιν ἀνομοίοις, 96E–F), in Lamprias’ scenario, like shall not be seated with like: instead, assembled guests will be sorted by character type and offered provocation by those who differ from them, in what perhaps could be seen as a version of what Blanchot, discussing friendship, called ‘the interruption of being’.Footnote 37 Since it is necessary to judge disposition as a determining factor for balanced sociality, the ‘likeness’ (ὁμοιότης, 96E) of spirit called for in On Having Many Friends cannot obtain here from the start, if the party is already to be composed of people known to have different temperaments. Moreover, on Lamprias’ view a good gathering needs people of different types.Footnote 38 In his elaboration of seating arrangements he effectively advocates, and indeed assumes the requisite conditions for, a kind of social variousness. At 1.2 it is precisely a variety of guests, arranged so as to encounter persons unlike themselves, that becomes the basis for potential connection.

Lamprias’ analogy to shipwrights encourages the reader to think analogically in other places, too, and to read for moments in Table Talk that make good on Plutarch’s claim that the acme of true understanding is ‘to philosophize without seeming to philosophize’ (συνέσϵως ἄκρας φιλοσοφοῦντα μὴ δοκϵῖν φιλοσοφϵῖν, 614A). Subsequent conversations in fact intimate such parallels between ostensible topics of sympotic discourse and analogues in the social sphere. Consider Quaest. conv. 3.1, where a stray reference to variety in the decorative orbit carries potential analogical implications for social variety and the possibilities of sympotic poluphilia. The scene concerns whether garlands made of flowers rather than leaves should be used at drinking parties, conjuring the fraught relationship between poikilia and luxury, ornament and barbarism (646B). Ammonius hints at the danger of visual variety: the host Erato’s multicoloured flowery garlands (ποικίλων χρωμάτων καὶ ἀνθηρῶν, 645E) are evidence, he says, that although Erato supposedly spurns the chromatic scale in music, he ‘leads into our souls through eyes and nose, as if through other doors, the excess and luxury that he excludes through the ears, making the garland a matter of pleasure, not piety’ (τὴν διὰ τῶν ὤτων ἀποκλϵίϵι τρυφὴν καὶ ἡδυπάθϵιαν, ταύτην τὴν κατὰ τὰ ὄμματα καὶ κατὰ τὰς ῥῖνας ὥσπϵρ καθ’ ἑτέρας θύρας ἐπϵισάγων τῇ ψυχῇ καὶ τὸν στέφανον ἡδονῆς ποιῶν οὐκ ϵὐσϵβϵίας, 645E). Cosmetic colouration introduces the perils of ‘excess and luxury’. This recalls the issue of permeability discussed above (De audiendis poetis 15B–C; De amicorum multitudine 96F–97A), in which character may be affected by external forces, with explicit attention here to sensory perception that reaches the soul.

For his part, however, Erato offers an upbeat defence of the flowery wreaths and the ‘kaleidoscope of inimitable colours and complexions’ (ποικιλίαν δ’ ἀμιμήτοις χρώμασι καὶ βαφαῖς, 646D) that nature produces. Colouration is a natural delight (ἡδύ, 646D), which Erato distinguishes from the ‘deceitful raiment and tinctures’ (δολϵρὰ ϵἵματα καὶ χρίματα) of human manufacture. Nature, he argues, is a positive pleasure and therefore above suspicion, even when producing apparent luxury (646E). To the extent that it picks up on Plutarch’s scene-setting detail that ‘garlands of various sorts’ (παντοδαπῶν … στϵφάνων, 645D) had been distributed to the many guests (πλϵίονας ἑστιῶντος, 645D), Erato’s defence of variegated garlands indirectly reinforces the image of him as host of a variegated gathering. The reference to floral variety (646D), then, is only apparently superficial; it in fact adumbrates, in the context of a mixed gathering at which assorted garlands are distributed, a parallel between the dappled aesthetics of the party’s decorative scheme and the social characteristics of the diverse crowd. Ammonius’ worries about ‘excess and luxury’ are thus analogically allayed: the variegation of the garlands comes to stand not for ‘deceitful’ (δολϵρά) colouration but rather for a naturally occurring poikilia (646D) recapitulated by the presence of the party’s many guests.

This metaphorical blur between multicoloured garlands and social variety recurs in the scene immediately following (3.2).Footnote 39 In a conversation nominally focused on ivy (648B), readers are invited to connect the variegated garlands of 3.1 with the evening’s intellectual activity (similar to the way in which the description of skolion as intricate is made to refer to the party’s many contributors, 615B–C). At 3.2, Ammonius’ playful (μϵιδιῶν) reference to Trypho’s ‘dappled speech’ (ποικίλον … λόγον), ‘as though it were a garland’ (ὥσπϵρ στέφανον, 648B), draws an overt link between the ‘colourful’ talk of one guest, voiced among varied attendees, and the aforementioned variegated party garlands (648B ∼ 646D). The parallel not only brokers an artful transition between 3.1 and 3.2, but it also extends the idea of social poikilia. The work’s harmonics are such that synecdochic objects and speech from the party represent in discrete form the evening’s sundry components.Footnote 40 The negative associations of poikilia are recast in positive terms that reflect the tapestry of guests. Table Talk is again encouraging its readers to think connectedly.Footnote 41

Returning once more to 1.2, then: even if no ultimate mechanism exists within 1.2 to give a definitive imprimatur to Lamprias’ proposal, his argument posits a social configuration patently disjunctive to the presumed social arrangement that would arise were one to follow formal Plutarchan ideals on friendship in his essays. A structural elegance thus emerges in Lamprias’ offering his proposal after Plutarch has himself declined the role of judge, for the kind of variety called for creates social conditions that differ from those judged best by Plutarch elsewhere. The discernment required for determining friendship in On Having Many Friends is softened. The quality of sameness would impede both Lamprias’ diverse gathering and the variegated party that Erato throws at 3.1, where the garlands themselves reflect the mixed company in their different hues.

ii. Redefining friendship (Quaest. conv. 4 praef.)

Plutarch’s curbed authority at Quaest. conv. 1.2, and the seeming vindication of social variety at 3.1–2, may be programmatic, then, not only for the diverse atmosphere of Table Talk but also for how readers should situate the Plutarch of Table Talk in relation to Plutarch the author outside this particular text. In fact, several books on, in Table Talk’s most explicit discussion of friendship, Plutarch presents the chance to rethink the definition one might derive from other places in his corpus and to consider it anew in the sympotic circumstance. The preface to book 4, although iterated outside the symposium proper, nonetheless shows the Plutarch of Table Talk hailing a flexible idea of amity that differs from his treatises on friendship.

