Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T18:05:37.289Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

KOBAYASHI-OCHIAI’S FINITENESS THEOREM FOR ORBIFOLD PAIRS OF GENERAL TYPE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 April 2024

Finn Bartsch
Affiliation:
IMAPP, Radboud University Nijmegen, PO Box 9010, 6500GL, Nijmegen, The Netherlands ([email protected])
Ariyan Javanpeykar*
Affiliation:
IMAPP, Radboud University Nijmegen, PO Box 9010, 6500GL, Nijmegen, The Netherlands
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Kobayashi–Ochiai proved that the set of dominant maps from a fixed variety to a fixed variety of general type is finite. We prove the natural extension of their finiteness theorem to Campana’s orbifold pairs.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1 Introduction

In [Reference Kobayashi and OchiaiKO75], Kobayashi and Ochiai proved a higher-dimensional generalization of the finiteness theorem of De Franchis for compact Riemann surfaces. Namely, for X and Y smooth projective varieties over $\mathbb {C}$ with X of general type, the set of dominant rational maps is finite. In this paper, we prove a generalization of the classical finiteness theorem of Kobayashi–Ochiai for dominant rational maps in the setting of Campana’s orbifold maps (Theorem 1.1). The notion of orbifold pairs (also referred to as C-pairs [Reference Kebekus, Pereira and SmeetsKPS22]) was introduced in [Reference CampanaCam04, Reference CampanaCam11] and has already been shown to be fruitful in, for example, the resolution of Viehweg’s hyperbolicity conjecture [Reference Campana and PăunCP15].

Let k be an algebraically closed field. A variety (over k) is an integral finite type separated scheme over k. A $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifold (over k) $(X, \Delta )$ is a variety X together with a $\mathbb {Q}$ -Weil divisor $\Delta $ on X such that all coefficients of $\Delta $ are in $[0,1]$ . If $\Delta = \sum _i \nu _i \Delta _i$ is the decomposition of $\Delta $ into prime divisors, we say that $m(\Delta _i) := (1-\nu _i)^{-1}$ is the multiplicity of $\Delta _i$ in $\Delta $ . If all multiplicities of a $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifold are in $\mathbb {Z} \cup \{ \infty \}$ , we say that $(X,\Delta )$ is a $\mathbb {Z}$ -orbifold or simply an orbifold.

A $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifold $(X, \Delta )$ is normal if the underlying variety X is normal. Moreover, a $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifold $(X, \Delta )$ is smooth (over k) if the underlying variety X is smooth and the support of the orbifold divisor $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta $ is a divisor with strict normal crossings. This means that every component of $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta $ is smooth and that étale locally around any point of X, the divisor $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta $ is given by an equation of the form $x_1\cdots x_n=0$ for some $n \leq \dim X$ . (At this point, let us note that we follow Campana and employ the term “orbifold” in the less conventional sense of the word. Thus, a “smooth orbifold over k” does not refer to a finite type separated smooth Deligne-Mumford algebraic stack over k with a trivial generic stabilizer nor its coarse moduli space. What we refer to as an orbifold is nowadays also referred to as a C-pair.)

Let $(X, \Delta _X)$ be a normal $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifold and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ be a $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifold such that Y is locally factorial. In this case, we define a morphism of $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifolds $f \colon (X, \Delta _X) \to (Y, \Delta _Y)$ to be a morphism of varieties $f \colon X \to Y$ satisfying $f(X) \nsubseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _Y$ such that, for every prime divisor $E \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _Y$ and every prime divisor $D \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} f^*E$ , we have $t m(D) \geq m(E)$ , where $t \in \mathbb {Q}$ denotes the coefficient of D in $f^*E$ ; the local factoriality of Y ensures that E is a Cartier divisor, so that $f^\ast E$ is well defined. Note that, equivalently, we can require that $t - 1 + \nu _D \geq t \nu _E$ , where $\nu _D$ and $\nu _E$ are the coefficients of D in $\Delta _X$ and of E in $\Delta _Y$ , respectively.

If X is a normal variety, we identify X with the orbifold $(X, 0)$ . If X and Y are varieties such that X is normal and Y is locally factorial, every morphism of varieties $X \to Y$ is an orbifold morphism $(X,0) \to (Y,0)$ .

A $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifold $(X, \Delta )$ is proper (resp. projective) if the underlying variety X is proper (resp. projective) over k. A smooth proper $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifold $(X,\Delta )$ is of general type if $K_X+\Delta $ is a big $\mathbb {Q}$ -divisor, where $K_X$ denotes the canonical divisor of X. If $\Delta =0$ , we recover the usual notion of a smooth proper variety of general type. If the multiplicities of $\Delta $ are all infinite, then $(X,\Delta )$ is of general type if and only if the smooth quasi-projective variety $X\setminus \Delta $ is of log-general type. Finally, if X is a smooth proper variety of nonnegative Kodaira dimension, D is a strict normal crossings divisor, and $m \geq 2$ , then the orbifold $(X, (1-\frac {1}{m})D)$ is of general type if and only if $X \setminus D$ is of log-general type.

Theorem 1.1. If $(Y,\Delta )$ is a smooth proper orbifold pair of general type and X is a normal variety, then the set of separably dominant orbifold morphisms $X\to (Y,\Delta )$ is finite.

We prove a more general result in which we consider rational maps ; see Theorem 5.4 for a precise statement.

Theorem 1.1 (or, actually, its more precise version Theorem 5.4) generalizes Kobayashi–Ochiai’s finiteness theorem for dominant rational maps to a projective variety of general type in characteristic zero (take $\Delta $ to be trivial and k of characteristic zero) [Reference Kobayashi and OchiaiKO75]. It also implies Tsushima’s extension of Kobayashi–Ochiai’s theorem to varieties of log-general type (take the multiplicities of $\Delta $ to be infinity and k of characteristic zero) [Reference TsushimaTsu79]. Moreover, we also obtain the finiteness theorem of Martin-Deschamps and Menegaux for separably dominant morphisms to a proper variety of general type (take $\Delta $ to be trivial and k of arbitrary characteristic) [Reference Martin-Deschamps and Lewin-MénégauxMDLM78], as well as Iwanari–Moriwaki’s extension of Tsushima’s result to characteristic p [Reference Iwanari and MoriwakiIM07]. Finally, we obtain a new proof of Campana’s extension of De Franchis’s theorem for one-dimensional smooth proper orbifold pairs of general type; see [Reference CampanaCam05, §3].

The theorem of Kobayashi–Ochiai can be made effective in the sense that one can give effective upper bounds for the number of dominant maps from a fixed variety to a fixed variety of general type; see [Reference Bandman and DethloffBD97, Reference HeierHei05, Reference Naranjo and PirolaNP07]. It seems reasonable to expect that one can obtain similar effective statements in the orbifold setting.

One part of the Green–Griffiths–Lang conjecture predicts that every complex projective hyperbolic variety is of general type. In particular, the theorem of Kobayashi–Ochiai suggests that a similar finiteness statement for dominant maps should hold for projective hyperbolic varieties. Such a finiteness result for projective hyperbolic varieties was, in fact, already conjectured by Lang in the early seventies (see [Reference LangLan74]) and proven by Noguchi [Reference NoguchiNog92] (see also [Reference SuzukiSuz93]) in the early nineties.

We stress that, conjecturally, a complex projective variety is of general type if and only if it is “pseudo-hyperbolic” (i.e., there is a proper closed subset $\Delta {\subsetneq } X$ such that every entire curve ${\mathbb {C}}\to X^{\operatorname {\mathrm {an}}}$ lands in $\Delta $ ). The analogous finiteness statement for dominant maps to a pseudo-hyperbolic projective variety is currently not known. In particular, its extension to Campana’s orbifold pairs is not known either.

As a straightforward application of Theorem 1.1, we prove the finiteness of the set of surjective endomorphisms of an orbifold pair of general type; see Corollary 5.6 for a precise statement.

We were first led to investigate the orbifold extension of the theorem of Kobayashi–Ochiai in our joint work with Rousseau on rational points over number fields. We refer the reader to [Reference Bartsch, Javanpeykar and RousseauBJR, Theorem 1.1] for arithmetic applications of our orbifold extension of Kobayashi–Ochiai’s finiteness theorem.

Our proof of Theorem 1.1 follows the general strategy of Kobayashi-Ochiai (and Tsushima). However, these proofs crucially rely on properties of differential forms on (log-)general type varieties (see, for example, [Reference TsushimaTsu79, Lemma 7] for a key step in Tsushima’s proof relying on properties of tensor powers of the sheaf of differential forms). The main difficulty in proving Theorem 1.1 is that differentials for an orbifold pair $(X,\Delta )$ are not well-behaved. One may even say that there is no meaningful way to define a sheaf $\Omega ^1_{(X,\Delta )}$ of orbifold differentials on X. However, in his seminal work on orbifold pairs [Reference CampanaCam11, §2], Campana suggests to instead use locally free sheaves which mimick sheaves of symmetric differentials. These sheaves are abusively denoted by $S^n \Omega ^p_{(X,\Delta )}$ despite the lack of existence of $\Omega ^p_{(X,\Delta )}$ ; see Section 4 for a precise definition. The aforementioned key step in Tsushima’s proof is then replaced by an argument involving symmetric differentials on $(X,\Delta )$ ; see the proof of Proposition 5.2 for details.

1.1 Conventions

We work over an algebraically closed field k. A variety is an integral separated scheme of finite type over k. If X and Y are varieties, we write $X \times Y$ for $X \times _{\operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} k} Y$ . A point of a variety is a schematic point and need not be closed. If $\mathcal {L}$ is a line bundle, D is a $\mathbb {Q}$ -divisor, and n is a natural number such that $nD$ is a $\mathbb {Z}$ -divisor, we abuse notation and write $(\mathcal {L}(D))^{\otimes n}$ instead of $\mathcal {L}^{\otimes n}(nD)$ .

2 Orbifold near-maps

In this paper, we work with the more general notion of an orbifold near-map (Definition 2.4). This is a natural replacement of “rational map of varieties” in the setting of orbifold pairs.

Definition 2.1. An open subscheme $U \subseteq X$ of a variety X is big if its complement is of codimension at least two.

Definition 2.2. A rational map of varieties is a near-map if there is a big open $U \subseteq X$ such that is a morphism.

Note that a rational map is a near-map if and only if it is defined at all codimension one points of X. For example, for every normal variety X and any proper variety Y, every rational map is a near-map.

Remark 2.3. If X and Y are varieties with X locally factorial, and is a near-map, we can pull back a line bundle $\mathcal {L}$ on Y to a line bundle $\tilde {\mathcal {L}}$ on X. Indeed, while the pullback bundle $f^*\mathcal {L}$ is a priori only defined on a big open of X, as X is locally factorial, it extends uniquely to a line bundle on all of X by [Har77, Proposition II.6.5(b) and Corollary II.6.16]. Since locally factorial schemes are normal, global sections of $\mathcal {L}$ also pull back to global sections of $\tilde {\mathcal {L}}$ .

Definition 2.4. Let $(X, \Delta _X)$ be a normal orbifold and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ be an orbifold such that Y is locally factorial. Then an orbifold near-map

is a near-map satisfying $f(X) {\nsubseteq } \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _{Y}$ such that, for every prime divisor $E {\subseteq } \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _{Y}$ and every prime divisor $D {\subseteq } \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} f^{*}E$ , we have $t m(D) {\geq } m(E)$ , where $t \in {\mathbb {Q}}$ denotes the coefficient of D in $f^{*}E$ ; this pullback is well defined as E is Cartier. As before, this is equivalent to requiring $t - 1 + \nu _D \geq t \nu _{E}$ , where $\nu _D$ and $\nu _{E}$ are the coefficients of D in $\Delta _{X}$ and of E in $\Delta _{Y}$ , respectively.

Caution is advised: the composition of orbifold morphisms need not be an orbifold map. Indeed, although the condition on the multiplicities of divisor pullbacks is stable under composition, the image of the composition might be completely contained in the orbifold divisor of the target. For example, consider the morphism $\mathbb {P}^1 \to (\mathbb {P}^1, (1/2)\cdot \underline {\infty })$ given by $z \mapsto z^2$ and the inclusion of the point $\infty $ into $\mathbb {P}^1$ . While both morphisms are orbifold, their composition is the inclusion of the point $\infty $ into $(\mathbb {P}^1, (1/2)\cdot \underline {\infty })$ , which is not an orbifold morphism. There is, however, one situation in which we can compose orbifold morphisms. Namely, if the composition of two orbifold morphisms is dominant, then the composition is again an orbifold morphism. Similar composition behaviour continues to hold for orbifold near-maps.

Lemma 2.5. Let $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ be an orbifold such that Y is locally factorial. Let X and Z be locally factorial varieties. Let be an orbifold near-map, and let be a near-map. If the composition $f \circ g$ exists, is defined in codimension $1$ and does not factor over $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _Y \subset Y$ , it defines an orbifold near-map .

Proof. Let $U \subseteq Z$ be the open subset on which the naive composition $f \circ g$ exists, and let $V \subseteq X$ be the maximal open on which f is defined. Then, by assumption, U is a big open of Z. The morphism $f \circ g \colon U \to Y$ is the composition of the morphism of varieties $U \to V$ with the orbifold morphism $V \to (Y, \Delta _Y)$ . As the image of the composition is not contained in $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _Y$ , the composition $f \circ g \colon U \to (Y, \Delta _Y)$ is thus a morphism of orbifolds. This concludes the proof.

Remark 2.6. The assumption that the composition $f \circ g$ exists and is defined in codimension $1$ is necessary. In fact, the weaker condition that $f \circ g$ exists and extends to a map defined in codimension $1$ does not suffice. This was overlooked in an earlier version of the paper. We give a counterexample. Let Y be the blowup of $\mathbb {P}^2$ in one point $p \in Y$ , and let $E \subset Y$ be the exceptional divisor. The inverse of the blowup defines an orbifold near-map , as the pullback of E along this map is trivial. Now, if $C \subset \mathbb {P}^2$ is any smooth curve passing through the blown up point p, the composition is not defined at p. This map extends to a morphism of varieties $C \to Y$ . However, this composition is no longer an orbifold morphism, as the pullback of the divisor E to C is given by $[p]$ , which does not have the required multiplicity.

We note the following special case of Lemma 2.5.

Corollary 2.7. Let X be a smooth variety, and let $(Y,\Delta _Y)$ be a smooth proper orbifold. Let $Z \subset X$ be a locally closed smooth subvariety, and let be a dominant orbifold near-map. If $f|_Z$ exists, is defined in codimension one and is still dominant, then it defines an orbifold near-map .

In Section 4 and in the proof of Theorem 1.1, it will be convenient to use the following notion of products for orbifold pairs.

Definition 2.8. If $(X, \Delta _X)$ and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ are two orbifolds, then we define the product orbifold by

$$\begin{align*}(X, \Delta_X) \times (Y, \Delta_Y) := (X \times Y, \Delta_X \times Y + X \times \Delta_Y).\end{align*}$$

If X and Y are locally factorial, the product of orbifolds defined above satisfies the universal property of a product. More specifically, for any orbifold $(T, \Delta _T)$ and for any two orbifold morphisms

$$\begin{align*}\phi_X \colon (T, \Delta_T) \to (X, \Delta_X), \quad \phi_Y \colon (T, \Delta_T) \to (Y, \Delta_Y),\end{align*}$$

there is a unique orbifold morphism $\phi \colon (T, \Delta _T) \to (X, \Delta _X) \times (Y, \Delta _Y)$ such that $\phi _X = \pi _X \circ ~\phi $ and $\phi _Y = \pi _Y \circ ~\phi $ . Indeed, it is clear that there is a morphism $\phi \colon (T, \Delta _T) \to X \times Y$ , and we just have to check that this is indeed an orbifold morphism after equipping $X \times Y$ with its orbifold structure. First note that the set of closed points $t \in T$ satisfying $\phi _X(t) \notin \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _X$ is a nonempty, hence dense, open subset of T. Of course, the same holds for the condition $\phi _Y(t) \notin \mathrm {supp} \Delta _Y$ , so there is a closed point $t \in T$ satisfying both conditions. Thus, the image of $\phi $ is not contained in $\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} (\Delta _X \times Y + X \times \Delta _Y)$ . Now let $E \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} (\Delta _X \times Y + X \times \Delta _Y)$ be a prime divisor. Without loss of generality, we may assume that $E = E_X \times Y$ for some prime divisor $E_X \subseteq X$ . Now let $D \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \phi _X^* E_X$ be a prime divisor, and let r be its coefficient in $\phi _X^* E_X$ . Since we know that $\phi _X$ is an orbifold morphism, we have $r m(D) \geq m(E_X)$ . Now note that $\phi ^* E = \phi _X^* E_X$ , so that r is also the coefficient of D in $\phi ^* E$ . Furthermore, we have $m(E_X) = m(E)$ . Thus, $r m(D) \geq m(E)$ , and $\phi $ is an orbifold morphism, as desired.

3 Families of maps

In this section, we consider families of maps and prove that certain conditions on the maps are either open or closed. More precisely, we show in Lemma 3.1 that a morphism landing in a closed subscheme is a closed condition, in Lemma 3.6 that a rational function being dominant is an open condition, and in Lemma 3.9 that the pullback of a fixed differential form having no poles outside some fixed divisor is a closed condition.

Lemma 3.1. Let S be a scheme. Let $X\to S$ be a flat morphism whose geometric fibres are reduced. Let Y and T be S-schemes, and let $F \colon X \times _S T \to Y$ be an S-morphism. Then, for every closed subscheme $Z \subset Y$ , the set of t in T such that $F_t \colon X \times _S \{t\} \to Y$ factors over Z is closed in T.

Proof. Let $T_1\subset T$ be the set of t in T such that $F_t$ factors over Z. We consider $T_1 = \sqcup _{t\in T_1} \operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} \kappa (t)$ as an S-scheme. To show that $T_1$ is closed in T, it suffices to show that $\overline {T_1} = T_1$ . We endow $\overline {T_1}\subset T$ with the reduced closed subscheme structure. The natural morphism $T_1\subset \overline {T_1}$ is dominant. Since $X\to S$ is flat, the basechange $X\times _S T_1\to X\times _S \overline {T_1}$ is (also) dominant. Since $X\times _S T_1\to Y$ factors set-theoretically through Z and $X\times _S T_1\to X\times _S \overline {T_1}$ is dominant, we see that the restriction of F to $X\times _S \overline {T_1}$ (also) factors set-theoretically through Z. However, for any $t\in \overline {T_1}$ , the scheme $X\times _S \operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} \kappa (t)$ is geometrically reduced over $\kappa (t)$ . In particular, $F_t$ factors (scheme-theoretically) through Z, as required.

Definition 3.2. A rational map of varieties over k is separably dominant if it is dominant and $k(Y) \subset k(X)$ is separable.

Lemma 3.3. Let $f \colon X \to Y$ be a morphism of smooth varieties. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (a) The morphism f is separably dominant.

  2. (b) There is a closed point $x \in X$ such that $df_x \colon \textrm {T}_x X \to \textrm {T}_{f(x)} Y$ is surjective.

  3. (c) There is a closed point $x \in X$ such that f is smooth at x.

Proof. Assume (a) holds. Let $Z \subseteq X$ be the locus of points where the rank of $df_x$ is less than $\dim Y$ . Since $K(Y)\subset K(X)$ is a separable field extension, the arguments used to prove [Reference HartshorneHar77, Lemma III.10.5] and [Reference HartshorneHar77, Proposition III.10.6] show that the dimension of $\overline {f(Z)}$ is less than $\dim Y$ . Thus, since f is dominant, this implies that $Z \neq X$ . In particular, there is a closed point $x \in X$ such that the rank of $df_x$ is equal to $\dim Y$ . Since Y is smooth, this shows that (b) holds.

Assume (b) holds. Then [Reference HartshorneHar77, Proposition III.10.4] shows that (c) holds.

Now assume that (c) holds. There is an open neighborhood $U \subseteq X$ of x such that $f\vert _U$ is smooth. Smooth maps are flat, and flat maps of varieties are open. Hence, $f(U)$ is a nonempty open of Y. Thus, f is dominant. In particular, f maps the generic point of X to the generic point of Y. The smoothness of $f\vert _U$ also implies that f is smooth at the generic point of X. Since generically smooth morphisms are separable, we see that (a) holds. This concludes the proof.

Lemma 3.4. Let X and Y be varieties of the same dimension. Assume that X is smooth. Let $f \colon X \to Y$ be a morphism. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (a) The morphism f is separably dominant.

  2. (b) There is a closed point $x \in X$ such that $df_x \colon \textrm {T}_x X \to \textrm {T}_{f(x)} Y$ is an isomorphism.

Proof. Assume (a) holds. Let $U \subseteq Y$ be the locus of smooth points of Y. Then U is a dense open of Y, and the restriction of $f \colon f^{-1}(U) \to U$ is still separably dominant. Thus, we may assume that Y is smooth. In particular, by Lemma 3.3, there is a closed point x in X such that $df_x \colon \textrm {T}_x X \to \textrm {T}_{f(x)} Y$ is surjective. Since X and Y are smooth of the same dimension, it follows that $df_x$ is an isomorphism.

Assume (b) holds. Then, the point $f(x)$ is a regular point of Y. We can thus replace Y by an open neighborhood of $f(x)$ and replace X by the preimage of that. The assumption on the dimensions continues to hold, so we may assume that Y is smooth. Consequently, by Lemma 3.3, the morphism f is separably dominant.

Definition 3.5. If X, Y and T are varieties, we say that a rational map is a relative rational map (over T) if the maximal open subset $U \subseteq X \times T$ on which f is defined has nonempty intersection with every closed fiber $X_t := X \times \{t\}$ . In other words, it is a family of rational maps parametrized by the variety T.

Lemma 3.6. Let X and Y be varieties of the same dimension, and let T be any variety. Let be a relative rational map. Then the locus of $t \in T$ such that is separably dominant is open in T.

Proof. Replacing X by an alteration if necessary, we may assume that X is smooth [Reference de JongdJ96, Theorem 4.1]. Let $U \subseteq X \times T$ be the maximal open subset on which F is defined. The map F then induces a morphism of T-schemes $G \colon U \to Y \times T$ .

We claim that if $(x,t) \in U$ is any closed point, the differential $dG_{(x,t)}$ is an isomorphism if and only if the differential of the rational map is an isomorphism at $x \in X$ . To see this, note that the tangent spaces of $X \times T$ and $Y \times T$ are the products of the tangent spaces of the factors. Furthermore, the component of $dG_{(x,t)}$ which maps $\textrm {T}_t T \to \textrm {T}_{F(x,t)} X$ is the zero map, and the component which maps $\textrm {T}_t T \to \textrm {T}_t T$ is just the identity. Lastly, the component of $dG_{(x,t)}$ mapping $\textrm {T}_x X \to \textrm {T}_{F_t(x)} Y$ is just $dF_t$ . This implies the claim.

Let $t \in T$ be a closed point. By Lemma 3.4, $F_t$ is separably dominant if and only if there is a closed point $x \in X$ such that the differential $dF_{t,x}$ is an isomorphism. By the previous claim, this happens if and only if there is a closed point $x \in X$ such that $dG_{(x,t)}$ is an isomorphism.

Let $V \subseteq U$ be the set of all points at which the differential of G is an isomorphism. The set V is open in U, and hence open in $X \times T$ . The map $X \times T \to T$ is flat, and hence open. Thus, the projection of V to T is an open subset of T. By the previous paragraph, this is exactly the set of $t \in T$ for which $F_t$ is separably dominant, so we are done.

Remark 3.7. The locus of (separably) dominant maps is not necessarily closed in T in any characteristic; this seems to have been overlooked in [Reference Iwanari and MoriwakiIM07, Proposition 6.1]. We give two examples. First, in any characteristic, consider the map given by $(x,t)\mapsto xt$ . Its indeterminacy locus consists of the two points $(0,\infty )$ and $(\infty ,0)$ , so that this is indeed a relative rational map. If we fix any value $t \in \mathbb {P}^1 \setminus \{0,\infty \}$ , the resulting rational map is an isomorphism, and thus separably dominant. For $t \in \{0, \infty \}$ , the resulting map is constant. Thus, the locus where the map is separably dominant is $\mathbb {P}^1 \setminus \{0,\infty \} \subseteq \mathbb {P}^1$ ; this is open but not closed. Next, we give an example pointed out by the referee when k has characteristic two. Namely, let $C $ be the zero locus of $x^2-yz$ in $\mathbb {P}^2_{k}$ . Note that C is a strange curve [Reference HartshorneHar77, Theorem IV.3.9]. For $q\in \mathbb {P}^2(k)$ , let $\pi _q\colon \mathbb {P}^2 \setminus \{q\}\to \mathbb {P}^1$ be the projection away from the point q. Let be the rational map defined by $F(c,q) = \pi _q(c)$ . Note that, for every $q\in \mathbb {P}^2$ , the rational map extends to a surjective morphism. This morphism has the following properties.

  1. (i) For $q \in C(k)$ , the morphism $F(-,q)$ has degree one, and is thus an isomorphism from C to $\mathbb {P}^1$ .

  2. (ii) For $q \in \mathbb {P}^2(k) \setminus (C \cup \{(1:0:0)\})$ , the surjective morphism $F(-,q)$ is separable of degree two.

  3. (iii) For $q=(1:0:0)$ , the surjective morphism $F(-,q) $ is not separable.

Thus, $T=\mathbb {P}^2$ parametrizes dominant maps from C to $\mathbb {P}^1$ , but only over the non-closed open subset $ \mathbb {P}^2\setminus \{(1:0:0) \}$ are the maps separable.

The following statement is a purely algebraic result which we will use in the proof of Lemma 3.9 below. Recall that if M is an R-module, and $f \in R$ is an element, the element f is called M-regular if the morphism $M \to M$ , $m \mapsto fm$ is injective. In the special case that $M = S$ is an R-algebra, this is equivalent to f being a nonzerodivisor in S. If S is additionally assumed to be reduced and noetherian, this in turn is equivalent to asking that $\operatorname {\mathrm {V}}(f) \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} S$ has codimension $\geq 1$ (where the empty set is considered to have codimension $\infty $ ).

Lemma 3.8. Let R be a noetherian ring, let S be a noetherian R-algebra and let $f \in S$ . Let M be a finitely generated S-module. Assume that M is flat over R, and assume that for every maximal ideal $\mathfrak {m} \subseteq S$ , the element f is $M/(\mathfrak {m} \cap R)M$ -regular. Then f is M-regular and $M/fM$ is flat over R.

Proof. See [Reference MatsumuraMat80, §20F Corollary 1].

The following lemma and proof are essentially due to Tsushima [Reference TsushimaTsu79, Lemma 5]. Before starting the proof, we briefly discuss extending relative rational maps. Let be a relative rational map with X, T normal varieties, and Y a proper variety. Then, by properness of Y and normality of $X \times T$ , the rational map extends to a morphism $U \to Y$ on a maximal open set $U \subseteq X \times T$ with complement of codimension at least $2$ . However, for any given closed point $t \in T$ , it might still happen that $U_t := U \cap X_t \subseteq X$ has a complement of codimension $1$ . While the restriction of G to $U_t$ will extend to a rational map defined in codimension $1$ , this extension will in general not be compatible with .

Lemma 3.9. Let X and Y be smooth projective varieties of the same dimension n, and let T be a variety. Let be a relative rational map over T. Let $D_X$ be an effective divisor on X, and let $D_Y$ be a divisor on Y. Let $m \geq 0$ . Let $\omega \in \Gamma (Y, \omega _Y^{\otimes m}(D_Y))$ . Assume that for every closed point $t \in T$ , the rational map is separably dominant. Then, the set $T_\omega $ of $t \in T$ such that $G_t^*\omega $ lies in $ \Gamma (X, \omega _X^{\otimes m}(D_X))$ is closed in T.

Proof. The case $\omega = 0$ is clear, so suppose $\omega \neq 0$ . By replacing T with an alteration if necessary, we may assume that T is smooth.

Consider the pullback form $G^*\omega $ , and note that it defines a rational section of the vector bundle $(\Omega ^n_{X \times T})^{\otimes m}$ . For any closed point $t \in T$ , we pullback $G^*\omega $ along the inclusion $\iota _t \colon X := X\times \{t\} \subseteq X \times T$ to get the form $\iota _t^*G^*\omega = G_t^*\omega $ . Let E and F be the divisors of zeroes and poles of $G^*\omega $ , respectively. For t in T, we define $E_t := E \cap X_t$ and $F_t := F \cap X_t$ . Since $G_t$ is separably dominant and $\omega \neq 0$ , we have that, for every t in T, $E_t$ and $F_t$ are (possibly trivial) effective divisors in $X_t$ . Note that whenever $G_t$ is defined in codimension one, we have that $E_t$ (resp. $F_t$ ) is the divisor of zeroes (resp. poles) of $G_t^*\omega $ . However, if $G_t$ is not defined at all points of codimension $1$ , it may happen that $E_t$ and $F_t$ are strictly bigger than the divisor of zeroes and poles, respectively.

We now prove the result by induction on $\dim (T)$ . The case $\dim (T)=0$ is clear. Consider the set S of all t in T such that $\dim (E_t \cap F_t) = n-1$ . By semicontinuity of fiber dimension, S is closed in T (since $\dim (E_t \cap F_t)> n-1$ cannot occur). The condition $t \in S$ implies that $G_t$ cannot be defined in codimension $1$ . Otherwise, the form $G_t^*\omega $ would have to have both a pole and a zero along the codimension $1$ subset $E_t \cap F_t$ , which is absurd. Since G is defined at all points of codimension $1$ , we see $\dim (S)<\dim (T)$ . By the inductive hypothesis, it follows that $S_\omega =S \cap T_\omega $ is closed.

We now show that $F\to T$ is flat using Lemma 3.8. First, note that it is locally cut out by the vanishing of a single equation given by the denominator of $G^*\omega $ . Furthermore, the morphism $X \times T \to T$ is flat and, for every closed point t in T, the scheme-theoretic fiber $F_t$ of $F \to T$ is a divisor of $X_t$ . Thus, we conclude that $F \to T$ is flat by Lemma 3.8.

In particular, there is a morphism $T \to \mathrm {Hilb}(X)$ representing the family $(F_t)_{t \in T}$ , where $\mathrm {Hilb}(X)$ is the Hilbert scheme of X over k. Now, as there are only finitely many effective divisors with the property of being $\leq D_X$ , the set of such divisors form a (finite) closed subscheme of $\mathrm {Hilb}(X)$ . It follows that $F_t \leq D_X$ is a closed condition on t.

For t in T, the condition $F_t\leq D_X$ implies that $G_t^* \omega \in \Gamma (X,\omega _X^{\otimes m}(D_X))$ . Moreover, outside the set S (defined above), the condition $G_t^*\omega \in \Gamma (X,\omega _X^{\otimes m}(D_X))$ is equivalent to $F_t \leq D_X$ . Thus, a point $t \in T$ lies in $T_\omega $ if and only if we have $t \in S \cap T_\omega $ or $F_t \leq D_X$ . As $S\cap T_\omega $ is closed in T and the set of t in T with $F_t\leq D_X$ is closed in T, this concludes the proof.

4 Symmetric differentials on orbifolds

In this section, we collect some statements regarding the sheaf of symmetric differentials on an orbifold. We start by recalling their definition, first given by Campana in [Reference CampanaCam11, Section 2.5].

Definition 4.1. Let $(X, \Delta )$ be a smooth orbifold. Let $n, p \geq 0$ be natural numbers. The sheaf of symmetric differentials, written $S^n \Omega ^p_{(X,\Delta )}$ , is the locally free subsheaf of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^n \Omega ^p_X(\log \left \lceil {\Delta } \right \rceil )$ which is étale-locally generated by the following elements:

$$ \begin{align*}x^{ \left\lceil {k/m} \right\rceil } \bigotimes_{i=1}^n \frac{dx_{J_i}}{x_{J_i}}.\end{align*} $$

Here, the following notation was used:

  • $x_1,...,x_{\dim (X)}$ are a set of local coordinates which exhibit $\Delta $ in normal crossing form.

  • The $J_i$ are subsets of $\{1,...,\dim (X)\}$ of size p.

  • $dx_{J_i} := \bigwedge _{j \in J_i} dx_j$ and $x_{J_i} := \prod _{j \in J_i} x_j$

  • k is a tuple of $\dim (X)$ integers, where the j-th entry counts the number of occurrences of j in the $J_i$ .

  • m is a tuple of $\dim (X)$ integers, where the j-th entry is the multiplicity of the coordinate $x_j$ in $\Delta $ .

  • $x^{ \left \lceil {k/m} \right \rceil } := \prod _{j=1}^{\dim (X)} x_j^{ \left \lceil {k_j/m_j} \right \rceil }$

Definition 4.2. Let $(X, \Delta _X)$ be a normal orbifold. Choose a big open $U \subseteq X$ such that U is smooth and $\Delta _U := \Delta _X \cap U$ has strict normal crossings. We define $S^n \Omega ^p_{(X, \Delta _X)} := \iota _* S^n \Omega ^p_{(U, \Delta _U)}$ , where $\iota \colon U \to X$ is the inclusion.

For smooth proper varieties X without any orbifold structure, the sheaves $S^n \Omega ^p_{(X,0)}$ defined this way coincide with the usual symmetric powers of the module of differentials $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^n \Omega ^p_X$ . More generally, if $(X, \Delta )$ is an orbifold where all multiplicities in $\Delta $ are equal to $1$ or $\infty $ , the sheaves $S^n \Omega ^p_{(X,\Delta )}$ defined above coincide with the symmetric powers of the module of log differentials $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^n \Omega ^p_X(\log \Delta )$ . However, in general, the sheaves $S^n \Omega ^p_{(X,\Delta )}$ are not the symmetric powers of any coherent sheaf (so that calling them symmetric differentials is a significant abuse of language). The main use of $S^n \Omega ^p$ for us comes from the fact that these sheaves behave nicely when they are pulled back by orbifold morphisms.

Lemma 4.3. If $f \colon (X, \Delta _X) \to (Y, \Delta _Y)$ is a morphism of smooth orbifolds and $n, p \geq 0$ , then pullback of differential forms induces a morphism $f^*S^n \Omega ^p_{(Y, \Delta _Y)} \to S^n\Omega ^p_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ .

Proof. Campana shows this when $k=\mathbb {C}$ using computations in the analytic topology; see [Reference CampanaCam11, Proposition 2.11]. His arguments adapt to positive characteristic, as we show now.

We have a morphism of sheaves

$$\begin{align*}f^* \operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^n \Omega^p_Y(\log \left\lceil {\Delta_Y} \right\rceil ) \to \operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^n \Omega^p_X(\operatorname{\mathrm{supp}} (\Delta_X + f^* \Delta_Y)).\end{align*}$$

As $f^*S^n \Omega ^p_{(Y, \Delta _Y)}$ (resp. $S^n\Omega ^p_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ ) is a subsheaf of the source (resp. the target) of this morphism, we may argue étale-locally around a fixed point $\eta $ . As the sheaves involved are locally free, we may and do assume that $\eta \in X$ is of codimension $1$ (except for in the trivial situation in which X is zero-dimensional).

Locally around $\eta $ , the sheaf $f^* S^n \Omega ^p_{(Y,\Delta _Y)}$ is generated by the pullbacks of the local generators of $S^n \Omega ^p_{(Y,\Delta _Y)}$ around $f(\eta )$ (see Definition 4.1). Let $\omega \in S^n \Omega ^p_{(Y, \Delta _Y)}$ be such a generator. Let $\widetilde {Y} \to Y$ be a connected étale neighborhood of $f(\eta )$ such that

  1. (i) $\widetilde {Y}$ is an étale open of $\mathbb {A}^d$ with $d = \dim Y$ ,

  2. (ii) $\Delta _Y$ is in normal crossing form (i.e., $\Delta _Y$ is given by the pullback of $x_1\cdot \ldots \cdot x_\ell =0$ in $\mathbb {A}^d$ for some $\ell \geq 0$ ),

  3. (iii) $f(\eta )$ specializes to the origin of $\mathbb {A}^d$ , and

  4. (iv) $\omega $ has the form described in Definition 4.1.

There is a connected étale neighborhood $\widetilde {X} \to X$ of $\eta $ such that $f\vert _{\widetilde {X}}$ factors over $\widetilde {Y}$ and such that $\Delta _X$ is in normal crossings form. Since the induced morphism $f \colon (\widetilde {X}, \widetilde {X} \times _X \Delta _X) \to (\widetilde {Y}, \widetilde {Y} \times _Y \Delta _Y)$ is (still) orbifold, we may replace $(X, \Delta _X)$ by $(\widetilde {X}, \widetilde {X} \times _X \Delta _X)$ and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ by $(\widetilde {Y}, \widetilde {Y} \times _Y \Delta _Y)$ .

As Y is an étale open of $\mathbb {A}^d$ , we obtain a map $X \to \mathbb {A}^d$ given by d maps $f_1,...,f_d \colon X \to \mathbb {A}^1$ . For $i=1,\ldots ,d$ , we let $m_i$ denote the multiplicity of the (pullback of the) prime divisor $\{y_i=0\}$ in $\Delta _Y$ . Since $f(X)$ is not contained in $\Delta _Y$ , we know that whenever $m_i> 1$ , the function $f_i$ is not identically zero. Viewing $f_i$ as an element of the DVR $\mathcal {O}_{X, \eta }$ , we decompose it as $f_i = t^{\nu _i} g_i$ with t a uniformizer and $g_i(\eta ) \neq 0$ . Since f is an orbifold morphism, for any i with $\nu _i \neq 0$ , we have $\nu _i \geq \left \lceil {m_i/m_\eta } \right \rceil $ , where $m_\eta $ is the multiplicity of the divisor $\eta $ in $\Delta _X$ .

Let $J \subseteq \{1,...,d\}$ be a p-element subset, and consider the rational p-form $dy_J/y_J$ on Y. If none of the functions $f_i$ with $i \in J$ vanish along $\eta $ , the pullback $f^*(dy_J/y_J)$ has no pole at $\eta $ . If such an $i \in J$ exists, then $f^*(dy_J/y_J)$ has a pole of order at most $1$ . Since we can always write $f^*(dy_J/y_J) = (dt/t) \wedge u + v$ , where u is a $(p-1)$ -form with no pole at $\eta $ and v a p-form with no pole at $\eta $ , the pullback of $\omega $ is given by

$$\begin{align*}f^*\omega = \prod_{i=1}^d (f_i)^{ \left\lceil {k_i/m_i} \right\rceil } \bigotimes_{\alpha=1}^n \left( (\frac{dt}{t} \wedge u_\alpha) + v_\alpha \right).\end{align*}$$

Here, as before, $u_\alpha $ and $v_\alpha $ are forms with no pole at $\eta $ . We can write the tensor product of sums as a sum of tensor products. When doing this, the order at $\eta $ of each summand occuring in such a rewriting is at least

$$ \begin{align*}\left(\sum_{i=1}^d \left\lceil {\frac{k_i}{m_i}} \right\rceil \nu_i\right) - k_t,\end{align*} $$

where $k_t$ counts the number of $((dt/t) \wedge u_\alpha )$ -factors occuring in that summand (as opposed to $v_\alpha $ -factors). Note that $k_t \leq \sum k_i$ , where the sum runs over those i for which $\nu _i \geq 0$ . Using our estimate $\nu _i \geq \left \lceil {m_i/m_\eta } \right \rceil $ from before, we obtain that the order at $\eta $ of each summand is at least

$$ \begin{align*}\left(\sum_{\substack{i=1 \\ \nu_i \neq 0}}^d \left\lceil {\frac{k_i}{m_\eta}} \right\rceil \right) - k_t \geq -k_t + \left\lceil {\frac{k_t}{m_\eta}} \right\rceil ,\end{align*} $$

so the pole at $\eta $ is at most of the order we allow for elements of $S^n \Omega ^p_{(X, \Delta _X)}$ . Hence, $f^*\omega \in S^n \Omega ^p_{(X, \Delta _X)}$ , which concludes the proof.

If X is a smooth variety of dimension n, the sheaf $S^1 \Omega ^n_{(X,0)}$ is just the canonical sheaf $\omega _X$ . Thus, one might guess that for a smooth orbifold $(X, \Delta )$ , the sheaf $S^1 \Omega ^n_{(X,\Delta )}$ should correspond to a line bundle related to the $\mathbb {Q}$ -divisor $K_X + \Delta $ . Of course, naively formulated like this, this guess does not really make sense, since $K_X + \Delta $ is not a $\mathbb {Z}$ -divisor and hence does not correspond to any line bundle. However, as we show now, the intuition can be saved. (Recall our convention that, for $\mathcal {L}$ a line bundle, D a $\mathbb {Q}$ -divisor, and n a natural number such that $nD$ is a $\mathbb {Z}$ -divisor, we write $(\mathcal {L}(D))^{\otimes n}$ instead of $\mathcal {L}^{\otimes n}(nD)$ .)

Lemma 4.4. Let $(X, \Delta )$ be a smooth orbifold of dimension n, and let N be a natural number such that $N \Delta $ is a $\mathbb {Z}$ -divisor. Then $S^N \Omega ^n_{(X, \Delta )} \cong \omega _X(\Delta )^{\otimes N} :=\omega _X^{\otimes N}(N \Delta )$ .

Proof. For the sheaf of log-differentials, we have $\Omega ^n_X(\log \left \lceil {\Delta } \right \rceil ) = \omega _X( \left \lceil {\Delta } \right \rceil )$ (see [Reference IitakaIit82, §11.1]). It follows that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^N \Omega ^n_X(\log \left \lceil {\Delta } \right \rceil ) = \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^N \omega _X( \left \lceil {\Delta } \right \rceil )$ . Since symmetric powers of line bundles agree with tensor powers, it follows that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^N \omega _X( \left \lceil {\Delta } \right \rceil ) = \omega _X( \left \lceil {\Delta } \right \rceil )^{\otimes N}$ . Thus, $S^N \Omega ^n_{(X, \Delta )}$ is by construction a locally free subsheaf of $\omega _X( \left \lceil {\Delta } \right \rceil )^{\otimes N}$ . More precisely, we see that locally around a point $p \in X$ , it is the subsheaf generated by the single element

$$ \begin{align*}x_1^{N/m_1}...x_n^{N/m_n} \bigotimes_{l=1}^N \frac{dx_1 \wedge dx_2 ... \wedge dx_n}{x_1x_2...x_n},\end{align*} $$

where $x_1,...,x_n$ are a set of normal crossing coordinates for $\Delta $ , and $m_i$ denotes the multiplicity of the coordinate $x_i$ in the orbifold divisor. The subsheaf generated by this element is equal to $\omega _X(\Delta )^{\otimes N}$ in some neighborhood of p. The claim follows since p was arbitrary.

Corollary 4.5. Let be a near-map of orbifolds with $n := \dim X = \dim Y$ . Assume that X is smooth and that $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ is smooth. Let N be a natural number such that $N \Delta _X$ and $N \Delta _Y$ are $\mathbb {Z}$ -divisors. Then there is an induced pullback morphism $f^* \omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N} \to \omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}$ of locally free sheaves on X.

Proof. By Lemma 4.4, we have $\omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N}= S^N \Omega ^n_{(Y, \Delta _Y)}$ . Similarly, as $n = \dim X = \dim Y$ , we have $\omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N} = S^N \Omega ^n_{(X, \Delta _X)}$ , as this equality holds over a big open and both sides are line bundles. By Lemma 4.3, we get a morphism $f^* S^N \Omega ^n_{(Y, \Delta _Y)} \to S^N \Omega ^n_{(U, \Delta _X \cap U)}$ of sheaves on U, where $U \subseteq X$ denotes the intersection of the domain of definition of f with the snc locus of $(X, \Delta _X)$ . Since $U \subseteq X$ is a big open, by Remark 2.3, the line bundle $f^*\omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N}$ on U extends to a line bundle on X. Furthermore, as the morphism of locally free sheaves extends as well by Hartogs, this concludes the proof.

If X and T are smooth varieties, and $\pi _X \colon X \times T \to X$ and $\pi _T \colon X \times T \to T$ denote the canonical projections, we get a direct sum composition for the Kähler differentials:

$$ \begin{align*}\Omega^1_{X \times T} \cong \pi_X^* \Omega^1_X \oplus \pi_T^* \Omega^1_T.\end{align*} $$

Passing to exterior powers, and noting that taking exterior powers commutes with taking pullbacks, we retain such a direct sum decomposition, although it gets slightly more involved:

$$ \begin{align*}\Omega^m_{X \times T} \cong \bigoplus_{i=0}^m \pi_X^* \Omega^i_X \otimes \pi_T^* \Omega^{m-i}_T.\end{align*} $$

Lastly, if A and B are modules over any commutative ring, we have the following direct sum decomposition for the symmetric powers:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^n(A \oplus B) \cong \bigoplus_{i=0}^n (\operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^i A \otimes \operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^{n-i} B).\end{align*} $$

By combining the two previous lines, we obtain that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^n \pi _X^* \Omega ^m_X$ is a direct summand of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^n \Omega ^m_{X \times T}$ . Hence, we get an idempotent endomorphism of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^n \Omega ^m_{X \times T}$ which projects an element into that summand. Furthermore, if $t \in T$ is any closed point and $\iota _t \colon X = X \times \{t\} \subseteq X \times T$ is the inclusion, then the pullback map $\iota _t^* \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^n \Omega ^m_{X \times T} \to \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^n \Omega ^m_X$ factors over that projection. We now prove the analogous result for orbifolds (see Definition 2.8 for the notion of a product of orbifold pairs).

Lemma 4.6. Let $(X, \Delta _X)$ and $(T, \Delta _T)$ be normal orbifolds. Let $\pi _X$ denote the canonical projection $X \times T \to X$ . Then for all natural numbers N and m, the sheaf $\pi _X^* S^N \Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ is a direct summand of $S^N \Omega ^m_{(X, \Delta _X) \times (T,\Delta _T)}$ .

Proof. First assume that the result is true in the case of the smooth orbifolds. Let $X^o \subseteq X$ and $T^o \subseteq T$ denote the snc loci, and note that these are big opens. Then, since forming the pushforward commutes with forming direct sums, we see that $\iota _{(X^o \times T^o)*}\pi _{X^o}^*S^N \Omega ^m_{(X^o, \Delta _{X^o})}$ is a direct summand of $S^N \Omega ^m_{(X, \Delta _X) \times (T, \Delta _T)}$ . Since $\iota _{(X^o \times T^o)*} \pi _{X^o}^* = \pi _X^* \iota _{X^o*}$ for locally free sheaves, the desired result follows.

By the above, we may assume that $(X, \Delta _X)$ and $(T, \Delta _T)$ are smooth. Assume first that $\Delta _X$ and $\Delta _T$ are $\mathbb {Z}$ -divisors (i.e., that all multiplicities are either $1$ or $\infty $ ). In this case, we have $S^N \Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)} = \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^N \Omega ^m_X(\log \Delta _X)$ . The latter is a genuine symmetric power of an exterior power of $\Omega ^1_X(\log \Delta _X)$ . Notice that the decomposition

$$ \begin{align*}\Omega^1_{X \times T}(\log (\Delta_X \times T + X \times \Delta_T)) = \pi_X^* \Omega^1_X(\log \Delta_X) \oplus \pi_T^* \Omega^1_T(\log \Delta_T)\end{align*} $$

is still valid. Thus, the discussion of the previous paragraph applies, proving the result in this case.

Finally, we treat the general case in which $\Delta _X$ and $\Delta _T$ are not $\mathbb {Z}$ -divisors. By definition, the sheaf $S^N \Omega ^n_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ is a subsheaf of

$$\begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^N \Omega^m_{X}(\log \left\lceil {\Delta_X} \right\rceil ), \end{align*}$$

and, similarly, the sheaf $S^N \Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)\times (T,\Delta _T)}$ is a subsheaf of

$$\begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^N \Omega^m_{X\times T}(\log \left\lceil {\Delta_X\times T + X\times \Delta_T} \right\rceil ). \end{align*}$$

By the previous paragraph, we know that the morphism

$$\begin{align*}\pi_X^* \operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^N \Omega^m_{X}(\log \left\lceil {\Delta_X} \right\rceil ) \to \operatorname{\mathrm{Sym}}^N \Omega^m_{X\times T}(\log \left\lceil {\Delta_X \times T + X \times \Delta_T} \right\rceil ) \end{align*}$$

is injective and has a retract. Since the projection map $\pi _X$ is orbifold, it follows from Lemma 4.3 that the above injection sends the subsheaf $\pi _X^*S^N\Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ to the subsheaf $S^N\Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)\times (T,\Delta _T)}$ . To prove the claim, it thus suffices to show that the retraction also respects these subsheaves. This can be checked locally, and it suffices to consider the generators. This can be done very explicitly.

Indeed, let $(x,t) \in X \times T$ be any closed point, let $dx_1,...,dx_n$ be local coordinates for X around x which exhibit $\Delta _X$ in normal crossings form, and let $dt_1,...,dt_r$ be local coordinates for T around t which exhibit $\Delta _T$ in normal crossings form. Then $dx_1,...,dx_n, dt_1,..., dt_r$ are local coordinates for $X \times T$ exhibiting its orbifold divisor in normal crossings form. Let $\omega $ be a local generator of $S^N \Omega ^m_{(X, \Delta _X) \times (T,\Delta _T)}$ around $(x,t)$ . If $\omega $ contains any factors containing a $dt_i$ , the pullback $\iota _t^* \omega $ will be identically zero. Thus, it remains to consider the case where the only differentials appearing in $\omega $ are products of $dx_i$ terms. Pulling back such a generator of $S^N\Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)\times (T,\Delta _T)}$ along $\iota _t$ yields a (formally identical) generator of $S^N \Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ . This finishes the proof.

Lemma 4.7. Let $(X, \Delta _X)$ be a normal orbifold, and let $(T, \Delta _T)$ be a smooth orbifold. For a closed point $t \in T \setminus \Delta _T$ , write $\iota _t \colon X = X \times \{t\} \subseteq X \times T$ . Then, for any natural numbers m and N, the pullback map $\iota _t^* S^N \Omega ^m_{(X, \Delta _X) \times (T, \Delta _T)} \to S^N \Omega ^m_{(X, \Delta _X)}$ factors over the projection to $\iota _t^* \pi _X^* S^N \Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ .

Proof. We first show that the pullback map considered in the statement is well defined. To do so, let $X^o\subseteq X$ be the snc locus of $(X,\Delta _X)$ , and note that $X^o$ is a big open of X. The morphism $\iota _t \colon X \to X\times T$ induces an orbifold morphism $X^o\to X^o\times T$ (i.e., $\iota _t$ is orbifold over the snc locus). In particular, by Lemma 4.3, there is an induced morphism $\iota _t^* S^N \Omega ^m_{(X^o, \Delta _{X^o}) \times (T, \Delta _T)} \to S^N \Omega ^m_{(X^o, \Delta _{X^o})}$ . Since the sheaves involved are reflexive, this pullback map extends to a pullback map $\iota _t^* S^N \Omega ^m_{(X, \Delta _X) \times (T, \Delta _T)} \to S^N \Omega ^m_{(X, \Delta _X)}$ .

To see that the pullback map factors as claimed, note that $\pi _X \circ \iota _t = \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_X$ is the identity morphism, so that, in fact, $\iota _t^* \pi _X^* S^N \Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)} = S^N \Omega ^m_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ . This concludes the proof.

5 Kobayashi–Ochiai’s theorem for orbifold pairs

In this section, we prove the finiteness theorem for dominant maps into a smooth orbifold of general type $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ . The first step of the proof is to show that given a dominant morphism $f \colon (X, \Delta _X) \to (Y, \Delta _Y)$ , we can recover f from its induced map on global sections of the canonical bundles $\omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N}(Y) \to \omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}(X)$ for sufficiently large N, where N only depends on $(X, \Delta _X)$ and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ but not on f. This allows us to shift the focus from studying dominant morphisms to studying linear maps $\omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N}(Y) \to \omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}(X)$ satisfying certain conditions.

To state the next lemma, we introduce some terminology. We call a line bundle very big if the rational map to projective space induced by its global sections is birational onto its image. Note that every big line bundle has a tensor power which is very big. Of course, a very ample line bundle is very big. Also, if V is a vector space, the projective space $\mathbb {P}(V)$ parametrizes subspaces of codimension $1$ .

Lemma 5.1. Let X and Y be projective varieties. Assume that X is locally factorial. Let $\mathcal {L}_X$ and $\mathcal {L}_Y$ be line bundles on X and Y, respectively. Assume that $\mathcal {L}_X$ is very big and that $\mathcal {L}_Y$ is very ample. Consider the following set:

If $(f,\phi )$ and $(g,\psi )$ have the same image under the composed map of sets

$$ \begin{align*}S \to \operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}(\mathcal{L}_Y(Y), \mathcal{L}_X(X))\setminus\{0\} \to \{\text{rational maps from }\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{L}_X(X))\text{ to }\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{L}_Y(Y)) \},\end{align*} $$

then $f=g$ .

Proof. Before starting the proof, we note that the set S is well defined by Remark 2.3.

Let $(f, \phi )$ and $(g, \psi )$ be elements of S which induce the same rational map

By our assumptions on the line bundles, the space $\mathbb {P}(\mathcal {L}_X(X))$ contains a birational copy $\overline {X}$ of X and $\mathbb {P}(\mathcal {L}_Y(Y))$ contains Y. The following square commutes whenever the compositions are defined:

Here, the upper horizontal arrow can be either f or g. Note that the indeterminacy locus of $\gamma $ is a linear subspace and that $\overline {X}$ is not contained in any proper linear subspace of $\mathbb {P}(\mathcal {L}_X(X))$ . Hence, $\gamma $ is defined on some open of $\overline {X}$ , and the commutativity of the diagram above implies that $\gamma $ sends $\overline {X}$ to Y. So we get a rational map . The composition is equal to both f and g whenever it is defined, showing that $f=g$ on a dense open subset. As Y is separated, this implies that $f=g$ everywhere.

We now have all the prerequisite results needed for our proof of the announced theorem. We follow the general proof strategy of [Reference TsushimaTsu79].

Proposition 5.2. Let $(X, \Delta _X)$ and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ be proper orbifolds. Assume that X is smooth and that $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ is smooth and of general type. If $\dim X=\dim Y\kern-1pt$ , then there are only finitely many separably dominant near-maps .

Proof. If there are no separably dominant near-maps from $(X,\Delta _X)$ to $(Y,\Delta _Y)$ , then we are done. Otherwise, let be a separably dominant near-map. By Corollary 4.5, for $N \in \mathbb {N}$ sufficiently divisible, we get an induced morphism of line bundles $f^* (\omega _Y(\Delta _Y))^{\otimes N} \to \omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}$ . Since f is separably dominant, the morphism of line bundles $f^* (\omega _Y(\Delta _Y))^{\otimes N} \to \omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}$ is non-zero, and hence injective. This implies that $\omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}$ is a big line bundle. Increasing N if necessary, we can thus assume that all of the following hold:

  • $\omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}$ and $\omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N}$ are well-defined line bundles.

  • The line bundle $\omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}$ is very big.

  • There is an effective divisor $C \subseteq Y$ such that $(\omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N})(-C)$ is very ample.

We fix the integer N and the effective divisor $C \subseteq Y$ from the last bullet point. We define $V_X := \Gamma (X, \omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N})$ and $V_Y := \Gamma (Y, \omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N}(-C))$ . Note that we obtain a closed immersion $\iota _Y \colon Y \to \mathbb {P}(V_Y)$ and a rational map which is birational onto its scheme-theoretic image $\overline {X}$ . For every dominant near-map f, we get an induced vector space morphism $f^* \colon V_Y \to V_X$ . By Lemma 5.1, we can recover f from $f^*$ and even from $\mathbb {P}(f^*)$ . Thus, we are led to studying linear maps $V_Y \to V_X$ .

Let $H := \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(V_Y, V_X)^\vee $ , with $^\vee $ denoting the dual. Composition of functions is a canonical bilinear map $V_X^\vee \times \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(V_Y, V_X) \to V_Y^\vee $ , and after identifying $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(V_Y,V_X)$ with its double dual, we get a bilinear morphism $V_X^\vee \times H^\vee \to V_Y^\vee $ . It induces a relative (over $\mathbb {P}(H)$ ) rational map . For every closed point $h \in \mathbb {P}(H)$ , we denote by $F_h$ the rational map .

To prove the proposition, we are first going to construct a “small” locally closed subset $H_3$ of $\mathbb {P}(H)$ such that the set of separably dominant near-maps (still) injects into $H_3$ via $f\mapsto \mathbb {P}(f^\ast )$ .

Let $H_1 \subseteq \mathbb {P}(H)$ be the subset for which $F_h$ maps $\overline {X} \subseteq \mathbb {P}(V_X)$ to $Y \subseteq \mathbb {P}(V_Y)$ . To see that this is a meaningful condition, note that the indeterminacy locus of $F_h$ is a linear subspace and that $\overline {X} \subseteq \mathbb {P}(V_X)$ is contained in no proper linear subspace. Let $\eta _{\overline {X}}$ be the generic point of the scheme $\overline {X}$ . Since $H_1$ is the set of h in $\mathbb {P}(H)$ such that the morphism

$$\begin{align*}\{\eta_{\overline{X}}\}\times \mathbb{P}(H)\to \mathbb{P}(V_Y) \end{align*}$$

factors over Y, it follows from Lemma 3.1 that it is closed in $\mathbb {P}(H)$ .

Note that we obtain a relative rational map . Let $H_2\subset H_1$ be the subset of elements of $H_1$ for which the induced rational map is separably dominant. By Lemma 3.6, the set $H_2$ is open in $H_1$ .

Let $H_3\subset H_2$ be the subset of rational maps such that, for every global section $\omega $ of $\omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N}$ , the pullback $(g\circ \iota _X)^*\omega $ is a global section of $\omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}$ . By applying Lemma 3.9 to every single $\omega $ and taking the intersection over all closed sets obtained this way, we see that $H_3$ is closed in $H_2$ . Hence, $H_3$ is locally closed in $\mathbb {P}(H)$ , and we give it the reduced scheme structure.

If is a separably dominant orbifold near-map, then the induced map $\mathbb {P}(f^*)$ lies in $H_3$ . As we mentioned before, by Lemma 5.1, different separably dominant orbifold near-maps induce different elements of $H_3$ . Therefore, to prove the proposition, it suffices to show that $H_3$ is finite. To do so, let $H_4$ be an irreducible component of $H_3$ , so that $H_4$ is a quasi-projective variety. Since $H_3$ is quasi-projective, it has only finitely many irreducible components. Therefore, to conclude the proof, it suffices to show that $H_4$ is a point.

Let $\overline {H_4}$ be the closure of $H_4$ in $\mathbb {P}(H)$ , and note that $\overline {H_4}$ is a projective variety. Since $H_1$ is closed in $\mathbb {P}(H)$ , we see that $\overline {H_4}$ is contained in $H_1$ . In particular, we can interpret every closed point of $\overline {H_4}$ as a (possibly non-dominant) rational map . Let $\widetilde {H_4}$ be a smooth projective variety, and let $\widetilde {H_4} \to \overline {H_4}$ be an alteration such that the preimage of $\overline {H_4} \setminus H_4$ in $\widetilde {H_4}$ is a strict normal crossings divisor $D_H$ (this exists by [Reference de JongdJ96, Theorem 4.1]). We let be the relative rational map induced by the above map .

By Lemma 4.6, the sheaf $S^N \Omega ^n_{(X, \Delta _X) \times (\widetilde {H_4}, D_H)}$ has $\pi _X^* S^N \Omega ^n_{(X,\Delta _X)}$ as a direct summand. We denote by

$$\begin{align*}\pi \colon S^N \Omega^n_{(X, \Delta_X) \times (\widetilde{H_4}, D_H)} \to \pi_X^* S^N \Omega^n_{(X,\Delta_X)}\end{align*}$$

the projection. We now define the morphism $\Psi \colon \widetilde {H_4} \to \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}(V_Y,V_X) = H^\vee $ by $\Psi (h) = \left [ \omega \mapsto \iota _h^*\pi (G^*\omega ) \right ]$ , where $\iota _h\colon X\to X\times \widetilde {H_4}$ is the inclusion map $x\mapsto (x,h)$ . We now show that $\Psi $ is a well-defined morphism of varieties.

To do so, fix a closed point $h \in \widetilde {H_4}$ and $\omega \in V_Y$ . Then $\omega \in \Gamma (Y, \omega _Y(\Delta _Y)^{\otimes N})$ . We now analyze the possible poles the pulled back form $G^* \omega $ on $X \times \widetilde {H_4}$ can have. First, we note that all occurring poles of $G^* \omega $ are logarithmic, as $\omega $ has only logarithmic poles. Furthermore, on the open $X \times (\widetilde {H_4} \setminus D_H)$ (which lies over $X \times H_3$ ), the form $G^* \omega $ can only have poles along $ \left \lceil {\Delta _X} \right \rceil \times \widetilde {H_4}$ , and these poles have orders bounded by the coefficients of $N\Delta _X$ by definition of $H_3$ . It follows that $G^* \omega $ defines a global section of $S^N \Omega ^n_{(X, \Delta _X) \times (\widetilde {H_4}, D_H)}$ . Consequently, $\pi (G^*\omega )$ is a global section of $\pi _X^* S^N \Omega ^n_{(X, \Delta _X)}$ . Global sections of $\pi _X^* S^N \Omega ^n_{(X, \Delta _X)}$ only have poles along subsets of $ \left \lceil {\Delta _X} \right \rceil \times \widetilde {H_4}$ , with these poles being logarithmic and of order bounded by the coefficients of $N\Delta _X$ . In particular, they can be pulled back along $\iota _h$ , and then give global sections of $S^N \Omega ^n_{(X, \Delta _X)} = \omega _X(\Delta _X)^{\otimes N}$ . In particular, we have $\iota _h^* \pi (G^*\omega ) \in V_X$ , as required.

On the open subset $\widetilde {H_4} \setminus D_H$ , which consists of the elements lying over $H_4$ , the morphism $\Psi $ has the simpler description $\Psi (h) = \iota _h^*G^*\omega $ . The two descriptions agree by Lemma 4.7. As elements of $H_4$ represent dominant rational maps , we could even slightly abuse notation and write $\Psi (h) = h^*\omega $ .

Let $h_1$ and $h_2$ be elements of $\widetilde {H_4}$ lying over $H_4$ such that $\Psi (h_1) = \Psi (h_2)$ . Since $\Psi (h_1) \colon V_Y \to V_X$ is the injective map $\omega \mapsto (G\circ \iota _{h_1})^\ast \omega $ and $\Psi (h_2) \colon V_Y\to V_X$ is the injective map $\omega \mapsto (G\circ \iota _{h_2})^\ast \omega $ , it follows from Lemma 5.1 that the dominant near-maps $G\circ \iota _{h_1}$ and $G\circ \iota _{h_2}$ are equal. This implies that $h_1$ and $h_2$ lie over the same element of $H_4$ (via the alteration $\widetilde {H_4}\to \overline {H_4}$ ).

However, since $\widetilde {H_4}$ is a projective variety and $H^\vee $ is affine, the morphism $\Psi $ is constant. Since $\Psi $ separates elements lying over distinct points of $H_4$ (see previous paragraph), we conclude that $H_4$ is a singleton. This concludes the proof.

As we show now, we may drop the properness and smoothness assumptions on X.

Corollary 5.3. Let $(X, \Delta _X)$ and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ be normal orbifolds with $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ a smooth proper orbifold of general type. If $\dim X = \dim Y$ , then there are only finitely many separably dominant near-maps .

Proof. Let $U \subseteq X \setminus \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _X$ be a smooth open subset. Let $V \to U$ be an alteration with a smooth compactification $V \subseteq \overline {V}$ (see [Reference de JongdJ96, Theorem 4.1]). Shrinking U if necessary, we may assume that $V \to U$ is quasi-finite and dominant. Then, by Lemma 2.5, the set of separably dominant near-maps injects into the set of separably dominant near-maps . Shrinking V if necessary, we may assume that the boundary $\overline {V} \setminus V$ is a (reduced) divisor $D \subset \overline {V}$ . Then, the set of separably dominant near-maps equals the set of separably dominant near-maps . The latter is finite by Proposition 5.2.

Corollary 5.3 implies that the statement of Theorem 1.1 holds, under the additional assumption that $\dim X = \dim Y$ . To prove Theorem 1.1, we use a cutting argument.

Theorem 5.4. Let $(X, \Delta _X)$ and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ be normal orbifolds with $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ smooth, proper and of general type. Then there are only finitely many separably dominant near-maps .

Proof. We may assume that the base field k is uncountable. As before, we may replace $(X, \Delta _X)$ by a dense open subset of $X \setminus \operatorname {\mathrm {supp}} \Delta _X$ , so we may assume that X is smooth and quasi-projective and that $\Delta _X$ is empty.

We argue by contradiction. Assume that is an infinite sequence of pairwise distinct separably dominant near-maps. If $\dim (X)> \dim (Y)$ , we will construct an $(\dim (X)-1)$ -dimensional subvariety $Z \subset X$ which still admits infinitely many pairwise distinct separably dominant orbifold near-maps to $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ . By iterating this process, we obtain a contradiction to Corollary 5.3. As the case $\dim (Y)=0$ is trivial, we may assume $\dim (X) \geq 2$ .

Let $X \subseteq \mathbb {P}^n$ be an immersion, and let $Z \subset X$ be a very general hyperplane section. Then Z is a smooth variety. Since Z is not contained in the indeterminacy locus of any $f_i$ , all of the $f_i$ induce rational maps . Moreover, being very general, Z does not contain any irreducible component of the indeterminacy locus of any $f_i$ . This implies that all are defined in codimension $1$ . For fixed $i, j$ , the locus where $f_i$ and $f_j$ are equal is contained in a proper closed subset of X, so that $f_i$ and $f_j$ are distinct after restricting to a generic hyperplane section. Thus, the near-maps $(f_i\vert _Z)_{i \in \mathbb {N}}$ are pairwise distinct. By the implication $(a) \implies (b)$ of Lemma 3.3, for every $i \in \mathbb {N}$ , there is a point $x \in X$ such that $df_{i,x} \colon \textrm {T}_x X \to \textrm {T}_{f_i(x)} Y$ is surjective. As this is an open condition on x, we see that the map on tangent spaces is surjective at a general point of X. Moreover, if $V \subset \textrm {T}_x X$ is a generic subspace of codimension $1$ , the composed map $V \to \textrm {T}_{f_i(x)} Y$ will still be surjective, as $\dim \textrm {T}_x X = \dim X> \dim Y = \dim \textrm {T}_{f_i(x)} Y$ . Consequently, we see that the restricted maps still have a surjective differential map at some point. Hence, they are separably dominant by the implication $(b) \implies (a)$ of Lemma 3.3. By Corollary 2.7, the separably dominant near-maps are orbifold near-maps. This concludes the proof.

Remark 5.5. Theorem 5.4 also holds if we allow $(X, \Delta _X)$ and $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ to be $\mathbb {Q}$ -orbifolds (but still requiring $(Y, \Delta _Y)$ to be smooth, proper and of general type). Indeed, as before, we immediately reduce to the case that X is a smooth variety. Writing $\Delta _Y = \sum (1-\frac {1}{m_i}) D_i$ , we can define $\widetilde {\Delta _Y} = \sum (1-\frac {1}{ \left \lceil {m_i} \right \rceil }) D$ . Then every morphism $X \to (Y, \Delta _Y)$ is also a morphism $X \to (Y, \widetilde {\Delta _Y})$ ; hence, we are reduced to the case of $\mathbb {Z}$ -orbifolds.

As a straightforward application of our result, we can show that every surjective endomorphism of a general type orbifold is an automorphism.

Corollary 5.6. If $(X, \Delta )$ is a smooth proper orbifold pair of general type, then every separably dominant morphism $(X, \Delta ) \to (X, \Delta )$ is an automorphism of finite order, and the group of automorphisms of $(X,\Delta )$ is finite.

Proof. Let $f \colon (X, \Delta ) \to (X, \Delta )$ be a separably dominant orbifold morphism. Let $f^n$ be the n-fold composition of f. Since every $f^n$ is a separably dominant orbifold morphism, by the finiteness of the set of separably dominant orbifold morphisms $(X,\Delta )\to (X,\Delta )$ , there are distinct positive integers m and n with $m>n$ such that $f^m = f^n$ . As f is dominant, it follows that $f^{m-n} = \operatorname {\mathrm {id}}_X$ , so that f is an automorphism of finite order. The finiteness of the automorphism group follows immediately from Proposition 5.2.

Let $(X,\Delta )$ be a smooth proper orbifold pair of general type. We do not know whether every separably dominant orbifold near-map is birational and has finite order (in the group of birational self-maps of X). Indeed, it is not clear to us whether the iterates $f^i = f \circ \ldots \circ f$ of f are orbifold near-maps.

Acknowledgements

The second-named author thanks Erwan Rousseau for many helpful discussions on Campana’s theory of orbifolds. We thank Pedro Núñez for pointing out a mistake in an earlier version of the paper (see Remark 2.6). We thank the referee for the second example in Remark 3.7 and the helpful comments.

Competing interest

None.

References

Bandman, T. and Dethloff, G., Estimates of the number of rational mappings from a fixed variety to varieties of general type, Ann. Inst. Fourier (Grenoble) 47(3) (1997), 1997.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartsch, F., Javanpeykar, A. and Rousseau, E., Weakly-special threefolds and non-density of rational points, Preprint, 2023, arXiv:2310.09065.Google Scholar
Campana, F., Orbifolds, special varieties and classification theory, Ann. Inst. Fourier (Grenoble) 54(3) (2004), 499630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campana, F., Fibres multiples sur les surfaces: aspects geométriques, hyperboliques et arithmétiques, Manuscripta Math. 117(4) (2005), 429461, 2005.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campana, F., Orbifoldes géométriques spéciales et classification biméromorphe des variétés kählériennes compactes, J. Inst. Math. Jussieu 10(4) (2011), 809934.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campana, F. and Păun, M., Orbifold generic semi-positivity: an application to families of canonically polarized manifolds, Ann. Inst. Fourier (Grenoble) 65(2) (2015), 835861.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Jong, A. J., Smoothness, semi-stability and alterations, Inst. Hautes Études Sci. Publ. Math. 83 (1996), 5193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartshorne, R., Algebraic Geometry (Graduate Texts in Mathematics) vol. 52 (Springer-Verlag, New York- Heidelberg, 1977).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heier, G., Effective finiteness theorems for maps between canonically polarized compact complex manifolds, Math. Nachr. 278(1–2) (2005), 133140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iitaka, S., Algebraic Geometry (Graduate Texts in Mathematics) vol. 76 (Springer-Verlag, New York-Berlin, 1982). An introduction to birational geometry of algebraic varieties, North-Holland Mathematical Library, 24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iwanari, I. and Moriwaki, A., Dominant rational maps in the category of log schemes, Tohoku Math. J. (2) 59(4) (2007), 481525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kobayashi, S. and Ochiai, T., Meromorphic mappings onto compact complex spaces of general type, Invent. Math. 31(1) (1975), 716.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kebekus, S., Pereira, J.-V. and Smeets, A., Failure of the Brauer-Manin principle for a simply connected fourfold over a global function field, via orbifold Mordell, Duke Math. J. 171(17) (2022), 35153591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lang, S., Higher dimensional Diophantine problems, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 80 (1974), 779787.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matsumura, H., Commutative Algebra (Mathematics Lecture Note Series) vol. 56, second edn. (Benjamin/Cummings Publishing Co., Inc., Reading, MA, 1980).Google Scholar
Martin-Deschamps, M. and Lewin-Ménégaux, R., Applications rationnelles séparables dominantes sur une variété de type général, Bull. Soc. Math. France 106(3) (1978), 279287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noguchi, J., Meromorphic mappings into compact hyperbolic complex spaces and geometric Diophantine problems, Internat. J. Math. 3(2) (1992), 277289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naranjo, J. C. and Pirola, G. P., Bounds of the number of rational maps between varieties of general type, Amer. J. Math. 129(6) (2007), 16891709.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suzuki, M., Moduli spaces of holomorphic mappings into hyperbolically imbedded complex spaces and hyperbolic fibre spaces (abridged and revised version) , no. 819 (1993), 157166. International Symposium “Holomorphic Mappings, Diophantine Geometry and Related Topics” (Kyoto, 1992).Google Scholar
Tsushima, R., Rational maps to varieties of hyperbolic type, Proc. Japan Acad. Ser. A Math. Sci. 55(3) (1979), 95100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar