Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-01T01:49:10.892Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Failing the state self: on the politics of state shame

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 November 2024

Zeger Verleye*
Affiliation:
Department of History and Art History, Utrecht University, Utrecht, Netherlands
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Observers have noted that world politics is replete with shame. Whether they observe this concerning the apologies regarding past atrocities, the felt necessity for revenge after a humiliating defeat, the feelings that populist leaders find antithetical to the greatness of their nation, or the affective responses to the latter's election, shame seems to be ubiquitous. Vital to understanding the particular politics of this emotion is the concept of state shame. However, the origins, divergent effects, and social and moral roles of state shame are left obscure in International Relations (IR) scholarship, making the concept undertheorized and in need of further elaboration. The primary goal of this research is to (re)conceptualize state shame as a narrative on the social position of the state by building on insights developed by IR theory, sociology, and social psychology. Moreover, the article proposes four types of state shame narratives, namely situational shame, narcissistic shame, aggressive shame, and deferential shame, that can separately account for the divergent effects and social and moral roles that the emotion can be attributed with. These four types, and the politics that characterize them, aim to capture and explain lived practices and meanings that state shame can come to hold.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Shame seems out of place in the realm of world politics. Observers often comment on how hegemonic or rogue states flagrantly defy and transgress international law with a sense of impunity and even self-righteousness. If anything, it is shamelessness that is believed to guide the actions of states in international affairs. Researchers in International Relations (IR) have, however, observed that shame is far more prevalent in world politics than is commonly assumed. These contributions point to, among others, the importance of the emotion in inter- and intrastate reconciliation,Footnote 1 revenge,Footnote 2 social pressure,Footnote 3 and normative behaviour by states.Footnote 4 In short, shame is more ubiquitous in contemporary international and domestic politics than intuitively assumed.

Regardless of the finding that shame is widespread in international politics, its role and significance remain undertheorized in IR. Although scholars of this field have used insights from sociology or psychology to understand how shame relates to particular social dynamics within or between states, the emotion is rarely treated holistically.Footnote 5 The goal of this paper is to argue for a more comprehensive and theoretically grounded understanding of shame in international politics in order to explain divergent state behaviours that can be linked to this emotion. It aims to expose and criticize the central assumptions regarding shame in IR to evaluate the concept's current use with the purpose of gaining more insight into its contingency and epistemic commitments. The main argument is that shame, in its generic characterization, can be more adequately conceived as a negative narrative on the social status of a state. More specifically, shame is a political emotion attributed to the state self when the state is placed in a situation where its social status is believed to be unwarranted. Competing political agents conceive their state's position as a ‘shame situation’, with which they deal with by constructing divergent types of shame narratives (i.e. situational, narcissistic, aggressive, and deferential) that each inform particular coping and defence mechanisms. This typology aids in identifying narrative competition between political agents that aim to maintain or change narratives on the shameful status of the state. In so doing, the narrative understanding of the politics of shame can explain why a state copes with shame the way that they do and how it comes to inform their behaviour.

The paper starts off by giving a cursory overview of how shame has been conceived in IR theory. After identifying the causes for its absence in mainstream theoretical traditions, it turns to a broad discussion on the role and meaning of shame in the ontological security literature. The following section lists three critiques regarding how ontological security scholarship has conceived state shame and argues for a novel understanding. The subsequent sections build the main argument by clarifying how states are capable of emotions and developing on psychological and sociological insights to argue that state shame is more adequately understood as a narrative on the state's social status. Afterwards, an argument is made for conceiving a conceptual framework surrounding the shame situation. This, in turn, proposes that political agents construct four types of state shame narratives, namely situational shame, narcissistic shame, aggressive shame, and deferential shame, each inspiring distinct state behaviours. Before concluding this paper, a preliminary perspective is given on some characteristics particular to the politics that this understanding of state shame can expose.

Shame in IR

Mainstream IR and the assumption of shamelessness

Mainstream theories of IR do not consider shame to be a potential motivator in international politics. Although emotions are always implicitly present in this field's theorization,Footnote 6 shame is a notable absentee in the discourse of IR's major theoretical traditions.Footnote 7 Theorists that ascribe to classical realism expect, to a point, that states are rational unitary actors that do not abide by international rules unless it is in their interest. This makes states fundamentally disconnected from their peers, effectively generating and justifying security dilemmas that are predicated on fear.Footnote 8 Furthermore, as neorealists assume that world politics have an anarchic, unprincipled nature these IR scholars consider that states do, or even should, not have the restraint or ethical reflection that is believed to be characteristic of shame. Any psychological factors, after all, are marginal to variables that relate to the structure of the international system or the security dilemma.Footnote 9

In contrast, theories of IR such as liberal institutionalism or the English School have been more inclined to understand world politics to be subject to moral actions and emotions. The focus of IR liberalism on explaining cooperation has led to stressing the importance of moral emotions and emotional relationships between states.Footnote 10 Empathy, trust, and other emotions that facilitate connection are often assumed in these discussions and act as mechanisms that underlie rational considerations for international communities.Footnote 11 Similarly, some English school scholars have emphasized the emotional underpinnings of international society.Footnote 12 Building on Norbert Elias, they focus on the evolution of how emotions have come to be displayed in the response towards the harm of others. Regardless of the interest of these two IR traditions into the role of cosmopolitan and moral emotions, both do not attribute a significant role to shame.

Shame did come to figure in IR constructivism. In their seminal article on international norm dynamics, Martha Finnemore and Kathryn SikkinkFootnote 13 argued that states follow norms that are associated with their identity because these standards for behaviour act as sources of pride and self-esteem. Social norms are, in so doing, also sustained through the punishing prospect of disapproval and stigma by others when they are violated. In short, norm-breaking behaviour among states can generate shame, guilt, and embarrassment.Footnote 14 This inspired research in ‘naming and shaming’, which is generally considered a process of ‘moral consciousness-raising’Footnote 15 often employed by the human rights community for bringing pariah states into the fold. Yet, regardless of the emotion figuring in the literature's moniker, it is not accredited with a notable role. Although the ideal goal of naming and shaming is to make individual policymakers of targeted governments feel shame for their transgressions,Footnote 16 the emotion itself is not a requirement to act upon the threat of naming and shaming to their state's status in international community.Footnote 17 In the naming and shaming literature, shame thus acts more as a metaphor for a state's rational reflection on its reputation costs and status management.Footnote 18

Ontological security, anxiety, and shame

A growing body of work in IR considers shame to be a more fundamental notion for understanding state behaviour.Footnote 19 These scholars are not interested in shame in the narrow sense,Footnote 20 for example as it is expressed by individual leaders during public apologies or other forms of remorse but approach the emotion from a so-called macro or communitarian perspective.Footnote 21 This approach has most notably been used by authors that engage with the notion of ontological security,Footnote 22 which assumes that a state, or any actor for that matter, is primarily concerned with the need to ‘maintain consistent self-concepts’.Footnote 23 State behaviours that are otherwise considered to be irrational, such as costly humanitarian actions or unwinnable wars, are thus understood and explained as strategies or coping mechanisms for securing a state's sense of self.

The role of shame is considered to be key in this process. This claim originates from Anthony Giddens, a central theorist for the ontological security literature, who argues that unconscious emotional commitments are inextricably linked to the experience of having a ‘protective cocoon’. Although feelings of trust are essential to sustaining the latter, shame ‘eats away’ at it.Footnote 24 Giddens does not consider shame to be the negative equivalent of trust, nor does he argue that it is an experience that has to be avoided at all costs. He views shame as ‘anxiety about the adequacy of the narrative by means of which the individual sustains a coherent biography’.Footnote 25 This experience can thus be both a potentially destructive force, as a necessary feature in the psychological development of an individual. In other words, by countering narcissistic tendencies through the necessary acceptance of imperfections and limitations of the self, the individual can develop feelings of pride or self-esteem.Footnote 26

Shame was introduced in IR ontological security studies (OSS) by the seminal work of Brent Steele.Footnote 27 Building on the argument that Giddens puts considerable weight on the need for a consistent biographical narrative,Footnote 28 he argues that the sense of continuity, stability, and order that an agent desires can only be achieved through constructing stable ‘stories of the Self’.Footnote 29 Because the stability of the agents' narrative is a central feature to ontological security for Steele, so does the emotion that can threaten it. Analogous to Giddens, then, Steele primarily uses the term ‘shame’ as a shorthand to denote the anxietyFootnote 30 that originates from the disparity between a state's self narrative and its self-identity.Footnote 31 In other words, state shame refers to the tension caused by an inability of a state to narrate how it sees its self. When states experience shame, according to Steele, they are compelled towards social action, or state behaviour that is commonly described as moral, humanitarian, or honour-driven. Rather than compelled by the international context, such as through the influence of norms or regimes,Footnote 32 these prosocial actions are considered to be rational pursuits that principally serve self-identity needs.Footnote 33 The origins of these actions do not lie with a challenge to the routines of the state, but instead on their ability to narrate their sense of self.

For Steele, then, shame functions as an internal, subjective motivator for states. It compels them towards prosocial actions that are believed to counter the threat to their self-identity. However, other authors have contended that state shame should not be seen as strictly internally generated and experienced.Footnote 34 Following Catarina Kinnvall'sFootnote 35 interpretation of ontological security, Ayşe ZarakolFootnote 36 takes a middle ground concerning the sources of ontological security, and as such, works with an approach that makes state shame more complex. Specifically, this position assumes that ontological security is a fundamental search for narrative stability about the state self.Footnote 37 However, states, just like individuals, always define their self through interactions with others, making self representations impossible to be separated from representations of others.Footnote 38 In this sense, both state self-identity and shame are co-constituted by the agent's interrogation into its self as well as their relations to others. The self-narrative of a state is, then, both a product of domestic factors and its place in international society. Rebecca Adler-Nissen, building on the work of Zarakol, argues that this means that shame also acts as a means to reinforce the notion of normality in international order, specifically through the process of stigmatization.Footnote 39 More specifically, acts of shaming and stigmatization reinforce the boundaries of international norms and through this, ensure ontological security and moral cohesion for the liberal international order. How states cope with this situation is, however, varied. In effect, the expression of state shame would be indicative of the politics surrounding the country's self-image and its international status.Footnote 40

The turn towards more existentialist and Lacanian-inspired OSS has driven more recent theorization towards anxiety and less on shame.Footnote 41 However, in contributions focussed on state narcissism,Footnote 42 shame is considered to be a significant emotion and these works hint at a more radical understanding of shame and its politics. More specifically, feelings of pride and shame are considered in this research as central to self-securitizing processes but mediated by narcissistic narratives of the state. Pride and shame thus define narcissistic self-identification and self-security-seeking of states but they interact in a variety of ways with state narratives.Footnote 43 The narrative of shame, in particular, is aimed at emphasizing the weakness of the state and the shame that this fear of inadequacy generates.Footnote 44 As such, the greatness of the self remains always assumed, regardless of the existence of these feelings of shame.Footnote 45 Shame in international politics can thus also be conceived as a narrative, rather than purely as a political emotion or a metaphor for a social mechanism. This narrative conception implies that the meaning and role of shame might be more subject to politics than is generally assumed by earlier theories in OSS. It is the central goal of this article to further explore and theorize this narrative conception of shame.

Critique

Before going into formulating conceptual and theoretical wagers, it would serve the clarity of the argument to first stipulate its critiques against prevailing conceptions of shame in OSS. The conceptual development of shame in IR has indicated a notable change from its initial understanding as a social mechanism for interstate conformityFootnote 46 to a metaphor for insecurities that arise when the self-identity cannot be reconciled with past or current actions by the state.Footnote 47 This has brought a new understanding as to how the emotion of shame can be political in IR. Yet, as this conception is rooted in OSS theorization, it is also susceptible to the broader critiques that have been levelled against this literature. It has been claimed that OSS validates status quo-seeking behaviour by focussing on how states maintain their sense of self.Footnote 48 OSS has also been criticized for obscuring power relations and ordering tactics,Footnote 49 and sustaining a problematic one-sided understanding of political identity.Footnote 50 In short, the focus of OSS on state self-securitization makes it forgo the layered politics that characterize this phenomenon.

These critiques also hold true for how state shame is conceived in this literature. The emotion acts as a central social mechanism that maintains the status quo by compelling states to secure their sense of self. They namely assume that states want to avoid this insecurity regarding their sense of self or aim to regain the validation to restore the existing situation. State shame thus leaves little room agency or as a potential site for social change. Yet, some states wilfully explore and even offer rectification for shameful episodes in their past.Footnote 51 Others actively engage and even celebrate past defeats and commemorate heinous crimes as a part of their state's sense of self.Footnote 52 There are also those states that resist this shame and actively refute it.Footnote 53 In effect, state shame seems a far less one-sided social mechanism than is assumed.

Additionally, three more specific critiques can be levelled against the current conception of state shame in OSS. First, it is unclear how shame relates to anxiety. Although fundamental questions have been raised regarding the latter concept,Footnote 54 it remains unclear whether state shame should be understood as a metaphor for a source of anxiety,Footnote 55 as an emotional projection following anxiety,Footnote 56 or as a related emotion to this more general mood.Footnote 57 Moreover, the added difficulty of separating state emotions from state narratives that surround emotionsFootnote 58 raises questions about the particularity of state shame and what this concept specifically denotes.

Second, the literature is in doubt whether shame, or ontological insecurity more generally,Footnote 59 is fundamentally contingent in natureFootnote 60 or if it is caused by specific events. On the one hand, the ontological security literature generally assumes that life is contingent,Footnote 61 implying that shame is an unforeseeable phenomenon, making its causality something that cannot be theorized upon.Footnote 62 On the other, there is empirical research that would suggest that there is some form of structural pattern to be discerned regarding the causes of state shame.Footnote 63 Certain identifiable ‘external shocks’, such as power transitions, scandals, global financial crises, or transnational migration, are namely believed to cause ontological insecurity, implying that this can also be the case for state shame.Footnote 64

Third, the current conceptualization of state shame cannot account for the divergent and contradicting effects that it has been attributed with.Footnote 65 Steele argues that states are compelled towards social actions as a result of shame,Footnote 66 whereas other research has suggested that state shame can generate paralysis,Footnote 67 avoidance behaviour,Footnote 68 denials of wrongdoing, feelings of resentment,Footnote 69 hostile bravado,Footnote 70 or even potentially inspire interstate violence.Footnote 71 State shame is thus effectively subject to the constructivist problem of codetermination, namely that a concept simultaneously explains both stability and change without clarifying what drives agents to one or the other.Footnote 72

Based on these critiques, it can be concluded that this concept is both unwieldy and seemingly unsubstantial. This begs the question whether state shame produces ‘a thoughtful ordering of empirical reality’Footnote 73 or if it generates more issues than it aims to clarify. Although this comment is reasonable, it forgoes the tangibility of the concept of state shame and its analytical and explanatory potential. More specifically, as an emotion, rather than a mood or ‘generalized state of being’ (cf. anxiety), shame is more concrete and resonates with particular empirical phenomena in world politics that are otherwise difficult to explain in a parsimonious way. Specific practices such as apologies or reconciliation work but also dynamics of violence following humiliation, bouts of policy paralysis, and historical taboos, all somehow make more sense when discussed in light of this emotion. Practitioners and observers use it more naturally and effortlessly to denote what they experience, and it would be understood when it is applied by others. In short, state shame seems to be a grounded notion in social life, a more ‘experience-near concept’ as Clifford Geertz would call it.Footnote 74 There is thus value in reconceiving state shame as a concept, as it provides an impetus to question what it means to apprehend and capture broader truths about world politics.

The emotional lives of states

State shame thus ought to be reconceived. Key for this exercise is to clarify how collectives are capable of having emotions and how this relates to the affective connection between individuals and their respective group or polity.Footnote 75 Although there is significant debate on this topic,Footnote 76 constructivist scholarship generally allows emotions and affect to play a notable role in international politics. Building on the theorization of Alex WendtFootnote 77 regarding state personhood and subjectivity, these authors assume that states are ‘purposive actors with a sense of Self’.Footnote 78 The subjectivity of a state, or of any collective actor for that matter, consists primarily of ‘narratives, of stories that constitute our diverse experiences as those of a coherent Self’.Footnote 79 Simply put, states are narrative constructs surrounding a collective that positions a self against an other.Footnote 80 Individuals use these stories to define their membership which, in turn, constitutes their respective identities. Consequently, Wendt argues, states are unitary actors that are capable of having and feeling a sense of self.Footnote 81

The narrative conception of state subjectivity is used by IR scholars to ground the claim that states exhibit attitudes similar to emotions. More specifically, a state self-narrative constitutes a ‘national habitus’,Footnote 82 which is an internalized set of structured and structuring dispositions that collectively limit the thoughts and behaviours of citizens.Footnote 83 A national habitus should not be considered as a stable and unchanging Volksgeist nor does it correspond with the rather vague notion of ‘national identity’.Footnote 84 Rather, it is a process that cannot be essentialized and serves purely as an analytical category to capture collective dispositions that are permanently changing. It is in this national habitus that the collective consciousness of the state becomes manifest.Footnote 85 Because of this shared subjectivity, emotional reactions can be attributed to states without them being reduced to behavioural responses by individuals. Yet, recent theorization on the state self has challenged the notion that a singular, unitary, and stable state self can manifest itself through a national habitus, and the associated collective memories and habits that support it.Footnote 86 Based on a variety of influences, they argue that state identity is, in fact, essentially incomplete, fragile, and deeply social. The state self is thus not a fixed, singular, or stable narrative. State self-securing then becomes a social process, i.e. ‘security-as-becoming’,Footnote 87 where competing narratives are used to overcome the instability and incoherence of the state self.Footnote 88

If one understands that being part of a collective is something that an individual feels and does,Footnote 89 it can be argued that the state is spoken, written, and enacted into existence.Footnote 90 Shared memories and habits come to act as means through which collective emotions cut across individuals and forge meaningful associations between them.Footnote 91 This does not assume that all state subjects share the same affective experience. Rather, the shared memories and habits constitute an emotional space where feelings towards the state exist. This space has been denoted by the terms ‘emotional’ or ‘affective community’Footnote 92 or ‘community of feeling’,Footnote 93 and denotes a site where ‘citizens enact and vicariously experience collective national self-hood’.Footnote 94 It is through this community of feeling that emotions regarding the state can arise and facilitate, for example, the support for a military intervention in a foreign conflict or public outrage towards a national scandal. During times of crises and conflict, individuals will be subject to feeling rules that guide them into experiencing appropriate emotions.Footnote 95 In effect, collective emotions, and the standards of behaviour that surround them, generate social conformity and come to shape both individual and collective bodies through their circulation.Footnote 96

These communities of feeling both constitute and challenge the state's legitimacy. Similar to the Lacanian subject, the state self is continuously produced, challenged, and reproduced through emotional dynamics and is in a permanent state of becoming.Footnote 97 Because the Lacanian subject always strives for ‘wholeness’ to make up for its ‘lack’, it constructs fantasies and imaginations that obfuscate their inherently split and ever-changing self.Footnote 98 Similarly, political actors construct, reiterate, or circulate narratives of national unity with the aim of delineating their imagined community and resonating with their respective constituents. Yet, the dominant understandings of what the state self ought to be are essentially contested in the community of feeling. This ‘arena of emotions’ acts as a site where subjects try to enact, assert, and change their understanding of the state self.Footnote 99 Competing political agents, such as activists, lobby groups, and politicians, attempt to build on feelings that are circulating in this arena to service their political or psychological needs. In effect, they reproduce rituals, memories, symbols, and narratives to mediate, neutralize, or amplify extant emotions in this community of feeling and bring the state towards particular actions.Footnote 100 These affectively charged and mobilizing narratives about the state can become widely and uncritically reproduced in different communities of feeling and eventually reach the status of common sense.Footnote 101 The goal of these political agents is, generally speaking, to influence how the state deals with political problems and steer it towards behaviour that they deem desirable.

State shame reconceived

Shame in international politics can be reconceived by linking the previous discussion with psychological, sociological, and philosophical understandings of shame. Although these conceptions have generally been conceived with individuals' experiences in mind, they can be used as ex-ante assumptions and expectations for more macro approaches.Footnote 102 The starting point of this argument is the assumption that state shame denotes a particular narrative on the state. It rests on the notion that states are narrated as being subjects that are capable of experiencing emotions, regardless if they physically can. In turn, this builds on the idea that humans understand subjectivity only through how they themselves experience it. Part of the process of anthropomorphizing other actors is that emotions are projected onto them as key experiences for their formation and are conceived as significant motivations for their actions. This is how Israel can be conceived of taking ‘vengeance’ on Hamas for the attack on 7th October of 2024, that Germany ‘feels guilty’ for the Holocaust, or that Argentina was ‘proud’ of winning the 2022 FIFA World Cup. States thus experience emotions because they are understood as subjects that have an emotional life.

Shame can become a salient emotion regarding the state and resonate in the community of feeling. In so doing, it can circulate among members of this community so that it builds a shared sense among a significant group and comes to shape the collective body.Footnote 103 It is specifically projected onto the state when a dominant or unquestioned collective self is challenged. This could be, for example, a disastrous war, a widespread scandal, an economic downturn, or a humiliating loss in sports. During this moment of anxiety, an arena of emotions develops towards this existential challenge. Political agents present themselves in response to this situation as actors that can translate, arouse, appropriate, manage, and suppress emotions that circulate in the community of feeling. Consequently, shame can figure as an emotion that is being embedded in (one of the) competing narratives to describe the particular feeling that the state is, or ought to, experience. In so doing, state shame is a narrative on how the state self deals with anxiety.

However, shame is an emotion with specific characteristics that will only be projected onto the state when it seems appropriate to a community of feeling.Footnote 104 The general consensus in the literature is that shame is an essentially socialFootnote 105 and self-conscious emotion.Footnote 106 It is common in the literature to distinguish shame from adjacent self-conscious feelings of guilt, embarrassment, and humiliation. Although guilt is often conceived as the ‘self-punishing anger, reacting to the perception that one has done a wrong or a harm’,Footnote 107 shame is commonly understood as the painful feeling that focusses on a defect or imperfection of the self.Footnote 108 In short, the former implies that you have done something wrong, whereas the latter is the feeling based on the notion that you are wrong.Footnote 109 Embarrassment is often conceived as an uneasy feeling following public transgressionFootnote 110 and humiliation as the extreme and unbearable sentiment following intentional public focus and participation in the actor's failure.Footnote 111 Although contrasting these emotions is helpful, it must be noted that this analytical reduction erases some of the more elaborate features of self-conscious emotions and neglects the nuanced way in which they interact, as the borderline between them ‘seems fuzzier than one might imagine’.Footnote 112

The experience of shame is commonly characterized by an intense feeling of pain, a burning sensation, a blushing face, the image of being naked, or the desire to hide and disappear. When experiencing shame, the individual assumes the view of a different actor, who makes a judgement of the self.Footnote 113 The view that is assumed, makes the individual see themselves as if they were this other. Put succinctly by Sara Ahmed, by feeling shame, ‘I expose to myself that I am a failure through the gaze of an ideal other’.Footnote 114 This connects the individual to a community where the experience of shame acts as the affective cost for not abiding by ‘the scripts of normative existence’.Footnote 115 More specifically, shame can inform social conformity through the ideal other's gaze and the subsequent self-evaluation and self-reflection that it gives cause to. The focus onto the self brings individuals to self-regulating and adjusting behaviour so as to conform to these normative expectations.Footnote 116 However, shame does not only retroactively make individuals adjust their behaviour to this ideal other's judgement, the memory to this painful experience also acts as a deterrent for normative transgressions.Footnote 117

The social and self-conscious nature of shame might also hold true for state shame. More specifically, that it is not only present during extreme moments of existential anxiety but also as a response to more common social pressures. The state is exposed to extant social hierarchies, norms, and identities in international politics. One of these dynamics is that states, and other international actors, continuously comparatively assess themselves and others, which normatively orders them into having a social status.Footnote 118 This position mediates the social pressures which channel their respective behaviour, both in national as well as in international politics. The performances of states and other collective actors are continuously assessed through formal (e.g. technical rankings), informal (e.g. diplomatic interactions at summitsFootnote 119), internal (e.g. national media), and external (e.g. reports of international non-governmental organisations) means and tools. As a reaction to negative assessments, states can be narrated as being subject to shame. This means that state shame, in a generic sense, is a narrative on how the state self is negatively judged in comparison to an idealized self or other. It is, in other words, a narrative on a negative appraisal of the state's social status.

Yet, shame is a complex emotion with multiple social and moral roles. When individuals feel shame, they are compelled towards restorative actions, which can be performed by rituals such as apologies or compensating behaviour like being intensely focussed on the desires and expectations of others.Footnote 120 These are primarily aimed at reaffirming the relationship between themselves and the ideal other by correcting hubristic desires and narcissistic self-conceptions or by facilitating emphatic insight into the lives of others.Footnote 121 In so doing, shame can inspire individuals to enact prosocial behaviour and come to a more humble notion of self.

At the same time, restorative actions can also be instrumentalized to tend to a ‘narcissistic wound’ without having the intended aim of restoring a relationship or generating more empathy for the other.Footnote 122 Similarly, shame can also give cause to ego or narcissistic defencesFootnote 123 such as denial, undoing, isolation, sublimation, projection, and displacement.Footnote 124 Shame, then, does not always lead to conformity.Footnote 125 Moreover, it can prompt its opposite by inspiring aggressive behaviour that challenges the place of the actor in the social bond and even the bond itself.Footnote 126 When repeatedly and intensely experienced, shame can also generate such acute self-hatred within an individual that it can develop negative spirals that lead to self-effacement, self-harm, and even suicide.Footnote 127 These reflexes stem from the desire to end the intolerable psychic pain and suffering experienced by negative self-evaluation and to escape from the other's gaze.Footnote 128

This large variety of phenomenological expressions, roles, and effects of shame compels psychologists, sociologists, and philosophers to argue against conflating it into one single concept. The rich understandings, notions, and processes that it is connected to indicate that the emotion is multifaceted in its expression. In effect, state shame as a generic concept might be too restraining as well. This would mean that there is variation in how a state shame narrative is constructed and how states deal with it. The basis of this variation can be understood in divergent ways, prompting extensive typologies that build on psychological, sociological, or ethical assumptions.Footnote 129 As the goal of this paper is to make state shame a suitable and broad analytical tool for IR, the choice is made to construct a typology that takes power and social interaction into account while also combining various understandings and theories.

The state shame situation

Building on the symbolic interactionist work of Theodore Kemper and the collaboration of the latter with interaction ritual theorist Randall Collins,Footnote 130 Jack Barbalet proposes a model that aims to encapsulate the variety of behaviours that shame can inspire.Footnote 131 Here it is key to understand that Kemper considers shame to originate from status loss, especially where there is an initial expectation for status gain.Footnote 132 The attribution of loss, or who or what is the cause of the failure of status gain,Footnote 133 informs how shame is coped with. Barbalet proposes here that how a person experiences and copes with shame depends on their conception of the particular social situation that they find themselves in.Footnote 134 In other words, a person finds themselves in a shame situation Footnote 135 when they are confronted with a conception of self that is unaligned with their own. Following this understanding, state shame narratives are believed to bifurcate based on how political agents understand the situation that their state is placed in. This situation is made intelligible by analytically, and thus not ontologically, separating two key components that inform different means of coping with shame.

A first component is the assessing actor, or the source of assessment. As shame is characterized by an acute awareness of the self, it can effectively lead to a more entrenched notion of this self and those that supposedly belong to this in-group. Every actor that is not conceived as part of the community of feeling will be seen as an other or an agent in an out-group. Whether this actor is conceived as part of the former or the latter can significantly impact how shame is experienced and, in turn, inform the behaviour of the shamed agent. On the one hand, an actor can be assessed by an agent that is identified as part of their self or in-group. In the case of a state this could, for example, be an MP or a journalist that brings out a scathing report on human rights abuses in the state's military. A close ally could also take up this role, because friendship and trust do exist between states.Footnote 136 On the other, an actor can be assessed by an agent that is considered as an outsider, or as part of an out-group. For a state, a typical example could be a particular minority group that criticises how the state treats them or a non-governmental organisation that spearheads an international naming and shaming campaign against a particular policy. The sources of assessment can thus vary between self and other.Footnote 137

A second component refers to whether the failure of the self is believed to be against prevailing social norms or self-ideals, or the source of failure.Footnote 138 On the one hand, shame can originate because the actor believes that they did not behave according to dominant normative scripts in their respective society. A state can, for example, observe that it transgressed international standards regarding climate change or that its representatives failed in maintaining diplomatic etiquette. On the other, shame can originate from the actor's belief that they failed some idealized notion that is considered to be an inherent part of their self. These can be, for example, imagined traits of the nation-state or prominent political relationships that the state holds in high regard. The sources of failure can thus vary between social norms and self-ideals.Footnote 139 The variations in these two components generate a matrix that categorizes four different types of shame narratives (see Table 1).

Table 1. Shame situation, based on the social typology of shame by Jack BarbaletFootnote 141

There are undoubtedly significant differences as to how an individual or a state manages this shame situation. It would be problematic to uncritically project it onto the state and assume that the mechanisms would work in a similar manner.Footnote 140 To this end, empirical research is necessary to explore the various ways in which these types of shame narratives are present. That being said, there are some considerations that can already be made regarding the level of analysis. First, when an individual finds themselves in a shame situation, they go through a moment of recognition and a moment of response.Footnote 142 States can go through similar phases but there are significant differences in timing and agency. Although the moment of recognition and reaction is often immediate for an individual, a state can be suspended in its existential anxiety for a longer period in time. This means that there is time and agency for deliberation, reflection, strategic positioning, and so on, which is less an option for an individual.Footnote 143 Second, individuals experience shame affectively, which is not necessarily the case with state shame. The state might be considered to be in a shame situation, yet citizens can distance themselves from experiencing shame vicariously, for example by dissociating themselves from the state or by feeling indifferent regarding the subject at hand. The state still copes with being in a shame situation for which political agents, depending on how they conceive the sources of assessment and failure, construct one of the four following types of shame narratives.

Situational shame

Situational shame is a shame narrative that originates from a shame situation where a failure of a social norm is negatively assessed by the self. More specifically, the actor is made aware of a norm transgression by an agent believed to be part of the self. The failure is conceived as a wrongful, but temporary, transgression that has to be understood as caused by a particular situation, rather than a wrongful intension, hence ‘situational’ shame.Footnote 144 For example, imagine going to a high-class restaurant only to notice that you fail in meeting the particular dress code that is demanded of patrons. You will feel out of place not because of a wrongful action, but because you sense that you do not belong. Although there might not be any material consequences associated with this type of shame narrative, if there are any, they are conceived as superficial or limited in their cost. Coping and ego defence strategies that can be connected to this type of shame narrative are rationalization, for example arguing that the relevant actors were unaware of the norm, and some forms of undoing, like ruminations on counterfactuals.Footnote 145 To cope with the situation in the preceding example, for instance, you can mention that you were not informed about the dress code or you can apologize and ruminate about how this situation could have been avoided. To be clear, this does not exclude the experiences of guilt or embarrassment but the person will still experience themselves as being out of place.

When projected onto a state, the situational shame narrative understands the state's self not to be fundamentally challenged, as the failure will not act as a permanent negative evaluation of self. However, the state's social status does need to be reaffirmed through a reparative action like an apology or a restitution of material losses. The action is aimed at getting outside respect, admiration, and recognition for the state's legitimate place in the international order, allowing it to maintain a positive self-image.Footnote 146 This means that the goal of the restorative behaviour is not necessarily to sympathize with the victims of their actions. An example of this could be seen in recent historical apologies regarding the colonial past of Western states.Footnote 147 Particularly intriguing is the apology of the Belgian state for its involvement in the murder of Patrice Lumumba, the former prime minister of Congo. In the official apology, acknowledged its ‘moral responsibility’ in the murder but avoided accepting any direct involvement and emphasized its current day progressive course (the apology being proof of that).Footnote 148 Because of the propensity to apologize or perform similar acts of remorse, this type of shame is closely connected to, and often conflated with, the experience of guilt.Footnote 149 The difference between a narrative of state guilt and one of situational shame can be separated by the narrative's object of concern, namely if it is focussed on the self (situational shame) or the self's action (guilt). Depending on the particular cultural context, it can be expected that guilt and shame will be referred to interchangeably in these state narratives.Footnote 150

Narcissistic shame

Narcissistic shame is a shame narrative where the actor is made aware of transgressing self ideals by an agent that is conceived as part of their self or in-group. The narrative evokes an intense realization that the shamed actor has had an inflated sense of self, which was based on narcissistic fantasies and hubristic beliefs. Although the latter initially served as a source of pride, the excessive attribution of status to the self comes to be seen as unwarranted.Footnote 151 For example, when someone claims to be a skilled musician (which may or may not be the case) but fumbles during a jam session, they might reconsider their self-narrative (i.e. ‘being a skilled musician’) or practice frantically before performing again to become what they claim to be. The narrative, in other words, recognizes the wrongfulness of the self. In so doing, it recounts the disillusionment in the self being (morally, socially, politically, etc.) acceptable, which is characterized by an intense feeling of loss and pain. The narcissistic state shame narrative thus conceives the self as a fragile actor that is trying to reconcile with its wrongfulness.

As a narrative projected onto the state, the narcissistic shame narrative triggers a reflection on the state self and what its legitimate social position should be. In effect, this existential search can lead to a renewed state self narrative and, potentially, the active repositioning of its place in the world. It can inspire actions that aim to restore relations with other actors and make them commit to genuine care for victims as a consequence of their previous beliefs and behaviour.Footnote 152 An example of this type of narrative can be found in the current dominant discourse on the Holocaust in Germany.Footnote 153 The acknowledgement of the horrors of the Nazi past and the consequent actions towards the Jewish community and the state of Israel, resonate with this kind of narcissistic shame narrative. As the narcissistic shame narrative entails a fragile and searching state self it can give cause to such coping behaviours as isolation, to protect the process of repair, and, potentially, sublimation. This latter defence mechanism entails the transformation of a fantasy or desire into a more socially accepted activity or belief.Footnote 154 Because of the fragility that this shame narrative implies, there is always a need to be delicate regarding further actions and discourses.

Aggressive shame

Aggressive shame is a shame narrative that originates when an actor is believed to be negatively assessed by an other for transgressing a social norm, effectively challenging their place in the social and moral world. The member of an out-group or a different agent is believed to shame the self because the latter did not follow the normative scripts of international society. However, the aggression originates primarily from the idea that the self's narcissistic beliefs and fantasies are questioned by an actor that is unwarranted to do so. The negative judgement is then understood as a coercive act to challenge, even change, the self and force it towards conforming behaviour.Footnote 155 An example of this narrative is that of a married couple where one partner feels taunted by their significant other regarding their ability to clean the house. Because they are held up to the standards that their partner finds desirable, they feel challenged in their place in the world (i.e. they are ‘pushed out of their own house’) and will respond through what they feel are reciprocate actions, such as being overly fixated on the cleaning mistakes of the other. Instead of diminishing the narcissistic fantasies and beliefs, the aggressive shame narrative feeds a grandiose notion of self and the hatred for the assessing other.Footnote 156 Importantly, the assessing agent can effectively become constructed as an other by the aggressive shame narrative. Aggressive shame narratives namely inspire a close identification of self and the difference, even oppositeness, from the other.

The projection of this narrative onto a state would conceive the state self as treated unjustly and requires defending. This situation would be described with terms such as rage, anger, contempt, and humiliation to justify aggressive actions. In so doing, the narrative will show similarities with narcissistic rage,Footnote 157 namely the total lack of empathy towards the source of assessment which can be manifested as a grudge, spite, anger, or even vengeance.Footnote 158 An example of this type of narrative can be found in the dominant discourse of Iran regarding the condemnation of its nuclear activities by the International Atomic Energy Agency and various countries. Conceiving these threats, and the subsequent boycotts, as illegitimate and unwarranted, Iran has repeatedly escalated its nuclear programme, maintained support for proxy wars in the Middle East, and act more aggressively in the Persian Gulf regarding oil tankers and fishing vessels. As this shame narrative defends the self in the most explicit way, it also holds the more recognizable coping mechanisms such as avoidance, active refutation, externalized aggression, or hypercriticism (i.e. being acutely focussed on how the other behaves and criticizing them on every minor misstep). Apart from these, the narrative can also inspire ego defences such as denial and projection, a mechanism that involves perceiving the other as having a negative trait that the self is – inaccurately – believed not to have.Footnote 159 To illustrate this with the previous example, Iranian statesmen often conceive the West, and in particular the USA, as aggressive oppressors and that any Westernization ought to be combatted to ‘return to the Self’.Footnote 160 In effect, aggressive state shame narratives inspire and facilitate conflict escalation and general feelings of hatred towards other groups by feeding irreconcilable narratives.Footnote 161

Deferential shame

Deferential shame is the shame narrative where the state is assessed by an other for not being committed to their self-ideals. The assessing agent is not just any actor that is not part of the in-group but one with a higher social status, which could be a parent, a teacher, a boss, or a celebrity. Their negative judgement is considered warranted and focussed on dismantling a fantasy or narcissistic desire regarding the self that is believed to be false.Footnote 162 In effect, the deferential state shame narrative conceives the actor as deficient and unworthy of pride. The self is thus narrated in a manner that agrees with the gaze of the idealized other and, as such, can lead to the relinquishing of a part of the dominant conception of self.Footnote 163 For example, when someone who conceives themselves as progressive is shamed for expressing racist views, they will conceit to this claim. If the deferential shame narrative is, however, often repeated and becomes part of the common sense of the actor, it can develop into a stigma. In so doing, deep-seated feelings of inferiority towards other individuals or groups will be sustained.Footnote 164 In giving up their sovereignty of narrating their own self, whether formally or informally, there are no specific actions or coping mechanisms that can be connected to this particular narrative. However, the assumption can be made that it informs a general sense of melancholiaFootnote 165 and resentment.Footnote 166 In effect, the shamed actor can come to resent their presumed inferior position and develop feelings of animosity towards the shaming actor, effectively breeding an aggressive shame narrative. Following the previous example, the formerly progressive actor might come to resist the negative judgement of them being racist and, potentially, develop more reactionary views as a result of that.

The deferential shame narrative, if it is projected onto a state, would entail the negative judgement of the state self by an actor that is conceived to be superior, for example a regional hegemon, an idealized country in the past, or an international leader like the Pope. In response, the state submits itself to the will of the other and acts in a way that mirrors the latter's desires and expectations. This narrative would express a form of submission towards this judgement, through explicit or implicit acknowledgement of the inferiority of the state self or dominance of the other. The deferential state shame narrative would be present in its most extreme form in conquered states or polities that have been aggressively coerced into specific behaviour. Post-Second World War Japan was, for example, occupied by Allied forces and needed to rescind its self-narrative on military strength and imperial expansion. This situation was experienced as humiliating, especially paired with the economic hardship that followed and the pacifism that Japan had to abide by. Similar to a stigma, deferential shame does not, however, necessarily lead to the internalization of the idealized other's gaze.Footnote 167 As the state comes to conceive their position to be radically different from the idealized other, they might come to hold the notion that they can never amount to the same standard. In effect, such a difference might fuel reflection of the own position and can develop into a source for later refutation of the deferential position. This resentment might fuel an aggressive state shame narrative that ends up challenging the other and feed a new state self-narrative based on antagonistic, narcissistic fantasies and desires. Following the previous example, in recent years Japanese nationalist groups have come to resent the pacifism and the subservience to the USA, effectively aiming to reassert their understanding of the Japanese state self. The deferential state shame narrative thus sustains subservience but also contains the fuel for its own transformation.

The politics of state shame

The narrative understanding of state shame, and the theorization that the conceptual framework generates, is an analytical tool that sheds light onto complex and interlinked processes. It describes how such shame narratives could operate and provides insight into why states might behave the way they do when they encounter a shame situation. Additionally, the typology offers an insight into the politics of state shame. In artificially crystallizing political dynamics, the typology exposes when and where power is introduced and makes its mark. One of the central aims of an empirical analysis of state shame would be to determine when structural power comes into play, how political agents can enforce agency, and how state shame can lead to political change. However, some aspects of these dynamics can already be qualified based on the literature and the previous discussion.

First, the sources of assessment and failure can be reframed by political agents. The latter are capable of shaping who is conceived as a self or an other through a variety of discursive strategies such as scapegoating, vilification, or identification.Footnote 168 Similarly, sources of failure can be discursively framed as externally imposed social norms but also as inherent to the state or particular community of feeling.Footnote 169 The interpretation of the shame situation can thus act as a site of agency for political actors. However, there are limits to the amount of leeway that the shame situation allows. That the sources of assessment and failure are discursively constructed, and can thus be de- and reconstructed, does not mean that they are easily adjustable or are allowed to be adjusted without difficulty. Notions of self and other, and prevailing social norms and self-ideals are deeply ingrained social constructs that are linked to the national or group specific habitus and their particular memories and habits. Political agents who want to change sources of assessment and failure thus encounter robust notions that are profoundly obvious and familiar to many. How this negotiation takes place will be one of the principal focal points of empirical analysis.

Second, structural inequality and hierarchy in IR mediates how states cope with a shame situation. What this means for the narrative competition is that, for one, social status can determine the tenacity of narcissistic beliefs and desires regarding the state self.Footnote 170 A great power state or hegemon will, for example, have a more grandiose conception of self and thus more confidence and trust regarding its own assessment. In the opposite case, a lesser or subaltern power can be coerced in accepting the negative appraisal out of fear for severe repercussions, which can effectively lead to structural shaming or stigma.Footnote 171 Moreover, a state's historical relationship can also influence how they receive international negative assessment.Footnote 172 If the state conceives itself as being at the ‘heart’ of the liberal international order, for example, they will concede more quickly to social pressures following international criticism. Negative past experiences with international society or a subaltern position in it can, in contrast, lead to a proneness of shame refutation. However, because of the focus on narratives and how political agents frame them, the theory presented here is far more agency-focussed. Rather than expose more structural elements of political conflicts, this type of perspective works best when it either builds on structural assumptions or forgoes them completely. Nevertheless, empirical analyses can focus on how these international status tensions figure in and inform state shame narratives.

Third, state shame narratives can bring about both political change and sustain the status quo. Although political identities or discourses might not be infinitely malleable, the shock of having a challenge to the sense of self can offer an opportunity to reimagine alternative understandings of how the world works.Footnote 173 It allows for a hybrid position in a liminal space where boundaries that were previously placed are questioned and can be realigned.Footnote 174 Shame, in this sense, can be considered a revolutionary emotion.Footnote 175 However, the potential for change that a moment of existential anxiety offers does not need to be overstated, as existing narratives always constrain the capacity for adaptation.Footnote 176 It is for this reason that ‘change is only possible to the extent that it can be accounted for within one's biographical narrative’,Footnote 177 a narrative that is, at the same time, continuously rewritten and reshaped to accommodate present needs.Footnote 178 To sum up, existential anxiety, and by extension state shame, can act as a precondition for both change as for maintaining a status quo.Footnote 179

Finally, the ethical roles of state shame are particular to the context. Both IR and the literature on the politics of shame has a problematic penchant to simplify shame's inherent moral ambiguity by only emphasizing the ‘dangerous’ or the ‘necessary’ role of shame in social life.Footnote 180 It is equally problematic to argue that there would be a ‘good’ and ‘bad’ form of shame in political life,Footnote 181 as this Manichean categorization severs the emotion's moral role from its particular social context. In so doing, it is assumed that state shame, or any emotion for that matter, has the possibility to be both vicious or virtuous in politics regardless of its phenomenological characteristics.Footnote 182 For example, narcissistic state shame challenges unfounded beliefs and narcissistic fantasies about the state's self but this would not necessarily imply that the new sense of state self is morally ‘good’. A state narrative could be imbued with notions of humility and modesty, but could equally lead to an exaggerated sense of unimportance that makes them withdraw from international politics altogether. Situational state shame might be fitting for an accident at sea between two navies, yet is completely inappropriate regarding a past genocide. Similarly, deferential state shame can be considered ethically warranted in response to an international naming and shaming campaign, or problematic when it is seen as the result of prolonged stigmatization. Although aggressive state shame might be questionable in most cases, it may have merit in the situation where a superpower tries to shame a smaller state into compliance.Footnote 183 Consequently, understanding the politics of state shame does not mean identifying whether a state copes with the shame situation in a ‘good’ or ‘bad’ way but focusses on how states deal with state shame and how political agents attempt to influence this.

Conclusion

The central goal of this paper has been to make state shame a more suitable tool for IR. To this end, it gave a conceptual and theoretical overview of how shame has been conceived in IR, in particular by OSS, and criticized the concept's current use. Rather than understand the concept to be unwieldy and untenably, the paper presents a novel conception of state shame that entangles insights from IR, social psychology, and sociology. More specifically, the central argument is that state shame should be understood as a negative narrative on the social status of the state. Depending on how political agents understand the particular shame situation that their state is placed in, four types of narrative can develop as a result to cope with the negative self-conception. The typology consists of situational shame, narcissistic shame, aggressive shame, and deferential shame and relegates diverging state behaviours to each of these four types. In effect, the proposed conceptual framework provides insight into the particularity, causality, and effects of state shame, effectively countering the critiques that have previously been levelled. The politics surrounding state shame are argued to be characterized by the active reframing of the sources of assessment and failure, the role of international hierarchy, the ability of all state shame narratives to bring about both political change and sustain the status quo, and the contextual nature of the ethics surrounding state shame.

In proposing this novel conception of shame, the current paper contributes to the literature in three ways. First, it develops upon a relatively obscure concept that has acted as an implicit or taken-for-granted assumption in multiple literatures on international norm dynamics, status, stigma, and ontological security. Second, it interacts with the specific debate on ontological security's productive, yet problematic, focus on self-securitization by decentring and transcending the dichotomic ontological security–insecurity conception. Although the reconfiguration of shame does not resolve this particular issue, it does offer an insight into the politics that ground collective self-narration and, as such, can inspire an approach that surpasses the determinism embedded in the ontological security literature. Finally, the paper also contributes to the broader academic debate on the politics of shame by discussing how this emotion is political on higher levels of analysis while not using an anthropomorphic perspective.

Rather than conceiving this conceptual work as a finished exercise, the framework that has been presented here should be seen as a starting point for understanding what lived practices and meanings state shame can come to hold. Rather than solely ‘test’ this conception and assess whether it corresponds with reality, empirical research can engage with the claims that have been presented here and come to more nuanced or situated conceptions of state shame. It could problematize the Western understanding of shame or elaborate on additional types of state shame narrative that are obscured by the four dimensional framework that has been argued. Future theoretical work regarding this concept can also focus more on further elucidating the various types and linking them to broader theories and observations in international politics. In so doing, it could provide insight into the various state behaviours that can be inspired by state shame and reveal its politics in a more substantive manner.

Acknowledgements

The author would like to acknowledge the research group International Politics at the University of Antwerp, and in particular Jorg Kustermans, the EISA panel on Anxiety, Authenticity, and Political Culture, Jamie Johnson, Owen Thomas, Ana Flamind, Victoria Basham, and Italo Brandimarte for their comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Competing interests

None.

Footnotes

2 E.g., Harkavy Reference Harkavy2000; Saurette Reference Saurette2006; Homolar and Löfflmann Reference Homolar and Löfflmann2021.

3 E.g., Finnemore and Sikkink Reference Finnemore and Sikkink1998; Adler-Nissen Reference Adler-Nissen2014; Towns and Rumelili Reference Towns and Rumelili2017.

4 E.g., Ilgit and Prakash Reference Ilgit and Prakash2019; Koschut Reference Koschut2021; Bassan-Nygate and Heimann Reference Bassan-Nygate and Heimann2022.

7 This stands in contrast to the discourse of preeminent classical realists and the progenitors of international relations theory, whose work is scattered with references to shame and self-conscious emotions (such as Niebuhr, Machiavelli, and Thucydides). For some texts that go a bit deeper into these claims, see Donnelly (Reference Donnelly2004, 66–67; 178–80) and Ross (Reference Ross2013).

8 Mason Reference Mason2010, 405; Crawford Reference Crawford2000, 119.

9 Harkavy Reference Harkavy2000, 346.

10 Crawford Reference Crawford2000, 116.

13 Finnemore and Sikkink Reference Finnemore and Sikkink1998.

16 Friman Reference Friman2015, 3.

18 Ilgit and Prakash Reference Ilgit and Prakash2019. Moreover, Friman (Reference Friman2015, 44) claims that ‘for the naming and shaming concept to be useful, it should not depend on the actual psychological state of the target’.

20 As would be the case in the ‘naming and shaming’ literature (cf. Friman Reference Friman2015, 3) or more individualist approaches to emotions in politics. See Ilgit and Prakash (Reference Ilgit and Prakash2019) for an extensive critique of this approach.

22 To clarify, the ‘ontological’ aspect of this name does not refer to the philosophical study of being. Ontological in this sense only denotes the sense of being, which one wants to secure by maintaining continuity of self and their surroundings.

24 Giddens Reference Giddens2006, 67.

29 Footnote Ibid., 10–12.

30 Anxiety is considered by Giddens (Reference Giddens1984, 61) a ‘generalized state of the emotions of the given individual’. Moreover, it is ‘fear which has lost its object through unconsciously formed emotive tensions that express ‘internal dangers’ rather than externalised threats’ (Reference Giddens2006, 45), and generates repression and its behavioural symptoms, rather than the other way around.

31 Steele Reference Steele2008, 2–3; Browning Reference Browning2019.

32 Cf. Mitzen Reference Mitzen2006.

33 Steele Reference Steele2008, 2–5.

34 For an overview of this divide see Krickel-Choi (Reference Krickel-Choi2022).

37 Zarakol Reference Zarakol2010, 7.

38 Kinnvall Reference Kinnvall2004, 749.

39 Adler-Nissen Reference Adler-Nissen2014, 149.

40 Adler-Nissen Reference Adler-Nissen2014, 170; Subotić and Zarakol Reference Subotić and Zarakol2012, 916. As anxiety generates a broad spectrum of emotions, it also offers more options for analysis. However, as anxiety is in itself not an emotion, but more akin to a ‘mood’ (Rumelili Reference Rumelili2021; Ringmar Reference Ringmar2017, Reference Ringmar2018) a deeper analysis of the politics and state behaviour that follows anxiety requires dedicated theorization and conceptualization of emotions that are generated by anxiety and ontological (in)security more generally.

43 Hagström Reference Hagström2021, 5.

45 Cf. Ahmed Reference Ahmed2014, 109; Nussbaum Reference Nussbaum2004; Tarnopolsky Reference Tarnopolsky2010.

46 Cf. Finnemore and Sikkink Reference Finnemore and Sikkink1998.

47 Cf. Steele Reference Steele2008.

55 Cf. Steele Reference Steele2008, 2–3.

56 Kinnvall and Mitzen Reference Kinnvall and Mitzen2020, 249.

57 Krickel-Choi Reference Krickel-Choi2022, 7.

58 Cf. Hagström Reference Hagström2021.

59 Adler-Nissen Reference Adler-Nissen2016, 34.

60 Steele Reference Steele2008, 164; Hagström Reference Hagström2021, 3.

61 Steele Reference Steele2008, 164.

62 Hagström Reference Hagström2021, 3.

65 A similar problem can be identified with the focus on anxiety. See Krickel-Choi Reference Krickel-Choi2022 and Lebow Reference Lebow2016.

72 Flockhart Reference Flockhart2016, 801; Krickel-Choi Reference Krickel-Choi2022, 11.

74 Geertz Reference Geertz1983, 57.

75 Koschut Reference Koschut, Van Rythoven and Sucharov2020, 79. The emotions that are attributed to the state should be analytically separated from what Hall (Reference Hall2015) calls ‘state emotions’. These are phenomena where state agents actually act out emotions, meaning that they express them in behaviour that is recognized as being emotional. State emotions are characterized by properties and feeling rules that are distinctly different from individual and popular feelings (Hall Reference Hall2015, 26) and do not necessarily imply that they are shared by the rest of the population.

78 Wendt Reference Wendt1999, 194.

79 Wendt Reference Wendt2004, 313.

81 Wendt Reference Wendt1999, 225.

82 Subotić and Zarakol Reference Subotić and Zarakol2012, 918.

85 Subotić and Zarakol Reference Subotić and Zarakol2012, 918.

87 Cash and Kinnvall Reference Cash and Kinnvall2017, 269. This is also a position that can counter the status quo bias that is common in ontological security research (Kinnvall and Mitzen Reference Kinnvall and Mitzen2020).

89 It is necessary to stress, however, that ‘nationhood’ in this sense does not imply that the nation is a concrete and delineable group, but rather a ‘nation-ness’ (Heaney Reference Heaney and Demertzis2013, 257).

90 Cf. Epstein Reference Epstein2011, 341–42.

91 Ross Reference Ross2006, 199; Deleuze and Guattari Reference Deleuze and Guattari1987, 400.

93 Berezin Reference Berezin2002, 44–45; Williams Reference Williams1993, 80.

94 Berezin Reference Berezin2002, 44.

96 Ahmed Reference Ahmed2014, 15; Pettigrove and Parsons Reference Pettigrove and Parsons2012, 508. As Febvre (Reference Febvre and Burke1973, 14) puts it, ‘emotions are contagious’. They bring ‘together large numbers of people acting sometimes as initiators and sometimes as followers, finally reached the stage where they constituted a system of inter-individual stimuli which took on a variety of forms according to situation and circumstance, thereby producing a wide variety of reactions and modes of sensibility in each person’ (Ibid., 14–15). Effectively, Febvre develops an argument similar to the one that is claimed in this research, as ‘the harmony thus established and the simultaneity of the emotional reactions thus guaranteed, proved to be of a kind that gave greater security or greater power to the group; utility thus soon justified the constitution of a veritable system of emotions. The emotions became a sort of institution. They were controlled in the same way as a ritual. Many of the ceremonies practised by primitive peoples are simulated situations with the obvious aim of arousing in all, by means of the same attitudes and gestures, one and the same emotion, welding them all together in a sort of superior individuality and preparing them all for the same action’ (Ibid., 15).

97 Kinvall and Mitzen Reference Kinnvall and Mitzen2018; Arfi Reference Arfi2020, 291; Krickel-Choi Reference Krickel-Choi2022, 10.

99 Berezin Reference Berezin2002, 44–45.

100 E.g., Wolf Reference Wolf2011, 118, Reference Wolf2017, 11; Hall Reference Hall2015, 25.

104 This entails taking into account the particular cultural, linguistic, and historical context of said community of feeling. There are highly diverse ways to understand shame, or any other emotion, the following overview is primarily inspired by Western conceptions and Anglo-Saxon literature.

105 E.g., Williams Reference Williams1993; Scheff Reference Scheff2000.

107 Nussbaum Reference Nussbaum2004, 207.

108 Other conceptions of this divide give more extensive analytical arguments. See Lewis Reference Lewis1971, Barrett Reference Barrett, Tangney and Fischer1995, Tangney and Dearing Reference Tangney and Dearing2002.

109 Erikson [1950] Reference Erikson1993; Taylor Reference Taylor1985.

112 Konstan Reference Konstan2006, 102; Tarnopolsky Reference Tarnopolsky2010, 157.

113 Barbalet Reference Barbalet2001, 103.

114 Ahmed Reference Ahmed2014, 106

115 Footnote Ibid., 107.

119 Telling of this is the ‘international packing order’ among UN diplomats. See Pouliot Reference Pouliot2011.

123 Shame refutation can also take the form of flattery, in that the agent recognizes the shamefulness of the situation and assumes the view of the other in such a way that they do not reveal any inadequacies (Tarnopolsky Reference Tarnopolsky2010, 19).

124 McAdams Reference McAdams1998, 1125–27; Baumeister et al. Reference Baumeister, Dale and Sommer1998. It has been argued that, when the narcissistic tendencies of the self are more compelling than the normative scripts or the ideal other's gaze, the shamed actor might consistently deal with shame in a non-conforming way, giving cause to pathological and anti-social behaviour (Kohut Reference Kohut1977; Morrison Reference Morrison1989).

125 Tarnopolsky Reference Tarnopolsky2010, 191; Goffman Reference Goffman1963.

128 Lester Reference Lester1997. The death of the self can be conceived as both a defence against as a restorative action following shame.

133 Kemper and Collins Reference Kemper and Collins1990.

135 The concept of shame situation is borrowed from Tarnopolsky (Reference Tarnopolsky2010), who uses it to indicate the separate stages of a shame refutation. However, it is argued here that it is also suited for understanding the particular phases of any experience of shame.

136 Koschut and Oelsner Reference Koschut and Oelsner2014. States are also less likely to criticize their friends and allies but if they do, the shamed actor is more likely to agree with the critique. See Terman and Voeten Reference Terman and Voeten2018.

137 Barbalet Reference Barbalet2001, 122. It might be a bit confusing to use other in this way, since an other can also be significant (see previous section). Yet, this particular term does link up to the process of othering that can be generated by a shame situation. For a discussion of how the self/other dynamic can be conceived as both dialectical and dialogical, see Der Derian (Reference Der Derian1987), Neumann (Reference Neumann1996, 55–56), and Lebow (Reference Lebow2008, 474–79). In general, this paper assumes that the self/other dynamic generates a boundary and reproduces a binary that is undeniably Western (Onar and Nicolaïdis Reference Onar and Nicolaïdis2013). At the same time, shame is a self-conscious experience that brings an intense focus to the boundary between self and other, effectively producing this binary in one of its most extreme forms.

139 Barbalet Reference Barbalet2001, 123

141 Barbalet Reference Barbalet2001, 123.

142 Tarnopolsky Reference Tarnopolsky2010, 57.

143 To be clear, an individual can experience shame for a long period of time. This claim only refers to the moment of perplexity, not shame in general. Additionally, it can also be argued that the timing is dependent on the type of state shame that is experienced, as the situational type is short-lived (e.g. the 2001 naval incident of the Ehime Maru) whereas narcissistic shame can extend over a couple of decades (such as Germany's reckoning with the Holocaust).

145 Baumeister et al. Reference Baumeister, Dale and Sommer1998, 1096.

149 Konstan Reference Konstan2006, 102; Tarnopolsky Reference Tarnopolsky2010, 157.

150 This was the case in the previous example given. See Verleye Reference Verleye2021.

152 Cf. Braithwaite Reference Braithwaite2000; Koschut Reference Koschut2021.

153 There has been some discussion in philosophical debates regarding this issue between Karl Jaspers, who claimed that this position ought to be referred to as collective guilt, whereas Hannah Arendt believed that the feeling of shame is more appropriate in this regard. See Zembylas Reference Zembylas2019, 308 on this disagreement.

154 Baumeister et al. Reference Baumeister, Dale and Sommer1998, 1103.

157 Although it is not evident to analytically separate the particular dynamics of shame induced hatred with that of other forms, the general assumption is that aggressive shame is primarily centred around securing the sense of self.

159 Baumeister et al. Reference Baumeister, Dale and Sommer1998, 1090.

160 Horemans Reference Horemans2023, 172.

163 Morrison Reference Morrison1989, 63.

165 Cf. Gilroy Reference Gilroy2005.

166 Cf. Scheff Reference Scheff2000.

168 To be clear, othering is a complex process and can serve many purposes in that ‘persons will identify positively with some aspects of other person’ identities and will seek to emulate these “desirable” qualities’ but ‘it may still be possible for a person to reject some aspects of an other with whom it identifies positively, criticizing this very same other for their perceived faults’ (Naudé Reference Naudé2022, 67–68). For more on the connection between scapegoating and shame, see Girard (Reference Girard1989, 155).

169 Although political agents might not make this difference as clearly in empirical reality as is assumed here, this analytical perspective on the source of the wrongdoing is still helpful in the overall analysis of state shame.

175 Cf. Marx [1843] Reference Marx1967; Deleuze Reference Deleuze1995; O'Donnell Reference O'Donnell2017.

177 Krickel-Choi Reference Krickel-Choi2022, 14.

178 Lebow Reference Lebow2016, 24.

179 Kinnvall and Mitzen Reference Kinnvall and Mitzen2020, 247.

180 Tarnopolsky Reference Tarnopolsky2010, 7.

181 Cf. Nussbaum Reference Nussbaum2004. Ironically, Tarnopolsky (Reference Tarnopolsky2010), on whose work this critique is based, falls in the same trap by designating ‘flattering shame’ and ‘Socratic respectful shame’ to be less fortuitous in politics than the more balanced ‘Platonic respectful shame’.

182 Cf. Tarnopolsky Reference Tarnopolsky2010, 6; Locke Reference Locke2016, 169. To be clear, the argument is not that devastating and painful emotions such as humiliation or disgust are morally desirable. The reasoning follows a more sociological position, in that emotions play a complex role in social and political life and their ethical meaning should be interpreted according to their particular context rather than from a universalist principle.

183 Cf. Pettigrove and Parsons Reference Pettigrove and Parsons2012.

References

Adler-Nissen, Rebecca. 2014. “Stigma Management in International Relations: Transgressive Identities, Norms, and Order in International Society.” International Organization 68 (1): 143–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adler-Nissen, Rebecca. 2016. “The Social Self in International Relations: Identity, Power and the Symbolic Interactionist Roots of Constructivism.” European Review of International Studies 3 (3): 2739.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agamben, Giorgio. 1999. Remnants of Auschwitz: The Witness and the Archive. New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Ahmed, Sara. 2014. The Cultural Politics of Emotion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arfi, Badredine. 2020. “Security qua Existential Surviving (while becoming Otherwise) through Performative Leaps of Faith.” International Theory 12 (2): 291305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagdonas, Ąžuolas. 2018. “Historical State Apologies.” In The Palgrave Handbook of State-Sponsored History After 1945, edited by Bevernage, Berber and Wouters, Nico, 775–99. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barbalet, Jack M. 2001. Emotion, Social Theory, and Social Structure, A Macrosociological Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barrett, Karen C. 1995. “A Functionalist Approach to Shame and Guilt.” In Self-conscious Emotions: The Psychology of Shame, Guilt, Embarrassment, and Pride, edited by Tangney, June Price and Fischer, Kurt W., 2563. New York: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Bassan-Nygate, Lotem, and Heimann, Gadi. 2022. “Dealing with Guilt and Shame in International Politics.” International Relations 38 (2): 256–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baumeister, Roy F., Dale, Karen, and Sommer, Kristin L. 1998. “Freudian Defense Mechanisms and Empirical Findings in Modern Social Psychology: Reaction Formation, Projection, Displacement, Undoing, Isolation, Sublimation, and Denial.” Journal of Personality 66 (6): 1081–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentley, Tom. 2015. “The Sorrow of Empire: Rituals of Legitimation and the Performative Contradictions of Liberalism.” Review of International Studies 41 (3): 623–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berenskötter, Felix. 2020. “Anxiety, Time, and Agency.” International Theory 12 (2): 273–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berezin, Mabel. 2002. “Secure States: Towards a Political Sociology of Emotion.” The Sociological Review 50 (2): 3352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bevernage, Berber. 2011. “History by Parliamentary Vote: Science, Ethics and Politics in the Lumumba Commission.” History Compass 9 (4): 300311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhabha, Homi K. 1994. The Location of Culture. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Braithwaite, John. 2000. Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Branscombe, Nyla R., and Doosje, Bertjan, eds. 2004. Collective Guilt, International Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brassett, James, Browning, Christopher S., and O'Dwyer, Muireann. 2021. “EU've Got to be Kidding: Anxiety, Humour and Ontological Security.” Global Society 35 (1): 826.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browning, Christopher S. 2016. “Ethics and Ontological Security.” In Ethical Security Studies: A New Research Agenda, edited by Nyman, Jonna and Burke, Anthony, 160–73. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browning, Christopher S. 2019. “Brexit Populism and Fantasies of Fulfilment.” Cambridge Review of International Affairs 32 (3): 222–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browning, Christopher S., and Joenniemi, Pertti. 2016. “Ontological Security, Self-Articulation and the Securitization of Identity.” Cooperation and Conflict 52 (1): 117.Google Scholar
Cash, John, and Kinnvall, Catarina. 2017. “Postcolonial Bordering and Ontological Insecurities.” Postcolonial Studies 20 (3): 267–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crawford, Neta. 2000. “The Passion of World Politics: Propositions on Emotion and Emotional Relationships.” International Security 24 (4): 116–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daase, Christopher, Engert, Stefan, Horelt, Michel-André, Renner, Judith and Strassner, Renate. 2015. Apology and Reconciliation in International Relations, The Importance of Being Sorry. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deleuze, Gilles. 1995. Negotiations. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Deleuze, Gilles, and Guattari, Félix. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Der Derian, James. 1987. “Mediating Estrangement: A Theory for Diplomacy.” Review of International Studies 13 (2): 91110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnelly, Jack. 2004. Realism and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Eberle, Jakub. 2019. “Narrative, Desire, Ontological Security, Transgression: Fantasy as a Factor in International Politics.” Journal of International Relations and Development 22 (1): 243–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eberle, Jakub and Handl, Vladimír. 2020. “Ontological Security, Civilian Power, and German Foreign Policy Toward Russia.” Foreign Policy Analysis 16 (1): 4158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eberle, Jakub, and Daniel, Jan. 2022. “Anxiety Geopolitics: Hybrid Warfare, Civilisational Geopolitics, and the Janus-Faced Politics of Anxiety.” Political Geography 92: 19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ejdus, Filip. 2018. “Critical Situations, Fundamental Questions and Ontological Insecurity in World Politics.” Journal of International Relations and Development 21 (4): 883908.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Charlotte. 2011. “Who Speaks? Discourse, the Subject, and Identity in International Politics.” European Journal of International Relations 17 (2): 327–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Charlotte. 2012. “Stop Telling Us How to Behave: Socialization or Infantilization?International Studies Perspectives 13 (2): 135–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erikson, Erik. 1993. Childhood and Society. London: Paladin Grafton Books.Google Scholar
Febvre, Lucien. 1973. “Sensibility and History: How to Reconstitute the Emotional Life of the Past.” In A New Kind of History, From the Writings of Febvre, edited by Burke, Peter, 1226. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Fessler, Daniel M. T. 2007. “From Appeasement to Conformity: Evolutionary and Cultural Perspectives on Shame, Competition, and Cooperation.” In The Self-Consciousness Emotions: Theory and Research, edited by Tracy, Jessica L., Robins, Richard W., and Tangney, June P., 174–93. New York: Guildford Press.Google Scholar
Finnemore, Martha, and Sikkink, Kathryn. 1998. “International Norm Dynamics and Political Change.” International Organization 52 (4): 887917.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flockhart, Trine. 2016. “The Problem of Change in Constructivist Theory: Ontological Security Seeking and Agent Motivation.” Review of International Studies 42 (5): 799820.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friman, Richard H., ed. 2015. The Politics of Leverage in International Relations: Name, Shame, and Sanction. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geertz, Clifford. 1983. “‘From the Native's Point of View’: On the Nature of Anthropological Understanding.” In Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology, 5570. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Giddens, Anthony. 1984. The Constitution of Society. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Giddens, Anthony. 2006. Modernity and Self-Identity. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Gilroy, Paul. 2005. “Multiculture, Double Consciousness and the ‘War on Terror’.” Patterns of Prejudice 39 (4): 431–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Girard, René. 1989. The Scapegoat. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goffman, Erving. 1956. The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh Press.Google Scholar
Goffman, Erving. 1963. Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled Identity. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Hagström, Linus 2021. “Great Power Narcissism and Ontological (In)Security: The Narrative Mediation of Greatness and Weakness in International Politics.” International Studies Quarterly 65 (2), 331–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, Todd D. 2015. Emotional Diplomacy: Official Emotion on the International Stage. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Harkavy, Robert E. 2000. “Defeat, National Humiliation, and the Revenge Motif in International Politics.” International Politics 37 (3): 345–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heaney, Jonathan G. 2013. “Emotions and Nationalism: A Reappraisal.” In Emotions in Politics: The Affect Dimension in Political Tension, edited by Demertzis, Nicolas, 243–63. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hochschild, Arlie R. 1979. “Emotion Work, Feeling Rules, and Social Structure.” American Journal of Sociology 85 (3): 551–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Homolar, Alexandra, and Löfflmann, Georg. 2021. “Populism and the Affective Politics of Humiliation Narratives.” Global Studies Quarterly 1 (1): 111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horemans, Rikkert. 2023. “Reconceptualizing Iran's Regional Influence: The Case for Authority.” PhD diss., Department of Political Sciences, Faculty of Social Sciences, University of Antwerp.Google Scholar
Hutchison, Emma. 2016. Affective Communities in World Politics, Collective Emotions After Trauma. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ilgit, Asli, and Prakash, Deepa. 2019. “Making Human Rights Emotional: A Research Agenda to Recover Shame in ‘Naming and Shaming’.” Political Psychology 40 (6): 1297–313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Innes, Alexandria J. 2017. “Everyday Ontological Security: Emotion and Migration in British Soaps.” International Political Sociology 11 (4): 380–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kemper, Theodore. 1978. A Social Interactional Theory of Emotions. New York: John Wiley.Google Scholar
Kemper, Theodore D., and Collins, Randall. 1990. “Dimensions of Microinteraction.” American Journal of Sociology. 96 (1): 3268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keohane, Robert. 1990. “Empathy and International Regimes.” In Beyond Self-Interest, edited by Mansbridge, Jane J., 227–36. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina. 2004. “Globalization and Religious Nationalism: Self, Identity, and the Search for Ontological Security.” Political Psychology 25 (5): 741–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina. 2015. “The Postcolonial has Moved Into Europe: Bordering, Security and Ethno-Cultural Belonging.” Journal of Common Market Studies 54 (1): 152–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina. 2018. “Ontological Insecurities and Postcolonial Imaginaries: The Emotional Appeal of Populism.” Humanity & Society 42 (4): 523–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina, and Mitzen, Jennifer. 2018. “Ontological Security and Conflict: The Dynamics of Crisis and the Constitution of Community.” Journal of International Relations and Development 21 (4): 825–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina, and Mitzen, Jennifer. 2020. “Anxiety, Fear, and Ontological Security in World Politics: Thinking with and Beyond Giddens.” International Theory 12 (2): 240–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohut, Heinz. 1971. The Analysis of the Self: A Systematic Approach to the Psychoanalytic Treatment of Narcissistic Personality Disorders. New York: International Universities Press.Google Scholar
Kohut, Heinz. 1977. The Restoration of the Self. New York: International Universities Press.Google Scholar
Konstan, David. 2006. The Emotions of the Ancient Greeks: Studies in Aristotle and Greek Literature. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koschut, Simon. 2020. “Communitarian Emotions in IR: Constructing Emotional Worlds.” In Methodology and Emotion in International Relations, Parsing the Passions, edited by Van Rythoven, Eric and Sucharov, Mira, 7996. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Koschut, Simon. 2021. “Reintegrative Shaming in International Relations: NATO's Military Intervention in Libya.” Journal of International Relations and Development 25 (2): 497522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koschut, Simon and Oelsner, Andrea, eds. 2014. Friendship in International Relations. Houndmills, Bastingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krickel-Choi, Nina C. 2022. “The Concept of Anxiety in Ontological Security Studies.” International Studies Review 24 (3): 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lacan, Jacques. 1998. The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psycho-Analysis. London: Hogarth.Google Scholar
Lebow, Richard Ned. 2008. “Identity in International Politics.” International Relations 22 (4): 473–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lebow, Richard Ned. 2016. National Identities and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lerner, Adam B. 2020. “What's It Like to be a State? An Argument for State Consciousness.” International Theory 13 (2): 260–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lester, David. 1997. “The Role of Shame in Suicide.” Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior 27 (4): 352–61.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lethi, Marko, and Penannen, Henna-Riikka. 2020. “Crises of the West: Liberal Identities and Ontological (In)Security.” In Contestations of Liberal Order: The West in Crisis?, edited by Lethi, Marko, Penannen, Henna-Rikka, and Jouhki, Jukka, 6198. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Lewis, Helen B. 1971. Shame and Guilt in Neurosis. New York: International Universities Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Lewis, Michael. 1995. “Embarrassment: The Emotion of Self-Exposure and Evaluation.” In The Self-Consciousness Emotions: Theory and Research, edited by Tracy, Jessica L., Robins, Richard W., and Tangney, June Price, 198218. New York: Guildford Press.Google Scholar
Linklater, Andrew. 2004. “Norbert Elias, The ‘Civilizing Process’ and the Sociology of International Relations.” International Politics 41 (1): 335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, Jill. 2016. Democracy and the Death of Shame: Political Equality and Social Disturbance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lu, Catherine. 2008. “Shame, Guilt and Reconciliation After War.” European Journal of Social Theory 11 (3): 367–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lupovici, Amir. 2012. “Ontological Dissonance, Clashing Identities, and Israel's Unilateral Steps towards the Palestinians.” Review of International Studies 38 (4): 809–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malesevic, Siniša. 2011. “The Chimera of National Identity.” Nations and Nationalism 17 (2): 272–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1967. Writings of the Young Marx on Philosophy and Society. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Mason, Michelle B. 2010. “On Shamelessness.” Philosophical Papers 39 (3): 401–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAdams, Dan P. 1998. “The Role of Defense in the Life Story.” Journal of Personality 66 (6): 1125–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitzen, Jennifer. 2006. “Ontological Security in World Politics: State Identity and the Security Dilemma.” European Journal of International Relations 12 (3): 341370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, Andrew P. 1989. Shame, The Underside of Narcissism. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Muldoon, Paul. 2017. “A Reconciliation Most Desirable: Shame, Narcissism, Justice and Apology.” International Political Science Review 38 (2): 213–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naudé, Bianca. 2022. Revisiting State Personhood and World Politics, Identity, Personality and the IR Subject. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Navari, Cornelia, and Green, Daniel M. 2013. Guide to the English School in International Studies. Chichester: John Wiley and Sons.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neumann, Iver B. 1996. “Self and Other in International Relations.” European Journal of International Relations 2 (2): 139–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2004. Hiding From Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
O'Donnell, Aislinn. 2017. “Shame is Already a Revolution: The Politics of Affect in the Thought of Gilles Deleuze.” Deleuze Studies 11 (1): 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Onar, Nora Fisher, and Nicolaïdis, Kalypso. 2013. “The Decentring Agenda: Europe as a Post-Colonial Power.” Cooperation and Conflict 48 (2): 283303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrove, Glen, and Parsons, Nigel. 2012. “Shame: A Case Study of Collective Emotion.” Social Theory and Practice 38 (3): 504–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pouliot, Vincent 2011. “Diplomats as Permanent Representatives, The Practical Logics of the Multilateral Pecking Order.” International Journal 66 (3): 543–61.Google Scholar
Probyn, Elspeth. 2005. Blush: Faces of Shame. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Rathbun, Brian C. 2011. “Before Hegemony: Generalized Trust and the Creation and Design of International Security Organizations.” International Organization 65 (2): 243–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Retzinger, Suzanne M. 1995. “Identifying Shame and Anger in Discourse.” American Behavioral Scientist 38 (8): 1104–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ringmar, Erik. 1996. Identity, Interest and Action, A Cultural Explanation of Sweden's Intervention in the Thirty Years War. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ringmar, Erik. 2017. “Outline of a Non-Deliberative, Mood-Based, Theory of Action.” Philosophia 45 (4): 1527–39.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ringmar, Erik. 2018. “What are Public Moods”, European Journal of Social Theory 21 (4): 453–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Risse, Thomas, Ropp, Stephen C., and Sikkink, Kathryn. 1999. The Power of Human Rights, International Norms and Domestic Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, Andrew A. G. 2006. “Coming in from the Cold: Constructivism and Emotions.” European Journal of International Relations 12 (2): 197222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, Andrew A. G. 2013. “Realism, Emotion, and Dynamic Allegiances in Global Politics.” International Theory 5 (2): 273299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rossdale, Chris. 2015. “Enclosing Critique: The Limits of Ontological Security.” International Political Sociology 9 (4): 369–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rumelili, Bahar. 2020. “Integrating Anxiety into International Relations Theory: Hobbes, Existentialism, and Ontological Security.” International Theory 12 (2): 257‒72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rumelili, Bahar. 2021. “[Our] Age of Anxiety: Existentialism and the Current State of International Relations.” Journal of International Relations and Development 24 (4): 1020–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saurette, Paul. 2006. “You Dissin Me? Humiliation and Post 9/11 Global Politics.” Review of International Studies 32 (3): 495522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheff, Thomas J. 2000. Bloody Revenge: Emotions, Nationalism and War. Lincoln: iUniverse.Google Scholar
Solomon, Ty. 2015. The Politics of Subjectivity in American Foreign Policy Discourse. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, Brent J. 2008. Ontological Security in International Relations: Self-Identity and the IR State. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, Brent J., and Subotić, Jelena 2018. “Moral Injury in International Relations.” Journal of Global Security Studies 3 (4): 387401.Google Scholar
Subotić, Jelena 2016. “Narrative, Ontological Security, and Foreign Policy Change.” Foreign Policy Analysis 12 (4): 610–27.Google Scholar
Subotić, Jelena 2018. “Political Memory, Ontological Security, and Holocaust Remembrance in Post-Communist Europe.” European Security 27 (3): 296313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Subotić, Jelena, and Zarakol, Ayşe. 2012. “Cultural Intimacy in International Relations.” European Journal of International Relations 19 (4): 917–8.Google Scholar
Tangney, June Price, and Dearing, Rhonda L.. 2002. Shame and Guilt. New York: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Tangney, June Price, Stuewig, Jeff, and Mashek, Debra J.. 2007. “Moral Emotions and Moral Behavior.” Annual Review of Psychology 58 (1): 345–72.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tarnopolsky, Christina H. 2010. Prudes, Perverts, and Tyrants, Plato's Gorgias and the Politics of Shame. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Gabrielle. 1985. Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Terman, Rochelle, and Voeten, Erik. 2018. “The Relational Politics of Shame: Evidence from the Universal Periodic Review.” The Review of International Organisations 13 (1): 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, Krista K. 2018. Naked: The Dark Side of Shame and Moral Life. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Towns, Ann, and Rumelili, Bahar. 2017. “Taking the Pressure: Unpacking the Relation between Norms, Social Hierarchies, and Social Pressures on States.” European Journal of International Relations 23 (4): 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tracy, Jessica L., Robins, Richard W., and Tangney, June Price, eds. 1995. The Self-Consciousness Emotions, Theory and Research. New York: Guildford Press.Google Scholar
Untalan, Carmina Yu. 2020. “Decentering the Self, Seeing Like the Other: Toward a Postcolonial Approach to Ontological Security.” International Political Sociology 14 (1): 4056.Google Scholar
Verleye, Zeger. 2021. “The Lumumba Commission (1999-2002): Shame, Guilt, and the Post-Imperial Self.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 50 (1): 328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vieira, Marco A. 2016. “Understanding Resilience in International Relations: The Non-Aligned Movement and Ontological Security.” International Studies Review 18 (2): 290311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vieira, Marco A. 2018. “(Re-)imaginging the ‘Self’ of Ontological Security: The Case of Brazil's Ambivalent Postcolonial Subjectivity.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 46 (2): 142–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Max. 1999. “Die ‘Objektivität’ Sozialwissenschaftlicher und Sozialpolitischer Erkenntnis.” In Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, edited by Flitner, Elizabeth, 146214. Potsdam: Internet-Ausgabe.Google Scholar
Weisband, Edward. 2000. “Discursive Multilateralism: Global Benchmarks, Shame, and Learning in the ILO Labor Standards Monitoring Regime.” International Studies Quarterly 44 (4): 643–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 2004. “The State as Person in International Theory.” Review of International Studies 30 (2): 289316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1993. Shame and Necessity. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, Reinhard. 2011. “Respect and Disrespect in International Politics: The Significance of Status Recognition.” International Theory 3 (1): 105–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, Reinhard. 2017. “Identifying Emotional Reactions to Status Deprivations in Discourse.” International Studies Review 19 (3), 11–6.Google Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2010. “Ontological (In)Security and State Denial of Historical Crimes: Turkey and Japan.” International Relations 24 (1): 323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2011. After Defeat: How the East Learned to Live with the West. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2014. “What Made the Modern World Hang Together: Socialisation or Stigmatisation.” International Theory 6 (2): 311–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe, ed. 2017. Hierarchies in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zembylas, Michalinos. 2019. “‘Shame at Being Human’ as a Transformative Political Concept and Praxis: Pedagogical Possibilities.” Feminism & Psychology 29 (2): 303–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Shame situation, based on the social typology of shame by Jack Barbalet141