Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-19T11:55:03.392Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Recomplementation as a paratactic phenomenon: Evidence from Spanish and English

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 December 2022

JULIO VILLA-GARCÍA
Affiliation:
Department of English, French and German, Faculty of Humanities, University of Oviedo, Amparo Pedregal s/n, 33011, Oviedo, Principality of Asturias, Spain [email protected]; [email protected]
DENNIS OTT
Affiliation:
Hizkuntzalaritza Teorikorako Taldea (HiTT), University of the Basque Country, Centro de Investigación Micaela Portilla Ikergunea, Office 3.7 Justo Vélez de Elorriaga, 1, 01006, Vitoria-Gasteiz, Basque Country, Spain [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We provide a variety of empirical arguments in favor of a paratactic account of recomplementation constructions, in which a left-dislocated element appears in between two complementizers. Contrary to integrated analyses assuming Complementizer Phrase (CP) recursion or Rizzi’s split periphery, we assume that the dislocated phrase is structurally independent from the embedded clause it precedes, which in turn is an elliptical sentence fragment. The juxtaposed fragmentary sentences are linked by the doubled complementizer, which serves to overtly flag a ‘restart’ in discourse. We show that this account makes a range of welcome predictions while sidestepping non-trivial problems that arise for integrated/cartographic analyses, which assume that dislocated XPs are in left-peripheral positions (such as Spec-TopicP) and that the doubled complementizer spells out Topic0. A further advantage of the approach is that it provides a handle on recomplementation constructions beyond the core cases involving left-dislocation, which reduce to a mere subcase of the general phenomenon of elliptical ‘restarts’ in discourse.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction: the phenomenon of recomplementation

Languages such as present-day Spanish display embedded dislocations, including Clitic Left-dislocation (ClLD) with an optional additional complementizer (in boldface):

This recomplementation variety of dislocation, henceforth R-ClLD, is a feature of colloquial language (Demonte & Fernández-Soriano Reference Demonte and Fernández-Soriano2009; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2016, Reference Villa-García2019) and is also attested in spoken varieties of other languages, such as English (Radford Reference Radford, Camacho-Taboada, Jiménez-Fernández, Martín-González and Reyes-Tejedor2013, Reference Radford2018; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2019):

The phenomenon of multiple-complementizer constructions illustrated in (1) and (2) has commanded much attention in the field in recent years and has emerged as a fruitful area of research for investigations into the left periphery (Escribano Reference Escribano1991; Campos Reference Campos1992; Iatridou & Kroch Reference Iatridou and Kroch1992; Fontana Reference Fontana1993; Uriagereka Reference Uriagereka and Kiss1995; Wanner Reference Wanner and Ruffino1998; Barbosa Reference Barbosa and Costa2000; Poletto Reference Poletto2000; Martín-González Reference Martín-González2002; Rodríguez-Ramalle Reference Rodríguez-Ramalle2003; Ledgeway Reference Ledgeway2005; McCloskey Reference McCloskey, Zanuttini, Campos, Herburger and Portner2006; Paoli Reference Paoli2006; Vincent Reference Vincent, Andreose and Penello2006, Reference Vincent, Butt, King and Toivonen2019; Cocchi & Poletto Reference Cocchi, Poletto, Picchi and Pona2007; Mascarenhas Reference Mascarenhas2007; Demonte & Fernández-Soriano Reference Demonte and Fernández-Soriano2009, 2014; Fernández-Rubiera Reference Fernández-Rubiera2009; Etxepare Reference Etxepare2010; González i Planas Reference González i Planas2010, Reference González i Planas2014; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2010, Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2016, Reference Villa-García2019; Haegeman Reference Haegeman2012; Kempchinsky Reference Kempchinsky, Howe, Blackwell and Quesada2013; Gupton Reference Gupton2014; Salvesen Reference Salvesen2014; Frank Reference Frank, Cuza, Czerwionka and Olson2016, Reference Frank2020; Munaro Reference Munaro2016; Martínez Vera Reference Martínez Vera2017, Reference Martínez Vera2019; Salvasen & Walken Reference Salvesen, Walkden, Mathieu and Truswell2017; Cerrudo Aguilar & Gallego Reference Cerrudo Aguilar and Gallego2018; Echeverría Reference Echeverría2021, Reference Echeverría2022).

Although previous research has revealed many empirical properties of the construction (such as its iterative character, the inability of focal phrases to be flanked by complementizers, the possibility of multiple dislocates appearing between complementizers, and the island-inducing effect of the secondary complementizer), many questions surrounding the syntactic behavior of such constructions remain open and will be taken up here. Most extant analyses are framed within a cartographic or CP-recursion-based approach to the left periphery. Departing from such monosentential accounts, we argue that the issues raised by prior analyses can be circumvented on the assumption that recomplementation actually instantiates a discursive arrangement of two juxtaposed root clauses, which stand in a paratactic rather than hypotactic configuration. The analysis thus furthers our understanding of left-dislocation constructions more generally.

The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we provide a brief overview of previous (monosentential/cartographic) accounts; we then move on, in Section 3, to present our paratactic account of recomplementation and its consequences. Finally, Section 4 offers some concluding remarks.

2. Previous accounts

Accounts of recomplementation patterns in the generative tradition so far have assumed a multiclausal monosentential structure, where both complementizers and the sandwiched dislocate XP (… que/that XP que/that …) are bona fide constituents of an embedded clause. There are various versions of this general approach on the market, illustrated below for (1a): CP recursion (3a); Rizzian split CP and a TopicP position (3b); and Uriagereka’s (Reference Uriagereka and Kiss1995) FP projection (3c) (see Villa-García Reference Villa-García2015):

A number of analyses of R-ClLD draw on Rizzi’s cartographic approach, varying mainly with respect to the left-peripheral head assumed to be occupied by the second complementizer. For instance, for López (Reference López2009), the first complementizer sits in Force0, while the second one occupies Finiteness0. Martín-González (Reference Martín-González2002) makes a proposal that departs slightly from the traditional Rizzian approach, in that the first complementizer also occupies Force0, whereas the second one heads a (Doubled)ForceP situated below TopicP in Rizzi’s periphery (i.e., ForceP > TopicP > (Doubled)ForceP > FocusP …); the sandwiched dislocate is in Spec-TopicP under this account. According to Rodríguez-Ramalle (Reference Rodríguez-Ramalle2003), Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2012), and Martínez Vera (Reference Martínez Vera2019), the second complementizer occupies the head of TopicP, whose specifier hosts the dislocated XP, as shown in (3b). For reasons of space, we will not review each proposal separately here; the reader is referred to Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2015: Ch. 2) for a critical review of existing accounts.

The difference between the accounts in (3) is mostly terminological (a matter of labels); they are summarized by the abstract tree in (4):

Empirically, an analysis that assumes this kind of complex CP structure has several advantages. For the sake of illustration, we will concentrate on the TopicP account shown schematically in (3b). First, this analysis provides an elegant account of why phrases that can be left-dislocated can occupy the pre-secondary-complementizer position, but not foci, which do not undergo ClLD:

If focal phrases like A NADIE in (5) occupy FocusP, then it follows from the peripheral template that they will not be able to occur before the secondary instance of que, which occupies Topic0 (i.e., ForceP > TopicP > FocusP > FinitenessP …).

Moreover, the possibility of multiple ques after each dislocated phrase (Escribano Reference Escribano1991; Rodríguez-Ramalle Reference Rodríguez-Ramalle2003; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2010, Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015; Radford Reference Radford2018) is straightforwardly accommodated once TopicP is assumed to be recursive, as argued independently by Rizzi (Reference Rizzi and Haegeman1997), among many others (though see Benincà & Poletto Reference Benincà, Poletto and Rizzi2004 for counterarguments):

English also allows for such iterative complementation:

Adopting the structure in (3b), Spanish (6) would be analyzed thus:

Despite their appeal, however, integrated/monosentential analyses of R-ClLD configurations such as those in (3) face major challenges. We will briefly outline these challenges below; they will be revisited and discussed more thoroughly in the course of the discussion of our paratactic-bisentential analysis in the following section:

  1. (i) intonation;

  2. (ii) connectivity (in relation to case/theta-roles and binding) and anticonnectivity (including lack of Condition B effects and seemingly doubled subjects);

  3. (iii) opacity for extraction (i.e., islandhood);

  4. (iv) dependence on first/high complementizer;

  5. (v) non-distinctness of complementizers;

  6. (vi) selectional restrictions.

As the examples provided so far show, a comma typically appears before the secondary complementizer (i). This comma is not arbitrary, but an orthographic rendition of the fact that the dislocated XP and the secondary complementizer are separated by a salient intonational boundary, typically represented by a pause before the second complementizer, which tends to be indicated in writing by means of a comma before que/that in the examples (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2019; Frank Reference Frank, Cuza, Czerwionka and Olson2016, Reference Frank2020; Radford Reference Radford2018; Martínez Vera Reference Martínez Vera2019). On an integrated, multiclausal-monosentential account, it is not obvious how to derive the presence of this intonational break without stipulation, in particular under those accounts that assume that the dislocate and the second complementizer occupy the specifier and head of the same projection, respectively (Kempchinsky Reference Kempchinsky, Howe, Blackwell and Quesada2013; Radford Reference Radford2018):

As far as connectivity and anticonnectivity (ii) are concerned, dislocates in R-ClLD exhibit properties that seemingly diagnose movement and base-generation simultaneously (a paradox first noted for ClLD generally in Cinque Reference Cinque1990). Regarding the former, contra the judgments reported in Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2012), local anaphors contained in a dislocate can be bound by an element occurring after the secondary complementizer:

Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015) has argued that the dislocate in R-ClLD is base-generated in the sandwiched position in between complementizers, since the secondary complementizer blocks extraction from the lower clause (iii). However, data such as (10) challenge this conclusion, suggesting that reconstruction of the dislocate is not systematically absent.Footnote 2 In addition, note that the dislocate is case-marked, as shown in (1a), repeated here for convenience:

If the dislocate is directly merged in the specifier of a left-peripheral projection headed by the second complementizer, then how the dislocate receives its case and theta-role is mysterious under standard assumptions, since the relevant case/theta assigner is lower in the structure and does not c-command the dislocate at any point in the derivation.Footnote 3

At the same time, invoking movement of the XP to a left-peripheral specifier is at variance with the non-movement properties of R-ClLD and ClLD in general (see Ott Reference Ott2014, Reference Ott2015 for detailed discussion); furthermore, it is unclear why such movement could not feed further, successive-cyclic movement to the higher clause. We turn to these properties of R-ClLD directly.

Regarding anticonnectivity (non-movement properties), two major issues arise for traditional monosentential analyses of R-ClLD. First of all, the dislocated phrase flanked by complementizers co-occurs with a coreferring lower pronominal/clitic correlate (i.e., a tu madre k ‘your mother’ – la k ‘her’ in (1a)/(11) above). On a monosentential analysis, it remains unclear why this configuration does not incur a Condition B violation (at least where the correlate is not further embedded). Put differently, no Condition B effect arises that would be expected if the dislocate locally c-commanded its pronominal correlate, as shown below for (1a)/(11):

Similarly, as illustrated in (13), R-ClLD can seemingly lead to doubling of the subject, which is generally impossible in null-subject languages such as Spanish (Barbosa Reference Barbosa2009), but common in non-null-subject languages like English (cf. Mary k , she k is cool):

(spontaneous speech, Asturias, Spain, reported in Villa-García Reference Villa-García2019)

Monoclausal analyses like (14) are forced to tolerate doubled subjects in such cases. Note that Condition B is again not violated, as we already saw above for cases such as (11).

The above problems are special cases of the general problems posed by ClLD for monosentential analyses, viz. the simultaneous occurrence of a dislocated XP and a pronominal correlate in what is hypothesized to be a single, integrated structure. Overall, the fact that the dislocate displays connectivity and anticonnectivity simultaneously yields a paradox that monosentential analyses are unfit to resolve (Ott Reference Ott2014, Reference Ott2015).

We now turn to problems posed specifically by the recomplementation variety of ClLD. Regular ClLD (without recomplementation) generally permits extraction across the dislocate into the main clause (Uribe-Extebarria Reference Uribe-Etxebarria1991; Rizzi Reference Rizzi and Belletti2004; Ott Reference Ott2015); by contrast, R-ClLD does not:

The empirical discovery that the secondary complementizer of recomplementation patterns blocks extraction (iii; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2010, Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015), as indicated by (15b), has spawned much research in the last decade (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2010, Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2019; González i Planas Reference González i Planas2014; MacDonald Reference MacDonald2015; Cerrudo Aguilar & Gallego Reference Cerrudo Aguilar and Gallego2018; Radford Reference Radford2018; Martínez Vera Reference Martínez Vera2017, Reference Martínez Vera2019; Petersen O’Farrill Reference Petersen O’Farrill2021; Torrego, in prep.). On monosentential analyses, it is unclear at best why doubling of the complementizer should have this effect, as is evident as soon as one considers the wide variety of proposals to account for it. As Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2019: 18) observes,

[t]he actual implementation of the locality issue remains a point of contention in the literature, with accounts that range from Comp-t effect violations, barrier/island violations, and CED (Constraint on Extraction Domains) violations to issues arising in relation to phase theory, antilocality, and the labeling algorithm.Footnote 4

In any case, under a recursive-CP or TopicP-based account, for instance, the assumption that the lexicalization of C0/Topic0 creates a locality violation that is suspended in its absence is necessarily stipulative (though see Villa-García Reference Villa-García2012 for an analysis of this kind). For this reason, the island-creating effect of secondary complementizers has eluded principled analysis.

As a further problem for monosentential accounts of R-ClLD, Demonte & Fernández-Soriano (Reference Demonte, Fernández-Soriano, Dufter and de Toledo2014) point out that the secondary complementizer is contingent on the first one (iv), i.e., it can only appear when the preceding clause contains a complementizer as well:Footnote 5

This criticism is rooted in the fact that if the secondary que is a topic-marker lexicalizing the head of TopicP, then it is unclear why it would depend on the lexicalization of a higher left-peripheral head (Force0, by hypothesis). Demonte & Fernández-Soriano solve this issue by appealing to Martín-González’s (Reference Martín-González2002) (Doubled)ForceP (i.e., ForceP > TopicP > (Doubled)ForceP > FocusP…), but independent motivation for the existence of such a projection is not easy to come by, and thus the analysis remains stipulative. The issue is aggravated by the fact that TopicP, responsible for hosting the dislocate, hierarchically separates the postulated ForcePs.Footnote 6

Furthermore, as observed by João Costa (pers. comm. 2019), R-ClLD cross-linguistically employs form-identical complementizers (e.g., que – que; that – that) (v; see Section 3.7 for further evidence). This is mysterious under monosentential analyses, where each occurrence of the complementizer occurs in a different left-peripheral head (e.g., Force0 for que 1 and Topic0 for que 2). Note in addition that if que 2 is a bona fide exponent of a Top(ic) head, as held by proponents of the TopicP account (Rodríguez-Ramalle Reference Rodríguez-Ramalle2003; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2012), we would naturally expect a distinct morphological realization (rather than a default complementizer).Footnote 7 The verbatim repetition of the complementizer in R-ClLD is thus unaccounted for under monosentential analyses, barring additional stipulations.

Finally, Demonte & Fernández-Soriano (Reference Demonte and Fernández-Soriano2009: 47) observe that R-ClLD cannot be embedded under factive verbs (vi):

As indicated, regular ClLD is possible in these cases, but R-ClLD is infelicitous. How can this state of affairs be accounted for on monosentential analyses? Again, the answer is not evident: for example, on a TopicP account, the difference between R-ClLD vs. regular ClLD reduces to the lexicalization of Topic0 (or C0, under CP-recursion). Thus, to account for the incompatibility of certain predicates such as factives and R-ClLD complements, one would have to assume that the higher predicate conditions the (non)lexicalization of a lower, structurally remote complementizer:

One could, of course, assume a different, more limited left-peripheral structure for factives (in the spirit of de Cuba & MacDonald Reference de Cuba, MacDonald, Amaro, Lord, de Prada Pérez and Aaron2013), but we would still need to account for why regular ClLD is legitimate in the same environment.

Overall, then, a number of non-trivial problems call into question traditional multiclausal-monosentential approaches to recomplementation patterns, despite their initial appeal. In what follows, we develop a proposal that radically deviates from standard assumptions about ClLD and R-ClLD, building on the idea that both configurations involve multiple root clauses in a paratactic configuration, albeit in different ways. As we show, the proposal not only solves the issues raised above but also makes additional welcome predictions.

3. A paratactic analysis

The proposal advocated here draws on work by Ott (Reference Ott2014, Reference Ott2015, Reference Ott2017), who argues that left-dislocated XPs are remnants of elliptical sentences (i.e., fragments) that are juxtaposed to their host sentences in discourse.Footnote 8 That is to say, dislocated XPs are not intra-sentential constituents moving to or base-generated in a left-peripheral position (e.g., TopicP); instead, they are bona fide extra-sentential constituents. The analysis is illustrated below for (19a):

The dislocate in CP1 and its host CP2, each a root clause, are thus paratactically ordered but endophorically related by ellipsis and cross-sentential anaphora. Ott shows that this approach can resolve the paradox initially discovered by Cinque (Reference Cinque1990), i.e., the concurrent movement and non-movement (connectivity/anticonnectivity) properties of left-dislocation constructions.

One major advantage of this approach is that the obligatory co-occurrence of the clitic in CILD is no longer mysterious: the clitic is a pronoun in CP2 that anaphorically resumes the XP ese coche in the first clause (CP1), as would be the case across independently generated sentences:

The presence of the clitic in (R-)ClLD (and of a correlate more generally in left-dislocation) is thus a result of the fact that the clause containing it is indeed an entire sentence, which consequently must be syntactically complete. The following contrast in English (from Villa-García Reference Villa-García2019) highlights this point:

The dislocation in (21a) permits recomplementation since the second, structurally autonomous clause is syntactically complete, unlike in the fronting case (21b), where recomplementation forces a parse of the second clause as an independent, and consequently syntactically incomplete, root-clause fragment.Footnote 9

In the same vein, the paratactic analysis explains why left-dislocated XPs are typically intonationally separated from their hosts (because they are independent, elliptical root clauses), precede entire V2 configurations in languages like German, and can mismatch their correlates in phi-features in a precisely delimited range of cases; see Ott (Reference Ott2014, Reference Ott2015, Reference Ott2017) for detailed discussion and references.

Ott (Reference Ott2015) touches on embedded ClLD, exemplified in (22a), and adumbrates an analysis which assumes interpolation or intercalation of a parenthetical fragment, as in (22b) (cf. Ott Reference Ott2016; see Onea & Ott Reference Onea and Ott2022 on linear interpolation of fragments):

Building on Ott’s analysis of matrix and embedded ClLD, we propose to analyze R-ClLD cases as paratactic configurations, but involving a somewhat different arrangement compared to regular ClLD on Ott’s approach.

In order to illustrate the proposal, let us focus again on (1a), repeated here for convenience:

Unlike in the case of regular ClLDs just discussed, our claim is that R-ClLD instantiates a sequence CP1 ≺ CP2 of two elliptical root clauses, such that CP1 realizes an embedded fragment, while CP2 constitutes a ‘restart’ spelling out a parallel embedded clause in full but leaving the redundant main clause unpronounced:

This paratactic analysis captures rather directly the intuitive character of recomplementation as a bona fide ‘repetition’ or ‘reduplication’ (see, e.g., Vincent, Bentley & Samu Reference Vincent, Bentley and Samu2004; Ledgeway Reference Ledgeway2005; Kemchinsky Reference Kempchinsky, Howe, Blackwell and Quesada2013; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2019).

The juxtaposed root clauses CP1 and CP2 in (24) are syntactically parallel, modulo the difference between the dislocated XP in CP1 and its clitic correlate in CP2. In this sense, again, coreference between the two is ensured by text/discourse coherence, analogous to sequences of non-elliptical sentences (see Ott Reference Ott2017; Onea & Ott Reference Onea and Ott2022):

On this view, recomplementation as in (24) is thus a mere surface variant of the sequence of sentences in (25).Footnote 10

It is important to note that the type of ellipsis assumed in (24) is independently available in Spanish (and other languages). CP1 instantiates an embedded fragment analogous to B’s response in (26):

Such embedded fragments must involve abstract structure and deletion (see Merchant Reference Merchant2004; Temmerman 2013), as a María is case-marked and the complementizer que is not a case assigner (i.e., there must be an underlying transitive verb in (26B)). We return to this type of fragment when discussing the issue of selection in R-ClLD (Section 3.8).Footnote 11

The second sentence in the recomplementation sequence (i.e., … [CP2 dice [que la invitaron]] in the above example) involves Phonetic Form (PF) deletion of the material above the complementizer, including the subject (if present) and the verb, leaving only the lower, embedded clause as a remnant. This type of ellipsis, too, is generally available, as evidenced by clausal fragment responses (see (30) below and Merchant Reference Merchant2004 for discussion).

Ellipsis resolution in CP1 can only occur once the postcedent (CP2) has been uttered, as is generally the case in ‘backward’ ellipsis:

Note that for the embedded clause in CP2 to be a licit fragment, it must contain an instance of (possibly broad) focus, in the way remnants of ellipsis are generally distinguished from the informational background. A corollary of this basic requirement is that the XP sandwiched between complementizers in R-ClLD cannot be itself focal—if it were, the remainder of the embedded clause would invariably be backgrounded, undermining its ability to function as a ‘restart’ fragment. In this way, the ellipsis-based analysis derives the fact that sandwiched XPs in R-ClLD will be contrastive topics or independent interjections (see below), but never foci.Footnote 12

Ellipsis in both clauses is certainly favored, though not in any grammatical sense obligatory: non-elliptical counterparts are naturally overly redundant but not unacceptable (see also (25) above):

Importantly, however, in cases involving quotative complementizers à la Etxepare (Reference Etxepare2010) (see, e.g., (16b) above) and lacking an (overt) embedding predicate in CP1, if the material preceding the second instance of the complementizer does not undergo ellipsis in CP2, the resulting sentence improves significantly vis-à-vis (28):Footnote 13

Lastly, one might wonder why the second que survives ellipsis in R-ClLD. Our claim is that this que serves to mark the ‘restart’ in discourse (see Section 3.6); its PF realization indicates that the point of restart is the embedded domain. A parallel situation can be found in clausal fragments, which require the presence of the complementizer que, as shown by (30).

After all, a that-type complementizer is the hallmark of a finite embedded clause, the simplest way of signaling the presence of a clause (i.e., … [CP2 dice [ que …]]). In fact, as shown below in Section 3.7, complementizers other than the default declarative complementizer que/ that can appear in R-ClLD, which is fully consistent with our claim that reduplicative complementizers are overt manifestations of a ‘restart’ in discourse.

Overall, we conclude that there is nothing special about the types of ellipsis instantiated in (24): the composition of R-ClLD draws entirely on familiar and independently attested forms of phonological reduction. We take this to be an advantage over a recent proposal by Echeverría (Reference Echeverría2022), which, while similar in spirit, relies on multiple syntactic planes within a unitary representation to implement the intuition of R-ClLD as a restart (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2019). Since Echeverría’s proposal remains rather vague on the formal mechanisms involved, we merely note here that our proposal relieves the grammar of the burden of generating multidominance structures.

In the next subsections, we turn to a variety of empirical arguments in favor of a bisentential, paratactic account of R-ClLD configurations.

3.1. Argument 1: Intonation

The dislocated XP and secondary que are typically separated by a salient intonational boundary, represented by a comma in orthography, as shown again in (31) (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2019; Radford Reference Radford2018; Martínez Vera Reference Martínez Vera2019):

This is wholly compatible with our claim that the relation between fragment and host is paratactic, each sentence forming a separate intonational phrase (cf. Nespor & Vogel Reference Nespor and Vogel1986 and Dehé Reference Dehé, Dehé and Kavalova2007 on parentheticals and intonational phrasing):

Fragment and host thus exhibit ‘comma intonation’ (intonational isolation/separation), exactly as expected if the sequence is composed of linearly juxtaposed root clauses in a paratactic rather than hypotactic arrangement.

3.2. Argument 2: connectivity and anticonnectivity

As we saw above, the dislocated XP displays a range of connectivity effects, showing that it cannot be base-generated in its surface position sandwiched between the two complementizers (as claimed by some integrated, monosentential accounts such as Villa-García’s Reference Villa-García2012 TopicP analysis shown in (3b)).

By contrast, on the paratactic approach advocated here, these properties follow directly from the fact that ellipsis in CP1 is licensed under identity with CP2, so that the dislocate and the clitic share theta/case-properties (see Ott Reference Ott2015 and Merchant Reference Merchant2001, Reference Merchant2004 on ellipsis-mediated connectivity more generally). In an example such as (1a), a tu madre receives case and a theta-role from the elided verb invitaron in CP1 in a run-of-the-mill fashion; analogously, the accusative clitic la in CP2 receives its case and theta-role from overt invitaron in CP2:

Apparent reconstruction effects for Condition A are likewise mediated by elided parallel sentential structure, as expected under our analysis; in the example below, the anaphor is locally bound inside CP1 by al duque, as shown in (34b).

At the same time, the paratactic approach handles anticonnectivity effects which reveal that the dislocated XP is syntactically disjoint from the following clause headed by the doubled complementizer. Coreference between the dislocate and the pronominal correlate, on this approach, is an instance of cross-sentential anaphora, analogous to the following:

Therefore, the dislocated element sandwiched between complementizers and its correlate are never in a (symmetric or asymmetric) c-command relation at any stage of the derivation; the dislocate is simply not a constituent of the host clause/CP2, which accounts for why the simultaneous presence of dislocate and correlate does not give rise to a Condition B violation.

Furthermore, the apparent doubling of a preverbal subject in cases such as (13) above dissolves on the analysis pursued here, as dislocate and correlate are in separate sentences: the double can appear simply because CP2 is a syntactically complete sentence in its own right:

In sum, the connectivity and anticonnectivity effects found in R-ClLD constructions are accommodated straightforwardly by our approach, while posing an irresolvable paradox for integrated, multiclausal-monosentential analyses (as expounded in Section 2).

3.3. Argument 3: Non-clitic correlates

On the paratactic approach advocated here, recomplementation is a bona fide restart in discourse. Accordingly, we expect this restart to formally manifest itself in various ways beyond the ‘classical’ R-ClLD pattern, where some topical XP is resumed by a clitic correlate. As we will see presently, this expectation is borne out.

In addition to pronominal clitics, R-ClLD readily permits epithetic correlates:

(Note that no pause occurs between the epithetic correlate and the rest of the sentence). The ability of epithetic correlates to occur in CP2 is not surprising under a paratactic approach to R-ClLD, where the dislocate and its correlate belong to separate root clauses and are anaphorically related cross-sententially:

This is exactly as in an analogous sequence of non-elliptical sentences:

In contrast, traditional multiclausal-monosentential analyses including the TopicP account are at odds with data such as those in (37): one and the same predicate is required to assign identical cases (and theta-roles) to two separate elements. The problem does not vanish on the assumption that the dislocated phrase is externally merged in between ques (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2012), since there would still be only one single predicate (i.e., dan ‘give’ in (37a)) in the overall structure:

This non-trivial issue does not arise under the paratactic approach espoused here, as seen in (38). Epithetic correlates, in short, are a natural by-product of our paratactic analysis of recomplementation.Footnote 14

Non-clitic correlates are furthermore found when the XP sandwiched between complementizers is non-topical/non-referential, as is the case with quantifiers which do not undergo regular ClLD, since they cannot be resumed cross-sententially by clitics (Ott Reference Ott2015); in this case, the quantifier itself is repeated verbatim in CP2:

Note that in both cases the phrase is repeated in the embedded clause because the fragmentary clause must be syntactically complete; at the same time, no such function could be performed by a clitic (or epithetic) correlate.

Examples such as the above (as well as others to be discussed in Section 3.6 below) militate decisively against analyses of recomplementation that derive its occurrence directly from the activation of some dedicated topic position; they point instead to the conclusion that recomplementation is a phenomenon that occurs independently of ClLD, exactly as expected on our approach.

3.4. Argument 4: Clausal negation

A further argument for our paratactic approach derives from recomplementation patterns involving dislocated negatively quantified phrases. In the presence of such a negative dislocate, the host clause must obligatorily contain a negation (Martín-González Reference Martín-González2002; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015):Footnote 15

On a monosentential analysis, the obligatory appearance of negation no ‘not’ in (42) is puzzling and requires elaborate auxiliary assumptions. To illustrate, Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2015: 149–157) rationalizes the mandatory presence of negation in (42a) as follows: since the dislocate a ninguno de ellos ‘none of them’ is base generated where it surfaces (that is, in the position between complementizers), it never transits through Spec-NegP on its way to the left periphery (that is, to Spec-TopicP); since no spec-head relation is ever established between the dislocated negative quantifier and Neg0, the head no needs to be inserted as a last resort in Neg0, following the logic of Bošković (Reference Bošković2001). The reason is that Bošković treats negation as an affix that requires an n-phrase to be PF-adjacent to it at some point in the derivation. Since a base-generated dislocate in the sandwiched position is never PF-adjacent to Neg0, inserting no is necessary to circumvent a violation that would ensue if the negative affix were left stranded.

On our paratactic analysis, by contrast, the mandatory presence of negation naturally follows from the fact that the host clause must have the same polarity as the elliptical clause to satisfy ellipsis parallelism. The dislocated negative XP surviving ellipsis in CP1 does not negate CP2: no ‘not’ is thus required in CP2 for CP1 and CP2 to be semantically parallel, as shown schematically in (43).

In other words, the otherwise puzzling interaction of R-ClLD and negation in these cases emerges as a direct consequence of the ‘restart’ nature of the construction, implemented here as a paratactic sequence of elliptical root clauses.Footnote 16 The behavior of negation in a parallel sequence of non-elliptical sentences is exactly analogous, as expected:

We turn next to the by-now longstanding issue of the impossibility of extraction across secondary complementizers.

3.5. Argument 5: An extraction asymmetry

As illustrated in (15) above, unlike regular ClLD, R-ClLD prohibits extraction from the clause following the dislocate. On our terms, this follows from the structural disjointedness of the sentences involved, each a separately generated root clause. For purposes of illustration, compare the paratactic configurations in regular ClLD according to Ott (Reference Ott2015), in (45), and R-ClLD, in (46), on our approach:

ClLD in (45) permits extraction from the lower clause into the main clause because the former is structurally subordinate to the latter (hypotaxis); the dislocate a tu novia is a separate fragmentary expression interpolated in production.

By contrast, the attempted extraction in the R-ClLD case is cross-sentential (46) due to the paratactic nature of the configuration (CP1 and CP2 are separately generated expressions), hence ruled out on principled and general grounds as illicit extraction across sentences. Recall that no such explanation is available on monosentential analyses, which treat ClLD and R-ClLD as phonological variants and consequently struggle to account for asymmetries of this kind.

Note that our explanation building on the structural disconnect of CP1 and CP2 is not undermined by apparent cross-sentential binding, as in the following:

The binding dependency here is computed internally to the elliptical CP2, which, due to general parallelism requirements, contains a silent instance of the binder:

An anonymous reviewer wonders why the ungrammatical extraction in (15b) could not alternatively be derived as involving a wh-dependency in each of the juxtaposed sentences CP1 and CP2:

This would indeed be a plausible alternative if the required elliptical CP1 were independently licensed. But embedded fragments with concomitant wh-extraction appear to be illicit quite generally, and regardless of context:

(Compare English *What did you tell me that to your girlfriend? in the same context). The rather tight restrictions on embedded fragments are generally not well understood; see Temmerman (2013) for some preliminary observations. Whatever rules out fragmentary expressions such as (50), they are plainly not available as building blocks for R-ClLD configurations, ruling out the alternative suggested by the reviewer.

Overall, the extraction asymmetry observed above furnishes a strong argument in favor of the differential analysis of regular ClLD and R-ClLD advocated here: while the former involves bona fide subordination/hypotaxis (plus linear interpolation of the fragment dislocate), the latter instantiates a genuine restart in which no syntactic connection exists between the first sentence containing the embedded dislocate (CP1) and the second sentence introduced by the secondary complementizer (CP2).

3.6. Argument 6: Interdependence of complementizers

Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2019) contends that one of the functions of the additional occurrence of que is that of a discourse marker; in a similar vein, Casasanto & Sag (Reference Casasanto and Sag2008) argue that doubled complementizers aid processing. This general notion meshes well with our approach to R-ClLD, where the dislocated XP is syntactically disjoint from the subsequent clause, and as such a separate unit of discourse. While we cannot fully develop this idea within the confines of the present paper, we suggest that the discourse/processing-related function of the secondary complementizer in R-ClLD is to overtly signal a restart by identifying the following material as an embedded clause and thus necessarily a subsentential fragment. This is wholly consistent with our analysis, where the dislocate is part of the initial clause, and the two sentences involved in R-ClLD are cataphorically linked by ellipsis under identity.

R-ClLD is not the only case where a that-like element takes on this function. Clausal fragment responses generally require a complementizer, even when it can be omitted in the non-elliptical source sentence (see Merchant Reference Merchant2004 for discussion and sources, and (30) above for Spanish data):

As in the case of R-ClLD, the complementizer forces a parse of the clause as a subsentential fragment rather than a non-elliptical root clause, anaphorically anchoring it in the immediate linguistic context.

Recall from the discussion in Section 2 that the question of why the second que is contingent on the first one (i.e., the occurrence of second que depends on the occurrence of a higher que) is an unresolved issue on monosentential accounts. By contrast, the paratactic analysis advocated here offers a straightforward rationalization of this otherwise puzzling dependence: occurrence of the second que is contingent on that of the first simply because a ‘restart’ of an embedded clause is possible only where there is one to begin with.

What is more, the second complementizer can co-occur with an unambiguous discourse marker such as pues ‘then/thus,’ as in (53). Note that discourse-related particles tend to cluster together in many languages (Hansen Reference Hansen1998).Footnote 17

In fact, the paratactic approach naturally extends to instances of restarts in the absence of a dislocate, where instead a mere pause (54a) or some interjection (54b,c,d) separates the two fragmentary sentences (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2019), as is widely attested in spontaneous speech (recall also the facts in (41) in Section 3.3):

Echeverría (Reference Echeverría2021, Reference Echeverría2022: 10n4), who pursues an analysis of recomplementation in terms of multiple nonlinear planes, claims that the absence of a dislocate in such cases poses a problem for the paratactic analysis pursued here. On the contrary, we submit that this approach offers precisely the leeway required to accommodate such restarts more generally, permitting reflective pauses, interjections and the like to be intercalated in between both sentences:

As previously noted in Section 3.3, cases such as those in (54) show that recomplementation is not a corollary of ClLD but a more general production phenomenon.Footnote 18 It would therefore be inaccurate to model the observed complementizer doubling as a direct effect of dislocation, however this intuition is implemented.

3.7. Argument 7: Form-identity of complementizers

On the paratactic analysis, the fact that the doubled complementizer is form-identical to the first one is a straightforward corollary of the parallelism required of the sentences involved for purposes of ellipsis resolution:

By the same token, the paratactic approach to recomplementation can easily accommodate cases of multiple reduplicative complementizers (i.e., que/that XP, que/that XP, que/that …), as illustrated in (6) in Section 2. Recall that such iterative cases are analyzed on the TopicP account as cases of TopicP recursion (cf. (8)), argued for on independent grounds by Rizzi (Reference Rizzi and Haegeman1997). On the paratactic account, these are simply cases of sequential elliptical sentences, as shown in (57); nothing else needs to be said.

As a further argument, consider reduplicated interrogative complementizers in both Spanish and English (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2019):Footnote 19

This naturally follows from the paratactic analysis, whereby the repeated interrogative complementizer is selected by the predicate preguntar ‘ask’/wonder in CP2:

Further support for this line of reasoning derives from Plann’s (Reference Plann1982) discovery of a contrast in Spanish embedded questions under verbs that do not inherently take an interrogative clausal complement. As shown by the translations of the minimal pair in (60), the presence of que turns the embedded clause into a reported interrogative (i.e., an indirect question) (see RAE-ASALE 2009 for further discussion and examples):

With recomplementation, however, the presence of a second occurrence of the que-si sequence becomes obligatory (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2015: Ch. 5):Footnote 20

For monosentential analyses which assume a complex left periphery, accounting for this contrast is not straightforward: if, for instance, the interrogative complementizer heads Int(errogative)P (as in Rizzi’s Reference Rizzi, Cinque and Salvi2001 analysis), the only possibility to analyze (61) would be to invoke (discontinuous) recursion of IntP:

On this type of analysis, the high que would by hypothesis be the realization of Force0 and the second one the realization of Topic0. As noted, two occurrences of IntP would have to be postulated, one above and one below TopicP. Note that if we were to dispense with TopicP and locate the dislocate in the specifier of the lower IntP, this would in effect deprive us of the head position for secondary que, yielding the wrong result:

All in all, the above considerations strongly suggest that an account of this kind is untenable.

On our approach, on the other hand, the repetition of the que-si sequence in cases like (61) is predicted, simply because CP2 is an elliptical restart of the embedded indirect question:

Having only si without que would violate parallelism between CP1 and CP2, as it would not allow the surface remnant of CP2 to be interpreted as a reported question. Overall, the facts reviewed above provide further support for the paratactic account of recomplementation patterns advocated here.

It is worth stressing again that our reasoning vindicates the intuition behind the label re-complementation originally given by Higgins (Reference Higgins1988): the second que heralds the presence of a duplicated complement clause. Recomplementation truly is recomplementation.

3.8. Argument 8: Selection

As noted in Section 2 in relation to the data in (17), only certain predicates allow for R-ClLD in their complement domain. More specifically, in Spanish, factives such as lamentar ‘lament’ cannot take recomplementized clausal complements, as noted by Demonte & Fernández-Soriano (Reference Demonte and Fernández-Soriano2009), Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015), and González i Planas (Reference González i Planas2014). In principle, this is handled straightforwardly by the paratactic approach, given that the kind of embedded fragments argued here to feature in recomplementation is likewise restricted to verbs such as decir ‘to say,’ but unavailable with factive predicates such as lamentar ‘to lament:’

The same applies to other predicates, such as volitional querer ‘want,’ which are also incompatible with both recomplementation (66) and embedded fragments (67), much like factives.

Although the issue of selection should be further investigated in more detail in future work, the above observation adds to the repertoire of arguments in favor of a paratactic account of recomplementation.

3.9. Argument 9: No recomplementation with ClRD

Demonte & Fernández-Soriano (Reference Demonte and Fernández-Soriano2009) observe that embedded Clitic Right-dislocation (ClRD) cannot be accompanied by a doubled complementizer:

Under a TopicP-based account of ClRD, this is unexpected: everything else being equal, if a doubled que is the realization of Topic0, this topic marker ought to be licensed for right-peripheral topics as much as for left-peripheral ones.

Can the paratactic approach deal with this asymmetry between ClLD and ClRD? The answer to this question turns out to be positive.Footnote 21 Building on the bisentential analysis of right-dislocation proposed in Ott & De Vries (Reference Ott and de Vries2016) (see also Fernández-Sánchez Reference Fernández-Sánchez2017 for Romance), the attempted R-ClRD in (68) is analyzed as shown in (69a) vis-à-vis a corresponding R-ClLD case on our terms (69b):

Note, first, that in (69a) there is an incongruence between the nominal cataphoric clitic in the first clause and the subsequent (illicit) fragment, identified as clausal by the complementizer; (68) thus violates the expectation of a nominal fragment based on the rhetorical connection between the sentences (Ott Reference Ott2017; Onea & Ott Reference Onea and Ott2022).

Furthermore, the kind of fragment that (68) attempts to employ is simply not licensed in general; we can see this by considering (70B), which is a direct equivalent of CP2 in (69a) on our analysis:

This contrasts markedly with the kind of sequence comprising a verb such as decir ‘say’ + que + XP that appears in R-ClLD (as in CP1 in (69b) above) and that is independently available as a fragment response:

The incompatibility of recomplementation and ClRD thus follows straightforwardly on the bisentential paratactic analysis.

4. Conclusion

We have shown in this paper that a version of the paratactic account proposed by Ott (Reference Ott2014, Reference Ott2015) for regular ClLD adapted here to the recomplementation variety overcomes many of the problems raised for monosentential accounts of R-ClLD configurations (such as cartographic analyses adopting a Rizzian left periphery) and makes several welcome predictions.

The analysis has also helped unveil previously unnoticed properties of recomplementation, such as the fact that not only dislocated constituents, but also other kinds of intercalated expressions can occur in between the two complementizers. As we have argued, this is just what we expect if the secondary complementizer signals a ‘restart’ in discourse.

As noted by an anonymous reviewer, our analysis undermines the common idea (implicit, for instance, in the cartographic works referenced above) that Spanish and English differ in relevant respects regarding the composition of the left periphery; on our analysis, so-called recomplementation is the result of entirely general mechanisms. This is not to say that left-peripheral restarts will be uniform cross-linguistically; ellipsis options vary across languages, and this will affect the form of fragmentary expressions involved, among other factors. Needless to say, this paper merely scratches the surface of the phenomenon, and we hope that it can inspire deeper investigations into the interrelation of ellipsis and restarts across languages.

Overall, we have shown within the expressly narrow focus of this paper that a paratactic analysis of recomplementation for languages like Spanish and English not only directly implements Higgins’ (1988) original intuition about the phenomenon but also provides elegant and principled answers to a host of perennial questions that have proven difficult to resolve in a principled fashion on previous approaches.

Footnotes

We would like to thank three anonymous Journal of Linguistics reviewers for their comments and observations. We are also grateful to the conference abstract reviewers and/or the audiences at Going Romance (Leiden), Colloquium on Generative Grammar (Barcelona), Linguistic Association of Great Britain (LAGB) Annual General Meeting (Sheffield), Hispanic Linguistics Symposium (HLS, Wake Forest, North Carolina), Romance Languages: Recent Contributions to Linguistic Theory (Harvard University, Pontifical Catholic University of Rio de Janeiro, and Federal University of Santa Catarina, Brazil), as well as at the Centre for Advanced Study in Theoretical Linguistics (CASTL), University of Tromsø, Norway. More specifically, we would like to thank the following individuals for their valuable observations: Klaus Abels, Karlos Arregi, Adolfo Ausín, András Bárány, Delia Bentley, Jonathan Bobaljik, Željko Bošković, Elena Calegari, Jan Cassalichio, Lorena Castillo, Simone De Cia, João Costa, Carlos Echeverría, Francisco Fernández-Rubiera, Olga Fernández-Soriano, Alberto Frasson, Maria Lluïsa Hernanz, Natalia Jardón, Ángel Jiménez-Fernández, Anna Kocher, Adam Ledgeway, Francisco Martín Miguel, Ana I. Ojea López, Francisco Ordóñez, Erika Petersen O Farrill, Pilar Peinado, Andrew Radford, Gillian Ramchand, Gemma Rigau, Liliana Sánchez, Emanuela Sanfelici, Michelle Sheehan, Paul Stott, Imanol Suárez-Palma, Peter Svenonius, Jacopo Torregrossa, and Xavier Villalba.

JVG would like to acknowledge the support provided by a María Zambrano International Talent Attraction Grant (MU-21-UP2021-030 71880965), awarded by the Spanish Ministry of Universities, with funding from the European Union (#NextGenerationEU, NGEU), and by the Spanish-Government-funded project INFOSTARS (PGC2018-093774-B-I00). DO acknowledges financial aid from the Basque Government to the Basque Research Group in Theoretical Linguistics (HiTT, ref. IT1537-22). The authors are grateful to the University of Manchester for financially supporting the OA publication of this paper.

[2] See Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2012, Reference Villa-García2015, Reference Villa-García2019) for divergent results from bound-variable-interpretation cases, which may be related to word order and the presence of a complementizer disfavoring bound readings (Pasquereau Reference Pasquereau2018).

[3] See Villa-García (Reference Villa-García2012) for an analysis that inverts the standard probe-goal relationship à la Bošković (Reference Bošković2007).

[4] New accounts have emerged since, such as Petersen O’Farrill’s (Reference Petersen O’Farrill2021) proposal, rooted in the Phase-over-Phase constraint.

[5] (16b) instantiates a case of a quotative or evidentiality complementizer in matrix clauses, as indicated by the English paraphrase. The analysis of such constructions is contested in the literature (see, e.g., Etxepare Reference Etxepare2010 and Demonte & Fernández-Soriano Reference Demonte, Fernández-Soriano, Dufter and de Toledo2014). For our purposes, it is enough to note that such elements license the secondary complementizer.

[6] Furthermore, as pointed out by Peter Svenonius (pers. comm. 2022), the dependence of the second que on the higher one is at odds with a model of incremental, bottom-up structure-generation: the linearly first que would be merged later than its lower counterpart, the appearance of which would nevertheless be conditional on that of the former.

[7] As noted by Michelle Sheehan (pers. comm. 2021), there are varieties of Romance where the complementizers in what at first sight looks like recomplementation are morphologically distinct. See, in particular, the work of Ledgeway (Reference Ledgeway2005), who observes that in addition to the frequent cases of complementizer repetition with dislocated phrases in certain dialects of southern Italy (i.e., che – che), along the lines of what we observe in Spanish and English in the main text, there are che and ca complementizers (and other variants), ca-style complementizers being used for subjunctive clauses (cf. [ForceP che [TopicP [FocucP [FinitenessP ca [TP …]]]]], based on Ledgeway Reference Ledgeway2005: 364; see also Villa-García Reference Villa-García2015 on the low que complementizer in Spanish subjunctive clauses). Ledgeway’s cases also include complementizers below foci, which are not possible in Spanish. We leave to future work the question of whether these examples constitute cases of R-ClLD proper or a different phenomenon altogether.

[8] We use ‘dislocated’ as a descriptive term throughout, implying nothing about derivational mechanics. This is in line with the literature, where the label is standardly employed even under accounts whereby dislocated constituents are assumed to be base-generated in their left-peripheral position.

[9] For the same reason, the locative adverbial of locative-inversion constructions cannot appear in between thats, as shown in (i)a; as expected, rendering CP2 a syntactically complete sentence by addition of an expletive subject improves the result (i)b.

As noted by Jonathan Bobaljik (pers. comm. 2022), there is a register clash in the examples in (i), since locative inversion is much more formal than recomplementation, which is a phenomenon of spoken language; the relevant contrast holds regardless.

[10] In this connection, it should be noted that not all dislocates in Spanish occur with a correlate/resumptive element, as observed by Adolfo Ausín (pers. comm. 2021). For instance, PP arguments in Spanish do not have a clitic counterpart (Casielles-Suárez Reference Casielles-Suárez2004; Villa-García Reference Villa-García2015):

Despite the lack of an overt correlate following the second que, the second sentence is syntactically complete, and the construction is a proper instance of (R-)ClLD (see Ott Reference Ott2015: 241, fn. 22). An argument may not be overtly realized in CP2, but this does not make the second sentence syntactically incomplete; text/discourse coherence ensures that the sentence in CP2 is properly interpreted based on the preceding context (i.e., CP1). The same holds for incontrovertibly independent elliptical sentences, as in (ii):

Since (ii)B occurs in the context of (ii)A, B can only mean ‘counting on her,’ not ‘counting numbers,’ for example. The same applies to conditional sentences, as in (iii), where the conditional meaning is understood even if not overtly expressed (cf. (iv)B):

[11] We remain neutral as to whether the fragment/dislocate in cases like (24)/(26B) moves within CP1 or not. Whether or not clausal ellipsis generally requires such movement remains an open question (see, e.g., Merchant Reference Merchant2004 vs. Ott & Struckmeier Reference Ott and Struckmeier2018). The two possibilities are illustrated below:

[12] As far as we can see, and as one would expect given this explanation, the only way to render such configurations acceptable is by making the restarted embedded clause an emphatic repetition:

In such cases, the rhetorical demand for emphasis overrides considerations of focus–background structuring and redundancy avoidance.

[13] Note that we are not claiming that there is an elided verb of communication above quotative que, although clearly the quotative character of this pattern makes it compatible with bona fide verbs of communication like decir ‘to say’ for purposes of parallelism, for instance. See Etxepare (Reference Etxepare2010) and Demonte & Fernández-Soriano (Reference Demonte, Fernández-Soriano, Dufter and de Toledo2014) on matrix que with quotative/evidential meaning.

[14] Regarding epithetic correlates in regular ClLD, there seems to be considerable inter-speaker variation. For some speakers, a full (i.e., non-clitic) epithetic correlate is not possible; for others, it is possible as long as a pause occurs between the sentence and the epithetic correlate; finally, there are speakers for whom an epithetic correlate is unobjectionable, much like in the recomplementation cases in (37):

For cases of dialectal variation regarding the availability of epithets with ClLDs, see, e.g., Estigarribia (Reference Estigarribia2020), where a biclausal analysis à la Ott (Reference Ott2014) is advocated. We will leave a detailed comparison of epithetic correlates in ClLD vs. R-ClLD to future work.

[15] Dislocates involving negatively quantified constituents are rather infrequent and typically occur as foci instead (Villa-García Reference Villa-García2015: 350).

[16] Regarding non-recomplementation ClLD, in the regular case negation is impossible, as in (i):

However, if a prolonged pause (#) occurs after the ClLDed phrase a ninguno de ellos, then negation is again required:

[17] Altering the order pues > que is not possible. Similarly, dropping que in such contexts and leaving pues alone does not lead to an acceptable outcome at least in Iberian Spanish (see Martínez Vera Reference Martínez Vera2019 for Latin American Spanish recomplementation):

We would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this point.

[18] An important question for future research is just how generally such an analysis can be applied to restarts and other ‘disfluencies’ conditioned by grammatical factors (Ferreira et al. Reference Ferreira, Lau and Karl2004). We thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing up this issue, which, however, we cannot take up in the present paper.

[19] English non-finite complementizer for also exhibits reduplication, as noted by the following example, kindly provided by Andrew Radford (pers. comm. 2022):

See also Vincent, Bentley & Samu (Reference Vincent, Bentley and Samu2004) on cases of reduplicative complementizer de ‘of’ in non-finite clauses in Old Sardinian.

[20] Echeverría (Reference Echeverría2022: 78-83) provides experimental confirmation of the high acceptability of que si–que si sentences.

[21] See Echeverría (Reference Echeverría2022: 10, fn. 4) for a dissenting view.

References

Barbosa, Pilar. 2000. Clitics: a window into the null subject property. In Costa, João (ed.), Portuguese syntax: new comparative studies, 3194. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barbosa, Pilar. 2009. Two kinds of subject pro. Studia Linguistica 63, 258. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9582.2008.01153.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benincà, Paola & Poletto, Cecilia. 2004. Topic, focus and V2: Defining the CP subleyers. In Rizzi, Luigi (ed.), The structure of CP and IP (The Cartography of Syntactic Structures), 5275. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bošković, Željko. 2001. On the nature of the syntax-phonology interface: Cliticization and related phenomena. Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bošković, Željko. 2007. On the locality and motivation of Move and Agree: An even more minimal theory. Linguistic Inquiry 38, 589644. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2007.38.4.589CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campos, Héctor. 1992. Los bearneses que quequean, ¿y nosotros qué? (Béarnese speakers overuse ‘que’, and what about us?). Hispanic Linguistics 4, 329349.Google Scholar
Casasanto, Laura S. & Sag, Ivan A.. 2008. The Advantage of the Ungrammatical. In Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Austin, Texas: Cognitive Science Society.Google Scholar
Casielles-Suárez, Eugenia. 2004. The syntax-information structure interface: Evidence from Spanish and English. New York: Routledge. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203501719CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cerrudo Aguilar, Alba and Gallego, Ángel. 2018. Island effects under recomplementation in Spanish. Linguistic Analysis 42, 116.Google Scholar
Cinque, Guglielmo. 1990. Types of Ā-dependencies. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cocchi, Gloria & Poletto, Cecilia. 2007. Complementizer deletion and double complementizers. In Picchi, Cecilia & Pona, Alan (eds.), Proceedings of the 32nd Incontro di Gramatica Generativa, 4962. Firenze: Edizioni dell’Orso.Google Scholar
de Cuba, Carlos & MacDonald, Jonathan. 2013. On the referential status of embedded polarity answers in Spanish. In Amaro, Jennifer Cabrelli, Lord, Gillian, de Prada Pérez, Ana, & Aaron, Jesse (eds.), Selected proceedings of the 16th Hispanic Linguistics Symposium, 212323. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.Google Scholar
Dehé, Nicole. 2007. The relation between syntactic and prosodic parenthesis. In Dehé, Nicole & Kavalova, Yordanka (eds.), Parentheticals, 261284. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1075/la.106.15dehCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demonte, Violeta & Fernández-Soriano, Olga. 2009. Force and finiteness in the Spanish complementizer system. Probus 21, 2349. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/prbs.2009.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demonte, Violeta & Fernández-Soriano, Olga. 2014. Evidentiality and illocutionary force. Spanish matrix ‘que’ at the syntax-semantics interface. In Dufter, Andreas & de Toledo, Álvaro Octavio (eds.), Left sentence peripheries in Spanish; Diachronic, variationist, and typological Perspectives, 217252. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Echeverría, Carlos. 2021. Spanish recomplementation, restarts, and constructions: between discourse and grammar. Presented at the 2021 Hispanic Linguistics Symposium (HLS 2021), Wake Forest University, North Carolina.Google Scholar
Echeverría, Carlos. 2022. Recomplementation between discourse and grammar: a syntactic investigation combining experimental and corpus methods. Ph.D. dissertation, Pennsylvania State University.Google Scholar
Escribano, José Luis Rafael G. 1991. Una teoría de la oración (A theory of the sentence). Oviedo: Servicio de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Oviedo.Google Scholar
Estigarribia, Bruno. 2020. A biclausal account of Clitic Left-Dislocations with epithets in Rioplatense Spanish. Glossa: a journal of general linguistics 5(1). 33, 112. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.1008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etxepare, Ricardo. 2010. From hearsay evidentiality to samesaying relations. Lingua 120, 604627. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2008.07.009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fernández-Rubiera, Francisco José. 2009. Clitics at the edge: Clitic placement in Western Iberian Romance languages. Ph.D. dissertation, Georgetown University.Google Scholar
Fernández-Sánchez, Javier. 2017. Right dislocation as a biclausal phenomenon. Evidence from romance languages. Ph.D. dissertation, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona.Google Scholar
Ferreira, Fernanda, Lau, Ellen F., and Karl, G.D. Bailay. 2004. Disfluencies, language comprehension, and Tree-adjoining Grammars. Cognitive Science 28, 721749.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fontana, Josep M. 1993. Phrase structure and the syntax of clitics in the history of Spanish. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
Frank, Joshua. 2016. On the grammaticality of recomplementation in Spanish. In Cuza, Alejandro, Czerwionka, Lori, & Olson, Daniel (eds.), Inquiries in Hispanic Linguistics: From theory to empirical evidence, 3952. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1075/ihll.12.03fraCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frank, Joshua. 2020. An Experimental Approach to Recomplementation: Evidence from Monolingual and Bilingual Spanish. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Texas Austin.Google Scholar
González i Planas, Francesc. 2010. Cartografia de la recomplementació en les llengües romàniques. MA Thesis. University of Girona.Google Scholar
González i Planas, Francesc. 2014. On quotative recomplementation: Between pragmatics and morphosyntax. Lingua 146, 3974. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2014.04.007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gupton, Timothy. 2014. The syntax-information structure interface: Clausal word order and the left periphery in Galician. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haegeman, Liliane. 2012. Adverbial clauses, main clause phenomena, and composition of the left periphery (The Cartography of Syntactic Structures). Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199858774.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansen, Maj-Britt Mosegaard. 1998. The semantic status of discourse markers. Lingua 104, 235260. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0024-3841(98)00003-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Higgins, Roger. 1988. Where the Old English sentence begins. Ms., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.Google Scholar
Iatridou, Sabine & Kroch, Anthony. 1992. The licensing of CP-recursion and its relevance to the Germanic verb-second phenomenon. Working Papers in Scandinavian Linguistics 50, 125.Google Scholar
Kempchinsky, Paula. 2013. CLLD as a window into the left periphery. In Howe, Chad, Blackwell, Sarah, & Quesada, Margaret Lubbers (eds.), Selected proceedings of the 15th Hispanic Linguistics Symposium (HLS 2011), 310328. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.Google Scholar
Ledgeway, Adam. 2005. Moving through the left periphery: the dual complementizer system in the dialects of Southern Italy. Transactions of the Philological Society 103, 229396. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-968X.2005.00157.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
López, Luis. 2009. Ranking the linear correspondence axiom. Linguistic Inquiry 40, 239276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacDonald, Jonathan E. 2015. Review article on Julio Villa-García, The syntax of multiple-que sentences in Spanish: Along the left periphery, 2015. Iberia: An International Journal of Theoretical Linguistics 7, 6879.Google Scholar
Martín-González, Javier. 2002. The syntax of sentential negation in Spanish. Ph.D. dissertation, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Martínez Vera, Gabriel. 2017. On recomplementation, high adverbs and verb movement in the Spanish left periphery. Presented at the 46th meeting of the Linguistic Symposium on Romance Languages (LSRL 47). University of Delaware.Google Scholar
Martínez Vera, Gabriel. 2019. Phases, labeling, antilocality and intonational phrases: Recomplementation in Spanish. Probus: International Journal of Romance Linguistics 31(1), 187231. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/probus-2019-0002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mascarenhas, Salvador. 2007. Complementizer doubling in European Portuguese. Ms., Amsterdam/New York: ILLC/NYU.Google Scholar
McCloskey, James. 2006. Questions and questioning in a local English. In Zanuttini, Raffaella, Campos, Héctor, Herburger, Elena, & Portner, Paul (eds.), Negation, tense and clausal architecture: Cross-linguistic investigations, 86126. Georgetown: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Merchant, Jason. 2001. The syntax of silence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merchant, Jason. 2004. Fragments and ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy 27, 661738.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munaro, Nicola. 2016. A diachronic approach to complementizer doubling in Italo-Romance and the notion of downward reanalysis. Rivista di Grammatica Generativa 38, 215228.Google Scholar
Nespor, Marina & Vogel, Irene. 1986. Prosodic phonology. Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Onea, Edgar & Ott, Dennis. 2022. Nominal appositives in grammar and discourse. Language 98, 359391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ott, Dennis & de Vries, Mark. 2016. Right-dislocation as deletion. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 34, 641690.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ott, Dennis & Struckmeier, Volker. 2018. Particles and Deletion. Linguistic Inquiry 49(2), 393407. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00277CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ott, Dennis. 2014. An ellipsis approach to contrastive left-dislocation. Linguistic Inquiry 45(2), 269303. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00155CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ott, Dennis. 2015. Connectivity in left-dislocation and the composition of the left periphery. Linguistic Variation 15(2), 225290. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1075/lv.15.2.04ottCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ott, Dennis. 2016. Ellipsis in appositives. Glossa 1(1). 34, 146, DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ott, Dennis. 2017. The syntax and pragmatics of dislocation: a non-templatic approach. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Canadian Linguistic Association, 113.Google Scholar
Paoli, Sandra. 2006. The fine structure of the left periphery: COMPs and subjects: evidence from Romance. Lingua 117, 10571079. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2006.05.007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pasquereau, Jérémy. 2018. Responding to questions and assertions: embedded polar response particles, ellipsis, and contrast. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.Google Scholar
Petersen O’Farrill, Erika. 2021. The Phase-over-Phase constraint in a series of Spanish configurations. Presented at the Linguistic Symposium on Romance Languages 51 (LSRL 51), University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Illinois.Google Scholar
Plann, Susan. 1982. Indirect questions in Spanish. Linguistic Inquiry 13, 297312.Google Scholar
Poletto, Cecilia. 2000. The higher functional field: Evidence from Northern Italian dialects. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Radford, Andrew. 2013. The complementizer system in spoken English: Evidence from broadcast media. In Camacho-Taboada, Victoria, Jiménez-Fernández, Ángel, Martín-González, Javier, & Reyes-Tejedor, Mariano (eds.), Information structure and agreement, 1154. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1075/la.197.01radCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Radford, Andrew. 2018. Colloquial English: Structure and variation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108552202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
RAE-ASALE. 2009. Nueva gramática de la lengua española (New grammar of the Spanish language). Madrid: Espasa.Google Scholar
Rizzi, Luigi. 1997. The fine structure of the left periphery. In Haegeman, Liliane (ed.), Elements of grammar, 281337. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-5420-8_7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rizzi, Luigi. 2001. On the position “Int(errogative)” in the left periphery of the clause. In Cinque, Guglielmo & Salvi, Giampaolo (eds.), Current studies in Italian syntax: Essays offered to Lorenzo Renzi, 287296. Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rizzi, Luigi. 2004. Locality and Left Periphery. In Belletti, Adriana (ed.), Structures and Beyond: The Cartography of Syntactic Structures, Vol. 3, 223251. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodríguez-Ramalle, Teresa. 2003. La gramática de los adverbios en -mente o cómo expresar maneras, opiniones y actitudes a través de la lengua (The grammar of ‘-mente’ adverbs or how to express manner, opinion and attitudes through language). Madrid: Ediciones de la Universidad Autónoma de Madrid.Google Scholar
Salvesen, Chrisine & Walkden, George. 2017. Diagnosing embedded V2 in Old English and Old French. In Mathieu, Éric & Truswell, Robert (eds), Micro-change and Macro-change in Diachronic Syntax, 168181. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salvesen, Christine Meklenborg. 2014. Le complémenteur ‘que’ et la périphérie gauche: analyse diachronique (The complementizer ‘que’ in the left periphery: a diachronic analysis). Syntaxe et sémantique 15. 4780. DOI: https://doi.org/10.3917/ss.015.0047CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Torrego, Esther. n.d. In preparation. Remarks on que.Google Scholar
Uriagereka, Juan. 1995. An F position in Western Romance. In Kiss, Katalin (ed.), Discourse configurational Languages (Oxford Studies in Comparative Syntax), 153175. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam. 1991. On the Structural Positions of the Subjects in Spanish, their Nature and their Consequences for Quantification. Ms., University of Connecticut, Storrs.Google Scholar
Villa-García, Julio. 2010. Recomplementation and locality of movement in Spanish. Second General Examination Paper. University of Connecticut, Storrs.Google Scholar
Villa-García, Julio. 2012. Recomplementation and locality of movement in Spanish. Probus: International Journal of Romance Linguistics 24, 257314. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/probus-2012-0011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Villa-García, Julio. 2015. The syntax of multiple-que sentences in Spanish: Along the left periphery (Issues in Hispanic and Lusophone Linguistics). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1075/ihll.2Google Scholar
Villa-García, Julio. 2016. TP-ellipsis with a polarity particle in multiple-complementizer contexts in Spanish: on topical remnants and focal licensors. Borealis: An International Journal of Hispanic Linguistics 5(2), 135172. DOI: https://doi.org/10.7557/1.5.2.3781CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Villa-García, Julio. 2019. Recomplementation in English and Spanish: Delineating the CP space. Glossa: a journal of general linguistics 4(1). 56, 144. DOI: http://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.845CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vincent, Nigel, Bentley, Delia, & Samu, Borbàla. 2004. The syntax of the complementizer de in Old Sardinian. Presented at Multilingualism and Diachronic Change, Hamburg.Google Scholar
Vincent, Nigel. 2006. Il problema del doppio complementatore nei primi volgari d’Italia (The problem of the double complementizer in the earliest Italian vernaculars). In Andreose, Andrea & Penello, Nicoletta (eds.), LabRomAn: Giornata di lavoro sulle varietà romanze antiche, 2742. Padua: University of Padua.Google Scholar
Vincent, Nigel. 2019. CP and COMP in diachrony. In Butt, Miriam, King, Tracy Holloway, & Toivonen, Ida (eds.), Proceedings of the LFG 19 Conference, 314333. Australian National University, CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Wanner, Dieter. 1998. Les subordonnées à double complémentateur en roman medieval (Subordinate clauses with double complementizers in Medieval Romance). In Ruffino, Giovanni (ed.), Atti del XXI Congresso Internazionale di Linguistica e Filologia Romanza, 421433. Tübingen: Niemeyer. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110961522.421Google Scholar