Plutarch begins the preface by citing Polybius’ advice to Scipio Africanus never to return from the marketplace without having befriended a fellow citizen (659F). The counsel seems to offer a neat parallel: much like Polybius to Scipio, so does the Greek Plutarch now advise the Roman Senecio, the advisory act itself an index of amity.Footnote 42 But Plutarch uses the story somewhat against expectation. He exhorts Senecio to avoid rigid interpretation of the word ‘friend’ when contemplating the anecdote (659F): ‘We must avoid taking the word “friend” rigorously and pedantically (πικρῶς μηδὲ σοφιστικῶς) to mean the unchanging steadfast sort (τὸν ἀμϵτάπτωτον καὶ βέβαιον), but rather take it broadly (κοινῶς) to mean any person of goodwill (τὸν ϵὔνουν)’. Plutarch here recalls but also contravenes his own advice in On Having Many Friends, where only the person of steadfast character (βέβαιον ἦθος, 97B) can be the true friend, and where friendship depends on rigorous discernment. Senecio is advised, in effect, to reconsider some of Plutarch’s own definitions. To be sure, Plutarch does not excise earlier concepts wholesale: he still advises Senecio to make friends only with the good (660A) and remarks that friendship takes time (χρόνῳ πολλῷ, 659F), in line with tenets of On Having Many Friends. By refocusing matters on goodwill (ϵὔνοια), however, Plutarch isolates the essential ingredient of friendship while eschewing more restricted definitions of its contours.Footnote 43 The overture to a loosened definition, Plutarch’s moderating for Senecio ideas searchable elsewhere in ‘Plutarch’, is itself an act of intellectual goodwill on Plutarch’s part that intimates the spirit with which one ought to approach the party.Footnote 44

The direct relevance of the anecdote becomes clear a few lines later, in a passage that happens to clarify some lingering quandaries from the text’s opening sections (612D and 621C, quoted above). Plutarch now states that Polybius’ advice is applicable not only to the forum but also to the symposium (660A–B):

ἀλλ’ ὅρα τὸ τῆς παραινέσϵως, ϵἰ μὴ μόνον ἔχϵι δϵξιῶς πρὸς ἀγορὰν ἀλλὰ καὶ πρὸς συμπόσιον, ὥστϵ δϵῖν μὴ πρότϵρον ἀναλύϵιν ἢ κτήσασθαί τινα τῶν συγκατακϵιμένων καὶ παρόντων ϵὔνουν ἑαυτῷ καὶ φίλον. ϵἰς ἀγορὰν μὲν γὰρ ἐμβάλλουσι πραγμάτων ϵἵνϵκϵν καὶ χρϵιῶν ἑτέρων, ϵἰς δὲ συμπόσιον οἵ γϵ νοῦν ἔχοντϵς ἀφικνοῦνται κτησόμϵνοι φίλους οὐχ ἧττον ἢ τοὺς ὄντας ϵὐφρανοῦντϵς. διότι τῶν μὲν ἄλλων ζητϵῖν ἐκφορὰν ἀνϵλϵύθϵρον ἂν ϵἴη καὶ φορτικόν, τὸ δὲ φίλων πλέον ἔχοντας ἀπιέναι καὶ ἡδὺ καὶ σϵμνόν ἐστιν.

But consider whether you think the advice from Polybius appropriate not only in the public square but also at dinner: namely, one should not let a party wind down before acquiring for himself a new friend and well-wisher among the other diners and attendees. On some errand or other task people hurry into the marketplace, but they attend a party, if they are thinking about it the right way, as much to acquire new friends as to delight those whom they already count as friends. To the extent that it would be boorish and unsophisticated to want to carry off anything else, it is both a pleasing thing and a point of pride to come away with a bonus to one’s circle of friends.

This passage appears to pick up on some of the questions prompted by the work’s opening claims to friend-making, especially with regard to the assumption that the invitees should already be friends. Such is not the case, it would seem, if Plutarch views the party’s purpose as ‘acquiring friends’ (κτησόμϵνοι φίλους) no less than giving pleasure to those who already are (οὐχ ἧττον ἢ τοὺς ὄντας ϵὐφρανοῦντϵς). The reference to the marketplace recalls the initial advice from Polybius but also a rather different point that Plutarch makes in On Having Many Friends, where he states that we do not simply become friends with someone by ‘collecting them in the marketplace’ (ἀγορᾶς φιλίαν συλλέγουσιν, 94A). The surplus of friends (φίλων πλέον) in particular presents a clear change from the strictures of the friendship treatise, in which multitude signifies an undesirably multifaceted character (97A–B, above). In the preface to Table Talk book 4, then, Plutarch dials down the definition of philos, enabling a notion of acceptable sympotic poluphilia. If the symposium is a site of potentially anxious amity, Plutarch puts Senecio at ease, suggesting that abstract Plutarchan ideas of friendship can be reformulated for commensal reality.

Now, one could argue that the purpose of Table Talk is fundamentally different from Plutarch’s friendship essays, which explore the topic in a didactic manner. On this view, we should not expect the same authoritative pronouncements from the sympotic work as from a moral essay. This is perhaps especially so with regard to Table Talk, which presents a complicated oscillation between Plutarch’s assertiveness and self-effacement, part of its complex reworking of the sympotic role played by Socrates.Footnote 45 At the same time, Table Talk does aim to offer philosophical instruction.Footnote 46 Plutarch’s representation of himself as capable of being ‘taught’ (as at 1.2) or as reworking definitions (as at 4 praef.) helps to reinforce the necessarily dialogic, communal nature of the intellectual endeavour.Footnote 47 The dialogue is not confined to intra-diegetic characters but extends outwards to Plutarch’s engagement with his reader, who may well turn to other parts of Plutarch’s corpus in interpreting aspects of Table Talk. The fact, then, that Plutarch in the book 4 preface raises and reformulates the concept of ‘friend’ in ways that depart from his own pronouncements elsewhere implies that differences of genre cannot necessarily be taken for granted. Plutarch reformulates the definition not strictly because the generic context is different; he does so to show how that context works. The preface to book 4 amounts to an authoritative pronouncement, to be sure, but one that also authorizes Senecio’s (or any reader’s) capacity to read actively, even if it means reading Plutarch ‘against’ Plutarch.Footnote 48 If the protocols of genre were entirely obvious, Plutarch might not feel compelled to initiate Senecio’s adjustment for differences. Instead, by implicitly inviting comparison with his other statements, Plutarch not only authorizes that friendship can mean different things in different contexts, but he also performs Table Talk’s adaptive mode of knowledge: his encouragement of Senecio’s intellectual flexibility on the subject of (re)defining ‘friend’ enacts the very refining of viewpoint to which polyphonic, sympotic conversation might well lead.

