Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-rwnhh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-21T15:34:06.408Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Epistemic justification and the folk conceptual gap

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 February 2025

Dario Mortini*
Affiliation:
Barcelona Institute of Analytic Philosophy (BIAP), Barcelona, Spain Logos, University of Barcelona, Barcelona, Spain
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Recent experimental epistemology has devoted increasing attention to folk attributions of epistemic justification. Empirical studies have tested whether lay people ascribe epistemic justification in specific lottery-style vignettes (Friedman and Turri 2014, Turri and Friedman 2015, Ebert et al. 2018) and also to more ordinary beliefs (Nolte et al. 2021). In this paper, I highlight three crucial yet hitherto uncritically accepted assumptions of these studies, and I argue that they are untenable. Central to my criticism is the observation that epistemic justification is a philosophical term of art mostly foreign to lay people: as such, it is not suitable for direct empirical testing without being previously introduced. This point reveals a folk conceptual gap between the subject matter of these experimental studies and the conceptual repertoire we can reasonably expect lay people to possess. I elaborate on this worry, and I end on a cautiously optimistic note: after suggesting better strategies to survey folk attributions of epistemic justification, I conclude that the challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap remains difficult but can in principle be addressed.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

After a long-standing focus on lay ascriptions of knowledge, experimental epistemologists have recently turned the attention to folk attributions of epistemic justification.Footnote 1 In two extensive studies, Turri and Friedman (Reference Turri, Friedman and Beebe2014: 2015) investigated whether lay people ascribe epistemic justification to lottery propositions (i.e., that a particular ticket has lost a large enough lottery). The very same issue was further explored in another detailed study by Ebert et al. (Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018). Notably, interest in folk attributions of epistemic justification is not circumscribed to lottery-style cases: with the aim of assessing the thesis that knowledge entails justified belief, Nolte et al. (Reference Nolte, Rose, Turri, Lombrozo, Nichols and Knobe2021) have surveyed folk attributions of knowledge and epistemic justification in more ordinary scenarios than lottery-style vignettes. Taken together, these studies underscore a shift in interest towards folk attributions of epistemic justification. Individual differences aside, experimental epistemologists share one common expectation: folk attributions of epistemic justification ‘can straightforwardly be tested’ (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: 112) by simply asking to lay people whether they regard the belief under consideration to be justified.

In this paper, I cast serious doubt on this expectation. Folk attributions of epistemic justification cannot be straightforwardly tested nor should they be surveyed as they currently are. Unlike knowledge, epistemic justification is a technical concept that needs to be carefully introduced and explained. A folk conceptual gap has gone unnoticed: lay people can hardly be expected to possess and master the concept of epistemic justification familiar to epistemologists. One negative aim of this paper is to criticise the study design of these experimental studies in light of this folk conceptual gap. However, despite this criticism, I remain sympathetic to the general project of investigating folk attributions of epistemic justification, as these empirical data can benefit epistemological theorising. Accordingly, this paper also pursues a more positive aim: proposing a better way to survey folk attributions of epistemic justification.

My plan is as follows. In Section 2, I take a closer look at the design of these experimental studies, and in Section 3, I identify three crucial but uncritically accepted assumptions underlying the choice of their probe questions and vignettes. The significance and relevance of these studies essentially depend on the tenability of these assumptions. In Section 4, I reject each assumption in turn, and I articulate in more detail the difficult challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap. I end on a more cautiously optimistic note: after suggesting better strategies to survey folk attributions of epistemic justification, I conclude that the challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap remains difficult but can in principle be addressed.Footnote 2

2. A closer look: Vignettes and probe questions

The current studies surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification are very rich. Owing to limitations of space, I cannot do justice to their complexity here. Instead, I will focus directly on the details that matter for my purposes, namely the choice of vignettes and probe questions.Footnote 3

In their two experimental studies, Friedman and Turri are interested in the folk epistemology of lotteries: they aim to investigate whether lay people attribute knowledge and justification to lottery propositions (i.e., that particular ticket of a fair big enough lottery will lose). Epistemologists have often claimed that one cannot know that a particular ticket is a loser solely on the basis of the odds involved and that knowledge of lottery propositions requires testimonial evidence – for example, hearing on the evening news the announcement of the winning numbers (Pritchard Reference Pritchard2005; Williamson Reference Williamson2000). These claims play an important role also for theorising about epistemic justification, as some (though not all) epistemologists have claimed that one cannot justifiably believe that a particular ticket is a loser solely on the basis of the odds involved (Nelkin Reference Nelkin2000; Smith Reference Smith2010). Friedman and Turri’s experimental studies aim to examine whether folk judgements about lottery beliefs lend support to these claims often made by epistemologists. To achieve such aim, they presented the participants with these vignettes:

Lotto.Footnote 4 Abigail is out shopping with her son. In a store, they see a man with a super Lotto ticket. Abigail’s son says: ‘I bet that ticket’s not a loser. It might win the jackpot!’. Abigail answers, ‘It is a losing ticket’. And Abigail is exactly right: the ticket is a loser. (Friedman & Turri Reference Friedman and Turri2015: 1065)

News. Ellen bought a ticket in this week’s Super Lotto. Her numbers are 49-20-3-15-37-29-8. Ellen just finished watching the evening news, and they reported that a completely different number won. It was the same newscaster that reports the winning number every week on the local channel that Ellen watches. On that basis, Ellen concludes that her ticket lost. And she’s right: her ticket lost. (Turri & Friedman Reference Turri, Friedman and Beebe2014: 51)

The vignettes introduce the contrast of interest between statistical and testimonial evidence. To survey folk attributions of epistemic justification, the following were used as dichotomous test questions in Lotto and News: (1) Abigail is [justified/unjustified] in thinking that the ticket is a loser (Friedman & Turri Reference Friedman and Turri2015: 1066) and (2) Ellen is [justified/unjustified] in thinking that the ticket is a loser (Turri & Friedman Reference Turri, Friedman and Beebe2014: 49). Notably, these probe questions did not draw the attention to the evidence available to the protagonist of the vignette nor did they include additional qualifications specifying the relevant sense of epistemic justification.

Ebert et al. (Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018) are also interested in the folk epistemology of lotteries. To build the contrast between statistical and testimonial evidence, they presented participants with the following case-pairs:

Probabilistic Evidence. Harry owns a single ticket in a lottery. His numbers are 23-42-12-8-28-31. The only way for a ticket to win is to match all six numbers, and any other ticket is a losing ticket. Harry wasn’t able to watch the evening news at which the winning numbers were announced. He recalls from his statistics class that the chance of a single ticket winning this lottery is one in 14 million, i.e., there is a 99.999993% chance that his ticket has lost. (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: 116–117)

Testimonial Evidence. Harry owns a single ticket in a lottery. His numbers are 23-42-12-8-28-31. The only way for a ticket to win is to match all six numbers, and any other ticket is a losing ticket. Harry has just watched the evening news at which the winning numbers were announced and none of his numbers match. (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: 117)

It’s immediately worth noting that Ebert and colleagues’ study shows significant differences from the two studies on lottery beliefs run by Turri and Friedman. Firstly, these vignettes are more precise. The probabilities are made explicit, and it is clear that a winning ticket must match all the numbers. Moreover, since these vignettes do not specify that the ticket is in fact a loser, concerns about truth effects on belief evaluation and outcome bias are plausibly avoided (Gerken Reference Gerken2020). Secondly, and perhaps more importantly, Ebert and colleagues are more cautious. They explicitly refrain from drawing strong conclusions from their experimental surveys, and they do not reject any normative theory of epistemic justification on the basis of empirical data (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: 134).Footnote 5

Yet, despite these improvements and differences, the probe questions asked to the participants remain the same in both Probabilistic Evidence and Testimonial Evidence: (3) Suppose Harry believes that the ticket has lost. Is Harry justified in believing that the ticket has lost? Yes/No (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: 117). Participants could express confidence in their answer on a five-point Likert scale.Footnote 6 Once again, the probe question on (epistemic) justification did not include additional qualifications or mention the available evidence.

The study by Nolte, Rose and Turri (Reference Nolte, Rose, Turri, Lombrozo, Nichols and Knobe2021) has a different focus: they investigated whether folk attributions of knowledge and justification support the view that knowledge entails justified belief. Predictably, they presented a series of vignettes to the participants and ‘simply asked for both knowledge and justification’ (Nolte et al. Reference Nolte, Rose, Turri, Lombrozo, Nichols and Knobe2021: 32). Here’s one vignette of interest:

Accusation. Andy’s daughter has been accused of a serious crime. She lacks an alibi and the police have gathered strong evidence against her. But, even after considering it all, Andy feels that she must be innocent. And in fact he is correct: his daughter is innocent. (Nolte et al. Reference Nolte, Rose, Turri, Lombrozo, Nichols and Knobe2021: 34)

Two test statements followed, and participants could express agreement with each statement on a six-point Likert scale. The first statement concerned whether Andy knows that his daughter is innocent. The second statement was meant to survey attributions of epistemic justification: (4) Andy is justified in believing that his daughter is innocent (Nolte et al. Reference Nolte, Rose, Turri, Lombrozo, Nichols and Knobe2021: ${\rm{\S}}$ 1.4). In this experimental study too, the justification question did not include any additional qualification.Footnote 7

Let’s take stock. Each of these experimental studies is supposed to target folk judgements about epistemic rather than pragmatic or moral justification, but surprisingly enough none of these studies actually qualifies or mentions such target explicitly. To fully appreciate this point, here’s a list of the probe questions for epistemic justification used in each study:

  1. 1) Abigail is [justified/unjustified] in thinking that the ticket is a loser.

  2. 2) Ellen is [justified/unjustified] in thinking that the ticket is a loser.

  3. 3) Is Harry justified in believing that the ticket has lost? Yes/No.

  4. 4) Andy is justified in believing that his daughter is innocent.

These unqualified occurrences of justification should give us pause, as well as reasons to raise the alarm about possible equivocations. Why should we think that philosophically untrained participants correctly understood what they were asked? The validity of these experimental studies essentially depends on a satisfactory answer to this question and on further substantial assumptions. I tackle this question and bring out these assumptions in the next section.

3. The assumptions outlined

The success of these experimental surveys of folk attributions of epistemic justification is conditional on some substantial assumptions: if we are to take these surveys at face value, then these assumptions have to be granted. While these assumptions have never been made explicit, it is important to bring them out clearly in order to best assess the validity and the relevance of these experimental studies. The assumptions are the following:

Folk Understanding . Lay people can plausibly be taken to understand that they are being asked to assess whether a subject’s belief is epistemically justified.

Immediate Testability . Folk attributions of epistemic justification can be tested immediately without first introducing and explaining the concept of epistemic justification.

Theoretical Neutrality . Folk attributions of epistemic justification can be surveyed independently of any substantial theory of epistemic justification explicitly assumed by the experimenters or implicitly attributed to the participants.

A few comments on each. Firstly, Folk Understanding must be granted in order for the data to have any significance. For example, an interesting result replicated by each experimental study on lottery propositions is that lay people generally tend to ascribe justification to these propositions on the basis of both statistical and testimonial evidence (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: §5.1). This result can inform epistemological theorising on epistemic justification only if participants correctly understand the question and have a grasp of what it is for a belief to be epistemically rather than morally or prudentially justified. Without this assumption, lay people would be assessing a different type of justification, and the data would be about something else.Footnote 8

Secondly, and relatedly, Immediate Testability must also be granted; otherwise, the choice of vignettes and probe questions would be inapt: as highlighted in the previous section, neither the vignettes nor the probe questions make any attempt to introduce the concept of epistemic justification. As a result, it must be granted that folk attributions of epistemic justification can be tested without having to provide any preliminary explication of epistemic justification.

Finally, Theoretical Neutrality captures the ambitions of generality of these experimental studies. As Nolte et al. admit (Reference Nolte, Rose, Turri, Lombrozo, Nichols and Knobe2021: 46), these studies are not testing whether folk attributions of epistemic justification favour any particular theory of the nature or structure of justification (internalism or externalism, and coherentism or foundationalism). Instead, they are surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification in general and regardless of the implicit folk notion of epistemic justification that lay people operate with. Accordingly, we must also take for granted that folk attributions of epistemic justification can be surveyed neutrally, and without making any reference in the vignettes to substantive theories of epistemic justification.

Summing up, these are fairly minimal but ultimately necessary requirements for the validity and relevance of these experimental studies. First, that participants can plausibly be taken to understand and assess the epistemic justification of beliefs. Second, that the concept of epistemic justification needs no previous explication in the vignettes. Third, that lay people attribute epistemic justification independently of any substantial theory of epistemic justification.

Unfortunately, these assumptions will not hold up to scrutiny, and I will provide specific considerations against each of them. But before doing so, I want to be charitable and pause to make the following observation: there is a seemingly good reason why these assumptions were made in the first place. All these experimental studies were designed to survey attributions of both knowledge and epistemic justification, and these assumptions are innocent – perhaps even natural – for the purpose of surveying lay attributions of knowledge. Of course lay people understand the question when they are asked to attribute knowledge. Of course there is no need to previously explicate the concept of knowledge in order to survey knowledge attributions. And of course, lay people can attribute knowledge independently of any specific theory of knowledge: intuitively enough, knowledge attributions require no prior grasp of anti-Gettier conditions.Footnote 9

Yet, what is true of knowledge need not apply to epistemic justification, and in this case, it plausibly does not. As I show next, there’s an important asymmetry between lay attributions of knowledge and folk attributions of epistemic justification, and the assumptions made to investigate the folk epistemology of the former do not automatically carry over to the latter. The assumptions underlying these experimental studies neglect the following key point: lay people cannot be expected to already possess or immediately grasp and apply the epistemologist’s concept of epistemic justification. This reveals a folk conceptual gap between the subject matter of these experiments and the conceptual repertoire available to the participants. Rejecting each assumption in turn will bring out this gap more clearly; this is the task of the next section.

4. The assumptions rejected

The significance of the data concerning folk attributions of epistemic justification depends on whether the participants correctly understand the probe questions. However, none of the experimental studies explicitly qualify the kind of justification which is supposed to be surveyed. To evaluate the lottery vignettes, participants were asked whether the protagonist is ‘justified’ in thinking (or believing) that their ticket is a loser. Similarly, in Accusation, participants were asked if the protagonist is ‘justified’ in believing that their daughter is innocent.

The absence of a suitable qualifier is a problem for Folk Understanding . Participants may have reasonably picked up on the more ordinary sense of ‘justified’ and interpreted it as pragmatically or morally instead of epistemically justified. This diagnosis gains further support from empirical data recently gathered through corpus analysis. Broadly speaking, corpus linguistics aims to gain insight into ordinary language by surveying large collections of texts in plain English such as the Corpus of Contemporary American English (COCA), the British National Corpus (BNC), or the EnTenTen20 Corpus. Evidence from a recent corpus study on epistemic justification suggests that the expression ‘justified belief’ occurs almost exclusively in philosophical discourse: in the EnTenTen Corpus alone, 91% of the occurrences of justified belief belong to a philosophical context (Grindrod Reference Grindrod2022: 19). And when ‘justified’ and ‘justify’ occur in non-philosophical contexts, they are used to evaluate actions or emotions, not beliefs (Grindrod Reference Grindrod2022: 21). These results jointly indicate that the probe questions employ unusual terminology: in ordinary discourse, justification talk does not normally take belief as an object. This problem is compounded by the salient moral features in Accusation: the protagonist forms a belief about the guilt of his very own daughter. Participants may have reasonably attributed justification for reasons of partiality and thought that the protagonist is morally justified in believing that his daughter is innocent because he’s her father.Footnote 10 These considerations against Folk Understanding are however limited in the following important sense. They apply more clearly to the study run by Nolte and colleagues, but it remains unclear whether a similar problem affects the surveys of lottery beliefs. Despite the often noted connection between lottery beliefs and action (e.g., Hawthorne Reference Hawthorne2004: 29–30), it’s difficult to characterise with precision how exactly participants may interpret justification in a pragmatic sense when asked about a losing lottery ticket. Moreover, some sensitivity to epistemic cues may suggest that participants are picking up on the epistemic sense of justification. In support of this point, Ebert and colleagues found that folk attributions of epistemic justification are influenced by changes in probabilities due to the size of the lottery and also by further contextual information on the type of evidence in the vignettes (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: 126; 133). Relatedly, it’s hard to maintain that participants are confused about different senses of justification given the high confidence rates replicated in each of the three studies on folk attributions of justification in lottery cases. For these reasons, the problems I raised with Folk Understanding are particularly pressing for Nolte and colleagues’ study, but they are less troublesome for Ebert and colleagues and Turri and Friedman’s surveys.

Despite this acknowledged limitation, the assumption remains at the very least questionable. Taken together, the facts that the ordinary use of justification tracks pragmatic or moral propriety and that the vignette emphasises moral features cast some doubt on Folk Understanding : overall, participants could not obviously assess epistemic justification.

Immediate Testability , the assumption that folk attributions of epistemic justification can be tested immediately without providing any explication of the concept at issue, is also untenable. Technical concepts seem especially unsuited to be surveyed directly without first being introduced or explained, and epistemic justification is often taken to be a technical concept denoted by a philosophical term of art.Footnote 11 In fact, one point of agreement in the otherwise divided literature on epistemic justification is exactly that epistemic justification is a technical concept. In support of this, textual evidence abounds: as epistemologists have emphasised, epistemic justification is ‘a term from the philosophy classroom’ (Hawthorne & Stanley Reference Hawthorne and Stanley2008: 578) an instance of ‘philosophical jargon’ (Reynolds Reference Reynolds1998: 533), ‘a term of art in contemporary epistemology’ (Kvanvig Reference Kvanvig, Bernecker and Pritchard2010: 25) and ‘manifestly technical terminology’ (Williamson Reference Williamson, Dorsch and Dutantforthcoming: 3). For this reason, we should be sceptical of the possibility of surveying folk judgements about a distinctively technical notion that is not in any way introduced or explained.Footnote 12

Crucially, the problems with Immediate Testability will be more or less pressing depending on the exact dialectical role played by the empirical data. The more technical aspects of the concept of epistemic justification are particularly problematic when folk attributions of epistemic justification are taken to count against a normative theory of epistemic justification (Turri & Friedman Reference Turri, Friedman and Beebe2014: 64), or to support the more substantive thesis that knowledge entails justification (Nolte et al. Reference Nolte, Rose, Turri, Lombrozo, Nichols and Knobe2021: §5). These technical aspects may be less problematic when the empirical data are more modestly used to corroborate various armchair predictions on folk attributions of epistemic justification (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018 pursue this markedly different aim).

Bracketing such specific dialectical subtleties, the problems with Immediate Testability also affect Theoretical Neutrality . Since the concept of epistemic justification needs some introduction and explanation, folk attributions of epistemic justification can hardly be theory-neutral: these judgements will inevitably be constrained by the specific and substantive theory of epistemic justification which needs to be introduced. I return to this point in more detail below; now I just want to note that both generality and theoretical neutrality seem unfeasible given the theory-laden subject matter of these experimental studies.

Summing up, the design of all these experimental studies is problematic on the following fronts. Firstly, because it fails to specify the epistemic rather than the moral, pragmatic or prudential sense of justification, it employs ambiguous probe questions. Secondly, it purports to survey directly folk judgements on a technical notion which is neither introduced nor explained to the participants. Finally, it aims for a kind of theoretical neutrality which seems hard to achieve with the notion of epistemic justification.

With these observations in play, we can appreciate the more fundamental problem. These experimental studies neglect an important gap between their subject matter, folk attributions of epistemic justification, and the conceptual repertoire that we can reasonably expect lay people to possess. It is unreasonable to expect lay people to possess and master the concept of epistemic justification routinely employed by epistemologists, or to grasp it without previous explanations. It is equally unreasonable to survey folk judgements on justified belief directly using terms that are not ordinarily used to assess beliefs. Such is the folk conceptual gap, which crucially went unnoticed. Each experimental study trades on assumptions that overidealise the conceptual repertoire of the participants, and this overidealisation is reflected in the choice of the vignettes and probe questions.

It’s important to note that the folk conceptual gap does not necessarily point at a performance error nor does it predict that lay people make obvious mistakes in assessing the vignettes. The gap is in place because the probe questions employ ambiguous and technical terminology which led the participants to reasonably pick up on different aspects of the justification question. Participants are not being irrational because they should but nonetheless fail to appreciate the epistemic sense of justification: rather than highlighting the irrationality of the participants, the folk conceptual gap may underscore more subtle instances of dysrationalia, a term coined by Stanovich (Reference Stanovich2009) to denote the inability to think accurately despite adequate levels of intelligence and rational capacities. Dysrationalia is caused by mindware gaps (Stanovich Reference Stanovich2009: 129–130; 150–151; West Reference West2010: 102), broadly conceived as the lack of relevant concepts and the knowledge required for accurate responses to specific cognitive tasks. A strikingly similar analogy applies to folk attributions of epistemic justification: participants confidently assess the vignettes but nonetheless lack the relevant concepts, knowledge, and training to evaluate whether a belief is epistemically (as opposed to morally, or pragmatically) justified. Mindware gaps of this kind might constitute the cognitive bases of the folk conceptual gap.Footnote 13 Unless this gap can be bridged, a major challenge to survey folk attributions of epistemic justification remains unaddressed.

5. Folk attributions of epistemic justification: the way forward

The folk conceptual gap raises a considerable challenge. Can this challenge be addressed? If so, how? I will argue that while there are compelling reasons for a strongly pessimistic answer to these questions, different strategies to survey folk attributions of epistemic justification may warrant some cautious optimism. My aim is not to offer the perfect strategy to survey folk attributions of epistemic justification: more modestly, my main goal is to emphasise that the challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap is hard to address and thus worth taking seriously. I shall do so by pointing out the merits of pessimism, as well as the limitations of optimism.

5.1 Between strong pessimism and cautious optimism

The challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap turns out to be quite effective in casting serious doubt on the very possibility of surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification. Building on these initial doubts, a pessimistic line of response to the challenge will hold that folk attributions of epistemic justification simply cannot be surveyed. This pessimistic line of response enjoys a good deal of plausibility, and it can be motivated on the basis of two types of considerations.

Firstly, on fairly general grounds, we should not expect every phenomenon of philosophical interest to be amenable to empirical surveys. In a similar fashion, experimental epistemologists should not expect lay people to be able to make judgements on every relevant epistemological concept. Epistemic justification could plausibly be a key instance of these phenomena and concepts: given its technical nature, it may simply be unsuited to be surveyed experimentally.

Secondly, this pessimistic line of response can be further motivated by appeal to a local version of the so-called expertise defence (Kauppinen Reference Kauppinen2007; Ludwig Reference Ludwig2007; Williamson Reference Williamson2011; Egler & Ross Reference Egler and Ross2020). According to the advocates of a global version of the expertise defence, philosophers generally display special competence and privileged expertise in evaluating thought experiments and vignettes. As a result, trained philosophers are less prone to be influenced by other irrelevant and distorting factors (e.g., pragmatic implicatures or conceptual confusions). By contrast, given their lack of philosophical training, lay people do not possess such special competence and privileged expertise. Because their resulting judgements are more likely to be negatively affected and distorted, experimental surveys should not be given too much weight. Building on the global version of the expertise defence, supporters of a local version of the expertise defence will hold that the folk conceptual gap cannot be bridged exactly because lay people lack the specific training in epistemology which is necessary to competently evaluate whether a belief is epistemically justified. Since they have no training on the subtleties of the epistemic evaluation of belief, their judgements on this matter are intrinsically unreliable and too prone to errors and equivocations (e.g., lay people untrained in epistemology may too easily interpret justification in a pragmatic or moral sense). The fact that lay people are not trained to correctly apply the concept of epistemic justification provides reasons for strong pessimism on the possibility of survey folk attributions of epistemic justification: absent such essential training, it would appear that the folk conceptual gap simply cannot be bridged. Summing up, pessimism about the prospects of bridging the folk conceptual gap gains traction from the observation that some philosophical concepts may be simply unsuited to be surveyed experimentally, and from an independently supported local (and thus weaker) version of the expertise defence. Overall, strong pessimism seems warranted: taken together, the motivations for such a strong pessimism further highlight that the challenge raised by the folk concept is hard to meet.

However, even if well-supported and seemingly compelling, such a strong pessimism can (and should) be resisted: it would be premature to think that folk attributions of epistemic justification simply cannot be surveyed. The following observation begins to motivate a more optimistic stance towards the prospect of surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification. While epistemic justification may be a technical notion, lay people nevertheless seem to engage in genuinely epistemic assessments of belief which are distinct from knowledge attributions. In ordinary talk, lay people often ask about the reasons for belief, and criticise beliefs for being irrational or unreasonable. In certain contexts, lay people assess beliefs depending on whether they are supported by the available evidence: in a criminal trial, a lay jury may wonder whether the evidence adduced suffices to prove the defendant’s guilt beyond reasonable doubt, and in order to combat climate-change denial, a lay person might defer to scientists and appeal to the body of scientific evidence in support of anthropogenic climate change. These linguistic considerations are hardly decisive, but they are at the very least suggestive of the following: while lay people may lack the epistemologist’s technical concept of epistemic justification, they nevertheless can make judgements on the genuinely epistemic normative status of beliefs. These judgements inform epistemological theorising, and by adopting different strategies and a more cautious approach, they may also be investigated empirically. I now outline such strategies and approaches in detail.

5.2. Concept explication and alternative wording

In what follows, I will motivate a more cautiously optimistic approach to address the challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap. I will recommend two tentative strategies to better survey folk attributions of epistemic justification and also make sure to appreciate their most significant drawbacks. The upshot will be that while the challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap remains hard to address, adopting these strategies provides some reasons for cautious optimism.

A possible strategy attempts to remedy Immediate Testability , one of the untenable assumptions outlined in Section 3. Recall that a major factor contributing to the folk conceptual gap has to do with the design of the experimental studies surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification: these attributions are surveyed immediately without providing any preliminary explication of the relevant concept of epistemic justification. Accordingly, one way to bridge the folk conceptual gap is the concept explication strategy, which consists in providing the participants of the experimental studies with reliabilist or evidentialist explications of epistemic justification. For example, the surveys might include an explication that emphasises the importance of reliability and truth-conduciveness for epistemic justification (Goldman Reference Goldman and Pappas1979) or the role of conscious mental states (Conee & Feldman Reference Conee and Feldman1985). As a result, participants will be better positioned to assess whether the belief under consideration is epistemically justified.

While it might improve on Immediate Testability , this strategy runs into a number of further difficulties. Firstly, it does not seem practically feasible, as it remains unclear how to include a reliabilist or evidentialist explication of epistemic justification which is informative but also succinct. Perhaps ostensive definitions might do better: basic examples of epistemically justified perceptual or testimonial beliefs could give an intuitive sense of epistemic justification. However, this by itself still would not explicate the notion sufficiently well. In general, it will be very hard to explicate it within the space of a standard experimental survey.

On the top of this first worry, there’s a second (and perhaps deeper) worry: crucially, it will also be very hard to find a principled way to explicate the notion of epistemic justification that can avoid the experimenter bias. This bias refers to the experimenters’ unconscious dispositions that may affect the experiments in order to secure previously hoped for and more favourable results. The experimenter bias is pervasive in many areas of science, and it calls into question the viability of the concept explication strategy.Footnote 14 To be clear, the experimenter bias does not pose a problem for the current surveys of folk attributions of epistemic justification. However, this bias becomes more worrisome and pressing once an informative explication of the concept of epistemic justification is offered to the participants. To better articulate the threat posed by the experimenter bias, suppose again that the concept of epistemic justification is explicated in reliabilist or evidentialist terms. Either way, the choice very much risks to cue and influence the participants, who will likely adjust their assessments to the way the concept is explicated. More vividly put, reliabilist explications centred around truth-conduciveness risk to secure empirical results which would favour externalist theories of epistemic justification, and the same applies, mutatis mutandis, to any evidentialist explication emphasising the connection between epistemic justification and internal experiences. These difficulties should not be surprising: as the discussion of Theoretical Neutrality previously showed, we currently lack any principled and theory-neutral way to explicate the notion of epistemic justification. Thus, the concept explication strategy is not only practically unfeasible but also likely to be affected by the experimenter bias. These are serious limitations for the strategy.

A different approach clarifies further the probe questions on epistemic justification. This is the alternative wording strategy, which consists in formulating the probe questions of the surveys without overidealising the conceptual repertoire of the participants. Its key insight is to employ terminology and concepts that lay people can be reasonably expected to understand. To flesh out this strategy, I shall propose alternative wordings based on purported necessary conditions for epistemic justification which are more conceptually friendly insofar as they sufficiently match ordinary talk and thought: notions like rationality, reasonableness and evidence can fit the bill.

It is often noted that epistemic justification bears a connection to (epistemic) rationality. Indeed, epistemologists of an internalist stripe take the two to be synonymous (e.g., Huemer Reference Huemer2001, Smithies Reference Smithies2012, Dogramaci Reference Dogramaci2015). However, ‘rational’ is not obviously a technical expression: Cohen develops semantic and meta-semantic arguments for this point, concluding that ‘if you ask sophisticated English speakers whether a certain belief is rational, they will understand what they are being asked’ (Reference Cohen2016: 844). Cohen’s conclusion is disputable, and admittedly lacks clear empirical support. Still, if we grant it some prima facie plausibility, then ‘rational’ displays an advantage over ‘justified’. This tentatively suggests that ‘rational’ or ‘reasonable’ may provide slightly better (though still imperfect) wordings for the justification question. A different and potentially more helpful way to cash out epistemic justification is in terms of evidence: epistemically justified beliefs are supported by the evidence. This thesis can be developed in many different ways, depending on the nature of evidence and evidential support.Footnote 15 But regardless of these exact details, ‘evidence’ is also a more familiar term and conceptually friendly notion: as mentioned above, it figures prominently also in scientific and legal domains.Footnote 16

While by no means uncontroversial, these remarks have noteworthy consequences for the project of surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification. On the one hand, it is unreasonable to expect lay people to immediately and correctly comprehend questions on unqualified justification. On the other hand though, lay people may still be reasonably expected to understand the assessment of the rationality (or reasonableness) of a belief in light of the available evidence. For sake of illustration, here’s how one justification question may be reworded:

Is Harry justified in believing that the ticket has lost? Yes/No (Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018).

Alternative wording #1. Given the available evidence, is Harry’s belief that the ticket has lost rational? Yes/No.

Alternative wording #2. Given the available evidence, is Harry’s belief that the ticket has lost reasonable? Yes/No.

Alternative wording #3. Given the available evidence, is Harry’s belief that the ticket has lost justified? Yes/No.

Different combinations of these alternative wordings are possible, and the other justification questions can be similarly rephrased. This alternative wording strategy remains underdeveloped, but it still provides a better alternative to the current probe questions.

To be maximally clear, these necessary conditions on epistemic justification remain controversial. Many will reject the identification of epistemic justification and rationality (e.g., Lyons Reference Lyons2013: 9), and just as many will reject accounts of epistemic justification in terms of evidence (e.g., Goldman Reference Goldman1999: Section 3). However, just for the purpose of surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification, these adjustments will sharpen the justification question, as they employ terminology and concepts we can reasonably expect lay people to possess and understand. As already noted, aiming for theoretical neutrality is unrealistic. Because it’s a technical notion, surveying folk intuitions on epistemic justification requires to take a previous stand on substantive features of epistemic justification. This is a necessary but worthwhile trade-off: dropping ambitions of theoretical neutrality promises to yield more informative and precise data.Footnote 17

5.3. Methodological reform

I care to emphasise that I am not offering these strategies as a naive solution to the problems affecting the current surveys of folk attributions of epistemic justification: I am aware that my recommended probe questions may incur the very same difficulties faced by the probe questions they are meant to replace. Drawing the participants’ attention to the available evidence might achieve progress, but talk of ‘rationality’ and ‘reasonableness’ is also potentially ambiguous between a practical and epistemic sense. Perhaps these worries can be addressed by developing and combining more fine-grained versions of the alternative wording and concept explication strategies. For example, the probe questions may ask explicitly to bracket moral and pragmatic considerations, or instead of a strict definitional explication, participants might be provided with additional cues to better focus on the epistemic sense of justification. But even so, lingering ambiguities will inevitably remain, and further challenges are to be expected.

However, not all is lost. Once these difficulties are fully acknowledged, the project of surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification can be properly reassessed. Rather than constituting a definitive mark against the success of the project, these difficulties motivate a more cautious approach, as well as a general methodological reform. In light of a deeper appreciation of the complex subject matter of their surveys, experimental epistemologists should take a leaf from philosophy of science and adopt the more fruitful methodology of evidential triangulation, which consists in the use of multiple methods and independent sources of evidence to measure and detect the same phenomenon (Campbell & Fiske Reference Campbell and Fiske1959; Schickore & Coko Reference Schickore and Coko2013; Kuorikoski & Marchionni Reference Kuorikoski and Marchionni2016). Evidential triangulation is especially apt for experimental surveys of folk attributions of epistemic justification: experimental epistemologists may pursue different versions of both the concept explication and the alternative wording strategies, and then assess a larger body of data gathered by using independent sources of evidence and distinct methods. These methods should encompass a variety of strategies, including but not limited to different explications of epistemic justification and alternative probe questions rephrased in terms of evidence, reasonableness, and rationality.

This methodological reform opens fruitful avenues for future research, and it also further highlights the value of the three assumptions I have discussed. In general, keeping the focus on these assumptions helps to assess experimental surveys of folk attributions of epistemic justification. Here is a concrete (but quick) illustration of this point. One could maintain the same vignettes of the current surveys but then use a wider range of probe questions to test for the robustness of the responses. Crucially, diverging responses and confidence rates resulting from terminological changes in the probe questions would yield a more informed perspective on Folk Understanding . Alternatively, one could try to survey attributions of epistemic justification made by philosophy students while controlling for the views of their lecturer. Suppose that laypeople and philosophy students answered the questions differently. This would suggest that some expertise does underlie (folk) attributions of epistemic justification, and the case against Immediate Testability would then be stronger. Also, similarities between the answers of the students and the views endorsed by their lecturers would tentatively show that attributions of epistemic justification are influenced by substantive theories of epistemic justification. Such a result would count against Theoretical Neutrality .Footnote 18 These hypotheses are very speculative, but hopefully they illustrate the value of the three assumptions discussed in this paper.

Let’s take stock. Here’s the main upshot: the challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap remains difficult to meet. While my remarks are tentative, they nonetheless provide some reasons for cautious optimism. A more thorough development of my proposed strategies promises to address this difficult challenge. However, such a task is best left for another day.

6. Conclusion

Recent experimental surveys of folk attributions of epistemic justification are missing the mark: they underestimate a folk conceptual gap and overestimate the conceptual repertoire available to lay people. In this paper, I have drawn the attention to this gap and explained the problematic assumptions of these surveys. However, mine are not knockdown objections to the project of surveying folk attributions of epistemic justification. In a more constructive spirit, I also suggested some tentative strategies to address the challenge raised by the folk conceptual gap. This is a serious challenge: my recommended strategies are thus worthy of serious consideration, as they promise to inform future experimental surveys of folk attributions of epistemic justification.Footnote 19

Footnotes

1 See Brown & Gerken (Reference Brown, Gerken, Brown and Gerken2012: 11–14) for a thorough overview of the experimental studies on knowledge ascriptions. Experimental studies on knowledge ascriptions, and discussion thereof, can be found in Buckwalter (Reference Buckwalter2010), Schaffer & Knobe (Reference Schaffer and Knobe2012), Nagel (Reference Nagel, Brown and Gerken2012), Pinillos (Reference Pinillos, Brown and Gerken2012), Gerken (Reference Gerken2013, Reference Gerken2017) and Dinges & Zakkou (Reference Dinges and Zakkou2020).

2 The arguments and the hypotheses put forward in this paper can (and should) be empirically tested. However, while I am sympathetic to the project of running additional experimental surveys of folk attributions of epistemic justification, my aim in this paper is more modest. I am primarily concerned with key foundational issues underlying the current surveys, and my goal here is to lay the theoretical groundwork for running additional and more informative experiments. For these reasons, the main contribution of this paper paves the way for future empirical research but it does not strictly depend on mounting a novel experimental survey.

3 Two additional experimental studies are only indirectly relevant to folk attributions of epistemic justification, so I will not discuss them here. First, Sackris and Beebe (Reference Sackris, Beebe and Beebe2014) empirically survey a range of cases taken to suggest that an agent can have propositional knowledge without epistemic justification. However, as Nolte et al. point out, this study does not mention, nor ask about, epistemic justification. Secondly, Turri (Reference Turri2016) provides experimental evidence that folk evaluations of belief are generally sensitive to truth. While very valuable, these data do not obviously settle more specific questions concerning folk attributions of epistemic justification.

4 For the sake of clarity, a quick stylistic note. I shall label vignettes in capitalised Bold, general assumptions in capitalised underlined Bold , concepts in small caps and words in ‘single quotes’.

5 This dialectical point matters. Ebert and colleagues’ cautious approach stands in stark contrast with Turri and Friedman’s appeal to the empirical data. Crucially, Turri and Friedman seem to be more explicit in taking their surveys to weigh against normative theories of epistemic justification (e.g., Turri & Friedman Reference Turri, Friedman and Beebe2014: 50; 65).

6 While this point goes unnoticed in the experimental studies under discussion, it is interesting to observe that asking the binary question on a Likert scale may be a proxy to survey degrees of epistemic justification. However, it is difficult to draw robust conclusions on degrees of epistemic justification from the data. This is because the survey responses are skewed towards high confidence rates. In order to better capture these more fine-grained judgements, future experimental designs might benefit from a different sliding scale instead of a standard Likert scale.

7 In a second experiment, Nolte et al. (Reference Nolte, Rose, Turri, Lombrozo, Nichols and Knobe2021: §2) sharpened the justification question and asked whether the evidence justifies Andy in believing that his daughter is innocent. This question may be more precise, but it also assumes a narrower account of epistemic justification in terms of evidence. As I point out below (Section 5, footnote 17), this assumption bears crucially on the generality and theoretical neutrality of these experiments.

8 In fairness, Folk Understanding is actually shared by mainstream and experimental epistemologists alike. Mainstream epistemologists have made various claims on folk attributions of epistemic justification in lottery-style cases – claims that have been made mostly from the armchair. For example, according to Nelkin (Reference Nelkin2000: 374–375; fn. 4) denying that beliefs based on statistical evidence are rational is counterintuitive. Similarly, Sutton (Reference Sutton2007: 65) argues that folk attributions of epistemic justification to lottery propositions are based on a conceptual confusion between categorical and probabilistic lottery propositions (see also Ebert et al. Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: 114 for a discussion of Sutton’s claim) So, while the validity of the experimental studies under discussion does depend on Folk Understanding , it should also be noted that experimental epistemologists are not alone in making this assumption. A relevantly similar assumption traces back to discussions of lottery beliefs in mainstream epistemology.

9 Knowledge, ‘knows’ and knowledge will be more familiar to lay people given the prominence of knowledge attributions and their key social functions. Recent work in folk epistemology has forcefully acknowledged this point (Hannon Reference Hannon2015), also with reference to empirical data. For example, Gerken (Reference Gerken2017: 15) cites linguistic studies showing that ‘knows’ is a very frequent word in both English and other languages, while Nagel (Reference Nagel2013: Section 3) draws on ontogenetic evidence from developmental psychology suggesting that the concept of knowledge is acquired earlier than belief, and attributions of knowledge are more cognitively basic than attributions of belief. However, disagreement remains as to whether the prominence of knowledge attributions and these empirical data suffice to establish any sort of explanatory, metaphysical or representational priority.

10 Cusimano & Lombrozo (Reference Cusimano and Lombrozo2021) provide robust experimental evidence showing that lay people treat moral considerations as alternative (non-epistemic) justification for belief in case of clear social proximity. Accordingly, in addition to the already highlighted moral features of the vignette, the father-daughter relationship central to Accusation deepens ever further these concerns about partiality.

11 It’s worth being cautious on the relationship between concepts and words. Given my purposes, I assume that terms are linguistic entities (words, phrases), and concepts are mental representations (or abstract objects). This is clearly an oversimplification, but it will suffice to appreciate the problems with Immediate Testability .

12 This is not to say that the term is defective (Cohen Reference Cohen2016), or that disputes involving the term are merely verbal (Alston Reference Alston2005). In order to question Immediate Testability we need a much weaker claim, namely that the meaning of epistemic justification is not readily available, and it takes efforts to first introduce it and then explain it. This claim should be plausible, and it will resonate with the experience of any epistemologists who has ever taught a class on epistemic justification to uninitiated students.

13 On this point, I want to tread carefully. I am invoking mindware gaps to illustrate the phenomenon of the folk conceptual gap. Yet, deeper questions concerning the exact relationship between mindware gaps and the folk conceptual gap cannot be decided from the armchair: mine is an especially speculative hypothesis that needs extensive empirical testing. Also, if we grant that high confidence rates are incompatible with mindware gaps, then the consistently high confidence rates found in the answers to the justification questions would count against the mindware gap hypothesis.

14 See Rosenthal & Fode (Reference Rosenthal and Fode1963) for the classic demonstration of the experimenter bias. There is additional evidence of experimenter bias in the life sciences (Holman et al. Reference Holman, Head, Lanfear and Jennions2015), social psychology (Doyen et al. Reference Doyen, Klein, Pichon and Cleeremans2012) and, most crucially, also experimental philosophy (Strickland & Suben Reference Strickland and Suben2012).

15 See Conee & Feldman (Reference Conee and Feldman1985) for a locus classicus, and Fratantonio (Reference Fratantonio, Lasonen-Aarnio and Littlejohn2024) for a recent overview.

16 Kelly (Reference Kelly and Zalta2016: Section 1) makes this point vividly. He writes that ‘evidence’ is “hardly a philosopher’s term of art”, and that “the concept of evidence would thus seem to be on firmer pre-theoretical ground than various other concepts which enjoy similarly central standing within philosophy”. Interestingly, in this same passage Kelly lists the epistemologist’s “quasi-technical” concept of epistemic justification as a key example of such concepts.

17 This is the key difference between my recommended strategy and Nolte and colleagues’ study. After mentioning evidence in one probe question, they conclude that their findings “overall support the claim that knowledge entails justification” (2021: 46). But given the specificity of the probe question, this conclusion is too general: at best, their findings support the claim that knowledge entails a specific type of justification – evidential justification.

18 Ebert et al. (Reference Ebert, Smith and Durbach2018: 136, fn. 23) very briefly consider this possibility.

19 Acknowledgements. I am grateful to an associate editor for much appreciated additional advice and to an anonymous referee for insightful and constructive comments. I presented earlier versions of this paper at the Danish Philosophical Society Annual Meeting (University of Copenhagen, March 2023), the Experimental Conceptual Engineering Workshop (University of Zurich, September 2023), the Scottish Epistemology Early Career Researchers Work in Progress Meeting (online, October 2023) and the Metis Seminar (UNED, March 2024). Many thanks to these audiences for very helpful feedback. I also greatly benefited from discussing the topics of this paper with Sabina Dominguez Parrado, Giorgia Foti, and Lilith Mace. Finally, very special thanks to Mikkel Gerken for exceptionally generous guidance and unfailing encouragement. Work on this publication has been supported by grant CEX2021-001169-M (funded by MICIU/AEI/10.13039/501100011033).

References

Alston, W.P. (2005) Beyond Justification: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, J. and Gerken, M. (2012). ‘Knowledge Ascriptions: Their Semantics, Cognitive Bases and Social Functions.’ In Brown, J. and Gerken, M. (eds), Knowledge Ascriptions, pp. 130. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buckwalter, W. (2010). ‘Knowledge isn’t Closed on Saturday: A Study in Ordinary Language.Review of Philosophy and Psychology 10(3), 395406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, D.T. and Fiske, D.W. (1959). ‘Convergent and Discriminant Validation by the Multitrait-Multimethod Matrix.Psychological Bulletin 560(2), 81105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. (2016). ‘Theorizing about the Epistemic.Inquiry 590(7-8), 839857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conee, E. and Feldman, R. (1985). ‘Evidentialism.Philosophical Studies 480(1), 1534.Google Scholar
Cusimano, C. and Lombrozo, T. (2021). ‘Morality Justifies Motivated Reasoning in the Folk Ethics of Belief.Cognition 2090(C), 104513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dinges, A. and Zakkou, J. (2020). ‘Much at Stake in Knowledge.Mind and Language 360(5), 729749.Google Scholar
Dogramaci, S. (2015). ‘Communist Conventions for Deductive Reasoning.Noûs 490(4), 776799.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doyen, S., Klein, O., Pichon, C.-L., and Cleeremans, A. (2012). ‘Behavioral Priming: It’s All in the Mind, but Whose Mind?PloS One 70(1), e29081e29081.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ebert, P.A., Smith, M., and Durbach, I. (2018). ‘Lottery Judgments: A Philosophical and Experimental Study.Philosophical Psychology 310(1), 110138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Egler, M. and Ross, L.D. (2020). ‘Philosophical Expertise Under the Microscope.Synthese 1970(3), 10771098.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fratantonio, G. (2024). ‘Evidential Internalism and Evidential Externalism.’ In Lasonen-Aarnio, M. and Littlejohn, C.M. (eds), The Routledge Handbook for The Philosophy of Evidence. Routledge.Google Scholar
Friedman, O. and Turri, J. (2015). ‘Is Probabilistic Evidence a Source of Knowledge?Cognitive Science 390(5), 10621080.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerken, M. (2013). ‘Epistemic Focal Bias.Australasian Journal of Philosophy 910(1), 4161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerken, M. (2017). On Folk Epistemology. How We Think and Talk About Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gerken, M. (2020). ‘Truth-Sensitivity and Folk Epistemology.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 1000(1), 325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A.I. (1979). ‘What is Justified Belief?’ In Pappas, G. (ed), Justification and Knowledge, pp. 125. D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Goldman, A.I. (1999). ‘Internalism Exposed.Journal of Philosophy 960(6), 271293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grindrod, J. (2024). ‘Justification: Insights from Corpora.Episteme 21(3), 794818.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hannon, M.J. (2015). ‘The Importance of Knowledge Ascriptions.Philosophy Compass 100(12), 856866.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and Lotteries. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. and Stanley, J. (2008). ‘Knowledge and Action.Journal of Philosophy 1050(10), 571590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holman, L., Head, M.L., Lanfear, R., and Jennions, M.D. (2015). ‘Evidence of Experimental Bias in the Life Sciences: Why We Need Blind Data Recording.PLoS Biology 130(7), e1002190e1002190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Kauppinen, A. (2007). ‘The Rise and Fall of Experimental Philosophy.Philosophical Explorations 100(2), 95118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, T. (2016). ‘Evidence.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Winter 2016 edition.Google Scholar
Kuorikoski, J. and Marchionni, C. (2016). ‘Evidential Diversity and the Triangulation of Phenomena.Philosophy of Science 830(2), 227247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, J. (2010). ‘Epistemic Justification.’ In Bernecker, S. and Pritchard, D. (eds), Routledge Companion to Epistemology, pp. 2536. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ludwig, K. (2007). ‘The Epistemology of Thought Experiments: First Person Versus Third Person Approaches.Midwest Studies in Philosophy 310(1), 128159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, J.C. (2013). ‘Should Reliabilists be Worried About Demon Worlds?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 860(1), 140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, J. (2012). ‘Mindreading in Gettier Cases and Skeptical Pressure Cases.’ In Brown, J. and Gerken, M. (eds), Knowledge Ascriptions. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, J. (2013). ‘Knowledge as a Mental State.Oxford Studies in Epistemology 4, 275310.Google Scholar
Nelkin, D.K. (2000). ‘The Lottery Paradox, Knowledge, and Rationality.Philosophical Review, 1090(3), 373409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nolte, A.M., Rose, D., and Turri, J. (2021). ‘Experimental Evidence that Knowledge Entails Justification.’ In Lombrozo, T., Nichols, S., and Knobe, J. (eds), Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Volume 4. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pinillos, Á. (2012). ‘Knowledge, experiments, and practical interests.’ In Brown, J. and Gerken, M. (eds), Knowledge Ascriptions, p. 192. UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic Luck. UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reynolds, S.L. (1998). ‘Evaluational Illusions and Skeptical Arguments.Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 580(3), 529558.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenthal, R. and Fode, K. (1963). ‘The Effect of Experimenter Bias on the Performance of the Albino Rat.Behavioral Science 80(3), 183189.Google Scholar
Sackris, D. and Beebe, J.R. (2014). ‘Is Justification Necessary for Knowledge?’ In Beebe, J.R. (ed), Advances in Experimental Epistemology, pp. 175192. Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. and Knobe, J. (2012). ‘Contrastive Knowledge Surveyed.Noûs 460(4), 675708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schickore, J. and Coko, K. (2013). ‘Using Multiple Means of Determination.International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 270(3), 295313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M. (2010). ‘What Else Justification Could be.Noûs 440(1), 1031.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smithies, D. (2012). ‘Moore’s Paradox and the Accessibility of Justification.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 850(2), 273300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanovich, K.E. (2009). What Intelligence Tests Miss: The Psychology of Rational Thought. Yale University Press, New Haven.Google Scholar
Strickland, B. and Suben, A. (2012). ‘Experimenter Philosophy: The Problem of Experimenter Bias in Experimental Philosophy.Review of Philosophy and Psychology 30(3), 457467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sutton, J. (2007). Without Justification. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, J. (2016). ‘The Radicalism of Truth-insensitive Epistemology: Truth’s Profound Effect on the Evaluation of Belief.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 930(2), 348367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, J. and Friedman, O. (2014). ‘Winners and Losers in the Folk Epistemology of Lotteries.’ In Beebe, J. (ed), Advances in Experimental Epistemology, pp. 4569.Google Scholar
West, R.F. (2010). ‘A Taxonomy of Rational Thinking Problems.’ In Rationality and the Reflective Mind. p. 12. UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits. UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2011). ‘Philosophical Expertise and the Burden of Proof.Metaphilosophy 420(3), 215229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (forthcoming) ‘Justifications, Excuses, and Sceptical Scenarios.’ In Dorsch, F. and Dutant, J. (eds), The New Evil Demon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar