Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-16T06:36:50.823Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Preferences versus opportunities: on the conceptual foundations of normative welfare economics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 December 2022

Roberto Fumagalli*
Affiliation:
Department of Political Economy, King’s College London, London, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Normative welfare economics commonly assumes that individuals’ preferences can be reliably inferred from their choices and relies on preference satisfaction as the normative standard for welfare. In recent years, several authors have criticized welfare economists’ reliance on preference satisfaction as the normative standard for welfare and have advocated grounding normative welfare economics on opportunities rather than preferences. In this paper, I argue that although preference-based approaches to normative welfare economics face significant conceptual and practical challenges, opportunity-based approaches fail to provide a more reliable and informative foundation for normative welfare economics than preference-based approaches. I then identify and rebut various influential calls to ground normative welfare economics on opportunities rather than preferences to support my qualified defence of preference-based approaches.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Normative welfare economics (henceforth, NWE) commonly assumes that individuals’ preferences can be reliably inferred from their choices and relies on preference satisfaction as the normative standard for welfare (e.g. Bernheim Reference Bernheim2009; Hausman Reference Hausman2012; Adler and Fleurbaey Reference Adler and Fleurbaey2016). The idea is that individuals are well-off to the extent that their own preferences are satisfied and that policies enhance individuals’ welfare to the extent that they satisfy such preferences (e.g. Salant and Rubinstein Reference Salant and Rubinstein2008; Rubinstein and Salant Reference Rubinstein and Salant2012; Manzini and Mariotti Reference Manzini and Mariotti2014). In recent years, several authors have criticized welfare economists’ reliance on preference satisfaction as the normative standard for welfare and have advocated grounding NWE on opportunities rather than preferences (e.g. McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012; Infante et al. Reference Infante, Lecouteux and Sugden2016 a, Reference Infante, Lecouteux and Sugden2016 b). The idea is that welfare economists should rely on opportunities rather than preference satisfaction as the normative standard for welfare and that individuals’ opportunities have value irrespective of whether individuals’ choices reveal consistent and stable preferences (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2004, Reference Sugden2007, Reference Sugden2018: Chs 4–5; also Roemer Reference Roemer1998; Van Hees Reference Van Hees2010; Bavetta et al. Reference Bavetta, Maimone, Miller and Navarra2017).Footnote 1

The ongoing debate concerning the merits of preference-based approaches to NWE (henceforth, PREF) and opportunity-based approaches to NWE (henceforth, OPP) has substantial policy implications. For PREF and OPP respectively draw on different primitive concepts and frequently ground dissimilar evaluations of policies’ welfare implications (e.g. Adler Reference Adler2013, Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2016). And even in those cases where PREF and OPP ground similar welfare evaluations (e.g. Piacquadio Reference Piacquadio2017), PREF and OPP ground such evaluations on dissimilar justificatory principles (e.g. Hausman Reference Hausman2016; Sugden Reference Sugden2018: Chs 4–5). In this paper, I join the debate and argue that although PREF face significant conceptual and practical challenges, OPP fail to provide a more reliable and informative foundation for NWE than PREF. I then rebut various influential calls to ground NWE on opportunities rather than preferences to support my qualified defence of PREF. The paper is structured as follows. Section 2 outlines the main tenets of PREF and explicates some major challenges faced by PREF. Section 3 outlines the main tenets of OPP and explicates some major challenges faced by OPP. Section 4 identifies and rebuts three influential calls to ground NWE on opportunities rather than preferences to support my qualified defence of PREF.

Before proceeding, the following three preliminary remarks are worth making. First, my qualified defence of PREF does not rest on specific assumptions as to whether preference satisfaction is most plausibly taken to constitute welfare or merely provide evidence for welfare. Below I use the term ‘PREF’ broadly to encompass both approaches that take preference satisfaction to constitute welfare (e.g. Adler Reference Adler2019, on preference satisfaction theories of welfare) and approaches that take preference satisfaction to merely provide evidence for welfare (e.g. Hausman Reference Hausman2012: Chs 7–8, on the evidential account of welfare). These approaches differ in significant respects (e.g. Hausman Reference Hausman2011, for a critical appraisal of preference satisfaction theories; Sarch Reference Sarch2015, for a critical appraisal of the evidential account), but share the aim to vindicate economists’ ‘practice of making inferences concerning well-being from people’s preferences’ (Hausman and McPherson Reference Hausman and McPherson2009: 16).

Second, OPP are not the only approach alternative to PREF that has been developed in the NWE literature (e.g. Haybron and Tiberius Reference Haybron and Tiberius2015: 714, on value-based approaches, which advocate grounding policies’ welfare evaluations ‘on people’s values … as opposed to their preferences’; Kahneman and Sugden Reference Kahneman and Sugden2005, on experienced utility approaches, which advocate grounding policies’ welfare evaluations on measures of experienced utility rather than measures of preference satisfaction). Below I target OPP (rather than other approaches) since to date OPP are significantly more developed and widely supported than other approaches (e.g. Hersch Reference Hersch2020, for a critical appraisal of value-based approaches; Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2019, for a critical appraisal of experienced utility approaches). In doing so, I focus primarily on the influential works by Sugden (e.g. Reference Sugden2004, Reference Sugden and Olsaretti2006, Reference Sugden2008, Reference Sugden2010, Reference Sugden2015, Reference Sugden2018) rather than other proponents of OPP because these works provide one of the most systematic contemporary defences of OPP and offer a commendably clear formulation of OPP’s empirical and theoretical presuppositions. I shall expand in section 3 on such presuppositions. For now, I note that OPP sharply differ from PREF not merely because they articulate an alternative view of the currency of advantage (replacing preference satisfaction with opportunity), but also because they rest on a specific account of individuals as responsible agents who ‘at each moment, [identify with their] own actions, past, present, and future’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 106) and presuppose a contractarian approach which assesses policies’ welfare implications ‘from the several viewpoints of individual members of society, considered as potential parties to an agreement’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 14; sections 3–4). In these latter respects, OPP are quite distinct from both PREF and various influential opportunity-based views of the currency of advantage (e.g. Sen Reference Sen1985, Reference Sen1991, Reference Sen1999, Reference Sen2002: Ch. 20).

And third, the relative merits of PREF and OPP may importantly depend on the analytical and practical purposes for which PREF and OPP are applied. My critical evaluation of OPP by no means excludes that the notion of opportunity has significant analytical and practical applications in normative economic analysis (e.g. Vallentyne Reference Vallentyne2005; Bavetta et al. Reference Bavetta, Navarra and Maimone2014, on opportunity-based measures of freedom; Fleurbaey and Peragine Reference Fleurbaey and Peragine2013; Roemer and Trannoy Reference Roemer and Trannoy2016, on opportunity-based measures of equality). In fact, my evaluation grants that welfare economists may combine specific tenets of PREF and OPP (e.g. Sen Reference Sen1991, Reference Sen2002: Ch. 20, for accounts of freedom and opportunity freedom that endorse a preference-based view of opportunity; also Suzumura and Xu Reference Suzumura, Xu, Anand, Pattanaik and Puppe2009, for an axiomatic framework whose primitive concepts are preference orderings over outcomes and opportunity sets from which those outcomes are chosen). Still, as I argue in sections 2–4, one can offer a detailed assessment of PREF’s and OPP’s respective potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE.Footnote 2

2. Preference-Based Approaches

According to PREF, individuals’ preferences for some state of affairs count as satisfied if such state of affairs obtains (e.g. Hausman Reference Hausman2010: 326; also Sobel Reference Sobel1994; Sumner Reference Sumner1996). Knowing that one’s preferences are satisfied often gives one feelings of pleasure or satisfaction. Still, on PREF, preference satisfaction does not have to involve any feelings of pleasure or satisfaction and does not enhance welfare in virtue of such feelings (e.g. Hausman and McPherson Reference Hausman and McPherson2009; Angner Reference Angner and Fletcher2016). Two sets of PREF are especially prominent in the NWE literature. On the one hand, actual PREF take individuals to be well-off to the extent that their actual preferences – i.e. the preferences individuals happen to have – are satisfied (e.g. Binmore Reference Binmore1994; Gul and Pesendorfer Reference Gul, Pesendorfer, Caplin and Schotter2008). On the other hand, informed/ideal PREF take individuals to be well-off to the extent that their informed/ideal preferences – i.e. the preferences individuals would have if they were not affected by limitations of information, cognitive ability, or self-control – are satisfied (e.g. Griffin Reference Griffin1986: part I; Harsanyi Reference Harsanyi1997).Footnote 3

According to the critics of PREF, neither actual PREF nor informed/ideal PREF can provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE. The critics of PREF typically proceed as follows. Individuals’ preferences can be reliably inferred from individuals’ choices only if these preferences satisfy stringent consistency (e.g. transitivity) and stability (e.g. context-independence) requirements. However, the empirical findings collected over the last few decades demonstrate that individuals’ actual preferences frequently fail to satisfy these requirements (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden1991; Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011, on violations of transitivity; Rabin Reference Rabin2002; Kahneman Reference Kahneman2003, on violations of context-independence). Moreover, the satisfaction of individuals’ actual preferences often tracks factors that seem prudentially irrelevant (e.g. Tversky and Kahneman Reference Tversky and Kahneman1981; Camerer and Loewenstein Reference Camerer, Loewenstein, Camerer, Loewenstein and Rabin2004, on cases where individuals’ actual preferences are influenced by frames) or even detract from what many theories of welfare regard as individuals’ welfare (e.g. Hausman Reference Hausman2011; Bar-Gill Reference Bar-Gill2012, on cases where individuals’ actual preferences rest on inaccurate information about the available choice options; also Harsanyi Reference Harsanyi1995; Vromen Reference Vromen, Caldwell, Davis, Mäki and Sent2022, on antisocial preferences). For these reasons, the critics of PREF go, the satisfaction of individuals’ actual preferences cannot be plausibly regarded as the normative standard for welfare and actual PREF cannot provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE.