For all that, Plutarch’s modified definition is not without ambiguity. He recasts sympotic friendship as ‘goodwill’, but it remains unclear how goodwill in the sympotic context should be assessed. If goodwill is found, for instance, in those who do not disagree, then what of the temperamental opposite with whom one might be seated, should Lamprias have his way (1.2)? One idea of goodwill is inherent in the disposition of the right-minded guest, who when focused on the aim of friendship overcomes the base desires of the flatterer and parasite (4 praef., 660B):

καὶ τοὐναντίον ὁ τούτου παραμϵλῶν ἄχαριν αὑτῷ καὶ ἀτϵλῆ τὴν συνουσίαν ποιϵῖ καὶ ἄπϵισι τῇ γαστρὶ σύνδϵιπνος οὐ τῇ ψυχῇ γϵγονώς· ὁ γὰρ σύνδϵιπνος οὐκ ὄψου καὶ οἴνου καὶ τραγημάτων μόνον, ἀλλὰ καὶ λόγων κοινωνὸς ἥκϵι καὶ παιδιᾶς καὶ φιλοφροσύνης ϵἰς ϵὔνοιαν τϵλϵυτώσης.

Contrariwise, anyone who does not take care to make a friend renders the social event incomplete and ungratifying. He leaves having feasted with his stomach but not his mind. The true guest comes to share not only food, wine and dessert, but also as a companion to conversation, fun and the amiability that culminates in goodwill.

Rendering the social occasion ‘incomplete’ (ἀτϵλῆ) recalls the language of purpose from early in Table Talk about the ends of the sympotic gathering (τέλος, 621C). A mere attendee is philosophically irresponsible, thwarting the party’s purpose and making his own experience less delightful (ἄχαριν), having attended only in body and not in spirit, much like the parasite who is a ‘body of all belly’ (De adulatore et amico 54B).Footnote 49 The company is more important than the food. Plutarch implies that the true σύνδϵιπνος comes for both physical and mental sustenance as a ‘companion in conversation’ (λόγων κοινωνός) and intellectual play as well as, crucially, a companion on the trajectory of goodwill (ϵἰς ϵὔνοιαν), which serves the larger aim of all involved in expanding the circle of amity (τὸ δὲ φίλων πλέον).

Before moving to the scene at 4.1, which I suggest continues the themes of the preface to book 4, I wish to note how Plutarch drives home his closing prefatory detail that ‘wine mixed with conversation provides a point of contact for the holds of friendship’ (ταῖς δὲ φιλικαῖς λαβαῖς ὁ οἶνος ἁφὴν ἐνδίδωσι μιγνύμϵνος λόγῳ, 660B). Already in the friendship treatises Plutarch’s analogies of ‘mixing’ and ‘blending’ interrelate friendship with food and drink.Footnote 50 He closes the preface to book 4 with comments on wine’s contribution to the symposium’s desired sociality (660C): ‘For conversation, by means of wine, disperses its capacities for humane feeling and character formation from the body into the soul and spreads it about thoroughly’ (λόγος γὰρ αὐτῷ τὸ φιλάνθρωπον καὶ ἠθοποιὸν ἐπὶ τὴν ψυχὴν ἐκ τοῦ σώματος ἐποχϵτϵύϵι καὶ συνδιαδίδωσιν, 660C).Footnote 51 Key is the ‘mixing’ of wine with conversation, the very blending that applies by analogy to the mixing of company proposed by the work. While party talk (συμποτικός λόγος) moderates the effects of alcohol by ‘not allowing the drinkers to be completely carried away by the wine’ (οὐκ ἐᾷ διαφορϵῖσθαι παντάπασιν ὑπὸ τοῦ οἴνου τοὺς πίνοντας, 660C), wine ‘makes the company pliable and ready to take an impression, as it were, from the seal of friendship’ (καθάπϵρ σφραγῖδι φιλίας ϵὐτυπώτων καὶ ἁπαλῶν διὰ τὸν οἶνον ὄντων, 660C). On this claim, wine softens the company and readies it for minting, in a metaphor similar to that by which Theognis expressed worry over the ‘counterfeit’ man (κιβδήλου, 117 W). The interplay of conversation and wine, much as the work had earlier proposed an interaction of different forces (Quaest. conv. 618D–619A), produces a meaningful evening. Based on this image, readers may continue to sense the ways in which other discussions of food and drink reflect on the social dynamics at play.

iii. Harmony through diversity (Quaest. conv. 4.1)

In the scene immediately following, Plutarch’s looser definition of friendship and thoughts on sympotic harmony are analogically extended, during an exchange in which images of gastronomic, intellectual and social variety continue to converge. The fundamental contrast between the variegated and the simple recurs, and in light of the ethical resonances of these concepts described earlier, I suggest that discussion of such matters at 4.1 implicates larger concerns of social relation.

The scene nominally considers whether a varied diet (ποικίλη τροφή) is more easily digested than a simple one (τῆς ἁπλῆς). Set in the home of Philo the physician, the conversation is prompted by the ‘robust’ (νϵανικός) feast he has provided. After a preliminary exchange between Philo and Plutarch, in which the latter notes that despite the ‘fancy and costly provisions’ (τὰ πϵριττὰ καὶ πολυτϵλῆ, 660E) Philo has neglected to set out ‘basic staples’ (τῶν ἀναγκαίων καὶ χρησίμων, 660E), discussion turns to the merits of simple and elaborate eating. Philinus reminds the company of the host Philo’s own previously stated views: ‘We have more than once heard you say that simple fare is more digestible than fancy variety’ (σοῦ πολλάκις ἀκηκοότϵς ὅτι τῶν ποικίλων τὰ ἁπλᾶ μᾶλλον ϵὔπϵπτ’ ἐστίν, 661A). Meanwhile Marcion, contending that Philinus’ austere views might scare off the guests, proposes to make an argument in favour of ‘mixed food’ (ποικίλην τροφήν, 661A), thereby ensuring that Philo’s guests can enjoy the offerings. Philo, we are told, takes Marcion up on his offer, while Philinus is deputed to give the argument in favour of simplicity (661A).

Already from this opening setup we may conclude that Philo is willing, in the context of his own party, to compromise on the view he has often (πολλάκις) put forward at other times, by now hearing an argument in favour of variety if it has the potential to gladden his guests. The practicalities of the symposium induce adjustment of tenets, now echoing intra-diegetically what we have just read in Plutarch’s prefatory advice to Senecio to recalibrate his definition of friendship. There Plutarch in effect had encouraged an openness to social variety; the scene at 4.1 in turn includes an apparently unaccustomed view in favour of culinary potpourri that by its conclusion will also conjure parallels with social variety.

