Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T12:00:05.542Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Formal and informal institutions: some problems of meaning, impact, and interaction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2025

Geoffrey M. Hodgson*
Affiliation:
International Management, Loughborough University London, London, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Taking inspiration from the work of Douglass North, much institutional research attempts a distinction between ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ institutions. North often associated ‘formal institutions’ with rules enforced through a legal system. It is suggested here that this lead should be followed and refined. In which case ‘legal system’ and ‘law’ require definitions. An alternative claim, that ‘formal’ basically means ‘written down’, is arguably less useful. Stressing the importance of clear definitions in this area, this paper considers a case where slight modifications yield strikingly different results. Some options concerning the meanings of ‘culture’ and their relation to institutions are briefly noted. Changes in, and interactions between, ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ institutions are considered, with illustrative examples. Contrary to some authors, informal institutions can sometimes change rapidly, in some cases in response to state legislation.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Millennium Economics Ltd.

Introduction

It is commonly accepted that institutions are important. In recent decades, discussion over the impacts of ‘formal’ versus ‘informal’ institutions has increased. Unfortunately, while a near-consensus has emerged over the meaning of the term ‘institution’ – understood as a system of socially embedded rules and norms (see Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2019, and the appendix to this article) – the terms ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ are often undefined or used loosely. As Belay Seyoum (Reference Seyoum2011: 917) noted: ‘The term “informal institutions” has been used to describe a diverse set of practices … thus leading to a serious conceptual ambiguity.’ Among contrasting usages, ‘formal institution’ may refer to rule systems that are (a) written, (b) designed, or (c) made up of laws. These options are very different. But many, including Nobel Laureate Douglass North, have regarded a ‘formal’ rule as (potentially) enforceable in law. That is a tenable option, if there is an acceptable common understanding of the meaning of law.

Matters of definition are different from questions of analysis or causality. Further, identifying formal rules and institutions does not mean that informal rules are less important. Informal rules often play a vital role in the enforcement of legal rules. Law itself is sometimes ineffective: there can be law without order. And all societies sustain some order that does not rely on law.

‘Formal’ and ‘informal’ institutions are often said to have different impacts on economic development and wellbeing, including in less-developed countries. Questions arise about their respective roles, their mutual interactions, and their empirical measurement. Without a consensus on the meaning of these terms, deeper analysis is more difficult and effective policy design is impaired. In an important essay on formal institutions in a leading development journal, Mark Casson et al. (Reference Casson, Della Giusta and Kambhampati2010: 138) identified several limitations in ‘the existing literature on institutions and development’ including its failure to ‘precisely define the respective roles of formal and informal institutions in development processes’. The measurement of informal institutions is also tricky (Voigt, Reference Voigt2018). Without adequate definitional agreement, empirical progress will be impaired.

The next section examines definitions of ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ rules and institutions in the literature. It shows that ‘formal’ is often used to refer to rules or institutions (potentially) enforced by a legal system. It highlights some problems in interpreting ‘formal’ as ‘written down’. The third section considers why these issues are important, particularly for matters of economic development. The fourth section stresses the value of a clear definitional distinction between ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ institutions, especially when making empirical claims about their relative impacts. The fifth section considers the concept of culture and discusses the meaning of law. The sixth section considers possible ways in which formal and informal institutions interact. There are cases where legislative (formal) and other changes have caused rapid cultural (informal) change. The seventh section concludes the essay.

What are formal and informal institutions?

Searches were conducted on the JSTOR database for the term ‘formal institution’.Footnote 1 There are a few appearances in the 19th century. Many are unclear about the meaning of ‘formal’. Sometimes ‘institution’ appeared as a verb. Before 1950 the term ‘formal institution’ (or its plural) is infrequent in articles in English on the JSTOR database, with only 81 journal articles in which it appeared. ‘Informal institution’ (or its plural) appears in only five articles.

Moving on, from 1950 to 1999 inclusive, the term ‘formal institution’ appeared in 2,446 articles and ‘informal institution’ appeared in 570 articles. Usage of both terms increased dramatically thereafter. So far in the present century, the term ‘formal institution’ has appeared in 5,558 articles and ‘informal institution’ has appeared in 3,057 articles. Both terms appear in 1,693 articles. Academic discussion of ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ institutions is largely a 21st century phenomenon. But many works fail to propose a clear definition of the formal/informal distinction.

From about 1989, North made frequent use of the terms ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ in an institutional context. His work was a major stimulus behind the 21st century explosion in the usage of these terms. But his terminology raises questions as well as providing some answers. North wrote mostly of ‘informal constraints’ and sometimes of ‘informal norms’. He typically deployed the word ‘formal’ in ‘formal rules’ and ‘formal institutions’.Footnote 2 Why did he associate the word ‘formal’ with rules and ‘informal’ with constraints? North (Reference North1990: 3–4) indicated that constraints are the broader category. He did not claim that constraints and rules are mutually exclusive. This might suggest that many constraints are not rules. On the contrary, constraints typically serve as rules and many rules are constraints. ‘No trespassing’ is both a rule and a constraint. Constraints can be enabling. Rules that constrain drivers to keep on one side of the road help drivers to reach their destinations safely. North's reasons for associating ‘formal’ with ‘rules’ and ‘informal’ with ‘constraints’ are unclear (Voigt and Kiwit, Reference Voigt, Kiwit and Giersch1998: 87 n.). His distinction between ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ institutions has nothing fundamentally to do with any difference between ‘rules’ and ‘constraints’. It would have been better if he had not added further terminological complications.

Once North (Reference North1990: 46) saw the ‘difference between informal and formal constraints’ as ‘one of degree’. He envisaged ‘a continuum from taboos, customs, and traditions at one end to written constitutions at the other … from unwritten traditions and customs to written laws’. As far as I am aware, North did not continue with this ‘continuum’ idea. While we need not propose a continuum, definitional demarcations are rarely sharp. Fuzziness and boundary cases exist.

North (Reference North1991: 97; Reference North1994: 360; Reference North, Drobak and Nye1997: 6) gave examples of ‘informal constraints’ as sanctions, taboos, customs, traditions, conventions, codes of conduct, and norms of behaviour. He saw ‘formal rules’ as ‘constitutions, laws, property rights’.Footnote 3 North (Reference North1992: 4) similarly wrote that institutions are ‘composed of formal rules (statute law, common law, regulations)’ alongside ‘informal constraints conventions, norms of behavior’. Hence, for North, the term ‘formal’ is typically linked with legal matters. He never defined ‘formal’ pre-eminently as ‘written’, and he frequently linked ‘formal’ with legal enforcement.

In correspondence with the present author, North (Reference North2002) clarified his position. He wrote: ‘Formal rules are enforced by courts and things like that. Informal norms are enforced usually by your peers or others who impose costs on you if you do not live up to them.’ Here he focused on the means of enforcement. The key criterion to demarcate the formal from the informal is whether, respectively, there is enforcement by a legal court (or something like it), or enforcement without such an institution. If North had said this more clearly at the outset it would have saved some confusion.

For the philosopher and institutional analyst Chrys Mantzavinos (Reference Mantzavinos2001: 83–4), as for North and others, formal institutions are enforced by law, whereas informal institutions ‘do not need for their enforcement the state’. This is helpful, but some clarification is required. Some laws, such as driving on the same side of the road, are largely self-enforcing, and require state enforcement in exceptional cases only. Many laws are followed because people accept their moral validity. Consequently, formal rules should be defined in terms of potential, and not necessarily actual, enforcement by the state. Crucially, formal rules are potentially enforceable by the state, including some that are often self-enforcing.

There are frequent cases where laws are enforced by institutions that are not part of the state legal system. Unestablished religious institutions may enforce marriage laws. Private companies may enforce employment laws. And so on. By reasonable definition, if they are laws and the state is potentially involved as an enforcer of last resort, these rules remain formal. Otherwise they are informal.

At the start, North (Reference North1989a: 239; Reference North1993: 20) emphasised that ‘formal rules … must be complemented by informal constraints … that supplement them and reduce enforcement costs’. He added: ‘If the formal rules and informal constraints are inconsistent with each other the resulting tension is going to induce political instability.’ Consequently, he wrote of ‘complementary’ versus ‘competing’ formal–informal relationships.

The political scientists Gretchen Helmke and Steven Levitsky (Reference Helmke and Levitsky2004) also stressed the importance of ‘informal institutions’. They classified forms of interaction between the formal and informal. Working in two dimensions, they (p. 728) considered ‘the degree to which formal and informal institutional outcomes converge’. They asked whether following informal rules produces a similar or different result from that following a strict adherence to formal rules. When the outcomes ‘are not substantively different, formal and informal institutions converge’. Otherwise, divergence occurs. ‘The second dimension is the effectiveness of the relevant formal institutions, that is, the extent to which rules and procedures that exist on paper are enforced and complied with in practice. … Where formal rules and procedures are ineffective, actors believe the probability of enforcement (and hence the expected cost of violation) will be low.’ Hence they created a taxonomy of formal–informal interactions. With convergent outcomes and ‘effective formal institutions’ the formal–informal relationship is ‘complementary’. With convergent outcomes and ‘ineffective formal institutions’ the relationship is ‘substitutive’. With divergent outcomes and ‘effective formal institutions’ the relationship is ‘accommodating’. With divergent outcomes and ‘ineffective formal institutions’ the relationship is ‘competing’. Hence, they usefully distinguish between complementary, accommodating, competing, and substitutive relations.