For their part, informed/ideal PREF grant that individuals frequently have inconsistent and/or unstable actual preferences, but hold that individuals typically have consistent and stable informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare and that welfare economists can reconstruct such preferences. The idea is that despite the inconsistency and the instability of individuals’ actual preferences, welfare economists can take the satisfaction of individuals’ informed/ideal preferences as the normative standard for welfare. In this context, some contributions rely on model-less approaches, which attempt to reconstruct consistent and stable informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare without drawing on any specific models of the neuro-psychological processes that generate choices (e.g. Salant and Rubinstein Reference Salant and Rubinstein2008; Bernheim and Rangel Reference Bernheim and Rangel2009). Other contributions, instead, rely on model-based approaches, which attempt to reconstruct consistent and stable informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare by drawing on specific models of the neuro-psychological processes that generate choices (e.g. Rubinstein and Salant Reference Rubinstein and Salant2012; Manzini and Mariotti Reference Manzini and Mariotti2014).Footnote 4

Regrettably, the critics of PREF go, it is hard to establish what notion of informed/ideal preferences should be adopted by welfare economists unless one makes substantive normative assumptions about individuals’ welfare (e.g. McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012: 560, claiming that the concepts of ‘complete information’ and ‘unlimited cognition’ figuring in various informed/ideal PREF are ‘inescapably normative’). Moreover, different criteria have been proposed to reconstruct individuals’ informed/ideal preferences, and different criteria single out different subsets of informed/ideal preferences (e.g. Salant and Rubinstein Reference Salant and Rubinstein2008; Manzini and Mariotti Reference Manzini and Mariotti2012, on various divergences between the sets of informed/ideal preferences that are respectively singled out by model-based and model-less approaches). In fact, reconstructing some individuals’ informed/ideal preferences does not per se enable welfare economists to determine what is prudentially valuable for these individuals (e.g. Sobel Reference Sobel2009; Sugden Reference Sugden2018: Chs 4–5, on putative cases where individuals reveal context-dependent informed/ideal preferences). For these reasons, the critics of PREF go, the satisfaction of individuals’ informed/ideal preferences cannot be plausibly regarded as the normative standard for welfare and informed/ideal PREF cannot provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE.

3. Opportunity-Based Approaches

OPP hold that NWE should be ‘based on considered judgements about opportunity rather than on considered preferences’ (Sugden Reference Sugden and Olsaretti2006: 211, italics added; also McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012: 563, claiming that according to OPP, welfare economists should ‘use a normative criterion of opportunity rather than preference-satisfaction’). The idea is that welfare economists’ ‘normative theories [should be] based on opportunity rather than preference’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2020: 66), where an individual’s opportunities are ‘the set of options from which he can choose, options being described in such a way that they are mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 84). According to OPP, ‘a person is well-off by being able to choose whatever she might desire and be willing to pay for’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 55, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden2018: Ch. 5). In particular, ‘it is good for an individual to have a wide range of alternative options from which to choose’, and for each individual ‘opportunities to choose between alternative options have value, irrespective of whether or not those choices can be rationalized in terms of [consistent and] stable preferences’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2004: 1014 and 1016, italics added; also Van Hees Reference Van Hees2010: 687, holding that the opportunity ‘to make a choice from among a set of options … has a value that is at least partly independent of the actual choice we make or intend to make from that set’).

OPP sharply contrast with PREF. For according to OPP, ‘what ultimately matters [is] freedom of choice’ rather than preference satisfaction, and ‘rather than asking how far economic outcomes satisfy individuals’ preferences, we have to ask how far … those outcomes endow individuals with freedom of choice’ (McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012: 556, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden2015: 299). To be sure, OPP do not deny that individuals may value satisfying their own preferences. In fact, OPP explicitly hold that it is ‘in each individual’s interest to have opportunities to satisfy … any preferences she might come to have’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 99; also Sugden Reference Sugden and Olsaretti2006: 209). Still, according to OPP, opportunities rather than preference satisfaction are the normative standard for welfare. Therefore, rather than trying to reconstruct and satisfy individuals’ preferences, welfare economists should aim to increase the range of opportunities available to individuals (e.g. McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012; Sugden Reference Sugden2018: Chs 5–6).Footnote 5

OPP have become increasingly prominent in the NWE literature (e.g. McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012; Sugden Reference Sugden2015, Reference Sugden2018: Chs 4–5; Infante et al. Reference Infante, Lecouteux and Sugden2016 a, Reference Infante, Lecouteux and Sugden2016 b). Despite OPP’s increasing prominence, the hitherto proffered calls to ground NWE on opportunities (rather than preferences) face several major challenges. Below I focus on three major challenges in turn, which respectively concern (3.1) the measurement of opportunities, (3.2) the value of opportunities, and (3.3) the notion of agency presupposed by OPP.

3.1. Measurement of opportunities

According to OPP, ‘each individual has the opportunity to do whatever he might desire to do with those things to which he has entitlements’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 56). In particular, a policy P provides more opportunity than another policy P’ when P ‘contains all the options that [P’] does, and something in addition that the individual might conceivably want to choose’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 85). However, one cannot specify an individual’s set of opportunities independently of how other individuals choose to use their own opportunities. For although each individual is ‘free to choose from his own opportunity set’, the contents of this set are ‘determined by the choices that other individuals make from theirs’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 192). For this reason, ‘it is crucial [that] an individual’s opportunities are defined independently of her actual preferences’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 109, italics added). Moreover, ‘often, we cannot specify in concrete terms what a person [has] the opportunity to do’, and opportunity remains ‘an open-ended concept’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 48, italics added).

There are at least two reasons to doubt that OPP’s characterization of the notion of opportunity provides the basis to ground reliable and informative measurements of individuals’ opportunities. First, OPP’s characterization of the notion of opportunity does not enable welfare economists to compare pairs of opportunity sets ‘unless one [set] is a subset of the other’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2003: 804; also Hausman Reference Hausman2022). In fact, OPP ‘make no attempt to compare opportunity sets that are not nested’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 85, italics added). However, many opportunity sets are not nested, and profound divergences remain as to how non-nested sets should be ranked in terms of how many opportunities they provide (e.g. Harless and Pancs Reference Harless and Pancs2022). As a result, the proponents of OPP often lack the resources to reliably assess how many opportunities are provided by competing policies. This applies to not only individual opportunities, which are ‘defined in terms of the extent of each individual’s opportunity set’, but also interactive opportunities, which are ‘defined for each set of individuals in terms of what those individuals are able to achieve … by trading with one another’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2021: 425).

And second, it remains unclear what the basic metric for measuring individuals’ opportunities is supposed to be (e.g. Bernheim Reference Bernheim2021, on various divergences between measurements of individuals’ actual opportunities and measurements of individuals’ perceived opportunities). In particular, the proffered attempts to compare opportunity sets in terms of the number of options they offer and the related space of characteristics (e.g. Pattanaik and Xu Reference Pattanaik and Xu1990; Carter Reference Carter1999) fail to take into adequate account the diversity and the complementarity of the options figuring in opportunity sets (e.g. Weitzman Reference Weitzman1992; Van Hees Reference Van Hees2004). Yet, providing reliable and informative measurements of opportunity in concrete policy contexts requires one to specify ‘whether two putative options should be treated as distinct [and] how significant the difference is between one option and another’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2003: 803). And the proffered methods to measure the diversity and the complementarity of the options figuring in opportunity sets (e.g. Bervoets and Gravel Reference Bervoets and Gravel2007, for measurements targeting the most dissimilar pairs of options; Nehring and Puppe Reference Nehring and Puppe2002, for multi-attribute measurements; Pattanaik and Xu Reference Pattanaik and Xu2000, for measurements targeting similarity-based partitions) have implausible implications (e.g. Van Hees Reference Van Hees2004, on various methods’ tendency to let either diversity or cardinality considerations dominate; also Dowding and Oprea Reference Dowding and Oprea2022, for a recent review). In fact, it is rather hard to provide reliable measurements of options’ diversity and complementarity without relying on information concerning the preferences of the involved individuals (e.g. Sen Reference Sen1991; Van Hees Reference Van Hees2010). This, in turn, significantly constrains OPP’s potential to provide reliable and informative measurements of opportunity in concrete policy contexts. For OPP avowedly aim to ‘defin[e] people’s opportunities independently of their preferences’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: ix). And according to OPP, one ‘should not measure [opportunity] relative to preference [since] the whole point of opportunity is that … you can satisfy whatever preferences you might happen to have’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2020: 66).

A proponent of OPP may object that grounding reliable and informative evaluations of policies’ welfare implications ‘does not require the explicit specification of opportunity sets’ and that welfare economists and policymakers should ‘accept [opportunity’s] non-measurability’ rather than ‘try to measure opportunity directly’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 66, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden2003: 785). However, both welfare economists and policymakers frequently need to measure how many opportunities competing policies provide to individuals. In this respect, the open-endedness of OPP’s characterization of the notion of opportunity makes it extremely hard for welfare economists and policymakers to determine what counts as more and less opportunity in concrete policy contexts. To illustrate this, consider the notion of collective (rather than individual) opportunity, which figures centrally in the proffered evaluations of policies’ welfare implications (e.g. Stewart Reference Stewart2005). According to OPP, ‘each group of individuals has the opportunity to do whatever its members unanimously desire to do with those things to which, taken together, they have entitlements’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 56, italics added). This unanimity condition ‘introduces another element of open-endedness into the definition of opportunity’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 56). And this additional element of open-endedness, in turn, makes it prohibitively difficult for welfare economists and policymakers to reliably measure how many opportunities competing policies provide to distinct groups of individuals (e.g. think of policies having statistical targets or targeting vast population segments).Footnote 6

3.2. Value of opportunities

OPP are ‘premised on the idea that it is good that people are free to do what they want, when they want, even if their preferences are unstable’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2007: 678–679, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden2018: xi, proposing ‘the principle that, as viewed by each citizen separately, more opportunity for that person is better than less’). According to OPP, ‘any expansion of a person’s opportunity set promotes her interests, irrespective of her actual preferences and independently of [what] she has reason to prefer’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 99, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden and Olsaretti2006: 217). In particular, OPP are based on ‘the normative intuition that for each individual, opportunities to choose between alternative options have value, irrespective of whether or not those choices can be rationalized in terms of [consistent and] stable preferences’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2004: 1014, italics added; also Van Hees Reference Van Hees2010: 687). The idea is that an individual ‘may act on different preferences at different times [but] it is good for her that, at each moment, she is free to satisfy whatever preferences she then has’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2004: 1016, italics added; also Buchanan Reference Buchanan1986: part I).

There are at least two reasons to doubt that OPP’s claims about the putative intrinsic value of opportunities provide the basis to ground reliable and informative assessments of the value of opportunities. First, descriptively, individuals do not generally ascribe intrinsic value to the opportunity to act on their own preferences (e.g. Bernheim and Rangel Reference Bernheim and Rangel2004; Dold and Schubert Reference Dold and Schubert2018, on several cases where individuals who know that their own preferences are inconsistent and/or unstable do not ascribe intrinsic value to the opportunity to act on such preferences). This does not per se undermine OPP’s claim that opportunities have intrinsic value. Still, it challenges the proponents of OPP to provide more convincing reasons and/or evidence to explicate why many individuals fail to ascribe intrinsic value to opportunities and why exactly such individuals are mistaken. And second, the proponents of OPP have hitherto failed to substantiate the normative claim that opportunities generally have intrinsic value (e.g. Arneson Reference Arneson1999; Fleurbaey Reference Fleurbaey2012 a, on several cases where giving individuals opportunities that do not satisfy any of their preferences fails to enhance what many theories of welfare regard as individuals’ welfare). In fact, it is hard to see how the proponents of OPP may substantiate such normative claim unless they relinquish OPP’s declared aim to ‘maintain neutrality between different conceptions of the good’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 48; also Sugden Reference Sugden and Olsaretti2006: 218).Footnote 7

A proponent of OPP may object that welfare economists can assess the value of individuals’ opportunities by examining individuals’ potential preferences – i.e. the preferences that individuals ‘might have … in the relevant circumstances’ – rather than individuals’ actual preferences (Sugden Reference Sugden1998 a: 323; also Sugden Reference Sugden2003: 792). However, appeals to the preferences that individuals ‘might have’ in ‘the relevant circumstances’ are unlikely to ground reliable and informative assessments of the value of individuals’ opportunities unless the proponents of OPP supplement these appeals with precise and plausible specifications of what ‘the relevant circumstances’ are and what preferences individuals ‘might have’ in such circumstances. In this respect, attempts to reconstruct individuals’ potential preferences seem vulnerable to the same difficulties that OPP take to affect informed/ideal PREF’s attempts to reconstruct informed/ideal preferences (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden1998 a: 324, conceding that ‘there seems to be no way of avoiding appeal to contestable ideas of “normal”, “reasonable” or “natural” preferences’ when attempting to reconstruct individuals’ potential preferences). Moreover, even if reliable and informative assessments of the value of opportunities could be grounded on the notion of potential preferences, these assessments would seemingly assume that the value of opportunities is conditional on the value of preferences. And this assumption, in turn, would contradict OPP’s presupposition that opportunities have ‘normative significance in their own right … without explicit reference to individuals’ preferences’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 115, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden2003: 797, conceding that the proponents of OPP ‘have to find a measure [of opportunity] that does not refer to preferences, actual or potential’).

A proponent of OPP may further object that although opportunities do not always have intrinsic value, OPP can provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE because opportunities typically have instrumental value in virtue of their capacity to enhance what many theories of welfare regard as individuals’ welfare (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 106, claiming that ‘the more opportunities [one] has, the more [one] is free to do [irrespective of whether she has] coherent preferences’; also Van Hees Reference Van Hees2010: 702, holding that ‘we may value having the option to choose a non-valuable alternative because the alternative’s availability creates responsibility’). This objection correctly notes that expanding individuals’ opportunity sets often has a favourable impact on what many theories of welfare regard as individuals’ welfare (e.g. Vallentyne Reference Vallentyne2002; Bavetta et al. Reference Bavetta, Navarra and Maimone2014, on various opportunities’ contribution to individuals’ freedom of choice). However, not all opportunities enhance what many theories of welfare regard as individuals’ welfare (e.g. Dold and Rizzo Reference Dold and Rizzo2021, on opportunities to make choices that will predictably hinder one’s freedom of choice and one’s sense of agency; also Sen Reference Sen2002: 605, holding that ‘the opportunity to choose is not always an unmitigated advantage’). In fact, expanding individuals’ opportunity sets may hamper (rather than enhance) what many theories of welfare regard as individuals’ welfare both in individual choice settings (e.g. Fleurbaey Reference Fleurbaey2012 a; Hausman Reference Hausman2022, on several cases where expanding individuals’ opportunity sets leads to welfare losses due to greater cognitive/emotional decision costs and individuals’ vulnerability to harmful forms of addiction) and in strategic choice settings (e.g. Bicchieri Reference Bicchieri2017: Chs 3–4; Harless and Pancs Reference Harless and Pancs2022, on situations of strategic interaction where giving each player the option to defect turns the relevant cooperative games into prisoner’s dilemmas to the detriment of individuals’ payoffs). These concerns are exacerbated when one considers collective (rather than individual) opportunities. For showing that some collective opportunities are welfare-enhancing requires welfare economists ‘to convince each person separately that she benefits from being free to do as she likes’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 61, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden and Olsaretti2006: 209). This, in turn, is prohibitively hard to achieve in all policy settings where the examined policies only have statistical targets or target vast population segments rather than a limited number of well-identified individuals (e.g. Sunstein Reference Sunstein2021: 406, holding that ‘it is hard to identify any social institution [or public policy] that it is in the interest of each individual to accept’).

3.3. Agency

OPP rest on a specific account of individuals as responsible agents. On this account, an individual is a responsible agent ‘to the extent that, at each moment, she identifies with her own actions, past, present, and future’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 106, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 47–49). The idea is that a responsible agent ‘endorses the decisions made by all her selves, whether or not those decisions can be rationalised by a single system of coherent preferences’ (McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012: 563, italics added) and ‘thinks of the preferences on which [she] will act in the future as [her] preferences, even if [she] does not know what they will be and even if they will not be what [she] would currently like them to be’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2015: 299, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden2004: 1018). This account of individuals as responsible agents is not a dispensable tenet of OPP, but ‘provides philosophical underpinning’ to OPP (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 106). For the claim that ‘any increase in [an] individual’s opportunity is good for her’ irrespective of whether she has consistent and stable preferences avowedly rests on the assumption that the individual is ‘a continuing locus of responsibility’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 106) in the sense presupposed by OPP.

There are at least two reasons to doubt that OPP’s account of individuals as responsible agents provides the basis to ground a reliable and informative foundation for NWE. First, descriptively, individuals are not generally responsible in the sense indicated by OPP. In fact, many individuals do not seem responsible in such a sense. To illustrate this, consider individuals’ widespread and considered reliance on self-constraint, whereby individuals restrict their own short-term opportunities in order to expand their own long-term opportunities (e.g. Bernheim and Rangel Reference Bernheim and Rangel2004; Schubert and Cordes Reference Schubert and Cordes2013). The proponents of OPP acknowledge that in some cases, self-constraint might be a sign of responsibility (e.g. think of instances of self-constraint intended to counter harmful forms of addiction). Still, they object that ‘these cases are exceptional’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2015: 302). However, such cases seem far from exceptional. For individuals frequently rely on self-constraint (e.g. Dowding and Oprea Reference Dowding and Oprea2022; Harless and Pancs Reference Harless and Pancs2022). And OPP lack the resources to account for these decisions as the decisions of responsible agents (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2015: 300, holding that according to OPP, ‘present opportunities to restrict future opportunities [have] zero value’). And second, it remains unclear what exactly the normative import of individuals’ being responsible in the sense presupposed by OPP is. In particular, it is hard to see why welfare economists or policymakers should endorse OPP’s privileging of ‘the preferences of the acting self … rather than the self as the maker of plans or as the source of reflective judgements’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2004: 243). For in many cases, the choices of the planning self are more conducive to enhance what many theories of welfare regard as individuals’ welfare than the choices of the acting self (e.g. Rizzo and Whitman Reference Rizzo and Whitman2009 a; Schubert Reference Schubert2015). In this respect, what OPP depict as a responsible agent appears to resemble more ‘a faceless being that stumbles through life, driven around by whichever tastes she happens to acquire’ (Dold and Schubert Reference Dold and Schubert2018: 230) than an agent who qualifies as ‘responsible’ on any plausible common-sense definition of the term.

A proponent of OPP may object that pointing to common-sense definitions of responsible agents does not bear against OPP’s account of individuals as responsible agents since one of the major tenets of this account is precisely that welfare economists and policymakers ‘need a radically different conception of the continuing person’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 105, italics added). However, this objection does not provide independent reasons to endorse OPP’s account of individuals as responsible agents since it presupposes (rather than shows) that such an account provides the basis to ground a reliable and informative foundation for NWE. In this respect, it would be of limited import to object that several preference-based models developed to represent inconsistent and/or unstable preferences ‘equat[e] agency with coherent preferences [and] have no way of recognizing the continuing identity of a person whose preferences are incoherent’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 54; also Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 104–106, criticizing multiple selves models). For in primis, not all preference-based models face this limitation (e.g. Dietrich and List Reference Dietrich and List2011; Dietrich Reference Dietrich2018, for various models of preference change). And second, pointing to the limitations faced by some preference-based models falls short of indicating that the account of responsible agency presupposed by OPP provides the basis to ground a reliable and informative foundation for NWE. In particular, it remains hard to see why exactly welfare economists and policymakers should endorse OPP’s presupposition that responsible agency consists in one’s valuing ‘opportunities for herself as a continuing entity, whether or not her preferences remain constant’ rather than ‘in a coherent system of preferences or in a rational plan of life’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 55).

4. A Qualified Defence of Preference-Based Approaches

In this section, I argue that although informed/ideal PREF face significant conceptual and practical challenges, OPP do not provide a more reliable and informative foundation for NWE than informed/ideal PREF and therefore the hitherto proffered calls to ground NWE on opportunities rather than preferences do not withstand scrutiny. Below I support this qualified defence of informed/ideal PREF against three influential objections that leading proponents of OPP put forward against informed/ideal PREF, namely: (4.1) the objection from unfeasible preference reconstruction; (4.2) the objection from paternalism; and (4.3) the objection from contractarianism.Footnote 8

4.1. Objection from unfeasible preference reconstruction

The objection from unfeasible preference reconstruction proceeds as follows. Informed/ideal PREF fit the available empirical findings documenting the inconsistency and the instability of individuals’ actual preferences better than actual PREF (e.g. Salant and Rubinstein Reference Salant and Rubinstein2008; Bernheim and Rangel Reference Bernheim and Rangel2009). However, ‘there is no known psychological foundation’ for informed/ideal PREF’s assumption that individuals have consistent and stable informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare (Infante et al. Reference Infante, Lecouteux and Sugden2016 a: 22, italics added; also Infante et al. Reference Infante, Lecouteux and Sugden2016 b: 34, holding that ‘there is no general reason’ to think that consistent and stable informed/ideal preferences ‘exist at all’). Moreover, even if individuals had consistent and stable informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare, the idea that welfare economists ‘can reconstruct [these] preferences is a mirage’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 14, italics added; also Dold Reference Dold2018). For welfare economists lack the information and the evidence required to reconstruct such preferences (e.g. Rizzo and Whitman Reference Rizzo and Whitman2019: Chs 6–7, on cases where different methods of elicitation elicit dissimilar informed/ideal preferences; also Sugden Reference Sugden2018: Chs 4–5, on putative cases where individuals reveal context-dependent informed/ideal preferences).

This objection correctly notes that welfare economists’ attempts to reconstruct informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare face significant conceptual and practical challenges. Still, there are at least two reasons to doubt that the objection hampers informed/ideal PREF’s potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE. First, informed/ideal PREF do not rest on any psychological assumption as to whether individuals have inner rational agents with informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare. In particular, welfare economists may provide detailed specifications of the conditions under which individuals can be plausibly assumed to have informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare without having to posit any inner agent having such preferences (e.g. Hausman Reference Hausman2016; Beck Reference Beck2022). To be sure, welfare economists often do posit that individuals have ‘some mode of latent reasoning that generates [consistent and stable] preferences’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 62) in their attempts to reconstruct informed/ideal preferences. Yet, welfare economists may consistently posit that individuals have some mode of latent reasoning that generates consistent and stable preferences without having to make any assumption as to what mode of latent reasoning generates such preferences (e.g. Bernheim Reference Bernheim2021). In this respect, it would be overly restrictive to require that welfare economists provide general cross-contextual specifications of what neuro-psychological processes generate consistent and stable preferences. For dissimilar sets of neuro-psychological processes contribute to generate consistent and stable (as opposed to inconsistent and/or unstable) preferences across contexts (e.g. Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2013; Ross Reference Ross2014, for empirically informed criticisms of proposed identifications of the putative neuro-psychological substrates of rational decision making). And informed/ideal PREF frequently enable welfare economists to ground reliable and informative evaluations of policies’ welfare implications without having to draw on specific assumptions concerning what neuro-psychological processes generate consistent and stable preferences (e.g. footnote no. 4 on the welfare evaluations yielded by various model-less approaches).

And second, welfare economists may succeed in reconstructing informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare in a wide range of cases where the targeted individuals fail to exhibit consistent and stable actual preferences (e.g. Chambers and Hayashi Reference Chambers and Hayashi2012, for reconstructions of informed/ideal preferences from non-rationalizable choice data; Nishimura Reference Nishimura2018, for reconstructions of informed/ideal preferences from choice data that reveal a nontransitive preference relation). To be sure, welfare economists may find it unfeasible to reconstruct informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare in presence of widespread choice inconsistencies (e.g. Manzini and Mariotti Reference Manzini and Mariotti2014, on cases where model-less approaches fail to yield welfare rankings because the targeted individuals’ choices vary with changes in ancillary conditions; also Bernheim Reference Bernheim2016, on cases where the reliability of the welfare evaluations grounded on model-based approaches is constrained by the limited reliability of the models posited by such approaches). Still, individuals’ choice inconsistencies are rarely so widespread that they prevent welfare economists from being able to reconstruct informed/ideal preferences (e.g. Ross Reference Ross2011; Bernheim Reference Bernheim2021, on how non-choice data may help welfare economists reconstruct individuals’ informed/ideal preferences in situations where individuals’ observed choices are inconsistent or unstable). That is to say, welfare economists’ attempts to reconstruct informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare typically depend on normative presuppositions (e.g. Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2021, on normative presuppositions about the merits of different theories of welfare). However, this dependence does not reflect limitations inherent in informed/ideal PREF, but rather reflects the thickness of the notion of welfare, i.e. the fact that the notion of welfare involves both positive and normative dimensions and that in ascribing welfare to individuals, one implies that these individuals ‘have something worth having’ (Tiberius Reference Tiberius and Kirchin2013: 217; also footnote no. 1). Moreover, such dependence would not be avoided by grounding NWE on opportunities rather than preferences (e.g. section 3 on the normative presuppositions required to measure and assess the value of individuals’ opportunities).

A proponent of OPP may object that multiple conceptions of preferences have been advocated in the NWE literature and that informed/ideal PREF cannot provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE unless the proponents of informed/ideal PREF specify which conceptions of preferences they endorse (e.g. Lecouteux Reference Lecouteux, Badiei and Grivaux2022, arguing that the merits of different justifications of preference satisfaction as a normative criterion depend on whether one endorses a mentalistic or behaviouristic conception of preferences). This objection correctly notes that the proponents of informed/ideal PREF have to specify which conceptions of preferences they endorse if they are to demonstrate that the satisfaction of the informed/ideal preferences they reconstruct in particular choice settings can be plausibly taken to reliably track or constitute welfare. For multiple conceptions of preference have been advocated in the NWE literature, which sharply disagree concerning the nature of preferences (e.g. Broome Reference Broome, Frey and Morris1993; Hausman Reference Hausman2012: Chs 7–8; Moscati Reference Moscati2021, on the issue of whether preferences are more aptly characterized as judgments or feelings), the causal bases of preferences (e.g. Dietrich and List Reference Dietrich and List2016 a; Ross Reference Ross2011; Guala Reference Guala2019, on the issue of whether preferences are more aptly characterized as mental states, dispositions or behavioural patterns) and the relationship between preferences and choices (e.g. Hands Reference Hands2013; Vredenburgh Reference Vredenburgh2020; Thoma Reference Thoma2021, on the relationship between preferences and actual or hypothetical choices). Even so, it would be misguided to subordinate the justifiability of informed/ideal PREF to the provision of general necessary and sufficient conditions for the notion of preference. For what preferences are plausibly taken to be depends on the theoretical and pragmatic presuppositions of the models and the policy applications where such preferences figure (e.g. Angner Reference Angner2018). And different conceptions of preferences may be suitable for distinct modelling and policy purposes (e.g. Dietrich and List Reference Dietrich and List2016 b). This by no means indicates that all conceptions of preferences are equally plausible or that any such conception can provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE (e.g. Beck Reference Beck2022). Still, neither the availability of multiple conceptions of preferences nor the lack of general necessary and sufficient conditions for the notion of preference per se hampers informed/ideal PREF’s potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE.

4.2. Objection from paternalism

The objection from paternalism proceeds as follows. Suppose, for the sake of argument, that the proponents of informed/ideal PREF are able to reconstruct sets of consistent and stable informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare. On informed/ideal PREF, the inconsistency and the instability of individuals’ actual preferences indicate that ‘individuals [often] make inferior decisions in terms of their own welfare’ (Sunstein and Thaler Reference Sunstein and Thaler2003: 1162; also Thaler and Sunstein Reference Thaler and Sunstein2003; Bubb and Pildes Reference Bubb and Pildes2014). Moreover, according to many proponents of informed/ideal PREF, individuals’ failures to make welfare-enhancing decisions license a wide range of paternalistic interventions, i.e. interventions that ‘violate (or interfere with) the autonomy of their target agents … are implemented without the explicit consent of these agents [and] are designed with the primary aim to enhance the well-being of those agents’ (Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2016: 461; also New Reference New1999: 65; Hausman and Welch Reference Hausman and Welch2010: 126–130). Regrettably, the objection goes, many of these paternalistic interventions are unjustified or otherwise objectionable (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2008; Rizzo and Whitman Reference Rizzo and Whitman2009 b). This, in turn, casts doubt on informed/ideal PREF’s potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE.Footnote 9

This objection correctly notes that leading proponents of paternalistic interventions advocate informed/ideal PREF (e.g. Sunstein and Thaler Reference Sunstein and Thaler2003: 1162, assessing policies’ welfare implications by reference to what preferences individuals would have ‘if they had complete information, unlimited cognitive abilities, and no lack of self-control’; also Sunstein Reference Sunstein2014: 154, advocating interventions designed to ‘move people in the directions that they would go if they were fully rational’). Still, there are at least two reasons to doubt that the objection hampers informed/ideal PREF’s potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE. First, the proponents of the objection have hitherto failed to show that adopting informed/ideal PREF generally leads welfare economists and policymakers to advocate unjustified (or otherwise objectionable) paternalistic interventions. And second, it is dubious that adopting informed/ideal PREF generally leads welfare economists and policymakers to advocate unjustified (or otherwise objectionable) paternalistic interventions. In fact, the proponents of informed/ideal PREF have both welfare-related and non-welfare-related reasons to oppose these interventions. For those interventions often fail to enhance individuals’ welfare compared with a situation where such interventions are not implemented (e.g. Bernheim Reference Bernheim2016; Hausman Reference Hausman2022, on cases where the individuals targeted by paternalistic interventions are better informed about their own welfare than third parties). Moreover, in those cases where paternalistic interventions enhance individuals’ welfare, these interventions frequently involve morally problematic violations of individuals’ autonomy or consent (e.g. Hausman and Welch Reference Hausman and Welch2010; Qizilbash Reference Qizilbash2012). And many proponents of informed/ideal PREF oppose those interventions because of their commitment to respect individuals’ autonomy and consent (e.g. Bernheim Reference Bernheim2009: 291–293; Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2016: 468–471).

A proponent of OPP may object that the commitment of many proponents of informed/ideal PREF to respect individuals’ autonomy and consent frequently conflicts with their aim to enhance individuals’ welfare (e.g. Cowen Reference Cowen1993; Rizzo and Dold Reference Rizzo and Dold2020). The idea is that the proponents of informed/ideal PREF have to relinquish either their commitment to respect individuals’ autonomy and consent (e.g. Sunstein and Thaler Reference Sunstein and Thaler2003: 1167, claiming that ‘it would be fanatical [to treat autonomy] as a kind of trump, not to be overridden’) or their aim to enhance individuals’ welfare (e.g. Le Grand and New Reference Le Grand and New2015: Chs 5–6). However, the proponents of informed/ideal PREF may consistently retain both their commitment to respect individuals’ autonomy and consent and their aim to enhance individuals’ welfare in a wide range of cases, including many cases where individuals’ choices fail to enhance individuals’ own welfare. For the proponents of informed/ideal PREF are not committed to the extreme welfarist position that welfare enhancement is the sole goal of public policy (e.g. footnote no. 2 on the relative importance of welfare enhancement and other policy goals). And respecting individuals’ autonomy and consent does not require the proponents of informed/ideal PREF to relinquish their aim to enhance individuals’ welfare in all cases where their attempts to enhance individuals’ welfare would involve any minor violation of autonomy or consent (e.g. short-term mandatory cooling-off periods that aim to benefit individuals by inducing them to critically reconsider their own decisions), but only requires the proponents of informed/ideal PREF to relinquish such aim in those cases where their attempts to enhance individuals’ welfare would involve morally problematic violations of autonomy or consent (e.g. manipulative subliminal advertising campaigns). That is to say, informed/ideal PREF are compatible with a plurality of positions about the relative importance of welfare enhancement and respect for autonomy and consent (e.g. Rubinstein and Arad Reference Rubinstein and Arad2018; Ferreira Reference Ferreira2022). And pointing to cases where the commitment of many proponents of informed/ideal PREF to respect individuals’ autonomy and consent conflicts with their aim to enhance individuals’ welfare does not per se hamper informed/ideal PREF’s potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE.

A proponent of OPP may further object that the difficulties facing attempts to reconstruct informed/ideal preferences whose satisfaction reliably tracks or constitutes welfare hamper the ability of the proponents of informed/ideal PREF to provide effective safeguards against unjustified (or otherwise objectionable) paternalistic interventions (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2018: Ch. 3). The idea is that in concrete policy contexts it is often unfeasible for policymakers to reconstruct individuals’ informed/ideal preferences and that, as a result, policymakers’ attempts to ‘make choosers better off, as judged by themselves’ (Thaler and Sunstein Reference Thaler and Sunstein2008: 5) frequently end up promoting what policymakers regard as individuals’ welfare. This objection correctly notes that in concrete policy contexts, policymakers frequently end up promoting what they regard as individuals’ welfare rather than what individuals themselves regard as their own welfare (e.g. Hausman and Welch Reference Hausman and Welch2010; Whitman and Rizzo Reference Whitman and Rizzo2015, for illustrations). However, as noted above, the proponents of informed/ideal PREF can provide effective safeguards against unjustified (or otherwise objectionable) paternalistic interventions (e.g. Bernheim Reference Bernheim2009: 291–293; Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2016: 468–471, opposing paternalistic interventions that involve morally problematic violations of individuals’ autonomy or consent; also Bernheim Reference Bernheim2021, proposing to respect individuals’ consistent and stable choices while accepting normative ambiguity when individuals’ inconsistent or unstable choices do not result from demonstrable mistakes). Moreover, the proponents of OPP do not generally provide more effective safeguards against unjustified (or otherwise objectionable) paternalistic interventions than the proponents of informed/ideal PREF (e.g. think of cases where increasing the range of individuals’ opportunities involves trade-offs with other policy goals valued by those individuals). In fact, OPP’s presupposition that ‘it is good that people are free to do what they want, when they want, even if their preferences are unstable’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2007: 678–679) may hamper (rather than enhance) the ability of many proponents of OPP to resist unjustified (or otherwise objectionable) paternalistic interventions that exploit the inconsistency and the instability of people’s preferences (e.g. Qizilbash Reference Qizilbash2012; Sunstein Reference Sunstein2021, for illustrations).

4.3. Objection from contractarianism

The objection from contractarianism proceeds as follows. OPP presuppose a contractarian approach which assesses policies’ welfare implications ‘from the several viewpoints of individual members of society, considered as potential parties to an agreement’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 14, italics added). On this approach, for some agreement to be justified, ‘each party to [the] agreement must recognize that, for all the parties severally, agreement must be more beneficial than non-agreement’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 38, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden1998 b: 60). In particular, to justify her policy recommendations, a contractarian ‘has to show that her recommendations are in the separate interests of each individual, as that individual perceives those interests’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 29, italics added; also Buchanan Reference Buchanan1986: part III). Conversely, informed/ideal PREF assess policies’ welfare implications from the putatively impartial viewpoint of a social planner or choice architect who aims to enhance individuals’ welfare while respecting individuals’ judgements about their own welfare (e.g. Sunstein and Thaler Reference Sunstein and Thaler2003: 1164, holding that a choice architect should ‘give consumers what she thinks they would choose on their own’; also Bernheim and Rangel Reference Bernheim and Rangel2007: 464, holding that a social planner should ‘respect the choices an individual would make for himself’). Regrettably, the objection goes, there is no plausible and informative impartial viewpoint from which policies’ welfare implications may be reliably assessed (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2013, Reference Sugden2018: Chs 2–3). This, in turn, casts doubt on informed/ideal PREF’s potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE.Footnote 10

This objection nicely elucidates the contractarian approach presupposed by OPP. However, there are at least two reasons to doubt that the objection hampers informed/ideal PREF’s potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE. First, as illustrated in sections 3.1–3.2, in concrete policy contexts it is typically unfeasible to show that the proffered policy recommendations are ‘in the separate interest of each individual’ targeted by such recommendations. In this respect, it would be of limited import to object that informed/ideal PREF face similar difficulties since in concrete policy contexts it is often unfeasible to design and implement policies that satisfy the preferences of all the individuals targeted by such policies (e.g. Wilson Reference Wilson2011). For on informed/ideal PREF, public policies that satisfy the preferences of most (but not all) individuals may be justifiable if they do not significantly harm others (e.g. Adler Reference Adler2019: Chs 4–5). And this justification is not available to the proponents of OPP unless they relinquish their requirement to show that policy recommendations are ‘in the separate interest of each individual’ targeted by such recommendations.

And second, OPP do not ‘defend any specific normative proposal about the distribution of [opportunities]’ and do not allow for ‘the analysis of distributional issues’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 47 and 67, italics added; also Sugden Reference Sugden2004: 1020). This concern is exacerbated if one considers the relevant baseline from which OPP measure policies’ welfare implications for each individual targeted by these policies. For this baseline corresponds to individuals’ actual distributions of resources rather than ‘abstract principles of fairness’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 174; also Buchanan Reference Buchanan1972: 127, claiming that ‘we start always from here, not from an original position’). And such baseline is ill-suited to address distributional issues (e.g. if individuals’ actual distributions of resources result from previous injustice, then taking these distributions as the relevant baseline will likely tend to perpetuate injustice). In fact, as acknowledged by leading proponents of OPP (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2018: Ch. 8), the baseline presupposed by OPP sharply differs from the baselines presupposed by other leading contractarian theories (e.g. Qizilbash Reference Qizilbash2021, on Rawls’s theory; also Gauthier Reference Gauthier1986: Chs 5–7, requiring absence of coercion and approximate equality in the relevant baseline). To be sure, my point is not that OPP yield implausible recommendations to a putatively impartial social planner or choice architect. For OPP are not addressed to such planner or choice architect (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 24). Rather, my claim is that OPP yield recommendations that would often be regarded as unjustified (or otherwise objectionable) by many of the individuals targeted by such recommendations (e.g. Arneson Reference Arneson1989; Becker Reference Becker2005, on the tendency of many agreements based on individuals’ actual distributions of resources to unfairly disadvantage the poor and the disabled). And this, in turn, is rather problematic for OPP given OPP’s requirement that a contractarian ‘has to show that [her] recommendations are in the separate interests of each individual, as that individual perceives those interests’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 29, italics added).

A proponent of OPP may object that appeals to distributional issues do not undermine OPP’s potential to provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE since ‘complete equality of opportunity conflicts with’ individuals’ freedom of choice (Sugden Reference Sugden2020: 72), which is ‘what ultimately matters’ according to OPP (McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012: 556). The idea would be that even if one started with a putatively equal distribution of opportunities, inequalities in individuals’ abilities and talents would tend to generate major inequalities in the distribution of resources unless policymakers systematically interfere with individuals’ choices (e.g. Nozick Reference Nozick1974: Ch. 7; also Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 67). For this reason, major inequalities in the distribution of resources may well be regrettable, but do not call for correction (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2004; also Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 106, claiming that a responsible agent ‘accepts sole responsibility for the consequences [of his decisions]’). This objection correctly notes that there are significant trade-offs between equality of opportunity and individuals’ freedom of choice (e.g. Fleurbaey Reference Fleurbaey2012 b). Still, the existence of these trade-offs by no means implies that any major inequalities in the distribution of resources are normatively acceptable (e.g. Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2020). On the contrary, most prominent theories of fairness hold that fairness requires to correct (or at least alleviate) major inequalities in the distribution of resources even if such correction leads to some efficiency losses (e.g. Vallentyne Reference Vallentyne2000; Peragine Reference Peragine2004; Fleurbaey and Maniquet Reference Fleurbaey and Maniquet2011: Chs 2–3). This, in turn, challenges the proponents of OPP to specify why exactly all the theories of fairness that take major inequalities in the distribution of resources to call for correction would be mistaken or otherwise inadequate.Footnote 11

5. Conclusion

In recent years, several prominent authors have criticized welfare economists’ reliance on preference satisfaction as the normative standard for welfare and have advocated grounding NWE on opportunities rather than preferences. In this paper, I argued that although PREF face significant conceptual and practical challenges, OPP fail to provide a more reliable and informative foundation for NWE than PREF. I then identified and rebutted various influential calls to ground NWE on opportunities rather than preferences to support my qualified defence of PREF. This result does not per se exclude the possibility that some further arguments may be articulated which support grounding NWE on opportunities rather than preferences. Still, together with the major challenges that affect OPP, it makes it pressing for the proponents of OPP to articulate and support such arguments.

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Lukas Beck, Malte Dold, Marco Mariotti, Paolo Piacquadio, Robert Sugden, Jack Vromen, two anonymous reviewers and Matthew Adler (Editor of this journal) for their comments on previous versions of this paper. I also received helpful feedback from audiences at the University of Tokyo, the University of Urbino, the 15th Biennial Meeting of the International Network for Economic Method (Arizona State University), the conference ‘Preferences, Commitments and Choice’ (University of Zurich), the University of Pennsylvania, Blackfriars Hall (University of Oxford), the Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics (University of Oxford), the University of Helsinki and the 3rd Public Policy and Regulation Workshop (King’s College London).

Competing interests

The Author declares none.

Funding declaration

I acknowledge the support of the Centre for the Study of Governance and Society (King’s College London) and the John Templeton Foundation, ‘Political Economy of Knowledge and Ignorance’, Grant #61823.

Roberto Fumagalli is Senior Lecturer and Director of the Public Policy MA Program at King’s College London, and has research affiliations with the London School of Economics and the University of Pennsylvania. His research interests encompass a wide range of areas, including philosophy of economics, philosophy of science, moral and political philosophy, and philosophy and public policy. He has published articles in several international journals besides Economics and Philosophy, including Philosophical Studies, Philosophy of Science, Biology and Philosophy, Erkenntnis, Theory and Decision, Social Choice and Welfare, Journal of Social Philosophy, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Moral Philosophy and Politics, Bioethics, Public Health Ethics, Synthese, Philosophy, Studia Leibnitiana, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, and Journal of Economic Methodology.

Footnotes

1 I use the expression ‘normative welfare economics’ broadly to designate the wide range of studies in normative economics concerned with measuring welfare and with assessing policies’ welfare implications. This broad use of ‘normative welfare economics’ includes both welfarist and non-welfarist approaches to normative economics. Also, I speak of ‘well-being’ and ‘welfare’ interchangeably to refer to prudential value – i.e. what is non-instrumentally good for individuals (e.g. Griffin Reference Griffin1986: part I; Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2022) – as opposed to other kinds of value (e.g. Sumner Reference Sumner1996: Ch. 1, on moral and aesthetic value). Some welfare economists advocate mental state theories of welfare (e.g. Clark et al. Reference Clark, Flèche, Layard, Powdthavee and Ward2018, on hedonic theories) and objective list theories of welfare (e.g. Nussbaum Reference Nussbaum2000, on the capability approach) rather than preference satisfaction theories. Still, most contemporary welfare economists regard preference satisfaction as a major constituent or indicator of welfare (e.g. Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2021; Ferreira Reference Ferreira2022).

2 My evaluation of PREF and OPP focuses on welfare enhancement rather than other policy goals. Welfare enhancement is not the only goal of public policy (e.g. section 4 on distributive justice), and different authors ascribe dissimilar relevance to welfare enhancement versus other policy goals (e.g. Adler Reference Adler2012; Khosrowi Reference Khosrowi2019; also Sugden Reference Sugden, Hamlin and Pettit1989, arguing that it is not governments’ business to maximize social welfare). Still, most authors in the NWE literature agree that welfare enhancement is a significant goal of public policy in the sense that (other things being equal) policymakers should favour policies that enhance (rather than hamper) individuals’ welfare (e.g. Adler and Fleurbaey Reference Adler and Fleurbaey2016; Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2021).

3 I speak of ‘informed/ideal preferences’ broadly to encompass a wide range of notions of preference figuring in the NWE literature, including what various authors call ‘true preferences’, ‘latent preferences’ and ‘purified preferences’ (section 4). Different accounts of informed/ideal preferences require preferences to satisfy dissimilar conditions to qualify as informed/ideal. Still, all these accounts posit a set of preferences that are conceptually distinct from actual preferences. I shall expand on the dissimilarities between different accounts of informed/ideal preferences whenever such dissimilarities directly bear on my evaluation of PREF.

4 I am not concerned in this paper with assessing the merits of specific model-less and model-based approaches. For my evaluation, the following remarks about the contributions cited in the main text suffice. Bernheim and Rangel (Reference Bernheim and Rangel2009: 55) develop a framework for reconstructing informed/ideal preferences in settings where individuals’ choices depend on ancillary conditions, i.e. ‘feature[s] of the choice environment that may affect behaviour, but [are] not taken as relevant to a social planner’s evaluation’. Salant and Rubinstein (Reference Salant and Rubinstein2008: 1287) develop a framework for reconstructing informed/ideal preferences in presence of framing effects including ‘observable information that is irrelevant in the rational assessment of the alternatives, but nonetheless affects choice’. Manzini and Mariotti (Reference Manzini and Mariotti2014: 344) develop a framework for reconstructing informed/ideal preferences in settings where ‘the same choice data can have different welfare implications according to the cognitive process that has generated them’ and welfare inferences are grounded on specific models (e.g. Manzini and Mariotti Reference Manzini and Mariotti2013, on models of imperfect attention). Rubinstein and Salant (Reference Rubinstein and Salant2012: 375) develop a framework for reconstructing informed/ideal preferences in settings where ‘observed preference orderings [vary as the result] of some cognitive process that distorts the underlying preferences’.

5 A proponent of OPP may object that OPP occasionally juxtapose opportunities and welfare besides juxtaposing opportunities and preferences (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 57) and that according to OPP ‘opportunity is normatively prior to welfare’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2021: 419). However, as indicated by the several passages cited in this section, OPP predominantly juxtapose opportunities and preferences (rather than opportunities and welfare). Moreover, if OPP aimed to relinquish NWE’s focus on welfare (besides its focus on preferences), then several concerns about the value of opportunities and their relevance for normative economic analysis would become even more pressing (sections 3.2–3.3). In fact, the claim that NWE should relinquish its focus on welfare (besides its focus on preferences) would constitute a radical departure from NWE (e.g. Angner Reference Angner and Fletcher2016) and would fail to fit many authors’ agreement that welfare enhancement is a significant goal of public policy in the sense specified in footnote no. 2.

6 A proponent of OPP may object that ‘the benefits that any individual can derive from his opportunities depend on [her] real income” and that “given the background condition of competitive markets’, a real-income measure gives us ‘what we might want of a measurement of opportunity’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2010: 49 and 66; also Sugden Reference Sugden2004). However, the ‘background condition of competitive markets’ frequently fails to hold (e.g. Satz Reference Satz2010; Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2020), and the objection does not specify how welfare economists and policymakers should measure opportunity in the vast number of real-life situations where such background condition fails to hold.

7 A proponent of OPP may defend OPP’s claim that opportunities have intrinsic value on the alleged ground that ‘opportunities to make sequences of [choices] have positive value, even if … those sequences lead to unambiguous loss’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2007: 665; McQuillin and Sugden Reference McQuillin and Sugden2012: 564). The idea would be that an individual who incurs an unambiguous loss may still ‘say that she has done what she wanted to do, when she wanted to do it [and] that it was in her interests that she was able to do this’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 105). Yet, as leading proponents of OPP concede, substantiating OPP’s claim that opportunities have intrinsic value requires the proponents of OPP to provide ‘a criterion of individual interest that each individual can endorse’ (Sugden Reference Sugden2015: 299). And the proponents of OPP have hitherto failed to provide such criterion (e.g. Sunstein Reference Sunstein2021: 406).

8 My qualified defence focuses on informed/ideal PREF (rather than actual PREF) both because few authors in the contemporary NWE literature endorse actual PREF and because there are several reasons to doubt that actual PREF provide a reliable and informative foundation for NWE (section 2).

9 The definition of paternalistic interventions provided in the main text allows that paternalistic interventions are frequently unjustified or otherwise objectionable, but does not characterize paternalistic interventions as generally unjustified or otherwise objectionable (e.g. Schmidt Reference Schmidt2017; Teira Reference Teira2020). In fact, several authors (including many critics of paternalism) call to assess the justifiability of paternalistic interventions on a case-by-case basis or at least in terms of the different types of interference they involve (e.g. Le Grand and New Reference Le Grand and New2015: Chs 3–5; Bernheim Reference Bernheim2016, on the comparative merits of ‘means’ paternalistic interventions and ‘ends’ paternalistic interventions in public policy). I expand on the justifiability of various paternalistic interventions in the course of this subsection.

10 The objection from contractarianism targets not only informed/ideal PREF, but also accounts that invoke an ‘impartial spectator’ in the context of an opportunity-based view of NWE (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 24–28, criticizing Sen’s Reference Sen1999 assessment of policies’ welfare implications from the perspective of an impartial spectator as a ‘view from nowhere’). I focus on the putative implications of the objection from contractarianism for informed/ideal PREF (as opposed to accounts that invoke an impartial spectator in the context of an opportunity-based view of NWE) for the purpose of my qualified defence of informed/ideal PREF.

11 A proponent of OPP may object that OPP allow for the possibility of adopting redistributive policies (e.g. various forms of social insurance) to ensure that all citizens benefit from social arrangements and are compensated for brute bad luck (e.g. Sugden Reference Sugden2018: 204). However, appeals to the possibility of adopting redistributive policies would stand in profound tension with OPP’s assumption that the relevant baseline from which to measure policies’ welfare implications corresponds to individuals’ actual distributions of resources. For in concrete policy contexts, significant redistribution would be commonly required to ensure that all citizens benefit from social arrangements and are compensated for brute bad luck, and the baseline presupposed by OPP licenses only minimal levels of redistribution (e.g. Guala Reference Guala2021: 90–94, for illustrations).

References

Adler, M. 2012. Well-Being and Fair Distribution: Beyond Cost-Benefit Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Adler, M. 2013. Happiness surveys and public policy: what’s the use? Duke Law Journal 62, 15091601.Google Scholar
Adler, M. 2019. Measuring Social Welfare: An Introduction. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adler, M. and Fleurbaey, M., eds. 2016. Oxford Handbook of Well-Being and Public Policy. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Angner, E. 2016. Well-being and economics. In The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-being, ed. Fletcher, G., 492503. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Angner, E. 2018. What preferences really are. Philosophy of Science 85, 660681.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 1989. Equality and equal opportunity for welfare. Philosophical Studies 56, 7793.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 1999. Equality of opportunity for welfare defended and recanted. Journal of Political Philosophy 7, 488497.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-Gill, O. 2012. Seduction by Contract: Law, Economics, and Psychology in Consumer Markets. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bavetta, S., Navarra, P. and Maimone, D. 2014. Freedom and the Pursuit of Happiness: An Economic and Political Perspective. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bavetta, S., Maimone, D., Miller, P. and Navarra, P. 2017. More choice for better choosers: political freedom, autonomy, and happiness. Political Studies 65, 316338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beck, L. 2022. The Econ within or the Econ above? On the plausibility of preference purification. Economics and Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267122000141.Google Scholar
Becker, L. 2005. Reciprocity, justice, and disability. Ethics 116, 939.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bernheim, B.D. 2009. Behavioral welfare economics. Journal of the European Economic Association 7, 267319.10.1162/JEEA.2009.7.2-3.267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernheim, B.D. 2016. The good, the bad, and the ugly: a unified approach to behavioral welfare economics. Journal of Benefit-Cost Analysis 7, 1268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernheim, B.D. 2021. In defense of behavioral welfare economics. Journal of Economic Methodology 28, 385400.10.1080/1350178X.2021.1988133CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernheim, B.D. and Rangel, A. 2004. Addiction and cue-triggered decision processes. American Economic Review 94, 15581590.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bernheim, B.D. and Rangel, A. 2007. Toward choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. American Economic Review 97, 464470.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernheim, B.D. and Rangel, A. 2009. Beyond revealed preference: choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. Quarterly Journal of Economics 124, 51104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bervoets, S. and Gravel, N. 2007. Appraising diversity with an ordinal notion of similarity: an axiomatic approach. Mathematical Social Sciences 53, 259273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bicchieri, C. 2017. Norms in the Wild: How to Diagnose, Measure, and Change Social Norms. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K. 1994. Game Theory and the Social Contract, Vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 1993. Can a Humean be moderate? In Value, Welfare and Morality, eds. Frey, R. and Morris, C., 5173. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bubb, R. and Pildes, R. 2014. How behavioral economics trims its sails and why. Harvard Law Review 127, 15931678.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J. 1972. Rawls on justice as fairness. Public Choice 13, 123128.10.1007/BF01718857CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J. 1986. Liberty, Market and State. New York, NY: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Camerer, C. and Loewenstein, G. 2004. Behavioral economics: past, present, future. In Advances in Behavioral Economics, eds. Camerer, C., Loewenstein, G. and Rabin, M., 351. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, I. 1999. A Measure of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chambers, C. and Hayashi, T. 2012. Choice and individual welfare. Journal of Economic Theory 147, 18181849.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, A., Flèche, S., Layard, R., Powdthavee, N. and Ward, G. 2018. The Origins of Happiness: The Science of Well-Being over the Life Course. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cowen, T. 1993. The scope and limits of preference sovereignty. Economics and Philosophy 9, 253269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F. 2018. Savage’s theorem under changing awareness. Journal of Economic Theory 176, 154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. 2011. A model of non-informational preference change. Journal of Theoretical Politics 23, 145164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. 2016 a. Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: a philosophy-of-science perspective. Economics and Philosophy 32, 249281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. 2016 b. Reason-based choice and context dependence: an explanatory framework. Economics and Philosophy 32, 175229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dold, M. 2018. Back to Buchanan? Explorations of welfare and subjectivism in behavioral economics. Journal of Economic Methodology 2, 160178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dold, M. and Rizzo, M. 2021. The limits of opportunity-only: context dependence and agency in behavioral welfare economics. Journal of Economic Methodology 28, 364373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dold, M. and Schubert, C. 2018. Toward a behavioral foundation of normative economics. Review of Behavioral Economics 5, 221241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dowding, K. and Oprea, A. 2022. Nudges, regulations and liberty. British Journal of Political Science. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123421000685.Google Scholar
Ferreira, J. 2022. Which choices merit deference? A comparison of three behavioural proxies of subjective welfare. Economics and Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267121000365.Google Scholar
Fleurbaey, M. 2012 a. The importance of what people care about. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 11, 415447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleurbaey, M. 2012 b. Equal opportunity, reward and respect for preferences: reply to Roemer. Economics and Philosophy 28, 201216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleurbaey, M. and Maniquet, F. 2011. A Theory of Fairness and Social Welfare. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fleurbaey, M. and Peragine, V. 2013. Ex ante versus ex post equality of opportunity. Economica 80, 118130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2013. The futile search for true utility. Economics and Philosophy 29, 325347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2016. Decision sciences and the new case for paternalism: three welfare-related justificatory challenges. Social Choice and Welfare 47, 459480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2019. (F)utility exposed. Philosophy of Science 86, 955966.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2020. Buyer beware: a critique of leading virtue ethics defenses of markets. Journal of Social Philosophy 51, 457482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2021. Theories of well-being and well-being policy: a view from methodology. Journal of Economic Methodology 28, 124133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2022. A reformed division of labor for the science of well-being. Philosophy 97, 509543.10.1017/S0031819122000092CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. 1986. Well-Being: Its Measure and Importance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Guala, F. 2019. Preferences: neither behavioural nor mental. Economics and Philosophy 35, 383401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guala, F. 2021. Behavioural politics: social insurance and mutual benefit in Robert Sugden’s The Community of Advantage. International Review of Economics 68, 89100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gul, F. and Pesendorfer, W. 2008. The case for mindless economics. In The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics: A Handbook, eds. Caplin, A. and Schotter, A., 342. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hands, W. 2013. Foundations of contemporary revealed preference theory. Erkenntnis 78, 10811108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harless, P. and Pancs, R. 2022. A review of Robert Sugden’s Community of Advantage . Journal of Economic Literature 60, 233255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. 1995. A theory of prudential values and a rule utilitarian theory of morality. Social Choice and Welfare 12, 319333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. 1997. Utilities, preferences and substantive goods. Social Choice and Welfare 14, 129145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. 2010. Hedonism and welfare economics. Economics and Philosophy 26, 321344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. 2011. Mistakes about preferences in the social sciences. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41, 325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. 2012. Preference, Value, Choice, and Welfare. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. 2016. On the Econ within. Journal of Economic Methodology 23, 2632.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. 2022. Enhancing welfare without a theory of welfare. Behavioural Public Policy, 6, 342357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. and McPherson, M. 2009. Preference satisfaction and welfare economics. Economics and Philosophy 25, 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. and Welch, B. 2010. Debate: to nudge or not to nudge. Journal of Political Philosophy 18, 123136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haybron, D. and Tiberius, V. 2015. Well-being policy: what standard of well-being? Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1, 712733.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hersch, G. 2020. No theory-free lunches in well-being policy. Philosophical Quarterly 70, 4364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Infante, G., Lecouteux, G. and Sugden, R. 2016 a. Preference purification and the inner rational agent: a critique of the conventional wisdom of behavioural welfare economics. Journal of Economic Methodology 23, 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Infante, G., Lecouteux, G. and Sugden, R. 2016 b. On the Econ within: a reply to Daniel Hausman. Journal of Economic Methodology 23, 3337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. 2003. A psychological perspective on economics. American Economic Review 93, 162168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. and Sugden, R. 2005. Experienced utility as a standard of policy evaluation. Environmental and Resource Economics 32, 161181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khosrowi, D. 2019. Trade-offs between epistemic and moral values in evidence-based policy. Economics and Philosophy 35, 4978.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lecouteux, G. 2022. Reconciling normative and behavioural economics: the problem that cannot be solved. In The Positive and the Normative in Economic Thought, eds. Badiei, S. and Grivaux, A., 148166. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Grand, J. and New, B. 2015. Government Paternalism: Nanny State or Helpful Friend? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Manzini, P. and Mariotti, M. 2012. Categorize then choose: boundedly rational choice and welfare. Journal of the European Economic Association 10, 9391213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manzini, P. and Mariotti, M. 2013. Stochastic choice and consideration sets. Econometrica 82, 11531176.Google Scholar
Manzini, P. and Mariotti, M. 2014. Welfare economics and bounded rationality: the case for model-based approaches. Journal of Economic Methodology 21, 343360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McQuillin, B. and Sugden, R. 2012. Reconciling normative and behavioural economics: the problems to be solved. Social Choice and Welfare 38, 553567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moscati, I. 2021. On the recent philosophy of decision theory. Journal of Economic Methodology 28, 98106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nehring, K. and Puppe, C. 2002. A theory of diversity. Econometrica 70, 11551198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
New, B. 1999. Paternalism and public policy. Economics and Philosophy 15, 6383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nishimura, H. 2018. The transitive core: inference of welfare from nontransitive preference relations. Theoretical Economics 13, 579606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 2000. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2011. Neurobiology of economic choice: a good-based model. Annual Review of Neuroscience 34, 333359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pattanaik, P. and Xu, Y. 1990. On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice. Récherches Economiques de Louvain 56, 383390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pattanaik, P. and Xu, Y. 2000. On diversity and freedom of choice. Mathematical Social Sciences 30, 123130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peragine, V. 2004. Measuring and implementing equality of opportunity for income. Social Choice and Welfare 22, 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piacquadio, P. 2017. A fairness justification of utilitarianism. Econometrica 85, 12611276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qizilbash, M. 2012. Informed desire and the ambitions of libertarian paternalism. Social Choice and Welfare 38, 647658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qizilbash, M. 2021. Informed preference consequentialism, contractarianism and libertarian paternalism. International Review of Economics 68, 6788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabin, M. 2002. A perspective on psychology and economics. European Economic Review 46, 657685.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rizzo, M. and Dold, M. 2020. Can a contractarian be a paternalist? Public Choice 183, 495507.10.1007/s11127-020-00804-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rizzo, M. and Whitman, D. 2009 a. The knowledge problem of the new paternalism. Brigham Young University Law Review 4, 905968.Google Scholar
Rizzo, M. and Whitman, D. 2009 b. Little brother is watching you: new paternalism on the slippery slopes. Arizona Law Review 51, 685739.Google Scholar
Rizzo, M. and Whitman, D. 2019. Escaping Paternalism: Rationality, Behavioral Economics, and Public Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roemer, J. 1998. Equality of Opportunity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roemer, J. and Trannoy, A. 2016. Equality of opportunity: theory and measurement. Journal of Economic Literature 54, 12881332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, D. 2011. Estranged parents and a schizophrenic child: choice in economics, psychology and neuroeconomics. Journal of Economic Methodology 18, 217231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, D. 2014. Psychological versus economic models of bounded rationality. Journal of Economic Methodology 21, 411427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rubinstein, A. and Arad, A. 2018. The people’s perspective on libertarian-paternalistic policies. Journal of Law and Economics 61, 311333.Google Scholar
Rubinstein, A. and Salant, Y. 2012. Eliciting welfare preferences from behavioral datasets. Review of Economic Studies 79, 375387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salant, Y. and Rubinstein, A. 2008. (A, f): choice with frames. Review of Economic Studies 75, 12871296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarch, A. 2015. Hausman and McPherson on welfare economics and preference satisfaction theories of welfare: a critical note. Economics and Philosophy 31, 141159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Satz, D. 2010. Why Some Things Should not be for Sale: The Moral Limits of Markets. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmidt, A. 2017. The power to nudge. American Political Science Review 111, 404417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schubert, C. 2015. Opportunity and preference learning. Economics and Philosophy 31, 275295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schubert, C. and Cordes, C. 2013. Role models that make you unhappy: light paternalism, social learning and welfare. Journal of Institutional Economics 9, 131159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A.K. 1985. Well-being, agency, and freedom: the Dewey Lectures, 1984. Journal of Philosophy 82, 169221.Google Scholar
Sen, A.K. 1991. Welfare, preference and freedom. Journal of Econometrics 50, 1529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A.K. 1999. Development as Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A.K. 2002. Rationality and Freedom. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sobel, D. 1994. Full information accounts of well-being. Ethics 104, 784810.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, D. 2009. Subjectivism and idealization. Ethics 119, 336352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stewart, F. 2005. Groups and capabilities. Journal of Human Development 6, 185204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 1989. Maximizing social welfare: is it the government’s business? In The Good Polity: Normative Analysis of the State, eds. Hamlin, A. and Pettit, P., 6986. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. 1991. Rational choice: a survey of contributions from economics and philosophy. The Economic Journal 101, 751785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 1998a. The metric of opportunity. Economics and Philosophy 14, 307337.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. 1998b. Measuring opportunity: toward a contractarian measure of individual interest. Social Philosophy and Policy 15, 3460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2003. Opportunity as a space for individuality: its value, and the impossibility of measuring it. Ethics 113, 783809.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2004. The opportunity criterion: consumer sovereignty without the assumption of coherent preferences. American Economic Review 94, 10141033.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2006. Taking unconsidered preferences seriously. In Preferences and Well-being, ed. Olsaretti, S., 209232. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2007. The value of opportunities over time when preferences are unstable. Social Choice and Welfare 29, 665682.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2008. Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism. Constitutional Political Economy 19, 226248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2010. Opportunity as mutual advantage. Economics and Philosophy 26, 4768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2013. The behavioural economist and the social planner: to whom should behavioural welfare economics be addressed? Inquiry 56, 519538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2015. Opportunity and preference learning: a reply to Christian Schubert. Economics and Philosophy 31, 297303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2018. The Community of Advantage: A Behavioural Economist’s Defence of the Market. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2020. The Community of Advantage: an interview with Robert Sugden. Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 13, 6178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2021. A response to six comments on The Community of Advantage. Journal of Economic Methodology 28, 419430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sumner, L. 1996. Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. 2014. Why Nudge? The Politics of Libertarian Paternalism. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. 2021. Voluntary agreements. Journal of Economic Methodology 28, 401408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, C. and Thaler, R. 2003. Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. University of Chicago Law Review 70, 11591202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suzumura, K. and Xu, Y. 2009. Consequentialism and non-consequentialism. In The Handbook of Rational and Social Choice, eds. Anand, P., Pattanaik, P. and Puppe, C., 346373. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teira, T. 2020. A defence of pharmaceutical paternalism. Journal of Applied Philosophy 37, 528542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. and Sunstein, C. 2003. Libertarian paternalism. American Economic Review 93, 175179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. and Sunstein, C. 2008. Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth, and Happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Thoma, J. 2021. In defence of revealed preference theory. Economics and Philosophy 37, 163187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tiberius, V. 2013. Well-being, wisdom and thick theorizing. In Thick Concepts, ed. Kirchin, S., 217234. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. 1981. The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 211, 453458.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vallentyne, P. 2000. Equality, efficiency, and priority for the worse off. Economics and Philosophy 16, 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vallentyne, P. 2002. Brute luck, option luck, and equality of initial opportunities. Ethics 112, 529557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vallentyne, P. 2005. Debate: capabilities versus opportunities for well-being. Journal of Political Philosophy 13, 359371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Hees, M. 2004. Freedom of choice and diversity of options: some difficulties. Social Choice and Welfare 22, 253266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Hees, M. 2010. The specific value of freedom. Social Choice and Welfare 35, 687703.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vredenburgh, K. 2020. A unificationist defence of revealed preferences. Economics and Philosophy 36, 149169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vromen, J. 2022. Does the inclusion of social preferences in economic models challenge the positive – normative distinction? In Methodology and History of Economics. Reflections with and without Rules, ed. Caldwell, B., Davis, J., Mäki, U. and Sent, E., 218240. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Weitzman, M. 1992. On diversity. Quarterly Journal of Economics 107, 363405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitman, D. and Rizzo, M. 2015. The problematic welfare standards of behavioral paternalism. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6, 409425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, J. 2011. Why it’s time to stop worrying about paternalism in health policy. Public Health Ethics 4, 269279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar