Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-16T11:18:32.221Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Where will they be: hidden implications of solutions to the Fermi paradox

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 April 2022

Niklas Alexander Döbler*
Affiliation:
Department of General Psychology and Methodology, University of Bamberg, Bamberg, Bavaria, Germany Research Group EPÆG (Ergonomics, Psychological Aesthetics, Gestalt), Bamberg, Germany Bamberg Graduate School of Affective and Cognitive Sciences (BaGrACS), University of Bamberg, Bamberg, Germany
*
Author for correspondence: Niklas Alexander Döbler, E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Solutions to the Fermi paradox either deny the existence of extraterrestrials or offer alternative reasons to explain the non-occurrence of a first contact. While the latter, more optimistic approaches generally assume the existence of extraterrestrials, they simultaneously hint to limited future detectability. If solutions to the Fermi paradox are accepted as true, they must be evaluated in terms of how they affect the likelihood of success of future SETI efforts. Some solutions may lead to the so-called Fermi constraint: in order to explain why there has not been any contact so far, optimistic solutions to the Fermi paradox have to accept assumptions that, if the solution is assumed to be correct, indicate a very low probability of future contact. In other words: they are not here, and that is why they may never appear.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

If there are other, much older civilisations in the Milky Way, and if these civilisations have engaged in interstellar space travel for a long time, where are they? This simple question, ascribed to Italian Nobel prize winner Enrico Fermi, is a rough summary of the so-called Fermi paradox.

Much has been written about the Fermi paradox. The most fundamental remarks are that it is neither a paradox nor originated from Fermi in the first place (Freitas, Reference Freitas1985; Gray Reference Gray2015). Yet, Hart (Reference Hart1975) notably and pessimistically concluded that them not being here must mean that they do not exist. As SETI's most prominent mislabelled problem persists, several attempts have been made to explain the absence of extraterrestrials without denying their existence. We may call these approaches the optimistic solutions. They range from general criticism of the human search process (Freitas, Reference Freitas1985) to the idea that exponential expansion would not be a sustainable approach for extraterrestrial civilisations (Haqq-Misra and Baum, Reference Haqq-Misra and Baum2009). These and other optimistic solutions assume the general possibility of the existence of extraterrestrials and offer various reasons for why a first contact has not occurred yet.

This is opposed by the advocates of the pessimistic solution. Derived from the non-event of observation and some additional presumptions, the conclusion is that extraterrestrials do not exist (Hart, Reference Hart1975; Tipler, Reference Tipler1980, Reference Tipler1981; Sandberg et al., Reference Sandberg, Drexler and Ord2018). Whether one postulates the existence of extraterrestrials or denies it, the Fermi paradox is one of the key arguments of SETI criticism. It is frequently employed to either call for a revisited search strategy or to abolish SETI altogether (Ćirković, Reference Ćirković2013).

Hidden and future implications

There is no definitive solution to the Fermi paradox yet. However, when discussing the paradox, one fact unites the pessimists and the optimists: regardless of who will be proven correct, any solution to the Fermi paradox hints to a low or nonexistent chance for the future success of SETI.

Pessimists and optimists start from the same observation, a derivation from Hart's (Reference Hart1975) notorious Fact A: There has been no contact between extraterrestrials and humanity that has been confirmed beyond doubt. Every approach consequently offers a specific explanation (B XY) for A. B XY for pessimists is simply that there are no extraterrestrials. If this is true and humanity is the only advanced civilisation in the galaxy, the case is clear: A will never change as there is nobody with whom humanity could establish contact. Due to the non-existence of extraterrestrials (B Non-existence) A therefore leads to C = There will be no contact between humanity and extraterrestrials and p contact = 0.

In the scenario where the optimists are right; extraterrestrials do exist, but various factors have prevented detection so far, things get a little more complicated. For optimists, BXY can include a variety of reasons (Brin, Reference Brin1983). These reasons can not only constitute an explanation for the non-occurrence of a first contact in retrospect but also contain limitations for establishing contact with extraterrestrials in the future. Overall, these limitations are more versatile and flexible than the one limitation given by the pessimists. If for example the failure of detection was simply a matter of employing the wrong search strategy and thus a methodological issue, the adaptation of proper methodology would significantly increase chances of future success. Nevertheless, if social, psychological, technological, or cultural factors discourage extraterrestrials from seeking contact with humanity, there is little to nothing human SETI researchers can do about it. Either way, A due to Boptimistic leads to a weakened version of C: C' = Future contact between extraterrestrials and humanity is very unlikely, but may still be possible (p contact ≥ 0). Fig. 1 shows the internal structure of solutions to the Fermi paradox.

Fig. 1. The internal structure of solutions to the Fermi paradox.

Take, for instance, the simple explanation that extraterrestrials do not want contact with humanity. This solution simultaneously limits future detectability. We can, of course, assume that the motivation of extraterrestrials may be dynamic, i.e. open for change so that they may be motivated to contact us in the future. This assumption weakens the initial claim as it cannot explain why the motivation of every extraterrestrial in the galaxy has been seemingly consistent over the past decades of human SETI efforts (cf. Hart, Reference Hart1975).

This example demonstrates how any singular explanation of the Fermi paradox must be saturated in the sense that it must explain the absence of extraterrestrials for every given time period in which no first contact has happened. This means that optimistic solutions must be able to explain the failure of SETI in general as well as regarding specific periods of human SETI efforts. Therefore any solution to the Fermi paradox must first explain why extraterrestrials are not physically present on Earth, given its young age and the possibility of older civilisations on other planets (compare the reasoning of Hart (Reference Hart1975), Tipler (Reference Tipler1980), and Morris (Reference Morris2011) on this issue). After accounting for this, any solution to the Fermi paradox must then explain why humanity has not made contact in six decades of SETI. It is evident that some optimistic solutions cannot account for both aspects on their own. When we explain the absence of extraterrestrial signals with humans employing the wrong search strategy for them, this does not logically resolve the issue of their physical absence in the past. This demonstrates that several restrictive aspects must be taken into account in order to form a solution to the Fermi paradox.

While the pessimistic solution to the Fermi paradox (they do not exist) is sufficient alone, optimistic solutions may be more versatile and may not apply to every hypothetical extraterrestrial civilisation. Conversely, one solution may explain the absence of several civilisations, for instance the consideration of the effort and technological advancement needed for space travel and interstellar communication (Ashkenazi, Reference Ashkenazi and Shostak1995; Döbler, Reference Döbler2020).

Optimistic solutions assume the existence of extraterrestrials but simultaneously contain limiting factors for future detectability of the extraterrestrials in question. Therefore, solutions to the Fermi paradox without denying the existence of extraterrestrials may lead what we may call Fermi constraint: In order to explain why there has not been any contact so far, optimistic solutions to the Fermi paradox have to accept assumptions that, if the solution is assumed to be correct, indicate a very low probability of future contact. In other words: They are not here, and that is why they may never appear.

Applying the parameters of any optimistic solution to the Fermi paradox results in a prediction not all too different to those solutions that claim humanity is the only advanced species in the galaxy. Depending on how the question ‘Where are they?’ is answered, the chance of future contact either approximates or equals zero. The degree of this approximation depends on the parameters of the respective solution. Any solution that cites dynamic factors such as sociological and psychological ones, will have a hard time sufficiently justifying the past absence of extraterrestrials by itself. While dynamic solutions place fewer constraints on the probability of future contact than stable solutions, the latter can explain past absence more reliably, but at the same time impose greater limitations on the likelihood of success of future SETI efforts. Table 1 shows the difference between dynamic and stable solutions.

Table 1. Dynamic and stable optimistic solutions to the Fermi paradox

Note. Different types of solutions may be in place for different civilisations. Civilisations may be influenced by more than one solution.

Given the myriad of solutions that assume the existence of extraterrestrials, determining the exact chance of future contact is impossible. One can, however, examine how one specific explanation may or may not impact the success probability of future SETI efforts. This task must be fulfilled with great care, sophisticated statistical models, and interdisciplinary effort and is thus beyond the scope of this paper. Yet, the explanation for the retroactive absence of extraterrestrials, ‘They are not here because of B XY,’ implies the prospective prediction: ‘They may never come because of B XY.’

Adjusting search strategies

Any solution to the Fermi paradox accepted to be true has consequences for the assumed likelihood of success of future SETI efforts. This is where we see the paradoxical nature of solutions to the Fermi paradox. Generally, optimistic solutions are meant to justify SETI efforts: They posit that extraterrestrials exist, even though it may be hard to contact them. But at the same time, optimistic solutions thwart the original premise because of their hidden implications. Optimistic solutions should therefore be careful not to inadvertently undermine their justification for SETI projects.

Any quantitative measure of how likely future contact depends on the specific solution. Factors beyond human control may be more restrictive than others, such as the suitability of search strategies or the suitability of technical search capabilities. In a solution where the former factors outweigh the latter, humanity is reduced to a passive observer whose capability for interstellar contact is more in the hands of others than in ours. A wrong approach to SETI, given it is identified as such, grants humanity more capacity to act and is more permissive regarding the possibility of establishing contact on our own. Yet, it still depends on the principal motivation of the other to be contacted.

Nevertheless, certain loopholes exist. The recent SETI focus on detection by a variety of technosignatures allows for remote detection even without a deliberately sent signal (Frank et al., Reference Frank, Kleidon and Alberti2017; Sheikh, Reference Sheikh2020). Other exceptions may be the explanation ‘Messages or space ships are already on their way.’ But generally speaking, specific optimistic solutions to the Fermi paradox require adjusting search strategies to cope with the constraints these solutions impose on the contact probability.

Conclusion

The considerations presented here are not intended to undermine the SETI enterprise. Instead, the goal is to put things into perspective and encourage an open debate about the hidden implications of different solutions to the Fermi paradox and about necessary adjustments to search strategies. Even though we do not know whether extraterrestrial life exists, how we think about it will determine how we search for it.

Furthermore, it is necessary to think about extraterrestrials as independent from human detection (Döbler, Reference Döbler2020; Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). In order to detect them remotely, their technological development must be so advanced that they can be detected with humanity's technological capabilities. But this is no inevitable consequence of their development. They may never be detectable. Either way, this would not change their ontological status as factually existing, independently of our knowledge of them.

One function of scientific theories is the explanation to explain current phenomena in the world. These explanations can be validated by trying to predict future phenomena. Once we accept a certain theory, such as one explaining the previous absence of extraterrestrials, we submit ourselves to certain beliefs and hypotheses with all their predicted consequences. The problem is that we cannot validate which solution of the Fermi paradox is true, since almost all of them more or less lead to the same prediction: They will not come.

Arthur C. Clarke once famously said, ‘Two possibilities exist: either we are alone in the Universe or we are not. Both are equally terrifying.’ Considering the Fermi paradox, our ability to determine which possibility we should be afraid of is constrained by the same problem: Assuming we believe to know why they are not here, would we ever know that our explanation is correct?

Acknowledgements

The author wants to thank the two anonymous reviews for their idea sparking comments. Many thanks to Albrecht Kleinlein for his proofreading.

Financial support

No funding involved.

Conflict of interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

References

Ashkenazi, M (1995) Will ETI be space explorers? Some cultural considerations. In Shostak, S (ed). Progress in the Search for Extraterrestrial Life: Proceedings of the Bioastronomy Symposium 1993 Santa Cruz, California. San Francisco, U.S.: ASP Conference Series, pp. 507517.Google Scholar
Brin, GD (1983) The ‘great silence’: the controversy concerning extraterrestrial intelligent life. Quarterly Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society 24, 283309.Google Scholar
Ćirković, MM (2013) Who are the SETI sceptics? Acta Astronautica 89, 3845.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döbler, NA (2020) The concept of developmental relativity: thoughts on the technological synchrony of interstellar civilizations. Space Policy 54, 101391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döbler, NA and Raab, M (2021) Thinking ET: a discussion of exopsychology. Acta Astronautica 189, 699711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frank, A, Kleidon, A and Alberti, M (2017) Earth as a hybrid planet: the Anthropocene in an evolutionary astrobiological context. Anthropocene 19, 1321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freitas, RA (1985) There is no Fermi paradox. Icarus 62, 518520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, RH (2015) The Fermi paradox is neither Fermi's nor a paradox. Astrobiology 15, 195199.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haqq-Misra, J and Baum, SD (2009) The sustainability solution to the Fermi paradox. Journal of the British Interplanetary Society 62, 4751.Google Scholar
Hart, MH (1975) An explanation for the absence of extraterrestrials on earth. Quarterly Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society 16, 128135.Google Scholar
Morris, SC (2011) “Predicting what extra-terrestrials will be like: and preparing for the worst.” Philosophical transactions of the royal society A: mathematical. Physical and Engineering Sciences 369, 555571.Google Scholar
Sandberg, A, Drexler, E and Ord, T (2018) Dissolving the Fermi paradox. Available at https://arxiv.org/pdf/1806.02404.Google Scholar
Sheikh, SZ (2020) Nine axes of merit for technosignature searches. International Journal of Astrobiology 19, 237243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tipler, FJ (1980) Extraterrestrial intelligent beings do not exist. Quarterly Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society 21, 267281.Google Scholar
Tipler, FJ (1981) Additional remarks on extraterrestrial intelligence. Quarterly Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society 22, 279292.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1. The internal structure of solutions to the Fermi paradox.

Figure 1

Table 1. Dynamic and stable optimistic solutions to the Fermi paradox