Helmke and Levitsky (Reference Helmke and Levitsky2004: 727, emphasis in original) wrote:

We define informal institutions as socially shared rules, usually unwritten, that are created, communicated, and enforced outside of officially sanctioned channels. By contrast, formal institutions are rules and procedures that are created, communicated, and enforced through channels widely accepted as official. This includes state institutions (courts, legislatures, bureaucracies) and state-enforced rules (constitutions, laws, regulations), but also … the official rules that govern organizations such as corporations, political parties, and interest groups.

This is a thoughtful attempt to define informal and formal institutions. But it has some defects. First, taxonomic definitions should be parsimonious. It would be advisable to remove the words ‘usually unwritten’. Many informal rules are written down, such as in books on the rules of language, etiquette, and table manners. The words ‘usually unwritten’ are redundant and potentially misleading. Second, ‘officially sanctioned channels’ is too vague. Language is widely regarded as an institution (e.g., Searle, Reference Searle1995, Reference Searle2005). Arguably, it is best regarded as informal too. But state agencies often attempt to interfere with languages in various ways. In all countries, official policies favour one or more languages over others, in their administrative and education systems. In some countries (such as France) official attempts have been made to exclude some words, promote others, and to regularise spellings. The imperial Chinese state imposed the Mandarin language and a single writing system on a linguistically diverse population (Scheidel, Reference Scheidel2019: 312). Do these official interventions make all these rules formal? If so, then ‘formal’ rules become much more widespread. ‘Officially sanctioned’ is best removed from the definition of ‘formal’. With these modifications, the Helmke and Levitsky definitions become closer to those inspired by North, where ‘formal’ means ‘legal’ and ‘informal’ means ‘non-legal’.Footnote 4

As English dictionaries reveal, the word ‘formal’ has many meanings. These include ‘ceremonial’, ‘official’, ‘proper’, and so on, as well as ‘lawful’. It can mean ‘explicit’, but this does not necessarily imply ‘written’. With writers on institutional research, particularly because of the impact of North, the association of ‘formal’ with law is stronger. But this legal issue is often muddied by the addition of other terms.

Given the many meanings of ‘formal’, we cannot in this case refer to a single, prominent usage for the purpose of definition. Features like ‘written’ or ‘explicit’ have no obvious precedence over ‘legal’ as the defined meaning of ‘formal’. North did more than anyone to establish the formal/informal distinction in modern institutional analysis. He largely associated ‘formal’ with ‘legal’. Given his influence, any plea to change these meanings is unlikely to be successful.

It would be best to follow the example of North and others, and to link the ‘formal’ with the legal, and not necessarily with the written. Consequently, informal rules are rules that are not laws. Another option would be to define formal rules as both ‘legal’ and ‘written’. But the ‘legal’ part of the definition would be doing most of the work of demarcation. A great number of written rules are not laws, and they would remain ‘informal’. Some early legal systems, in which laws were unwritten, would be pushed out, but that would do no great harm in the modern context. Adding ‘written’ to the definition of ‘formal’ unnecessarily complicates the picture, without adding any demarcatory value.

The North-inspired definition of the formal/informal distinction does not rule out important subdivisions within each category. For example, some informal rules are against the law, while others are not. Informal rules differ greatly in their modes enforcement, in their strictness, and whether they are written or unwritten. Some formal rules are often ignored. Others are followed with diligence. Some formal rules have high moral salience. Others are matters of mere convenience or convention. Countless subdivisions are possible, and some of these may be useful.

Some important implications

Henceforth in this paper we associate ‘formal’ with law and potential legal enforcement. Informal (i.e., non-legal) rules are not laws, and are enforced apart from the legal system (somehow defined). Non-legal is not the same as illegal. Informal rules, being non-legal, may or may not comply with the law. Hence we need to distinguish between at least two kinds of informal institution or rule – between those that comply with the law and those that are illegal.

The prevalence of illegal informal rules is likely to be greater if the (formal) system of law is corrupt, or otherwise less effective (Keefer and Shirley, Reference Keefer, Shirley and Ménard2000). Sometimes, informal rules substitute for ineffective formal rules. It is widely recognised that problems of poor governance and corruption are especially severe in less-developed countries. Businesses may evade registration, taxation, safety standards, employment laws, and so on. This is sometimes referred to as the ‘shadow economy’ or the ‘informal economy’ (Gërxhani, Reference Gërxhani2004; OECD, 2002; Schneider and Enste, Reference Schneider and Enste2000).

Klarita Gërxhani and Stanisław Cichocki (Reference Gërxhani and Cichocki2023: 657) argued that ‘a proper functioning of the economy needs the formal and informal institutions to be complementary and well enforced’. As Gërxhani and Cichocki accepted, the idea that formal and informal institutions should be complementary and ‘well enforced’ would be problematic and questionable if many informal rules were harmful or illegal. If they were, the strengthening and enforcement of informal rules could act against or undermine the power of formal (legal) rules.

Earlier, Gërxhani (Reference Gërxhani2004: 294) reported that ‘there is a general agreement that, in the long run, the informal sector should be reduced in size or formalized’. This suggests a reduction of illegality in the ‘informal sector’. Since then there may have been a shift of opinion among development researchers. In their introduction to a forum on African ‘informal economies’, Kate Meagher and Ilda Lindell (Reference Meagher and Lindell2013: 58) reported that ‘informal economic activity has burgeoned across the developing world, particularly in Africa’. Efforts to limit the informal sector have largely failed.Footnote 5 In response, policymaking efforts have shifted ‘away from an emphasis on eliminating or absorbing the informal economy toward policy discourses of collaborative interaction, expressed in such terms as “hybrid governance,” “coproduction,” and “formal-informal linkages”’. The focus has become ‘the politics of inclusion’ whereby ‘informal’ (and often illegal) activities are seen in part as an understandable response to state failure. With the maxim of ‘inclusion’, the illegal is tolerated under cloak of the ‘informal’. This is important not simply because of moral qualms about illegality. It is also crucial for non-normative reasons. Since Max Weber, the perceived legitimacy of legal rules has been seen as crucial for their support. While in small-scale customary groups, legitimation may derive from local arrangements (Murtazashvili and Murtazashvili, Reference Murtazashvili and Murtazashvili2016); a large ‘informal’ sector may lack the mores and ideology to cultivate appropriate perceptions of legitimacy. In which case, toleration of an expanding informal sector (harbouring illegal activity) may exacerbate the problem of (partial) state failure.

Several authors have noted the importance of state capacity, including fiscal capacity, alongside appropriate constraints on the executive (Bardhan, Reference Bardhan2016; Besley and Persson, Reference Besley and Persson2011; Ogilvie, Reference Ogilvie2022; Ricciuti et al. Reference Ricciuti, Savoia and Sen2019; Savoia and Sen, Reference Savoia and Sen2023). Tolerating the illegal as part of the ‘informal’ may run against the enhancement of those elements of state capacity required to help promote economic development.

It is far beyond the scope of the present essay to assess the possibility of Africa or elsewhere finding a new path to economic development that dispenses with the need to build an effective system of state administration, involving higher standards of governance, politico-legal checks and balances, and the comprehensive rule of law (Waldron, Reference Waldron, Zalta and Nodelman2023). If that were achieved, it would be unprecedented. The point here is that narratives dominated by ‘informality’ and ‘inclusion’ may sidestep key questions of precedence and feasibility. How can a state function effectively while it accepts widespread illegality? Such toleration would heighten systematic corruption. The question is raised here, but it is not answered. We note simply that the loose rhetoric of ‘informality’ may push this issue into the background. It needs to be addressed more squarely.

The importance of a good definition of formal institutions

We turn to work by economists Claudia R. Williamson and Carrie B. Kerekes on formal and informal institutions, where they assess the differential impacts of these two main types of rule system (Williamson, Reference Williamson2009; Williamson and Kerekes, Reference Williamson and Kerekes2011). Williamson and Kerekes (Reference Williamson and Kerekes2011: 546) wrote: ‘Informal institutions are those rules that shape human behavior but are outside of government and are not part of a written legal framework.’ Their statements conform to the Northian view that informal rules are, by definition, non-legal in character. Williamson (Reference Williamson2009: 372) wrote: ‘Formal institutions are defined on political constraints on government behaviour enforced by legal institutions. Formal rules encompass constitutional constraints, statutory rules, and other political constraints.’ Williamson and Kerekes (Reference Williamson and Kerekes2011: 538) wrote similarly: ‘We define formal institutions as political constraints on government behavior and informal institutions as private constraints, such as norms or customs.’ These statements narrow considerably the meaning of ‘formal institutions’ to laws that constrain government.

Their modification of the formal/informal dichotomy had a major impact on the empirical design and results of their two studies. Williamson and Kerekes drew in part from the work of Edward L. Glaeser et al. (Reference Glaeser, La Porta and Lopez-De-Silanes2004) who also focused on political institutions that constrain governments. But Glaeser et al. (Reference Glaeser, La Porta and Lopez-De-Silanes2004) did not distinguish between ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ institutions. Their concern instead was to assess whether higher levels of education lead to democracy and other constraints on government, or whether there is stronger causation in the opposite direction. This is an important issue, but it is much narrower in scope than trying to assess the general differential impact of formal versus informal institutions. Williamson (Reference Williamson2009: 374) and Williamson and Kerekes (Reference Williamson and Kerekes2011: 545) took four types of formally constituted constraints on government from Glaeser et al. (Reference Glaeser, La Porta and Lopez-De-Silanes2004), namely ‘plurality, proportional representation, judicial independence, and constitutional review’. Williamson and Kerekes used these criteria to assess the strength of formal institutions. The strengths of informal institutions in each country were assessed in terms of cultural traits, including levels of trust. Accordingly, they developed indicative measures of the strengths of formal and informal institutions.

Williamson (Reference Williamson2009) compared her measure of the strength of formal institutions with GDP per capita (purchasing power parity) for the year 2000. The dependent variable in Williamson and Kerekes (Reference Williamson and Kerekes2011) is different – it concerns property rights. For reasons of brevity, I concentrate here on the GDP per capita analysis. Figure 1 displays the Williamson and Kerekes measure of the strength of formal institutions, plotted against levels of GDP per capita, as explored by Williamson (Reference Williamson2009) in 38 countries.

Figure 1. GDP per capita and the strength of ‘formal institutions’.

Data source: Williamson (Reference Williamson2009).

Six countries are within the ellipse at the top left of Figure 1, indicating high levels of GDP per capita and low estimated levels of the strength of formal institutions. These countries are the Netherlands plus the Nordic nations of Denmark, Finland, Iceland, Norway, and Sweden. Nine countries are located within the long, dashed oblong, with rounded corners, at the bottom of the figure. They all have low levels of development but vary enormously in the reported strength of their formal institutions. They are, moving from the left, Nigeria, Egypt, Jordan, Indonesia, and Bangladesh, followed by four clustered far to the right, namely Pakistan, Philippines, Uganda, and Zimbabwe. The figure shows negligible correlation between the adopted measure of formal institutional strength and GDP per capita. By implication, for economic development, the explanatory burden shifts instead onto the strength of informal institutions. As Williamson (Reference Williamson2009) concluded: ‘informal institutions rule’.

But questions can be raised about a methodology that deems formal institutions in the Nordic countries and the Netherlands to be very weak, and roughly equivalent in strength to those in (say) Nigeria. The idea that Pakistan, Philippines, Uganda, and Zimbabwe have among the highest levels of formal institutional strength should also be queried. These challengeable classifications and conclusions stem partly from the narrow focus on government constraints as defining the set of formal institutions. The choices of definitions and datasets matter.

Figure 2 displays a different measure of the strength of formal institutions in the same 38 countries, plotted against the same levels of GDP per capita. If formal institutions are defined more broadly as involving laws, then one possible measure of their strength could be some index of the rule of law. There are several datasets on this, a few of which go back to the year 2000, to which Williamson's (Reference Williamson2009) GDP data apply. The GlobalEconomy.com index for the rule of law goes back to 2000 and, in its publisher's words, ‘captures perceptions of the extent to which agents have confidence in and abide by the rules of society, and in particular the quality of contract enforcement, property rights, the police, and the courts, as well as the likelihood of crime and violence’. By this measure, all five Nordic countries plus the Netherlands were in the top 10 in 2000.

Figure 2. GDP per capita and the rule of law.

Data sources: Williamson (Reference Williamson2009) and https://www.theglobaleconomy.com/rankings/wb_ruleoflaw/. Retrieved 6 September 2023.

Twelve countries are located within the box at the top right of Figure 2, indicating high levels of GDP per capita and the strong rule of law. They all had a GDP per capita level of at least $25,000 and a rule of law score exceeding 1.5. They include the Nordic nations and the Netherlands, as in the preceding figure, with the addition of Australia, Austria, Canada, Ireland, the UK, and the US.

Nine countries are located within the dashed oblong at the bottom of Figure 2. They vary less in terms of the rule of law index: they are all at relatively low levels. They are, moving from left to right, Zimbabwe, Nigeria, Pakistan, Bangladesh, Uganda, Egypt, Indonesia, Philippines, and Jordan. Overall, Figure 2 shows a strong correlation between the rule of law measure and GDP per capita. While Williamson found little if any correlation using her measure of ‘formal institutions’ there is a strong positive correlation between her GDP per capita data for 2000 and the GlobalEconomy.com rule of law index for the same year.

Although measures of the rule of law by other agencies are different, the broad picture is often similar. At the time of the publication of the Williamson (Reference Williamson2009) paper, the World Justice Project had not fully developed its index of the rule of law. Since then, they have assessed the rule of law over eight dimensions, including ‘constraints on government powers’. The other dimensions include fundamental rights, the absence of corruption, open government, regulatory enforcement, and civil justice. Their data exclude Iceland, but in 2015 the remaining four Nordic countries plus the Netherlands were their top five places in their overall rule of law index. The same five countries were in the 2015 component ranking for ‘constraints on government powers’. This picture is very different from that reported in the Williamson (Reference Williamson2009) study.Footnote 6

By prominent studies of formal (legal) strength, none of the Nordic countries have ‘weak’ formal institutions. The same is true for the Netherlands. Even if we concentrate on ‘constraints on government powers’, reports by the World Justice Project broadly concur. The conclusion that ‘informal institutions rule’ is challenged. But informal institutions are still very important. The implementation of formal (legal) rules always depends to a degree on supportive informal norms and rules (Helmke and Levitsky, Reference Helmke and Levitsky2004). Formal institutions always rely on informal institutions to be effective. Informal institutions always matter. But formal (legal) rules matter as well.Footnote 7

North (Reference North1994: 367) opined that ‘long-run economic growth entails the development of the rule of law’. Much evidence supports his claim (Dam, Reference Dam2006; Haggard et al., Reference Haggard, MacIntyre and Tiede2008; Koyama and Rubin, Reference Koyama and Rubin2022: 39 ff.). While informal (customary) institutions are also important, the rule of law signals the dominance and effectiveness of formal (legal) rules.

Worthwhile indicators of the rule of law concern de facto operation and enforcement, as well as de jure legislation. Cases of ineffective formal legislation are well known (Aldashev et al., Reference Aldashev, Chaara, Platteau and Wahhaj2012). For example, discrimination by caste in India is illegal, yet it persists (Mosse, Reference Mosse2018). Many Latin American countries adopted a constitution similar to that in the US, but the enforcement of many rules has been ineffective, and consequently outcomes have been quite different (North, Reference North1990: 101). For formal rules to work, they must cater for diverse interest groups. Supportive informal rules (or cultural norms) and effective monitoring or persuasion by a critical mass of law-abiding actors are required. As Ian Ayres and John Braithwaite (Reference Ayres and Braithwaite1992) put it somewhat paradoxically, state regulation of business can operate well when there is ‘enforced self-regulation’.

Similar exercises could be tried using measures of state capacity, instead of the rule of law. But all measures have problems, and state capacity is not short of them. One major difficulty is that military capacity is often a major component of state capacity, and that is less relevant for our purposes (Ogilvie, Reference Ogilvie2022). The main point here is not to establish the best measure, but to show that different measures and definitions can lead to dramatically different results.

Problems with the meanings of law and culture

We mention culture and, in fear of raising too many difficulties, move quickly on to law. Famously, culture has many meanings (Kroeber and Kluckhohn, Reference Kroeber and Kluckhohn1952). It often refers to a set of prevalent rules, norms, values, and beliefs. We cannot go into all the nuances here. Instead, we briefly raise the issue of how the concept of culture might relate to institutional terms. A key problem is to distinguish the concept of culture from that of an institution, where both refer to rules and norms. One option is to use the word culture to describe a set of traits found in several institutions in a society (Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2001: 298–300). These might include cultural traits such as individualism, hierarchy, and masculinity, as defined by Geert Hofstede (Reference Hofstede1984) or others. Hence one might claim, for example, that the US has an individualistic culture, and this trait is reflected in some of its institutions. This might be contrasted with more group-oriented cultures in (say) East Asia. With this option, the distinction between formal and informal rules or institutions can exist alongside the concept of culture, and each term has a distinct meaning.

As another option, the institutional economist Svetozar Pejovich (Reference Pejovich1999: 166) proposed that informal institutions are ‘traditions, customs, moral values, religious beliefs, and all other norms of behavior that have passed the test of time … informal institutions are the part of a community's heritage that we call culture’. Alberto Alesina and Paola Giuliano (Reference Alesina and Giuliano2015: 902) followed this and made the further stipulation that the term institution is confined to ‘formal institutions (formal legal systems, formal regulation)’ and culture is applied to ‘values and beliefs’ and ‘informal rules’. Here the concept of informal institutions is replaced by culture. Another alternative would be to retain the ‘informal institutions’ wording but measure it using cultural variables. More discussion is needed on the options.

We now turn to the meaning of the concept of law. This is debated, including by legal theorists. At one end of the debate, law is associated with the state. Hence, for William Blackstone ([1765–69] Reference Blackstone1893: 44) in his famous Commentaries on the Laws of England, law is ‘a rule of civil conduct prescribed by the supreme power of the state’. A very different option is to associate law with custom in general. For example, James C. Carter (Reference Carter1907: 173), a president of the American Bar Association, wrote ‘law … is custom, and like custom, self-existing and irrepealable’. But if law consisted simply of custom, then any distinction between formal and informal rules based on whether they are enforceable by law would fail.

It is sometimes useful to reduce generality and concentrate on the modern period. We are concerned with law as it relates to populous, highly organised, and complex societies. Once we consider the problems of enforcement in complex systems with many agents, and the motivational reasons why individuals might obey the law, then arguably some public body like the state is required to ensure enforcement. As Ronald Coase (Reference Coase1988: 10) put it, with ‘a vast number of people with very different interests … the establishment and administration of a private legal system would be very difficult’. Hence trading agents depend ‘on the legal system of the State’. We broadly construe the state as a realm of public ordering based on institutionalised authority. Such a state establishes a monopoly of force within a territory. A state's commitment to operate within legal constraints can help to enhance its own legitimacy as a wielder of power (Weber [1921] Reference Weber1968: vol. 1: 212 ff.). Although law may be built upon custom and rely on informal rules, it also relies on the powers of state enforcement.

Although custom is a source of law, this does not mean that ‘customary law’ is law in the above sense. Furthermore, common law (necessarily involving an institutionalised judiciary and legislature) is much more than customary law (Hasnas, Reference Hasnas2005). Furthermore, customary mechanisms (although necessary to sustain small-group, face-to-face interactions and mutual trustFootnote 8) are insufficient to explain adherence to large-scale, complex systems of law (Engel, Reference Engel2008; Tyler, Reference Tyler2006).

In history, legal systems often dealt with cases where customs were inadequate or in conflict. Accordingly, the essence of law resides in its transcendence of custom, particularly when breaches or conflicts of customary conventions arise (Diamond, Reference Diamond1935; Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2015: ch. 3; Redfield, Reference Redfield1957; Seagle, Reference Seagle1941).

The picture is further complicated by the doctrine of ‘legal pluralism’ that upholds that societies contain groups with rival rule systems and normative orders (Griffiths, Reference Griffiths1986; Merry, Reference Merry1988). Examples include the imperialist imposition of European legal systems upon substrata of still functioning indigenous legal traditions in the colonial era. One problem is that theorists of legal pluralism regard any normative order or system of social control as ‘legal’ in character (Tamanaha, Reference Tamanaha1993). This broad conception of law goes beyond the notion that modern law is legitimated and (potentially) enforced by the state. It would include a host of customary and other stipulations. If law is broadened to include customs, then we may be inclined to overlook or downplay what is distinctive about modern legal systems.

All societies contain plural systems of normative rules, but this does not necessarily amount to plural systems of law. The more dramatic cases of conflicting systems of normative rules, in Africa, India, and elsewhere, are marks of tribal or clan-based societies with high degrees of religious, cultural, and ethnic fragmentation, some of which are arguably impediments to their institutional, legal, and economic development (Alesina et al., Reference Alesina, Baquir and Easterly1999; Dam, Reference Dam2006; Easterly and Levine, Reference Easterly and Levine1997).

In his critique of legal pluralism, the philosopher and legal theorist Klaus Günther (Reference Günther and Fabra-Zamora2020) noted that with a plurality of legal and normative orders, some kind of meta-law, which enables participants to deal with norm conflicts and collisions, either exists or is required for stability and coherence. National and international processes of development crucially involve the provision of encompassing systems of law to deal with disputes. The widening and development of markets and capitalism have promoted this encompassing process (Coase, Reference Coase1988: 10). In medieval England there was a variety of types of courts, relating to the church, feudal manors, guilds, and trade associations (Berman, Reference Berman1983: 333–56; Milgrom et al., Reference Milgrom, North and Weingast1990; Rogers, Reference Rogers1995). Gradually these were drawn into the clutches of the state (Hasnas, Reference Hasnas2005; Juenger, Reference Juenger2000; Pollock and Maitland, Reference Pollock and Maitland1898), partly because of problems of plural, contested authority in circumstances of growing social complexity. Parties found it easier to submit to a single, powerful, legal apparatus. Historically, capitalism has reduced the multiplicity of legal authorities, in favour of the state. Avner Greif and Guido Tabellini (Reference Greif and Tabellini2010) argued persuasively that the formation of a state legal system with associated moral norms was crucial in Europe's economic development.

There are also plentiful boundary cases, where what is and what is not a legal system is contestable or unclear. But we should not abandon the task of definition for this reason. The Celts did not assemble under national state institutions. But they had what some regard as systems of law, largely of a customary nature, and largely unwritten before their conversion to Christianity (Kelly, Reference Kelly1988). They may have been close to the definitional boundary. Sometimes religious institutions dispense and enforce laws, as in parts of medieval Europe and in theocratic states (Fox and Sandler, Reference Fox and Sandler2005). Boundary cases are inevitable in evolving systems with highly varied components.

In modern times the law is associated with the state, although it may derive originally from other sources. A key point is the operation of some strong public authority that is legitimated by religion, by tradition, by status, or by a measure of democracy. This observation can help to provide us with a definition of law that surpasses mere custom. We may thus define (modern) legal systems as necessarily involving organised legislative, judicial, and enforcement institutions, which are empowered by state authority. A law is a rule sustained or enforced by a legal system, as defined.Footnote 9

Formal rules are rules that are actually or potentially enforced by legal systems. This definition of law also helps us to distinguish between formal and informal institutions. But many institutions are driven and constrained by both formal rules (laws) and informal rules (which, by definition, are not laws). This applies, for example, to business firms, that operate according to legal rules. Businesses also have an internal culture, consisting of rules that are sometimes not even written down. No institution lacks informal elements. Hence the term ‘formal institution’ needs further thought. It might denote states, legal systems, modern business firms, and so on, where laws make up the dominant elements in its rule structures. Informal institutions might include phenomena like language, etiquette, and many customs or rituals. Most of their rules are not constituted by lawmaking institutions.

Some laws have a general and others a special or local application (Cloe and Marcus, Reference Cloe and Marcus1936). Normally, general law takes priority over special or local law, but that does not make special laws unimportant. Much of general corporate law, for example, resulted from the accumulation of acts of parliament that each set up specific corporations. Special laws and experiences helped to create general laws. In turn, general laws can nurture specific or private rules. Corporations today comply with general corporate legislation, but each contains special rules that are legally enforceable but specific to the corporation in question. Contract law similarly involves general rules that provide room for private rules. A contractual agreement involves some legally enforceable rules that are specific to the contract, such as when and how an item or service is to be delivered. Because of their legal enforceability, these may be regarded as formal rules.

An overemphasis on the formal and legal aspects can overlook the reliance of legal systems themselves on informal rules and norms. As Émile Durkheim ([1893] Reference Durkheim1984: 158) argued: ‘in a contract not everything is contractual’. Whenever a contract exists there are rules and norms that are not necessarily codified in law. The parties to the agreement are forced to rely on institutional rules and standard patterns of behaviour, which cannot for reasons of practicality and complexity be fully established as laws. Some markets will always be missing (Magill and Quinzii, Reference Magill and Quinzii1996). Legal systems are invariably incomplete, and they give scope for custom and culture to do their work (Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2015, Reference Hodgson2020). We always depend on informal rules as well.

On the interaction of formal and informal institutions

We now turn to the question of how formal and informal institutions may interact and evolve. It is widely upheld that the cultural norms and beliefs that make up informal institutions are generally more resistant to change. North (Reference North1990: 45; Reference North1994: 364, 366) noted the ‘tenacious survival ability’ of cultural traits and explained:

It is culture that provides the key to path dependence … Societies that get ‘stuck’ embody belief systems and institutions that fail to confront and solve new problems of societal complexity. … While the rules may be changed overnight, the informal norms usually change only gradually. Since it is the norms that provide ‘legitimacy’ to a set of rules, revolutionary change is never as revolutionary as its supporters desire …

The Nobel Laureate Oliver Williamson (Reference Williamson2000: 596–7) considered four levels of social analysis. He saw ‘Level 1’ as having the most ‘socially embedded’ features, including ‘norms, customs, mores, traditions, etc. … Religion plays a large role at this level. … Institutions at this level change very slowly – on the order of centuries or millennia.’ Reflecting on possible reasons for slow change at this level, he conjectured ‘that many of these informal institutions have mainly spontaneous origins – which is to say that deliberative choice of a calculative kind is minimally implicated. Given these evolutionary origins, they … display a great deal of inertia … the resulting institutions have a lasting grip on the way a society conducts itself.’ At other levels he included formal institutions, including the judiciary, polity, and other bureaucracies. He argued that these can change at faster rates than Level 1 institutions.

Similarly, the economist Gérard Roland (Reference Roland2004: 109) drew a distinction between ‘slow-moving’ and ‘fast-moving’ institutions. For him, a ‘prime example of a slow-moving institution is “culture,” including values, beliefs, and social norms. Fast-moving institutions do not necessarily change often but can change more quickly – sometimes nearly overnight. Political institutions can typically be viewed as fast-moving institutions.’ Roland examined possible interactions between these two kinds of institutions.

In line with North, Williamson, and Roland, there are several impressive case studies of the persistence of cultural traits (or informal institutions) and their lasting effects. Emmanuel Todd (Reference Todd1985, Reference Todd1987) showed that different, largely unwritten, family structures and property inheritance patterns persist in different parts of the world (see also Gutman and Voigt, Reference Gutman and Voigt2022). David H. Fischer (Reference Fischer1989) argued that US regional differences in family structure, gender relations, community attitudes, and propensities to violence emanate from different phases of immigration from the seventeenth to the nineteenth centuries, from contrasting cultures in different regions of Britain. Sonya Salamon and Jack T. Kirby (Reference Salamon and Kirby1992) showed that different cultural patterns of farm management, land tenure, and inheritance survived among Illinois farming communities, depending on whether they were of German or British Protestant descent. Richard E. Nisbett and Dov Cohen (Reference Nisbett and Cohen1996) provided experimental evidence of the survival of a potentially violent ‘culture of honor’ in the US South. They argued that it was derived from Scots-Irish immigrants. There are other case studies of long-term cultural persistence (Koyama and Rubin, Reference Koyama and Rubin2022: 79–87).

But sometimes, cultural norms change more rapidly. Helmke and Levitsky (Reference Helmke and Levitsky2004: 732) gave the example of the disappearance in China of the practice of binding the feet of women. It lasted a thousand years, but within a generation it disappeared, due to strong social campaigns against it (Mackie, Reference Mackie1996). The development economist Gani Aldashev et al. (Reference Aldashev, Chaara, Platteau and Wahhaj2012: 797) reported studies, in developing as well as developed economies, that show that ‘custom is far from being static and continuously evolves under the pressure of a changing environment’. Cultural shifts are often pressured by economic or legislative changes. In the US, female participation in the employed workforce rose from 33% in 1950 to 60% in 2000.Footnote 10 Rising female employment shifted gender-based norms and prompted equal gender rights legislation from the 1960s onwards (Meagher and Shu, Reference Meagher and Shu2019).

Rules and attitudes concerning sexual relations are often resilient components of a social culture. Frequently, they are based on religion. Williamson (Reference Williamson2000: 597) saw religion as deeply ingrained and slow to change. Consider homosexual acts, which have been regarded as sinful by major religions, including Christianity, Islam, and Judaism. According to the survey of British Social Attitudes, in the UK in 1990, 69% of adults thought that homosexual acts were ‘always’ or ‘mostly’ wrong, compared with 19% saying they were ‘rarely wrong’ or ‘not wrong at all’. But by 2010 these figures had shifted dramatically, to 30% saying that they were ‘always’ or ‘mostly’ wrong, compared with 53% saying they were ‘rarely wrong’ or ‘not wrong at all’.Footnote 11 This rapid transformation of previously enduring cultural beliefs may be partly explicable in terms of a series of legislative acts, including reductions in the age of consent for male partners in 1994 and 2000, the ban on gay people serving in the armed forces being repealed in 2000, the instigation of gay civil partnerships in 2004, and the banning of discrimination based on sexual orientation in 2007. It seems that the legislation played an important role in legitimating more tolerant attitudes. There was also an energetic movement for gay rights. In more secular societies, legislation was important in reversing previous, religiously grounded, attitudes.

As noted above, North (Reference North1994: 366) identified sources of legitimation from within culture itself. Legislation that is perceived to be legitimate can have stronger effects, especially in representative democracies under the rule of law. There are exceptions to this, where legislation has had little effect on attitudes. But there are cases where legislation has transformed some attitudes or beliefs. Aldashev et al. (Reference Aldashev, Chaara, Platteau and Wahhaj2012: 798) modelled how ‘the formal law can actually pull custom in its direction, thereby causing a progressive evolution of the prevailing mores’. They called this the ‘magnet effect’. They gave several examples and outline the conditions under which the ‘magnet effect’ can be more powerful.

Causality operates in both directions, from informal attitudes and rules to the formal, and from formal legislation to the informal domain. The legitimating power of legal and other institutional authority is confirmed by multiple studies, including the experiments of Stanley Milgram (Reference Milgram1974) showing how people can be manipulated to obey authority, and Tom Tyler's (Reference Tyler2006) analysis of why people comply with the law. Ever since Max Weber's (Reference Weber1968, vol. 1: 212 ff.) identification of key processes of legitimation, much evidence has been accumulated to suggest that the effective powers of formal (legal) institutions are in good measure due to perceptions of legitimate authority. Laws often have additional motivational powers, deriving from the perceived legitimacy of their authority. Law is not simply another set of rules.

Some rules and attitudes that are often seen as cultural and informal did in fact emanate, at least in part, from laws and formal institutions. For example, the historian Martin J. Weiner (Reference Weiner2004) argued that ‘English culture’ was resistant to industrialisation and economic growth. Hence, the rich and powerful sought country estates. But these motives did not spring originally from a culture that favoured country living, but from the survival of feudal institutions in politics and law that made familial landowning an essential means of economic, social, and political advancement. Land ownership was the principal source of status and power. English laws of land tenure included the duty to raise armies. The monarchy needed that system because it provided military forces for use in war. The English aristocracy and gentry sustained and contrived legal measures to keep land within their families, resisting for centuries the efforts of legislators to make more land saleable. Despite the revolutionary events of 1642–51 and 1688–89, the powers of the aristocracy and landed gentry largely remained intact. Despite the growing influence of industrialists and financiers, large landowners and aristocrats retained a powerful presence in the elite. The origins of their power and their landowning culture lie largely in formal institutions in the feudal and post-feudal era (Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2023: 40–1, 79–81, 101–5, 139–45).

Consider another example where legislation helped to create a noted cultural trait. In 1742, a systematic legal code was enacted in feudal Japan. But it was not designed to deal with disputes over property or contracts. Instead, informal settlements or compromises in such disputes were encouraged, sometimes by the threat of state punishment of both disputing parties. Hence, it is possible that customary Japanese aversions to commercial haggling and litigation may result more from draconian legislation to prevent such disputes in the 18th century than from earlier traditional practices or beliefs. The traditional Japanese aversion to litigation seems to have more to do with its evolving legal institutions, and less as something inherent and longstanding in the Japanese culture.Footnote 12

Although many informal rules are slow to change, this is not always the case. Some examples show that rapid changes in some cultural traits and moral beliefs are possible, particularly resulting from formal changes by governments and legal authorities, especially when they are perceived as legitimate.

Concluding definitions and remarks

The following definitions are suggested. They are not in alphabetical order but in a constructive sequence:

  • Rules. The term rule is understood as an injunction or disposition, that in circumstances X do Y (a positive rule), or in circumstances X do not do Z (a negative rule). A rule can be constitutive (interpret phenomena X as being Y) or regulative (concerning actions). Rules include norms of behaviour and social conventions, as well as legal or formal rules. Contrary to some accounts, rules do not have to be commonly known to be enforceable. In many cases, what is required is the common acceptance of authority. No-one is aware of more than a tiny fraction of legal rules. Yet they are enforceable, partly because many people accept the authority of the legal system.

  • Rules and norms. Sue Crawford and Nobel Laureate Elinor Ostrom (Reference Crawford and Ostrom1995: 583–4) differentiated between rules and norms. For them, unlike norms, rules contain the threat of an ‘or else’ component that points to the consequences of non-compliance. This may over-complicate the picture. First, it needs to be made clear whether the ‘or else’ sanctions, such as shunning or ostracism, might be socially rather than legally enforced. Second, in commonplace parlance, the term rule has a broad usage, including the non-threatening (and informal) rules of language, or practical (and informal) rules that are clearly recommendations. It may be better to regard a norm as a kind of rule that does not have a threatening ‘or else’ component. Hence norms would be a subcategory of rules.

  • Institutions. Institutions are systems of established and prevalent social rules that structure social interactions. To make rules operative, institutions must involve some shared conceptions. Systems of language, money, law, weights and measures, traffic conventions, table manners, and firms (and arguably all other organisations – see appendix below) are institutions. All institutions are social structures but not all social structures are institutions. For example, the demographic or gender structure of a society is not necessarily an institution.

  • Laws. Laws are codifiable rules in institutional systems involving legislatures and courts. These institutions and rules may be legitimated by religion, by tradition, or by a measure of democracy. Some laws may derive from customs and depend on them, but all laws involve legislative and judicial institutions subject to sovereign power.

  • Formal and informal institutions. Institutions may be subcategorised as formal or informal. Formal institutions are constituted or maintained through legally decreed procedures, and laws make up the dominant elements in their rule systems. Informal institutions include language, customs, rituals, or table manners. Most of their rules are not constituted by lawmaking institutions. Some rules in informal institutions may be illegal. Mafias and criminal gangs are illegal informal institutions.

  • Organisations. An organisation is a special type of institution involving (a) criteria to establish its boundaries and to distinguish its members from its non-members, (b) principles of sovereignty concerning who is in charge, and (c) a structure that delineates responsibilities within the organisation. These conditions imply the existence of social roles or positions that have properties irreducible to those who occupy them.

  • Formal organisations. Organisations are formal if they are constituted and maintained by laws and are dominated by legally enforceable rules. All formal organisations include some informal rules, but the dominance of legal formalities makes them formal. Otherwise, they are informal.

The relative importance of different types of institution in economic development is a matter of empirical study. All empirical work requires workable definitions. The discussion of definitions and datasets in the fourth section underlines the importance of a careful and accommodating definition of ‘formal institutions’. The third section highlights the importance of these definitional issues to questions of economic development.

The discussion and definitions above underline the importance of the criterion of whether rules or institutions are constituted and (potentially) enforced by law. That criterion is well established, but it is important to make it explicit and to explore its implications. Arguably, law is not simply an expression of authority but is also a constitutive part of the institutionalised power structure, and a major means through which control is exercised. Law is also a great motivational force. It works not simply through threat of punishment but also because of commitments to what is perceived as legitimate or moral authority. Many other rules do not have this motivational advantage, and obedience to them may depend more on the expected benefits and costs of compliance versus non-compliance. Research using the distinction between formal and informal institutions should take such factors into account.

Acknowledgements

The author is very grateful to Luca Andriani, Tim Besley, Mark Casson, Klarita Gërxhani, Richard Langlois, Chrys Mantzavinos, Ilia Murtazashvili, Jennifer Murtazashvili, Antonio Savoia, Gerhard Schnyder, Nikhilesh Sinha, Stefan Voigt, Claudia Wiliamson, and five anonymous referees for very helpful comments on previous drafts of this paper.

Appendix

An update on the near-consensus on the definition of an institution

There is a near-consensus that institutions are defined as systems of rules (Crawford and Ostrom, Reference Crawford and Ostrom1995; Knight, Reference Knight1992; Mantzavinos, Reference Mantzavinos2001; North, Reference North1981: 201–2, Reference North1990; Ostrom, Reference Ostrom1990). To be effective, these rules must be embedded in practice or in structures of authority. Some game theorists regard institutions as equilibria (Aoki, Reference Aoki2001; Binmore Reference Binmore1994, Reference Binmore1998; Lewis Reference Lewis1969). But the resulting game equilibria themselves establish rules. For example, with the coordination game of driving-on-the-left versus driving-on-the-right, the two possible equilibria are both (regulative) rules.

Frank Hindriks and Francesco Guala (Guala Reference Guala2016; Hindriks and Guala Reference Hindriks and Guala2015) attempted to synthesise the rule-based and equilibrium-based conceptions. Their principal argument against the exclusively rule-based approach is that it does not explain why rules are followed, or why they remain stable. But it is not the task of a taxonomic definition to explain why things work, or even to signal the type of explanation that would be required. A mammal is defined as a type of animal where females suckle their young. The definitional task is to demarcate and classify, not to explain. Consequently, taxonomic definitions should be as parsimonious as possible, while retaining effective demarcation criteria. The addition of the equilibrium concept may be important for explanatory purposes, but it is unnecessary for a taxonomic definition.

For primary taxonomic purposes the ‘embedded system of rules’ definition of an institution is adequate. Adding additional clauses such as ‘in equilibrium’ to the taxonomic definition would create more controversy than is necessary at the primary and definitional stage. After common agreement on the object of analysis, questions about how particular rules are sustained and enforced come into play. The explanations will vary from case to case.

The rules that constitute institutions include norms of behaviour and social conventions, as well as legal rules. Accordingly, systems of language, money, law, weights and measures, traffic conventions, table manners are all institutions. Some have expressed uneasiness with this broad taxonomic definition of institution, which includes so many different things. But lots of definitions are capacious. Humans, mice, and elephants are all mammals. Trees, grass, lettuce, and roses are all plants. There are thousands of different languages. Instead of a rejection of the primary classification, there is a need for sub-classification and further differentiation.

There is still some controversy over whether organizations are a type of institution, or organizations and institutions are mutually exclusive categories. Prominent members of the Society for Institutional and Organizational Economics regard institutions and organizations as mutually exclusive (Alston et al., Reference Alston, Alston, Mueller and Nonnenmacher2018). But others closely associated with that society do not. For example, Oliver Williamson described his analysis of business organisations as (new) ‘institutional economics’. Coase (Reference Coase and Perlman1977: 487) wrote of the ‘institutions which bind together the economic system: firms, markets for goods and services, labour markets, capital markets, the banking system, and so on’. Ostrom (Reference Ostrom2010: 646) wrote of ‘a diversity of institutional settings including … markets, private firms, families, community organizations, legislatures, and government agencies’. Barzel (Reference Barzel2002: 14n.), Dam (Reference Dam2006: 22–3) and Faundez (Reference Faundez2016) have criticised the claim that organisations are not institutions. Ménard (Reference Ménard1995) first proposed mutual exclusivity and was then persuaded otherwise (Ménard, Reference Ménard2014). Within the broad, multi-disciplinary area of institutional research, making institutions and organisations mutually exclusive is a minority habit. Many prominent scholars treat organisations as a kind of institution.Footnote 13

Dissidents to the near-consensus often cite North in support of their claim. But there is no unambiguous evidence that North took their view. North (Reference North1981: 18–19; Reference North1990: 4) sometimes implied that organizations were institutions. In correspondence with the present author, North agreed that organisations were institutions. When North made a ‘crucial distinction … between institutions and organizations’ he did not clearly state that they were mutually exclusive. There are important differences between humans and other mammals, but that does not mean that humans are not mammals.Footnote 14

Marshall (Reference Marshall1920: 45) argued that the terms used in economics should ‘conform … to the familiar terms of everyday life, and so far as possible [economists] must use them as they are commonly used’. Malthus (Reference Malthus1827: 4), Menger (Reference Menger1888: 6, 37), and others argued similarly: we should minimise arbitrary or unusual designations of words.Footnote 15 As noted above, the word formal has so many meanings that it is difficult to establish one conventional usage over another. But this is not the case with the terms institution and organisation. Many people describe organisations such as banks, corporations, or universities as institutions. For centuries, the word institution has been applied to organisations. For example, the Royal Institution was an organisation founded in London in 1799 to promote science. There are hundreds of documents from the 18th century where the noun institution is applied to an organisation. Those who wish to regard the two as mutually exclusive are playing havoc with the language and generating unnecessary disputes and complications. But we still need to distinguish institutions that are organizations from those institutions that are not organizations.

Footnotes

1 The searches were completed on 17 October 2023.

2 North (Reference North1989a: 239; Reference North1989b: 666; Reference North1990: 4, 6, 8, 23, 25, 27, 30, 36–45, 57, 87, 107–8, 110, 138; Reference North1991: 97; Reference North1992: 4; Reference North1993: 20; Reference North1994: 360; Reference North, Drobak and Nye1997: 6; Reference North2005: 48, 117). North (e.g. Reference North1990: 4, 66, 74) occasionally mentioned ‘informal institutions’ or ‘informal rules’. One article by him alone mentions ‘informal institutions’ (North, Reference North1989a: 244). No article by him alone mentions ‘informal rules’. An article that he co-authored with others mentions both ‘informal institutions’ and ‘informal norms’ several times (Mantzavinos et al., Reference Mantzavinos, North and Shariq2004). On his use of ‘formal rules’ or ‘formal institutions’ see North (Reference North1989a: 239, 244; Reference North1990: 138; Reference North1991: 97; Reference North1992: 4; Reference North1993: 20; Reference North1994: 360; Reference North, Drobak and Nye1997: 6).

3 Twice North (Reference North1994: 360; Reference North, Drobak and Nye1997: 6) added ‘rules’ as examples of ‘formal rules’. Here ‘formal’ becomes so broad that it includes all rules. North (Reference North2005: 48) referred to the (non-legal) rules of football as ‘formal’. But unlike some scholars, who envisage property without the state or law (Barzel and Allen, Reference Barzel and Allen2023), North (Reference North1981: 17; Reference North1989a: 239; Reference North1989b: 662–3; Reference North1991: 98, 101, 109–10; Reference North1992: 5) linked ‘property rights’ to state law.

4 Barzel and Allen (Reference Barzel and Allen2023: 81) also associate ‘formal’ with legal enforcement by the state.

5 Meagher and Lindell (Reference Meagher and Lindell2013: 58) described efforts to bolster the formal sector as ‘neoliberal’. But there is a lack of consensus on the meaning of the term (Boas and Gans-Morse, Reference Boas and Gans-Morse2009).

7 See Mike and Kiss (Reference Mike and Kiss2019). In correspondence, Stefan Voigt claimed that some ‘weak’ formal institutions are found in Scandinavian countries, such as the formal protection of judicial independence. These formal institutions rely on high levels of trust and social cohesion, which are ‘informal’ in character. Generally, the ‘formal’ rule of law always depends to some degree on ‘informal’ support. This complicates the measurement of the strength of formal institutions. Is their strength lower because of heavy reliance on informal supports, or rated higher because they can accommodate the latter with stronger overall effects?

8 In a controlled laboratory experiment with mandatory mask-wearing (as legislated in several countries during the COVID-19 pandemic), Cardella et al. (Reference Cardella, Depew and Williams2024) showed that face covering reduced altruistic and cooperative behaviour. This suggests complex trade-offs between the benefits of (informal) small group interactions (allowing face recognition) and (formal) laws that mandate behaviours (perhaps for good reasons) in large-scale societies.

9 Consider the rules and penalties that govern mafias and other illegal organisations. In some ways, these are like laws. But here the rule of law, typically understood as emanating from state authority (Waldron, Reference Waldron, Zalta and Nodelman2023), is incomplete.

10 Data from https://fred.stlouisfed.org/series/LNS11300002. Retrieved 11 September 2023.

12 Oda (Reference Oda1992: 20–4), Sorenson (Reference Sorenson2010), Hodgson (Reference Hodgson2023: 216). Ginsburg and Hoetker (Reference Ginsburg and Hoetker2006) summarised the debate over the causes of historically lower litigation rates in Japan.

13 Parsons (Reference Parsons1983), Scott (Reference Scott1995), Rosefielde (Reference Rosefielde2002), Runciman (Reference Runciman, Wheeler, Ziman and Boden2002) and Guala (Reference Guala2016) all regarded organisations as a type of institution. In Barzel and Allen (Reference Barzel and Allen2023: 138), in a chapter added by Allen, a distinction is attempted where, unlike institutions, organizations or contracts ‘arise out of relatively small groups’, are ‘more complicated’ and are not taken ‘as exogenous’. A few words later, the Declaration of Independence is listed as not being an institution. But surely most people would take it as exogenously given? Allen's distinctions are vague and questionable. It would have been better to stick to Barzel (Reference Barzel2002).

14 See Hodgson (Reference Hodgson2006) for the correspondence with North. But the North et al. (Reference North, Wallis and Weingast2009) book sometimes suggests that organisations are not institutions. As one of the authors of this book, Barry Weingast emailed me on 15 May 2016: ‘I dissented in the decision to claim that organizations were not institutions! I think it depends on the level of analysis. In treating the state and market, organizations are the players. But the modern theory of the firm treats the firm as an institution with individuals as players.’

15 See Robinson (Reference Robinson1950: 79–80) and Hodgson (Reference Hodgson2019, Reference Hodgson2023: 5–6).

References

Aldashev, G., Chaara, I., Platteau, J.-P. and Wahhaj, Z. (2012) Formal law as a magnet to reform custom. Economic Development and Cultural Change 60(4), 795828.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alesina, A. and Giuliano, P. (2015) Culture and institutions. Journal of Economic Literature 53(4), 898944.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alesina, A., Baquir, R. and Easterly, W. (1999) Public goods and ethnic divisions. Quarterly Journal of Economics 114(4), 12431284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, E., Alston, L.J., Mueller, B. and Nonnenmacher, T. (2018) Institutional and Organizational Analysis: Concepts and Applications. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aoki, M. (2001) Toward a Comparative Institutional Analysis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayres, I. and Braithwaite, J. (1992) Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bardhan, P.K. (2016) State and development: The need for a reappraisal of the current literature. Journal of Economic Literature 54(3), 862892.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barzel, Y. (2002) A Theory of the State: Economic Rights, Legal Rights, and the Scope of the State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barzel, Y. and Allen, D.W. (2023) Economic Analysis of Property Rights, 3rd Edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berman, H.J. (1983) Law and Revolution: The Formation of the Western Legal Tradition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Besley, T. and Persson, T. (2011) Pillars of Prosperity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. (1994) Playing Fair: Game Theory and the Social Contract. Volume I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. (1998) Just Playing: Game Theory and the Social Contract. Volume 2. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Blackstone, W. ([1765-69] 1893) Commentaries on the Laws of England, 2 vols. Philadelphia: Lippincott.Google Scholar
Boas, T.C. and Gans-Morse, J. (2009) Neoliberalism: From new liberal philosophy to anti-liberal slogan. Studies in Comparative International Development 44(2), 137161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cardella, E., Depew, B. and Williams, R.B. (2024) Behavioral responses of mandatory masking within social interactions. Public Choice 201, 123. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-024-01166-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, J.C. (1907) Law: Its Origin, Growth and Function. New York: Putnam's.Google Scholar
Casson, M.C., Della Giusta, M. and Kambhampati, U.S. (2010) Formal and informal institutions and development. World Development 38(2), 137141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cloe, L.H. and Marcus, S. (1936) Special and local legislation. Kentucky Law Journal 24(4), 351386.Google Scholar
Coase, R.H. (1977) Economics and contiguous disciplines. In Perlman, M. (ed.), The Organization and Retrieval of Economic Knowledge. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, pp. 481491. Reprinted in Journal of Legal Studies, 7(2), 201-211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coase, R.H. (1988) The Firm, the Market, and the Law. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Crawford, S.E.S. and Ostrom, E. (1995) A grammar of institutions. American Political Science Review 89(3), 582600.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dam, K.W. (2006) The Law-Growth Nexus: The Rule of Law and Economic Development. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.Google Scholar
Diamond, A.S. (1935) Primitive Law. London: Watts.Google Scholar
Durkheim, É. (1984) The Division of Labour in Society, Translated From the French Edition of 1893. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Easterly, W. and Levine, R. (1997) Africa's growth tragedy: Policies and ethnic divisions. Quarterly Journal of Economics 112, 12031250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engel, C. (2008) Learning the law. Journal of Institutional Economics 4(3), 275297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faundez, J. (2016) Douglass North's theory of institutions: Lessons for law and development. Hague Journal on the Rule of Law 8, 373419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer, D.H. (1989) Albion's Seed: Four British Folkways in America. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fox, J. and Sandler, S. (2005) Separation of religion and state in the twenty-first century: Comparing the Middle East and Western democracies. Comparative Politics 37(3), 317335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gërxhani, K. (2004) The informal sector in developed and less developed countries: A literature survey. Public Choice 120(3/4), 267300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gërxhani, K. and Cichocki, S. (2023) Formal and informal institutions: Understanding the shadow economy in transition countries. Journal of Institutional Economics 19(5), 656672. doi: 10.1017/S1744137422000522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsburg, T. and Hoetker, G. (2006) The unreluctant litigant? An empirical analysis of Japan's turn to litigation. Journal of Legal Studies 35(1), 3159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glaeser, E.L., La Porta, R. and Lopez-De-Silanes, A. (2004) Do institutions cause growth? Journal of Economic Growth 9, 271303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greif, A. and Tabellini, G. (2010) Cultural and institutional bifurcation: China and Europe compared. American Economic Review: Papers & Proceedings 100(2), 135140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, J. (1986) What is legal pluralism? Journal of Legal Pluralism 24(1), 155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guala, F. (2016) Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Günther, K. (2020) Normative legal pluralism: A critique. In Fabra-Zamora, J.L. (ed.), Jurisprudence in a Globalized World. Cheltenham, UK and Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar, pp. 8499.Google Scholar
Gutman, J. and Voigt, S. (2022) Testing Todd: Family types and development. Journal of Institutional Economics 18, 101118. doi: 10.1017/S1744137421000175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haggard, S., MacIntyre, A. and Tiede, L. (2008) The rule of law and economic development. Annual Review of Political Science 11, 205234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hasnas, J. (2005) Hayek, the common law, and the fluid drive. NYU Journal of Law and Liberty 1, 79110.Google Scholar
Helmke, G. and Levitsky, S. (2004) Informal institutions and comparative politics: A research agenda. Perspectives on Politics 2(4), 725740.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hindriks, F. and Guala, F. (2015) Institutions, rules, and equilibria: A unified theory. Journal of Institutional Economics 11(3), 459480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2001) How Economics Forgot History: The Problem of Historical Specificity in Social Science. London and New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2006) What are institutions? Journal of Economic Issues 40(1), 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2015) Conceptualizing Capitalism: Institutions, Evolution, Future. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2019) Taxonomic definitions in social science, with firms, markets and institutions as case studies. Journal of Institutional Economics 15(2), 207233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2020) How mythical markets mislead analysis: An institutionalist critique of market universalism. Socio-Economic Review 18(4), 11531174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2023) The Wealth of a Nation: Institutional Foundations of English Capitalism. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofstede, G. (1984) Culture's Consequences: International Differences in Work-Related Values. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Juenger, F.K. (2000) The Lex Mercatoria and private international law. Louisiana Law Review 60, 11331150.Google Scholar
Keefer, P. and Shirley, M.M. (2000) Formal versus informal institutions in economic development. In Ménard, C. (ed.), Institutions, Contracts and Organizations: Perspectives from New Institutional Economics. Aldershot: Edward Elgar, pp. 88107.Google Scholar
Kelly, F. (1988) A Guide to Early Irish Law. Dublin: Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies.Google Scholar
Knight, J. (1992) Institutions and Social Conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koyama, M. and Rubin, J. (2022) How the World Became Rich: The Historical Origins of Economic Growth. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Kroeber, A.L. and Kluckhohn, C. (1952) Culture: A critical review of concepts and definitions. Peabody Museum Papers 47(1), 1223.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1969) Convention: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mackie, G. (1996) Ending footbinding and infibulation: A convention account. American Sociological Review 61(6), 9991017.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magill, M. and Quinzii, M. (1996) Theory of Incomplete Markets. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Malthus, T.R. (1827) Definitions in Political Economy. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Mantzavinos, C. (2001) Individuals, Institutions, and Markets. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantzavinos, C., North, D.C. and Shariq, S. (2004) Learning, institutions, and economic performance. Perspectives on Politics 2(1), 7584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marshall, A. (1920) Principles of Economics: An Introductory Volume, 8th Edn. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Meagher, K. and Lindell, I. (2013) Introduction to African studies review forum: Engaging with African informal economies: Social inclusion or adverse incorporation? African Studies Review 56(3), 5776.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meagher, K.D. and Shu, X. (2019) Trends in U.S. gender attitudes, 1977 to 2018: Gender and educational disparities. Socius 5(1), 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ménard, C. (1995) Markets as institutions versus organizations as markets? Disentangling some fundamental concepts. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 28(2), 161182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ménard, C. (2014) Embedding organizational arrangements: Toward a general model. Journal of Institutional Economics 10(4), 567589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menger, C. (1888) Zur theorie des kapitals. Jahrbücher für Nationalökonomie und Statistik 17, 149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merry, S.E. (1988) Legal pluralism. Law and Society Review 22(5), 869896.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mike, K. and Kiss, G. (2019) Combining formal and informal contract enforcement in a developed legal system: A latent class approach. Journal of Institutional Economics 15(3), 521537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milgram, S. (1974) Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View. New York and London: Harper and Row, and Tavistock.Google Scholar
Milgrom, P.R., North, D.C. and Weingast, B.R. (1990) The role of institutions in the revival of trade: The law merchant, private judges and the champagne fairs. Economics and Politics 2(1), 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mosse, D. (2018) Caste and development: Contemporary perspectives on a structure of discrimination and advantage. World Development 110, 422436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murtazashvili, I. and Murtazashvili, J. (2016) The origins of property rights: States or customary organizations? Journal of Institutional Economics 12(1), 105128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, R.E. and Cohen, D. (1996) Culture of Honor: The Psychology of Violence in the South. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
North, D.C. (1981) Structure and Change in Economic History. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
North, D.C. (1989a) Final remarks – institutional change and economic history. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 145(1), 238245.Google Scholar
North, D.C. (1989b) A transaction cost approach to the historical development of polities and economies. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 145(4), 661668.Google Scholar
North, D.C. (1990) Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, D.C. (1991) Institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives 5(1), 97112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, D.C. (1992) Institutions and economic theory. The American Economist 36(1), 36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, D.C. (1993) Institutions and credible commitments. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 149(1), 1123.Google Scholar
North, D.C. (1994) Economic performance through time. American Economic Review 84(3), 359367.Google Scholar
North, D.C. (1997) Prologue. In Drobak, J.N. and Nye, J.V.C. (eds), The Frontiers of the New Institutional Economics. San Diego and London: Academic Press, pp. 328.Google Scholar
North, D.C. (2002) Letter to G. M. Hodgson dated October 7, 2002.Google Scholar
North, D.C. (2005) Understanding the Process of Economic Change. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, D.C., Wallis, J.J. and Weingast, B.R. (2009) Violence and Social Orders: A Conceptual Framework for Interpreting Recorded Human History. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oda, H. (1992) Japanese Law. London: Butterworths.Google Scholar
Ogilvie, S. (2022) State capacity and economic growth: Cautionary tales from history. National Institute Economic Review 262(1), 2850.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (2002) Measuring the Non-Observed Economy. Paris: OECD.Google Scholar
Ostrom, E. (1990) Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ostrom, E. (2010) Beyond markets and states: Polycentric governance of complex economic systems. American Economic Review 100(3), 641672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parsons, T. (1983) On Institutions and Social Evolution: Selected Writings. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Pejovich, S. (1999) The effects of the interaction of formal and informal institutions on social stability and economic development. Journal of Markets and Morality 2(2), 164181.Google Scholar
Pollock, F. and Maitland, F.W. (1898) The History of English Law Before the Time of Edward I, 2nd Edn, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Redfield, R. (1957) The Primitive World and its Transformations. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Ricciuti, R., Savoia, A. and Sen, K. (2019) How do political institutions affect fiscal capacity? Explaining taxation in developing economies. Journal of Institutional Economics 15(2), 351380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, R. (1950) Definition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rogers, J.S. (1995) The Early History of the Law of Bills and Notes: A Study of the Origins of Anglo-American Commercial Law. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roland, G. (2004) Understanding institutional change: Fast-moving and slow-moving institutions. Studies in Comparative International Development 38(4), 109131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosefielde, S. (2002) Comparative Economic Systems: Culture, Wealth and Power in the 21st Century. Oxford, UK and Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Runciman, W.G. (2002) Heritable variation and competitive selection as the mechanism of sociocultural evolution. In Wheeler, M., Ziman, J. and Boden, M.A. (eds), The Evolution of Cultural Entities. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 925.Google Scholar
Salamon, S. and Kirby, J.T. (1992) Prairie Patrimony: Family, Farming and Community in the Midwest. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savoia, A. and Sen, K. (2023) The origins of fiscal states in developing economies: History, politics and institutions. Journal of Institutional Economics 19, 303313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheidel, W. (2019) Escape from Rome: The Failure of the Empire and the Road to Prosperity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Schneider, F. and Enste, D.H. (2000) Shadow economies: Size, causes, and consequences. Journal of Economic Literature 38(1), 77114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott, W.R. (1995) Institutions and Organizations. Thousand Oaks, CA and London, UK: Sage.Google Scholar
Seagle, W. (1941) The Quest for Law. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Searle, J.R. (1995) The Construction of Social Reality. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Searle, J.R. (2005) What is an institution? Journal of Institutional Economics 1(1), 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seyoum, B. (2011) Informal institutions and foreign direct investment. Journal of Economic Issues 45(4), 917940.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorenson, A. (2010) Land, property rights, and planning in Japan: Institutional design and institutional change in land management. Planning Perspectives 25(3), 279302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tamanaha, B.Z. (1993) The folly of the ‘social scientific’ concept of legal pluralism. Journal of Law and Society 20(2), 192217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todd, E. (1985) The Explanation of Ideology: Family Structures and Social Systems. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Todd, E. (1987) The Causes of Progress: Culture, Authority and Change. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Tyler, T.R. (2006) Why People Obey the Law, 2nd Edn. New Haven: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voigt, S. (2018) How to measure informal institutions. Journal of Institutional Economics 14(1), 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voigt, S. and Kiwit, D. (1998) The role and evolution of beliefs, habits, moral norms, and institutions. In Giersch, H. (ed.), Merits and Limits of Markets. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, pp. 83103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J. (2023) The rule of law. In Zalta, E. N. and Nodelman, U. (eds), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2023/entries/rule-of-law/Google Scholar
Weber, M. (1968) Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretative Sociology, 2 vols, translated from the German edition of 1921-1922. New York: Bedminster Press.Google Scholar
Weiner, M.J. (2004) English Culture and the Decline of the Industrial Spirit, 1850-1980, 2nd Edn. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, O.E. (2000) The new institutional economics: Taking stock, looking ahead. Journal of Economic Literature 38(3), 595613.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, C.R. (2009) Informal institutions rule: Institutional arrangements and economic performance. Public Choice 139(3/4), 371387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, C.R. and Kerekes, C.B. (2011) Securing private property: Formal versus informal institutions. Journal of Law and Economics 54(3), 537572.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. GDP per capita and the strength of ‘formal institutions’.Data source: Williamson (2009).

Figure 1

Figure 2. GDP per capita and the rule of law.Data sources: Williamson (2009) and https://www.theglobaleconomy.com/rankings/wb_ruleoflaw/. Retrieved 6 September 2023.