At the start of his speech in favour of simplicity, Philinus reminds his listeners that the argument is really not his own, but rather should be thought of as Philo’s (οὐκ ἐμός … ὁ μῦθος, 661B), thereby underscoring for his listeners how the eventual claim (from Marcion) in favour of mixed fare contradicts the host Philo’s usual perspective. Philinus justifies simple fare through comparisons to animals, who do better on a simple diet (661B), and the ill, who should stick to staples as per doctors’ orders (661B). When divergent foods come together, Philinus asserts, they resist each other; he adduces the danger of mixing wines, too, commenting both indirectly and overtly on social issues: ‘Change and lack of regularity are unsettling … Persuasion and assent are more effectively obtained by conflicting views than by different types of food’ (ἐκστατικὸν γὰρ ἡ μϵταβολὴ καὶ τὸ ἀνώμαλον … μᾶλλον ἂν ἐκ λόγων ὑπϵναντίων γένοιτ’ ἂν πίστις καὶ συγκατάθϵσις ἢ πέψις ἐκ διαφόρων ποιοτήτων, 661D). The interlocutor’s point is one of contrast, but the reader will find it difficult, on the heels of the book’s preface on friendship, to miss the analogy between the social variety discussed there and the questions raised in 4.1 about gastronomic variety. Moreover, given that Philinus is deputed to offer what is in essence the ‘losing’ argument of this scene, his attempted separation of intellectual variety and mixed cuisine collapses: the argument favouring many foods will be given the last word, thus echoing with reference to food the implicit argument of 4 praef. favouring multitude (of friends).

In light of Philinus’ final point that harmony cannot be achieved by different types of drink but is achievable through ‘conflicting viewpoints’ (λόγων ὑπϵναντίων), it is notable, and indeed mimetic of the idea aired, that the opposed view offered next by Marcion, supposedly representing the counter-argument, in fact affirms Philinus’ statement. The scene thus creates through ‘conflicting views’ a kind of harmony. Insofar as Table Talk often concerns seemingly minor topics (for example, the relationship between lightning strikes and truffles (4.2); why firs and pines are not grafted (2.6); whether it is necessary to strain wine (6.7), etc.), its setting would appear vulnerable to the pettifogging that Plutarch describes in How to Tell a Flatterer from a Friend (see 59B–74E), in which false friends offer cheap bits of frankness of little consequence. Yet, as we have seen, apparently trivial matters in Table Talk have a way, through analogy, of allowing the text to comment on more serious issues. In this case, opposed discussants end up both endorsing and enacting disquisitional variety, creating unexpected harmony or argumentative echo through difference, in their discussion of gastronomic variety, all following on an authorial preface advocating a sort of social variety. Indeed, after making the point that the purpose of digestion is to effect change (μϵταβάλλϵιν τὴν τροφήν, 663B), Marcion says, ‘Like is not moved by like. It is instead opposition and difference (ἀντίταξις καὶ διαφορά) that through the mixing of opposites (τῇ πρὸς τὸ ἐναντίον μίξϵι) expel certain qualities and cause them to dissipate’ (663B).Footnote 52 In effect, although ostensibly staging an opposed set of views (for and against variety), the two speakers end up advancing similar claims about harmony as achieved through difference. For Philinus, opposed views produce harmony (661D), and for Marcion the mixing of opposites has a salutary effect (663B). Varied fare and varied discourse fold into each other, strengthening the sense that a variety of friends and views is needed to produce the desired intellectual atmosphere.

In fact, following the apparent conclusion of Marcion’s argument in favour of variety, he adds a dig at the advocates of a ‘salt-and-bean’ diet, close friends who proverbially show up even if all one offers is a feast of legumes (663F–664A):Footnote 53

You partisans of ‘salt and beans’ have somehow missed the fact that variety is more pleasant, and the more pleasant is more appetising (ὅτι τὸ μὲν ποικίλον ἥδιόν ἐστι, τὸ δ’ ἥδιον ϵὐορϵκτότϵρον), and the more appetising is healthier, so long as you remove surplus and excess … But these things [i.e. various condiments and sauces] are superfluities and frivolities (πϵρίϵργα καὶ σπϵρμολογικά).

This comparison ties the discussion directly to the social realm and points up the analogies I have been delineating. The very term ‘salt-and-bean’ endorses a brand of social exclusivity among persons whose genuine amicability is proved through virtuous disregard for fancy food. Marcion’s snipe is not, however, merely about a paltry meal. The shape of his argument up to this point implies that close friends who come over repeatedly, no matter the meal, not only miss the fact that culinary ‘variety is more pleasant’, but also that their repeated presence hinders social variety, and thus the potential to arrive at intellectual harmony through the presentation of opposed viewpoints.Footnote 54 On this understanding, intimacy among a constricted ‘focus group’ of friends is anathema to the symposium. Marcion’s argument, uttered in Philo’s home following his dappled repast (τὰ παντοδαπὰ ταῦτα καὶ ποικίλα, 661E), is not gainsaid by the end of 4.1. Instead, openness to a variety of foods, viewpoints and, through the analogous dismissal of salt-and-bean friends, to sympotic poluphilia is the preferred attitude at this juncture in Table Talk. As in the wider work, so in this episode does an idea of variety win out.

IV. The shadow knows (Quaest. conv. 7.6)

The final vignette I wish to examine, from the latter portion of the work, gathers together several of the concerns I have described throughout this paper while also introducing a new element. The scene reveals how dinners, if not always serving deeper friendship, nonetheless may engender incipient acquaintanceship, although not necessarily for the host. As such, the discussion shows how Plutarch’s ideal of the friend-making table may support a broad-minded notion of who is to do the friend-making.

The topic is shadows, secondary guests not directly invited. After a speech by Caesernius against allowing such people to appear, not knowing if they will be ‘graceful company’ (χαρίϵντϵς, 707D), Plutarch takes up their defence. Ideally, the host should anticipate who the shadows might be and issue pre-emptive, ‘rather friendly’ (φιλικώτϵρον) invitations (708B):

μϵίζων γὰρ ἡ τιμὴ καὶ ἡ χάρις, ὡς μὴ λανθάνοντος ὅτι τούτους ἀσπάζϵται μάλιστα καὶ τούτοις ἥδιστα σύνϵστι καὶ χαίρϵι τιμώμϵνοις ὁμοίως καὶ παρακαλουμένοις.

It is a greater honour and favour to our guest when it does not elude us that these [i.e. anticipated shadows] are the persons to whom he most cleaves and in whose company he takes the greatest pleasure, and whom he celebrates seeing honoured equally, invited along with him.

The accent falls less on the symposiarch’s accruing new intimates and more on his providing an atmosphere of social fertility for others. Plutarch says that it is vulgar (φορτικόν) to ask what food or wine someone enjoys, but neither ‘offensive nor out of place’ (οὐκ ἀηδὲς οὐδ ἄτοπον) to let invitees bring friends: doing so allows guests to be rather jovial (ϵὐφραίνϵται … μάλιστα, 708D).

Plutarch’s defence of shadows relies on the view that allowing guests to bring their friends offers a stay against randomness: ‘Guests must not be left to chance (οὐ τοὺς τυχόντας), but must be friends and intimates of one another (προσφιλϵῖς … καὶ συνήθϵις ἀλλήλοις) who take pleasure in getting together’ (708D). This urge against randomness recalls On Having Many Friends, where readers are encouraged to avoid ‘chance acquaintances’ (τοῖς ἐντυγχάνουσι, 94E). It also echoes comments from Table Talk 645F–646A, where Ammonius draws an analogy between the ‘natural’ pleasures of food (akin, he says, to guests of guests) and a disordered appetite (akin to uninvited guests). Plutarch likewise invokes a gastronomic analogy, but to unexpected effect (708D):

Cooks concoct their meals from different flavours (ἐκ χυμῶν διαφόρων) … but there would not be a positive and mutually delightful dinner arising from people unlike in their background and sympathies being melded together into the same group (μὴ ὁμοφύλων μὴδ’ ὁμοιοπαθῶν ϵἰς τὸ αὐτὸ συμφθαρέντων).

It now appears that the variety presumed at 1.2 (seating the unlike together) and 3.1 (where the ornate garlands reflect the varied company) is rejected. Consequently, the possibilities of new acquaintanceship are diminished, if in the effort to curb randomness the unlike are not to be present at all.

Yet Plutarch accords an important role to the shadow, who must exercise, he says, ‘ample discretion’ (πλϵίστης ϵὐλαβϵίας, 709C). Even if it must be allowed that their judgement will at times foster the randomness Plutarch seemingly wishes to avoid, he states that, among other considerations, it is up to the shadow to assess whether the invitee wants ‘there to be friendship between themselves and the main host and whether the host is a good person (χρηστόν) who is worthy of friendship’ (φιλίας ἄξιον, 709D). The shadow must also judge whether the host is likely to view him as a ‘starting point for friendship’ (φιλίας … ἀρχήν, 709E). In short, Plutarch’s argument admits that there are occasions when the host must cede invitational control to his friend: ‘There are times when we must let him decide’ (ἔστιν ὅτϵ ποιητέον ἐπ’ αὐτῷ, 708C). Flexibility extends down the social ladder. Even as Plutarch wishes to check randomness (708D), his argument ultimately leaves the door open to chance social surprise.

Just as Plutarch suggests (De audiendis poetis 25C–D) that poikilia in poetry can generate effects of surprise and emotional astonishment that hold the listener’s attention, so, too, might the potential surprise of the shadow’s contribution enliven the intellectual poikilia of the symposium. The role of judgement, programmatically complicated by the conversation at 1.2, returns here, only to be devolved to the shadows, based on their perception of the social potential of the gathering. Contrasting all of this with Plutarch’s comment that ‘topics of conversation, no less than our friends, should be permitted at dinner only if they have passed examination’ (ὅθϵν ἄξιόν ἐστι μηδὲν ἧττον λόγους ἢ φίλους δϵδοκιμασμένους παραλαμβάνϵιν ἐπὶ τὰ δϵῖπνα, 697E), one senses an unresolved tension. The latitude permitted the shadow exists primarily in the judgement required to shape the social dynamics of the dinner in the first place, the wishes of the host notwithstanding. Rather than the host’s judging among friends, the friend’s friend may now judge the host. The scene at 7.6 imagines the possible convergence of different poikilistic energies, with the unknown shadow heightening the potentially random quality of the dinner party, a notion itself contained by a text that is in tension with other Plutarchan ideas. In line with the sense that Table Talk is a reader-involving work, in which analogy between internal guest and external readerly ‘participant’ avails itself, the shadow functions as a further analogue for the reader and reiterates the aleatory surprises of setting Plutarch’s miscellany against other parts of his corpus.

V. Conclusion

Table Talk textualizes the fluctuations of sympotic conversation into the ‘aesthetics of the unexpected’.Footnote 55 Readers grapple with its changes in subject and perspective and are afforded opportunity to read the work in relation (harmonious, disjunctive or otherwise) to other parts of Plutarch’s oeuvre. In a work that invites readers to mirror the discussants in puzzling through problems, inconsistencies within Plutarch’s text and in relation to his other works act as provocations. Plutarch’s own non-sameness becomes a form of philosophical poikilia, jostling readers to reflection. By implicitly revisiting and sometimes challenging views from On Having Many Friends and How to Tell a Flatterer from a Friend that favour a more rigorous sociality, Table Talk encourages readers both to engage with Plutarch’s corpus and to exercise the intellectual flexibility that is a hallmark of the dialogic Table Talk. We have observed how ideas of friendship in the work, the fostering of which is among the symposium’s purposes, often sit at odds with more ‘formal’ Plutarchan treatments of the topic. We have also seen how the text’s discussions of variety on seemingly pragmatic topics (how to seat people, what kinds of garlands to have, what types of food to serve) are tinged with philosophical concerns, activating indirectly or by analogy questions about the value of social poikilia and sympotic poluphilia. The work elucidates a positive notion of variousness, social and intellectual, against the wider backdrop of variety’s potential complications. Plutarch reveals, especially in the preface to book 4, a contextual willingness to recast his ‘own’ criteria for friendship and amicable variety, a gesture that not only marks the complex interplay of his narratorial authority and humility but also models for readers the pliant thinking that the give-and-take of sympotic exchange should kindle.

If, finally, friendship offers, in Blanchot’s phrase, an ‘interruption of being’, an interruption of one’s own sense of completeness and correctness, we might say that sympotic thinking serves friend-making precisely in its capacity for provisionality, ‘interruption’ and reformulation. Indeed, at a fundamental level, the proposed seating of temperamental opposites or the admission of ‘shadows’ indicates an openness to alterity. Plutarch’s looser notion of friendship in Table Talk thus well suits the sympotic occasion, in which different viewpoints are likely to challenge one’s sense of certitude. A looser sociality is of a piece with the work’s indeterminateness and with allowing someone the necessary room and place (χώρα καὶ τόπος, Quaest. conv. 678E) to be an ‘other’ (De amicorum multitudine 93E), or even just someone else’s friend.

Acknowledgements

I thank Douglas Cairns, Lin Foxhall and the two anonymous reviewers for JHS for their improving comments. My thanks as well to the Washington, DC, audience of the International Plutarch Society panel at the 2020 meeting of the Society for Classical Studies, especially Zoe Stamatopoulou and Jeffrey Beneker.

Footnotes

1 On the Quaestiones conuiuales’ coherence, see König (Reference König, König and Whitmarsh2007) 44–45; Klotz and Oikonomopoulou (Reference Klotz, Oikonomopoulou, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011b) 26–27. On its blend of dialogue, philosophy and miscellany, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou (Reference Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011a). On the once-dominant tendency towards fragmented reading of Plutarch, Güthenke (Reference Güthenke, North and Mack2018) 184–85.

2 See Klotz (Reference Klotz2011) 164–65 (‘social ποικιλία’, p. 165). Further: Teodorsson (Reference Teodorsson1989–1996) 1.55–56; König (Reference König, König and Whitmarsh2007) 56; König (Reference König and Goldhill2009) 90; Titchener (Reference Titchener, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011) 48; König (Reference König2012) 70–71.

3 For the probable late date of Table Talk (ca. 99–116 CE), giving it a potentially retrospective angle, see Jones (Reference Jones1966) 72–73; Jones (Reference Jones1971) 137; Klotz and Oikonomopoulou (Reference Klotz, Oikonomopoulou, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011b) 4. Cf. Pelling (Reference Pelling2011) 207 n.3. On the relative chronology of Plutarch’s friendship texts, Helmbold (Reference Helmbold1939) 245; Jones (Reference Jones1966) 70–72.

4 The reader is in some sense invited to mirror the hallmark quality of Plutarch’s own flexibility (on which see Harrison (Reference Harrison1991) 4664–65; Eshleman (Reference Eshleman2013) 164).

5 On the work’s narratological complexity, wherein the ‘voice of Plutarch’s older self edits the words of the younger “Plutarch”’, see Klotz (Reference Klotz2011) 167. On Plutarch as author and internal persona, Kechagia (Reference Kechagia, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011) 78–79 n.4; Pelling (Reference Pelling2011) 229–31; Hobden (Reference Hobden2013) 231–32; Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 176–77.

6 On Senecio, see Wardman (Reference Wardman1974) 39; Duff (Reference Duff1999) 288–89; Pelling (Reference Pelling2011) 208. Senecio’s status as recipient of Table Talk, Progress in Virtue and Parallel Lives neatly encapsulates different aspects of Plutarch’s corpus: miscellany, moral essay, biography.

7 On 612D, see König (Reference König, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011) 190–92. Plutarch’s Greek texts are from the Loeb Classical Library, unless otherwise stated; translations are my own.

8 On memory’s philosophical implications, see Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 177–78.

9 Compare Conv. sept. sap. 156C–D, 158C, with Romeri (Reference Romeri2002) 172–76; Hunter (Reference Hunter2018) 105–06.

11 On the topics appropriate to the Plutarchan banquet, see Gonzàlez Julià (Reference Gonzàlez Julià2009) 67.

12 See, for instance, Eryximachus’ conclusion that erōs enables friendly feeling (ὁμιλϵῖν καὶ φίλους ϵἶναι) among humans and between humans and gods (Pl. Symp. 188d8–9). On the ethical focus of sympotic literature, Hobden (Reference Hobden2013) 213; Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 173.

13 Socrates’ definition of eroticized friendship includes genial conversation (ϵὐνοϊκῶς δὲ διαλέγϵσθαι), mutual trust (πιστϵύϵιν δὲ καὶ πιστϵύϵσθαι) and common support in fortune good and bad (8.18). See also Xen. Symp. 8.12–15, 25.

15 For Plutarch’s views on friendship and its philosophical background, see O’Neil (Reference O’Neil1997); Van der Stockt (Reference Van der Stockt, Roskam and Van der Stockt2011).

16 See Stadter (Reference Stadter, Ribeiro Ferreira, Leão, Tröster and Barata Dias2009) = (2015) 109–10. Compare Agathon’s command (Pl. Symp. 212d1) to admit a guest if he is ‘one of our friends’ (τις τῶν ἐπιτηδϵίων).

17 See De amicorum multitudine 96E–F, with below. On shadows, see section IV below.

18 See Whitmarsh (Reference Whitmarsh, Konstan and Saïd2006) on flattery; Hobden (Reference Hobden2013) 157–58 on deceit.

19 On the use of focalizing verbs at Quaest. conv. 1 praef. and 1.1, see Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 179.

20 See Neer (Reference Neer2002) 14–23; Whitmarsh (Reference Whitmarsh, Konstan and Saïd2006) 98–101. Cf. Thgn. 1071–74 W.

21 See, however, Quaest. conv. 645B on not raising subjects that might reveal others’ flaws, with Stadter (Reference Stadter, Montes Cala, Sánchez Ortiz de Landaluce and Gallé Cejudo1999) = (2015) 102. On the symposium’s revelation of character in Plutarch’s Lives, see Titchener (Reference Titchener1999) 496–99. On wine as producing either fellow feeling or enmity, compare Conv. sept. sap. 149C, 156D–E.

22 Cf. Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 194 on Maximus of Tyre’s denunciation of symposia as unbecoming for virtuous men (Orationes 25.6a).

23 On variety as an aesthetic good, see Briand (Reference Briand, Skoie and Bjørnstad-Velázquez2006) 43–44; Nünlist (Reference Nünlist2009) 198–201; Klotz and Oikonomopoulou (Reference Klotz, Oikonomopoulou, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011b) 23; Bevegni (Reference Bevegni2014) 321. Cf. [Plut.] De liberis educandis 7C: ‘Variety is delightful’ (ἡ δὲ ποικιλία τϵρπνόν). Compare Grand-Clément (Reference Grand-Clément, Destrée and Murray2015) 415.

24 Compare Oikonomopoulou (Reference Oikonomopoulou, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011) 109 on polymathy.

25 On the skolion as ‘emblematic’ of social interaction: Klotz (Reference Klotz2007) 653.

26 See Konstan (Reference Konstan1997) 100.

27 See Russell (Reference Russell1973) 94 on poluphilia as a ‘symptom of inconstant character’; Wardman (Reference Wardman1974) 137 on virtue’s consistency.

28 On poikilia and character, see Detienne and Vernant (Reference Detienne and Vernant1991) 18–20 regarding Odysseus; Briand (Reference Briand, Skoie and Bjørnstad-Velázquez2006) 44. On variety as inspiring a multitude of responses, from acclamation to anxiety, see Fitzgerald (Reference Fitzgerald2016) 7.

30 See Stadter (Reference Stadter, Montes Cala, Sánchez Ortiz de Landaluce and Gallé Cejudo1999) = (2015) 101 on the ‘problem’ of ‘proper proportion or blend’.

31 My focus on friendship’s and variety’s value is not meant to foreclose other possible subjects that intra-diegetic scenes may activate by analogy, such as the well-ordered soul or cosmic harmony.

32 On social arrangement in the scene, see Van der Stockt (Reference Van der Stockt, Stadter and Van der Stockt2002) 122–25; Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 182–85. Cf. Conv. sept. sap. 149B.

33 See De amicorum multitudine on discerning likeness and not regarding a friend as ‘other’ (ὡς ἕτϵρον, 93E), effected through a long period (πολλῷ χρόνῳ, 94F) of determining similarity of souls (96E–F). See further De adulatore et amico 51B, with Russell (Reference Russell1973) 93–96; Van der Stockt (Reference Van der Stockt, Roskam and Van der Stockt2011) 28–36.

34 On Plutarch’s alternating roles in the text as a ‘didactic figure’ and as ‘someone who can learn’ (171), see Klotz (Reference Klotz2011) 167–78; also König (Reference König, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011) 191–95. Cf. Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 186–91 on Plutarch’s ‘predominance’.

35 Note the jocular tone of Lamprias’ asking permission to ‘rebuke a judge [sc. Plutarch] who is talking mumbo-jumbo’ (νουθϵτῆσαι ληροῦντα δικαστήν, Quaest. conv. 617F), adding to the sense in which Plutarch is upstaged in this scene; see Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 183.

36 See De amicorum multitudine 96D–97B, with Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 184–85 on ‘reconfigurations of Plutarch’s moralizing input’.

37 See Critchley (Reference Critchley1998) 266–67.

38 Cf. Eshleman (Reference Eshleman2012) 22 n.5 on tensions between the ‘competing ideals’ of symposiastic heterogeneity and sociocultural homogeneity.

39 Titchener (Reference Titchener, Ribeiro Ferreira, Leão, Tröster and Barata Dias2009) 396 n.2 cites Quaest. conv. 3.1–.2 as among several scenes that are connected dramatically.

40 Compare De esu 994D on a courtroom argument packed with ‘many and varied emotions’ (πάθϵσι πολλοῖς … παντοδαποῖς), suited to the listeners’ ‘many different sorts of minds’ (ϵἰς ψυχάς … πολλὰς καὶ ποικίλας).

42 On Senecio as epitomizing companionship between Greek intellectuals and Roman elite, see Pelling (Reference Pelling2011) 208–09. See also Hobden (Reference Hobden2013) 234.

43 On ϵὔνοια, see De amicorum multitudine 93F with O’Neil (Reference O’Neil1997) 113–14.

44 See Xenophontos (Reference Xenophontos2016) 186 on Plutarch’s role in Table Talk in service of his readers’ ‘ethical well-being’.

45 See Brenk (Reference Brenk2009) 52; Klotz (Reference Klotz2011) 168–71. Cf. Hobden (Reference Hobden2013) 233–34 on Plutarch’s ‘authorial self-staging’ (234) in ‘meta-Sympotic’ (229) relation to predecessors.

46 Klotz (Reference Klotz2007) 656–59; Kechagia (Reference Kechagia, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011) 78–81 on Platonic, Xenophontic and Aristotelian forms.

47 See König (Reference König, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011) 194, 202–03.

48 See Titchener (Reference Titchener, Klotz and Oikonomopoulou2011) 44–45 on recall and comparison; Hobden (Reference Hobden2013) 232 on Plutarch’s ‘creatively develop[ing] appropriate new perspectives … for the reader to think his way through’.

49 See 7 praef. (697C), where Plutarch distinguishes between basic bodily nourishment and the richer fare of social interaction.

50 Compare De adulatore et amico 94D and Quaest. conv. 661B, 661E, with below; see κρᾶσις at De adulatore et amico 95B.

51 Interpretation is difficult: Hubert corrects to συνδιαδίδωσιν from T’s καὶ ἐν δίδωσιν, which would allow conversation to ‘contribute to’ wine’s effect (Clement and Hoffleit (Reference Clement and Hoffleit1969) 293). See Teodorsson (Reference Teodorsson1989–1996) 2.16 ad loc. (reading καὶ ἐν δίδωσιν).

52 This viewpoint on balanced opposites sets Marcion up for an argument in favour of moderation (663D), making good on Lamprias’ plan for achieving harmony through the joining up of opposite personalities (Quaest. conv. 1.2).

53 See Quaest. conv. 5.10 (684E–F), where Apollophanes says the phrase refers to ‘friends of such intimacy as to dine even on salt and beans with us’ (οὕτω συνήθϵις … τῶν φίλων, ὥστϵ καὶ πρὸς ἅλα δϵιπνϵῖν καὶ κύαμον). There is another slightly different definition (De amicorum multitudine 94A; De frat. amor. 482B): ‘salt-and-bean’ friends are those who have proved themselves true by sharing so many meals as to build up the proverbial ‘bushel of salt’. Even if one follows the latter idea, an idea of exclusivity obtains.

54 See Stadter (Reference Stadter, Ribeiro Ferreira, Leão, Tröster and Barata Dias2009) = (2015) 112–13 on the text’s preference for cross-talk over ‘shop-talk’.

55 Bevegni (Reference Bevegni2014) 329 (‘l’estetica dell’inatteso’).

References

Bevegni, C. (2014) ‘Osservazioni sul motivo della poikilia nella letteratura miscellanea greca di età imperiale e bizantina’, Paideia 69, 317–31Google Scholar
Brenk, F. (2009) ‘“In learned conversation”: Plutarch’s symposiac literature and the elusive authorial voice’, in J. Ribeiro Ferreira, D. Leão, M. Tröster and P. Barata Dias (eds), Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch (Coimbra) 51–61Google Scholar
Briand, M. (2006) ‘Aesthetics and ethics of poikilia in Longus’ Daphnis and Chloe ’, in Skoie, M. and Bjørnstad-Velázquez, S. (eds), Pastoral and the Humanities: Arcadia Re-Inscribed (Exeter) 4252 Google Scholar
Clement, P.A. and Hoffleit, H.B. (eds) (1969) Plutarch Moralia VIII (Cambridge MA)Google Scholar
Critchley, S. (1998) ‘The other’s decision in me (what are the politics of friendship?)’, European Journal of Social Theory 1, 259–79Google Scholar
Detienne, M. and Vernant, J.-P. (1991) Cunning Intelligence in Greek Culture and Society (tr. J. Lloyd) (Chicago)Google Scholar
Duff, T. (1999) Plutarch’s Lives: Exploring Virtue and Vice (Oxford)Google Scholar
Eshleman, K. (2012) The Social World of Intellectuals in the Roman Empire: Sophists, Philosophers, and Christians (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Eshleman, K. (2013) ‘“Then our symposium becomes a grammar school”: grammarians in Plutarch’s Table Talk ’, SyllClass 24, 145–71Google Scholar
Fitzgerald, W. (2016) Variety: The Life of a Roman Concept (Chicago)Google Scholar
Gonzàlez Julià, Ll. (2009) ‘Plutarch’s techne rhetorike for the symposium in Quaestiones convivales: the importance of speaking well to cultivate friendship’, in J. Ribeiro Ferreira, D. Leão, M. Tröster and P. Barata Dias (eds), Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch (Coimbra) 63–74Google Scholar
Grand-Clément, A. (2015) ‘ Poikilia ’, in Destrée, P. and Murray, P. (eds), A Companion to Ancient Aesthetics (Malden MA) 406–21Google Scholar
Güthenke, C. (2018) ‘After exemplarity: a map of Plutarchan scholarship’, in North, J. and Mack, P. (eds), The Afterlife of Plutarch (London) 179–91Google Scholar
Harrison, G. (1991) ‘The critical trends in scholarship on the non-philosophical works in Plutarch’s Moralia’, ANRW 2.33.6, 4646–81Google Scholar
Helmbold, W.C. (ed.) (1939) Plutarch Moralia VI (Cambridge MA)Google Scholar
Hobden, F. (2013) The Symposion in Ancient Greek Society and Thought (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Hunter, R.L. (2018) The Measure of Homer: The Ancient Reception of the Iliad and the Odyssey (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Jones, C.P. (1966) ‘Towards a chronology of Plutarch’s works’, JRS 56, 6174 Google Scholar
Jones, C.P. (1971) Plutarch and Rome (Oxford)Google Scholar
Kechagia, E. (2011) ‘Philosophy in Plutarch’s Table Talk: in jest or in earnest?’, in Klotz, F. and Oikonomopoulou, K. (eds), The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford) 77104 Google Scholar
Klotz, F. (2007) ‘Portraits of the philosopher: Plutarch’s self-presentation in the Quaestiones convivales ’, CQ 57, 650–67Google Scholar
Klotz, F. (2011) ‘Imagining the past: Plutarch’s play with time’, in F. Klotz and K. Oikonomopoulou (eds), The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford) 161–78Google Scholar
Klotz, F. and Oikonomopoulou, K. (eds) (2011a) The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford)Google Scholar
Klotz, F. and Oikonomopoulou, K. (2011b) ‘Introduction’, in Klotz, F. and Oikonomopoulou, K. (eds), The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford) 131 Google Scholar
König, J. (2007) ‘Fragmentation and coherence in Plutarch’s Sympotic Questions ’, in König, J. and Whitmarsh, T. (eds), Ordering Knowledge in the Roman Empire (Cambridge) 4368 Google Scholar
König, J. (2009) ‘Sympotic dialogue in the first to fifth centuries CE’, in Goldhill, S. (ed.), The End of Dialogue in Antiquity (Cambridge) 85113 Google Scholar
König, J. (2011) ‘Self–promotion and self-effacement in Plutarch’s Table Talk ’, in Klotz, F. and Oikonomopoulou, K. (eds), The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford) 179203 Google Scholar
König, J. (2012) Saints and Symposiasts: The Literature of Food and the Symposium in Greco-Roman and Early Christian Culture (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Konstan, D. (1997) Friendship in the Classical World (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Morgan, T. (2011) ‘The miscellany and Plutarch’, in Klotz, F. and Oikonomopoulou, K. (eds), The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford) 4973 Google Scholar
Neer, R.T. (2002) Style and Politics in Athenian Vase-Painting: The Craft of Democracy, ca. 530–460 BCE (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Nünlist, R. (2009) The Ancient Critic at Work: Terms and Concepts of Literary Criticism in Greek Scholia (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Oikonomopoulou, K. (2011) ‘Peripatetic knowledge in Plutarch’s Table Talk ’, in Klotz, F. and Oikonomopoulou, K. (eds), The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford) 105–30Google Scholar
O’Neil, E. (1997) ‘Plutarch on friendship’, in J.T. Fitzgerald (ed.), Greco-Roman Perspectives on Friendship (Atlanta) 105–22Google Scholar
Pelling, C. (2011) ‘Putting the -viv- into “convivial”: the Table Talk and the Lives’, in F. Klotz and K. Oikonomopoulou (eds), The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford) 207–31Google Scholar
Romeri, L. (2002) Philosophes entre mots et mets (Grenoble)Google Scholar
Russell, D.A. (1973) Plutarch (London)Google Scholar
Schmitz, T. (2012) ‘Sophistic philotimia in Plutarch’, in Roskam, G., de Pourcq, M. and Van der Stockt, L. (eds), The Lash of Ambition: Plutarch, Imperial Greek Literature and the Dynamics of Philotimia (Louvain) 6984 Google Scholar
Stadter, P. (1999) ‘Drinking, Table Talk, and Plutarch’s contemporaries’, in Montes Cala, J.G., Sánchez Ortiz de Landaluce, M. and Gallé Cejudo, R.J. (eds), Plutarco, Dioniso y el Vino: Actas del VI Simposio español sobre Plutarco (Madrid) 481–90 = (2015) Plutarch and His Roman Readers (Oxford) 98107 Google Scholar
Stadter, P. (2009) ‘Leading the party, leading the city: the symposiarch as politikos ’, in Ribeiro Ferreira, J., Leão, D., Tröster, M. and Barata Dias, P. (eds), Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch (Coimbra) 123–30 = (2015) Plutarch and His Roman Readers (Oxford) 108–15Google Scholar
Teodorsson, S.-T. (1989–1996) A Commentary on Plutarch’s Table Talks (3 vols) (Gothenburg)Google Scholar
Teodorsson, S.-T. (2009) ‘The place of Plutarch in the literary genre of symposium ’, in Ribeiro Ferreira, J., Leão, D., Tröster, M. and Barata Dias, P. (eds), Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch (Coimbra) 318 Google Scholar
Titchener, F. (1999) ‘Everything to do with Dionysus: banquets in Plutarch’s Lives’, in J.G. Montes Cala, M. Sánchez Ortiz de Landaluce and R.J. Gallé Cejudo (eds), Plutarco, Dioniso y el Vino: Actas del VI Simposio español sobre Plutarco (Madrid) 491–99Google Scholar
Titchener, F. (2009) ‘The role of reality in Plutarch’s Quaestiones conviviales ’, in Ribeiro Ferreira, J., Leão, D., Tröster, M. and Barata Dias, P. (eds), Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch (Coimbra) 395401 Google Scholar
Titchener, F. (2011) ‘Plutarch’s Table Talk: sampling a rich blend: a survey of scholarly appraisal’, in Klotz, F. and Oikonomopoulou, K. (eds), The Philosopher’s Banquet: Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire (Oxford) 3548 Google Scholar
Van der Stockt, L. (2002) ‘Kαρπὸς ἐκ φιλίας ἡγϵμονικῆς (Mor. 814C): Plutarch’s observations on the “old-boy network”’, in Stadter, P. and Van der Stockt, L. (eds), Sage and Emperor: Plutarch, Greek Intellectuals, and Roman Power in the Time of Trajan (98–117 AD) (Leuven) 115–40Google Scholar
Van der Stockt, L. (2011) ‘ Semper duo, numquam tres? Plutarch’s Popularphilosophie on friendship and virtue in On Having Many Friends ’, in Roskam, G. and Van der Stockt, L. (eds), Virtues for the People: Aspects of Plutarchan Ethics (Leuven) 1939 Google Scholar
Wardman, A. (1974) Plutarch’s Lives (London)Google Scholar
Whitmarsh, T. (2006) ‘The sincerest form of imitation: Plutarch on flattery’, in Konstan, D. and Saïd, S. (eds), Greeks on Greekness: Viewing the Greek Past under the Roman Empire (Cambridge) 93111 Google Scholar
Xenophontos, S. (2016) Ethical Education in Plutarch: Moralising Agents and Contexts (Berlin) Google Scholar