Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T08:09:38.609Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On the probability and direction of morphosyntactic lifespan change

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 May 2022

Lauren Fonteyn*
Affiliation:
Centre for Linguistics, Leiden University, Leiden
Peter Petré
Affiliation:
Department of Linguistics, University of Antwerp
*
*Corresponding author. E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The aim of this study is to further contribute to the ongoing debate regarding the nature of “morphosyntactic lifespan change,” defined here as observable shifts in the grammatical choices individuals make between competing morphosyntactic structures. Through a quantitative case study of competition between two types of ing-nominals in seventeenth-century English, in which we factor in the grammatical contexts in which the variant structures can be used, we show that individuals vary in the extent to which they participate in the contextual diffusion of a new structure. We furthermore show that there is interindividual variability with respect to whether and what kind of lifespan change—frequency, constraint, and inventory change—is attested and highlight different patterns of intraindividual change: progressive, retrograde, and “mixed.”

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

The question of whether individual language users modify their internalized grammatical system during adulthood is one that has long divided linguists of different theoretical persuasions. On the one hand, usage-based models of language tend to consider language as an inherently “adaptive” system that is in a constant state of change, both at the individual and the community level (Diessel, Reference Diessel2019). In such models, the linguistic behavior of individuals is considered to be based on the rules they have inducted from “the frequency of the different expressions and constructions encountered by the speaker” during the past social interactions they have had with other individuals (Barlow, Reference Barlow2013:444; also see Beckner, Blythe, Bybee, Christiansen, Croft, Ellis, Holland, Ke, Larsen-Freeman, & Schoenemann, Reference Beckner, Blythe, Bybee, Christiansen, Croft, Ellis, Holland, Ke, Larsen-Freeman and Schoenemann2009:14). Importantly, these utterance production rules inducted from language use are, essentially, never entirely fixed and can be affected by every new instance of language use the individual encounters (Bybee, Reference Bybee2006). Thus, the idea that an individual's internalized grammar is susceptible to change lies at the core of the utterance-based (Croft, Reference Croft2000:45-55) or usage-based model, in which the “current and past interactions [of individual language users] together feed forward into [their] future behavior” (Beckner et al., Reference Beckner, Blythe, Bybee, Christiansen, Croft, Ellis, Holland, Ke, Larsen-Freeman and Schoenemann2009:2).

On the other hand, there are various theoretical models of language where grammar, at least at the level of the individual speaker, is conceived as a relatively fixed system. Such models are often (but not exclusively) characterized by a more modular or componential view of language, wherein the linguistic knowledge of individuals comprises a lexicon and a separate rule system (or “grammar”) that generates the syntactic patterns in which lexical items can be inserted. With respect to the possibility of language change across the individual's lifespan then, it is generally held that modifications in the lexicon are not restricted by age (Kerswill, Reference Kerswill1996; Meisel, Elsig, & Rinke, Reference Meisel, Elsig and Rinke2013:26). By contrast, more “systemic changes” that affect the rule system that generates grammatical sentences, “only take place in the process of the transmission and incrementation of a change, that is, during childhood” (Meisel et al., Reference Meisel, Elsig and Rinke2013:37), when the grammatical system is imperfectly transmitted from parent to child (for recent proponents, see Anderson [Reference Anderson2016], Lightfoot [Reference Lightfoot2019]). Systemic (e.g., morphosyntactic) change through time is thus conceptualized as “merely a function of changes in the population, with older speakers becoming inactive and dying, and younger speakers continually entering the community” (Denison, Reference Denison and Hickey2002:61). Such models of language change, which have been proposed since at least the late nineteenth century (López-Couso, Reference López-Couso, Hundt, Mollin and Pfenninger2017:339), conceptualize grammatical change as being child-based (or, at least, child-centered) rather than utterance-based.

At the same time, the two types of models are not always at odds. Both the utterance-based model and current versions of the child-based model would, for instance, accept that it is possible for adults to participate in lexical or so-called “surface structure changes,” such as the replacement of the Early Modern English third-person suffix -(e)th by -(e)s (Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg2005), or cases of competition between different pronominal forms (e.g., Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Nevala and Palander-Collin2009). Furthermore, there is also consensus on the idea that, in cases of competition between mutually exclusive structural properties that relate to different grammars generating them (e.g., presence or absence of do-support in different clause types [e.g., Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Nevala and Palander-Collin2009]), adults freely (and frequently) change the rate by which they use either the old or the new system. In a wide range of studies, it has been shown that “adult frequencies of linguistic forms are labile” (Tagliamonte & D'Arcy, Reference Tagliamonte and D'Arcy2007:213; in reference to Labov, Reference Labov2001:447), empirically confirming that the language of adults, including the frequency with which they employ one morphosyntactic “rule” over another (or others), is not fixed in quantitative terms (Bergs, Reference Bergs2005; Buchstaller, Reference Buchstaller2015, Reference Buchstaller2016; Nahkola & Saanilahti, Reference Nahkola and Saanilahti2004; Neels, Reference Neels2020; Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg2005, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Nevala and Palander-Collin2009; Raumolin-Brunberg & Nurmi, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Narrog and Heine2011; Sharma, Bresnan, & Deo, Reference Sharma, Bresnan, Deo, Cooper and Kempson2008).

Having established that the grammar of adults can and does change in quantitative terms, the focus of the discussion on adult lifespan change has subsequently shifted to the question of whether adult grammar can also be altered in “qualitative terms.” Notably, it has proven much more difficult to attest instances of what is termed “core” grammatical change, which would involve a more or less radical change “from one invariable and uniform grammatical system to another” (Meisel et al., Reference Meisel, Elsig and Rinke2013:30) in adulthood (also see the comments in Raumolin-Brunberg [Reference Raumolin-Brunberg2005:47], [Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Nevala and Palander-Collin2009:192]). Within the variationist tradition, such radical categorical changes have, to our knowledge, not yet been documented. However, some studies have reported on partial categorical or “inventory” changes (Buchstaller, Krause-Lerche, & Mechler, Reference Buchstaller, Krause-Lerche, Mechler, Beaman and Buchstaller2021), where a novel form is introduced or is used in a novel way (or an older form or usage ceases to be used). Petré and Van de Velde (Reference Petré and Van de Velde2018) and Anthonissen and Petré (Reference Anthonissen and Petré2019) found that novel, grammaticalized uses of infinitive be going to are (to a limited extent) adopted in adulthood by speakers who previously only had the lexical use of infinitive be going to in their repertoire. Furthermore, adults may adopt uses that are more advanced on the grammaticalization scale than those in their repertoire, which may signal that usage constraints of grammatical patterns change qualitatively across the lifespan. A recent example includes the constraint change and inventory change in, among other variables, individuals’ systems of quotation reported in Buchstaller et al.'s (Reference Buchstaller, Krause-Lerche, Mechler, Beaman and Buchstaller2021) panel study. Such findings seem to call for amendment of the conclusions by Tagliamonte and D'Arcy (Reference Tagliamonte and D'Arcy2007:210), who observe changes in the constraints on the use of be like between generations, but not within generations.

The aim of this paper is to further contribute to the ongoing debate on morphosyntactic lifespan change, defined here as observable intraindividual shifts in the grammatical choices individuals make between functionally equivalent (or competing) structures. We focus on an ongoing change involving two types of ing-nominals in seventeenth-century English, using statistical model comparison.

Our first hypothesis is defined simply to corroborate earlier findings on frequency-based change, which state that when a competition-driven syntactic change is taking place in a linguistic community, individuals in that community will change the frequency or rate by which they use the competing syntactic structures across their lifespan (Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg2005, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Nevala and Palander-Collin2009). Furthermore, based on earlier studies, we hypothesize that these changes in frequency will predominantly proceed in the direction of the ongoing change in the rest of the community (Anthonissen, Reference Anthonissen2020:325; Baxter & Croft, Reference Baxter and Croft2016:156; Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Nevala and Palander-Collin2009:170).

A second hypothesis is formulated to assess how gradual contextual diffusion, through which syntactic changes often proceed at the community level, recurs in the linguistic behavior of individuals. Population-level studies have amply demonstrated that innovative grammatical structures tend to diffuse gradually from one grammatical context to another (e.g., Kroch, Reference Kroch1989; Rutten & van der Wal, Reference Rutten, van der Wal, Boogaert, Colleman and Rutten2014; Smirnova, Reference Smirnova, Barđdal, Smirnova, Sommerer and Gildea2015; Tagliamonte & Denis, Reference Tagliamonte and Denis2016; Traugott & Trousdale, Reference Traugott and Trousdale2013). Innovative variants tend to emerge in specific contexts and only after they become sufficiently frequent or entrenched in those contexts do they “spark off the innovations that constitute the following stage” (De Smet, Reference De Smet2016:100). Studies that consider such stepwise patterns of diffusion at the level of the individual are relatively rare, but it has tentatively been argued that the “innovation-entrenchment-further innovation” trajectory observable in population-level language also exists “in patterns of variation across individual speakers” (De Smet, Reference De Smet2016:100). By examining the frequency by which individuals adopt innovative variants in different grammatical contexts, we can help determine the extent to which this hypothesis holds true and whether the rate with which the variants occur in these contexts is comparable across individuals.

A third hypothesis we assess is that adults can participate in the diffusion of the new variant to new grammatical contexts and reach a more advanced stage of the development occurring at the community level (for similar endeavors, see Anthonissen & Petré, Reference Anthonissen and Petré2019; Buchstaller et al., Reference Buchstaller, Krause-Lerche, Mechler, Beaman and Buchstaller2021; De Smet, Reference De Smet2016; Mackenzie, Reference MacKenzie2019; Tagliamonte & D'Arcy, Reference Tagliamonte and D'Arcy2007:213). In investigating this hypothesis with real-time data, we provide some tentative (and relatively rare, see Mackenzie [Reference MacKenzie2019:17]) support for the idea that the grammar of adults may be susceptible to qualitative lifespan change if qualitative lifespan change is defined as changes in the grammatical contexts or constraints under which competing morphosyntactic constructions are used by each individual across their lifespan.

Data and method

Early Modern English ing-nominals

The case study chosen to address the issues at hand is the diachronically unstable variation between two types of English ing-nominals, illustrated in (1) and (2):

  1. (1) Idolatry consists in giving of that worship which is due to God, to that which is not God. (EMMA, Daniel Whitby, 1674)

  2. (2) … the greatest part of Leviticus is imploy'd in giving Laws concerning Sacrifices (EMMA, Daniel Whitby, 1697)

The two types of ing-nominals in (1) and (2) exemplify a well-known case of morphosyntactic variation in the Early Modern English period, whereby two different syntactic structures can be used largely interchangeably: in both examples, a derivational suffix -ing is attached to a base verb (i.e., give) to create a deverbal noun phrase that behaves much like other, more prototypical English noun phrases. The main difference between the examples in (1) and (2) appears to be that, in example (1), the object of giving occurs as an of-phrase, whereas the structure in (2) does not require an of-phrase. In terms of their contextual distribution in (Early) Modern English, both types of ing-nominal frequently functioned as prepositional complements but also occurred as the direct object or subject of a clause (De Smet, Reference De Smet2008; Fanego, Reference Fanego2004; Houston, Reference Houston, Fasold and Schiffrin1989; Nevalainen, Raumolin-Brunberg, & Manilla, Reference Nevalainen, Ramoulin-Brunberg and Manilla2011).

The distributional overlap between ing-OF and ing-Ø in Modern English can be explained by the fact that the two variants are historically related: the innovative variant, ing-Ø, most likely developed from ing-OF in the Middle English period. As shown by Fanego (Reference Fanego2004), the first instances of ing-Ø were attested around 1250. The subsequent diffusion of the progressive variant ing-Ø proceeded according to what Fanego (Reference Fanego2004:38) has termed a “hierarchy of relative nominality.” First, ing-Ø became a well-established alternative to ing-OF in “bare” contexts, where the ing-form was not preceded by a determiner. Such contexts are illustrated in (3):

[no determiner: bare]

  1. (3) a. The soul can't dye, cannot therefore the Man dye? If not, there is no such thing, as killing of Men, or mortal Men. (1673, PW3)

  2. b. It was a cruel mercy which Tamberlane shewed to three hundred Lepers in killing them to rid them out of their misery (1662, SG2)

It was only after ing-Ø was established in determinerless contexts that it further diffused to contexts with a determiner. Over the course of the Early Modern and Late Modern period, the second stage of diffusion involved a spread to contexts with a determiner that is a possessive, as illustrated in (4).

[possessive pronoun: POSS]

  1. (4) a. But I perswade my selfe, it cannot well be used in the defence of his killing of the Dragon: (1631, Peter Heylyn)

  2. b. then I must believe that his killing my Father was no murder, and that they died wrongfully who were Executed for having a hand in his Death (1680, Roger L'Estrange)

Finally, in the third stage of diffusion, ing-Ø spread further to contexts where the determiner “is an article, usually definite”—illustrated in (5) (Fanego, Reference Fanego2004:38).Footnote 1 At this point, ing-Ø also started appearing following demonstratives—as illustrated in (6a)—and indefinite articles—illustrated in (6b)—albeit to a lesser extent.

[definite article: the]

  1. (5) a. how long thou hast lived to little purpose, yea, to the killing of thy soul for ever (1659, George Swinnock)

  2. b. it was given out, that the killing an Usurper, was always esteemed a commendable Action (1679, Gilbert Burnet)

[demonstrative, indefinite article, quantifier: other]

  1. (6) a. Ninthly, Protest against that most terrible and odious shedding of the innocont blood of those 3 forementioned (1640, William Prynne)

  2. b. thou wert thereby kept from a further shedding the blood of thy soul. (1659, George Swinnock)

Specifying our hypotheses to the diachronically unstable variation between ing-OF and ing-Ø in the seventeenth century, we can reformulate them as follows:

  • Hypothesis 1: The proportion of ing-OF and ing-Ø in the linguistic output of individuals changes across their lifespan. These developments can, but need not be, in the direction of the community development (that is, an increase of ing-Ø at the expense of ing-OF).

  • Hypothesis 2: There is a determiner constraint hierarchy (bare contexts > possessives > (definite) articles). This hierarchy attested at the community level can also be witnessed in the linguistic output of individuals.

  • Hypothesis 3: Changing usage proportions of ing-Ø and ing-OF can occur and vary in extent and direction in different grammatical contexts within and between individuals. Additionally, determiner constraints (and accompanying usage of ing-OF and ing-Ø) can, but need not, be stable across an individual's lifespan.

Early Modern Multiloquent Authors (EMMA) corpus

The data was collected from the corpus of Early Modern Multiloquent Authors (EMMA), the compilation of which has been detailed by Petré, Anthonissen, Budts, Manjavacas, Silva, Standing, and Strik (Reference Petré, Anthonissen, Budts, Manjavacas, Silva, Standing and Strik2019). For the present study, it is important to highlight the following:

  • The corpus contains the works of fifty authors born between 1599 and 1686, whose oeuvres comprise at least 500,000 words and are relatively evenly distributed across a long career (average = thirty-eight years). The authors are grouped by birth date in five separate “generations.”

  • The authors included in EMMA constitute a relatively homogeneous group, with the majority (thirty-seven authors) being members of London society who spent a considerable time of their active life in London. The remaining thirteen authors are not strongly connected to London society (neither socially nor geographically). The corpus is enriched with metainformation about text type and the authors’ place of birth, social circles, and geographical mobility.

Rather than querying the entire corpus (87,126,198 words) for strings of more than two letters followed by ing (to exclude sing, king, etc.) and manually filtering tokens that did not represent instances of deverbal nominalizations (e.g., evening, something, etc.), we restricted our sample in the following ways:

  • To control for genre variation, we restricted querying to texts labeled as descriptive or argumentative prose and letters.

  • Our sample is restricted to texts produced by authors from the first three generations in the corpus (born between 1599 and 1644). As a result, the resulting dataset spans across approximately one hundred years (the ”oldest” tokens dating from 1626 and the most recent ones from 1721), during which the progressive variant ing-Ø was steadily on the rise. With respect to the stages of diffusion described by Fanego (Reference Fanego2004), ing-Ø had already been widely adopted in bare contexts. Following Nevalainen et al.'s (Reference Nevalainen, Ramoulin-Brunberg and Manilla2011:7) classification of Labov's (Reference Labov1994) five stages of linguistic change, the development in bare contexts was virtually completed (representing over 85% of all tokens). In possessive contexts, the stage of development can be classified as “mid-range” to “nearing completion” (between 35% and 85%), whereas ing-Ø was “new and vigorous” (15%-35%) in contexts with a (definite) article.

In total, twenty-one authors are included in our sample.Footnote 2 The total number of observations for each author is listed in Table 1.Footnote 3

Table 1. Absolute and relative frequencies of ing-OF and ing-Ø per author

For each of these individuals, the total number of ing-nominals they produced in their prose and letter writing was collected. This totals up to 16,633 tokens, of which 11,862 are examples of ing-Ø (69%) and 4,767 are examples of ing-OF (31%).

Statistical analysis

We fitted a number of different logistic regression models, ranging from a basic model with no independent variables to more complex multilevel models. In the multilevel models, the following variables are included: the author, the age of the author at the time a variant was produced (in order to model lifespan developments), and the determiner that preceded the variant (to model effects of grammatical conditioning). The independent variable “determiner” comprises four levels: bare contexts, possessive contexts, definite article contexts, and other contexts (including demonstratives and indefinite articles). Models will be fitted with varying “author” intercepts or varying “author” slopes. The final, most complex model includes an interaction effect between “age” and “determiner” with varying author slopes.

Bayesian regression models

A common problem for logistic mixed-effect models, which, unlike linear models, involve a binary dependent variable, is that there is a fairly high risk of (quasi-)separation problems, which occur when “one predictor completely or almost completely separates the binary response in the observed data” (Kimball, Shantz, Eager, & Roy, Reference Kimball, Shantz, Eager and Roy2019:231). Ideally, when logistic regression is used to model variation, there is at least partial overlap between the dependent variables with respect to all levels of the independent variables. Overlap is demonstrated by the dataset for John Dryden in Table 2, where the levels “bare,” “the,” and “other” include observations for both of the dependent variables. With the level “possessive,” however, John Dryden's data exhibits separation: there are ten ing-nominals preceded by a possessive, which are exclusively of the ing-Ø type. In John Dryden's data, the predictor level “possessive” thus perfectly predicts the dependent variable.

Table 2. Overlap and quasi-separation in the data set

Such (quasi-)separation could be due to the low number of observations for some conditioning factors or because one of the individuals in the dataset truly perfectly separates the dependent variable under particular conditions. Regardless, (quasi-)separation presents an issue for the way in which mixed-effect models (such as glmer) compute the probability of the observed data, as it can cause the estimates for the fixed and random effects to become extremely—even infinitely—large.Footnote 4 In the present case, the problems caused by quasi-separation ultimately led to a failure to converge for glmer.Footnote 5

The present study relies on a Bayesian implementation of binomial logistic regression fitted with brm (R [R Core Team, 2021]; package: brms [Bürkner, Reference Bürkner2017, Reference Bürkner2018]).Footnote 6 The function underlying the models is identical to that of glmer in that the logistic function of the proportion of the binary dependent variable is represented as a linear function of fixed and random effects. However, the way in which the results are computed differs slightly. Bayesian models do not start from the assumption that all possible estimate values of the effects are equally likely. Instead, Bayesian computation allows the analyst to impose expectations (and constraints) on estimate values in the form of priors. Such priors assume the shape of a distribution (normal/Gaussian, Cauchy, etc.) around a mean with a certain standard deviation. They are used to state, for instance, that estimate values for the effects are likely near a given mean and very unlikely to reach the extreme values that may cause failure to converge.

In the present case, the priors for all models are “weakly informative priors”: the expectations that are set still take a wide range of possible outcomes into account but exclude highly unlikely, extreme values that cause convergence issues. The (varying) intercept priors and priors for the fixed effects were set as distributed around a mean of zero (translating into the starting assumption that they have no effect on the choice between ing-OF and ing-Ø), with a standard deviation between one and five.Footnote 7

Model comparison

To demonstrate the procedure, we will start by formulating the basic hypothesis that there is a considerable amount of variation between authors in the extent to which they use ing-Ø. To assess whether this hypothesis holds true, we fit two models. First, we fit a simple intercept model (ing ~ 1), which estimates the probability of the dependent variable at the population level without taking any conditions (or effects) into account. Such a model assumes that all authors exhibit identical behavior and use the innovative variant at the same rate. Second, we fit a varying intercept model, which estimates the population-level rate or probability of the dependent variable while taking differences between authors into account (thus “correcting” the population estimate for differences between individuals).

The output of Bayesian regression models should be understood as follows: they do not report a single, most likely coefficient combined with a p-value, but an estimate coefficient mean, an error rate, and a credible interval within which the estimate is predicted to fall. In Table 3, we report the mean estimate of the intercept (to be understood as the log odds of the innovative variant for the entire population) for both the simple intercept and varying intercept models. The simple intercept model estimates the intercept mean at 0.91, reporting a 95% credible interval (or CI) between 0.88 and 0.95. The varying intercept model, described in the second column, lists a population-level effect as well as a group-level effect (i.e., varying author intercept). The main difference with the simple intercept model is that the varying intercept model yields a 95% credible interval that covers a much broader range (between 0.67 and 1.24).Footnote 8 Because the varying intercept model allows for intercept corrections by individual author, the increased range of the credible interval indicates substantial interindividual variation in terms of how often ing-Ø is used.Footnote 9

Table 3. Model comparison of simple intercept model, predicting the posterior probability of the dependent variable at the population level, and varying author intercept model predicting the posterior probability of the dependent variable and correcting the population estimate for differences between individuals (group level effects). Number of observations = 16629, chains = 4, iterations = 4000, warmup = 1000, thin = 1

The next step is to assess whether the fitted varying intercept model is better at generalizing to any new, out-of-sample data than the fitted simple intercept model. To this end, we can perform a model evaluation by means of Leave-One-Out cross-validation, or by examining their Widely Applicable Information Criterion (WAIC; Gelman, Hwang, & Vehtari, Reference Gelman, Hwang and Vethari2014; Watanabe, Reference Watanabe2010).Footnote 10 Smaller WAIC values are considered superior, but it is not immediately clear how much smaller the WAIC values should be. As such, we also calculate the WAIC weights, which take a value between zero and one and should be understood as the posterior probability that a particular model makes better out-of-sample predictions.Footnote 11

In Figure 1, the WAIC value of the varying intercept model is estimated at 19,052, which is 875 units smaller than that of the simple intercept model, which is estimated at 19,928. Figure 1 also demonstrates that the difference between the WAIC scores remains substantial, even when the standard error range of the WAIC estimates (represented by the width of the lines running through the dots) is taken into account. This suggests that the varying intercept model, which corrects estimates for interindividual variation, exhibits a better fit for the data, confirming our basic hypothesis of there being nontrivial differences between authors.Footnote 12 It is this model comparison procedure that has been applied to all models presented in the analysis below.

Figure 1. WAIC estimates and standard error of simple intercept model and varying author intercept model.

Model overview

The assessment of the three hypotheses hinges on the comparison of twenty-two models in total. A full overview of each model can be found in Table 4.Footnote 13 The models can be divided into four groups: base models, age-only models, determiner-only models, and full models.

Table 4. WAIC and WAIC weight (rounded to 0.000001) for all models, ranked by WAIC score (ascending)

As the first hypothesis stated that individuals change the extent to which they use the conservative (ing-OF) and innovative variant (ing-Ø) during their lifespan, we need to establish that a model including an independent variable “age” (e.g., ing ~ age) provides a better fit for the data than the base model (ing ~ 1).Footnote 14 Additionally, we wish to determine whether there is interindividual variation in the data with respect to these changing usage rates. We can model interindividual variation in two different ways. The first way is to simply add age as a fixed effect to the varying intercept model (ing ~ age + [1|author]). In such a model, we can correct the population-level intercept for interindividual variation (meaning that the proportion of variant usage can differ among individuals), but we still assume that the direction in which any potential lifespan change proceeds is identical across all individuals. In other words: while the population-level intercept is corrected for interindividual variation, the slope is not. Alternatively, then, we could introduce interindividual variation as a ”varying slopes” model (ing ~ age + age|author), which does allow for individual differences in terms of the direction of the change. The difference in how ing-nominal usage across the lifespan of individuals is modeled by a varying intercept model (left, by means of parallel lines) and varying slopes model (right, by means of nonparallel lines) is visualized in Figure 2.

Figure 2. Effect plots of varying intercept model and varying slope model (n = 500).

The second hypothesis relates to the effect of the grammatical context in which the ing-nominal is used. As such, we include three “determiner only” models in which the main effect ”determiner” is included, either in isolation or in relation to the behavior of individual authors with respect to these determiners (ing ~ det; ing ~ det + [1|author]; ing ~ det + [det|author]).

Finally, the third hypothesis relates to the combined effect of age and grammatical context. Besides the models where either age or determiner are considered as the only fixed effects, we also consider a number of “full” models, in which a range of different feature combinations are tested. The most basic version of the full model includes “age” and “determiner” as fixed effects, without including any random effects (ing ~ age_sd + det). A slightly more complex model also includes the interaction between “age” and “determiner” as a fixed effect (ing ~ age_sd * det). We also included versions of these models where the intercept is corrected for variation between authors (ing ~ age_sd + det + [1|author]; ing ~ age_sd * det + [1|author]). Finally, full model versions were fitted with varying author slopes for age (ing ~ age_sd + det + [age_sd|author]; ing ~ age_sd * det + [age_sd|author]), determiner (ing ~ age_sd + det + [det|author]; ing ~ age_sd * det + [det|author]), the interaction of age and determiner (ing ~ age_sd + det + [age_sd:det|author]; ing ~ age_sd * det + [age_sd:det|author]), and a combination of age, determiner, and their interaction (ing ~ age_sd + det + [age_sd*det|author]; ing ~ age_sd * det + [age_sd*det|author]).

Results

Model comparison

Table 4 lists the specifications for all models. The models are ranked according to their WAIC estimates (and accompanying weights). The estimated effective number of parameters per model is also listed (p_WAIC). To further discuss the effect of age and determiner type across authors, we report the results of the model with the highest WAIC weight (ing ~ age_sd + det + [age_sd*det|author]) in the next section (“Selected model”).

The two models with the lowest WAIC estimates are the most complex models, which include age, determiner, and their interaction as random effects (with varying author slopes). The model comparison supports the proposal that both age and grammatical context are meaningful parameters and that there is substantial variation between individuals with respect to those parameters. Particularly, the inclusion of grammatical context appears to have a substantial positive effect on the estimated prediction error of the model, as evident from the large difference between the WAIC values of the model that solely factors in determiner as a fixed effect (13067.1 [standard error: 158.5]) from the most complex age-only model (18856.5 [standard error: 118]).Footnote 15

Selected model

Table 5 summarizes the selected model's parameters. At the population level, the presence of a determiner has a strong negative effect: ing-Ø is less likely to occur following a possessive (mean coefficient estimate: −1.36 [95% credible interval: −1.69;−1.02]), a definite article (−3.78 [CI: −4.22;−3.29]), or any other determiner type (−3.35 [CI:−3.77;−2.86]). Age appears to have a small, positive effect (0.20 [CI: 0.01−0.40]). These effects are on the log-odds scale, which means the positive effect estimate of age can be interpreted as the odds of ing-Ø increasing by 20% as the age of the authors increases.

Table 5. For each parameter, we provide the population-level mean estimate coefficient (Estimate), the standard deviation of the posterior distribution of the estimate (Est.Error), and the 95% Credible intervals (CI lower bound and CI upper bound). Rhat helps evaluate the estimate the posterior distribution of the parameter (Rhat = 1.0 indicates convergence). The covariance matrix of group-level effects can be found in the online repository

Interindividual variation between authors can be examined by considering the estimated standard deviations at the group level. With the exception of the interaction between age and definite article and “other” contexts, the mean standard deviation estimates as well as their lower bound are clearly away from zero, which indicates the relevance of including the random intercept and random slope terms.

To better understand these figures, it is helpful to scrutinize the interaction between age and grammatical context per author, as visualized in Figure 3. For each graph in Figure 3, the y-axis represents the posterior probability of the incoming variant, ing-Ø. The x-axis represents a standardized representation of age, whereby the mean, which is set to zero, should be understood as approximately forty-five years old (the average age at which tokens were produced). From these figures, it is apparent why grammatical context has a substantial effect on the explanatory power of the model: despite interauthor variation with respect to the coefficient estimates per grammatical context, the probability of ing-Ø is highest when the ing-nominal is not preceded by a determiner (line marked with dots), followed by possessive contexts (line marked with squares), and lowest when the ing-nominal is preceded by a definite article (unmarked line) or other type of determiner (e.g., indefinite article, demonstrative, etc.; marked with triangles) for the majority of each author's life, mimicking the determiner constraint hierarchy observed at the population level.

Figure 3. Effect plots of interaction effect: age*det|author.

The figure also helps clarify why the effect of the inclusion of age as a predictor variable appears to be more modest: demonstrable age effects are not present for every individual in the sample. This is either because there is insufficient data to factor in age for some individuals (e.g., Aphra Behn, George Swinnock), or because usage rates appear to have remained largely stable across their lifespan (e.g., Thomas Pierce, William Penn). Furthermore, there appears to be quite some variation between individuals with respect to the interaction between age and grammatical contexts, particularly in the case of possessive determiners (standard deviation: 0.71 [CI: 0.33-1.26]).

Finally, the patterns in Figure 3 may also help identify individuals that seem to alter their grammatical preferences across their lifespan under certain grammatical conditions. An overview of the observed changes is presented in Table 6, which may help indicate how typical certain trajectory types may be (Sankoff, Reference Sankoff2019:223). Note that we treated the observed patterns very conservatively: despite there being more apparent patterns of change in the raw data, we retained the default assumption of stability if the 95% credible interval ranges presented in Figure 3 allow for horizontal (nonascending or nondescending) trend lines.Footnote 16 In total, eight individuals were flagged as altering their usage rates of ing-OF and ing-Ø. Of these eight individuals, there are five cases where the raw data suggest the possibility of a constraint change. For some individuals, such as Gilbert Burnet, the constraint change is a partial one: Burnet exhibited mixed usage but turned to categorical usage of ing-Ø in determinerless contexts later in life. While it is difficult to statistically verify categoriality, the rightmost (i.e., latest) mean posterior probability estimates of the relevant categories for these individuals closely approaches one.

Table 6. Observed changes and metadata per author (excluding Aphra Behn and George Swinnock)

A full constraint change may be attested for two individuals: the preferences of Peter Heylyn and William Prynne (the first and second author listed in Figure 3), born in 1599 and 1600 respectively, appear to switch radically from ing-OF to ing-Ø in possessive contexts. Given the low raw frequencies (twenty-nine tokens in total), and the possibility of more superficial, stylistic explanations, we should consider Heylyn's patterns with a healthy dose of uncertainty. Still, we could tentatively suggest the following: In his early prose and letters (before age thirty-seven), Heylyn exhibited variable use of the conservative (19%) and progressive variant (81%) in determinerless contexts. In contexts with a nominal determiner, however, Heylyn's early life grammar seemed to be largely or perhaps even entirely conservative: in the context of a possessive preceding the ing-form, the direct object of the ing-form required a periphrastic realization with of—conforming to the internal structure of a noun phrase. Later in life, Heylyn's writings start to allow progressive, mixed forms, and ultimately Heylyn develops a clear, near-categorical preference for the progressive form following possessives after the age of sixty. A similar picture emerges from the raw usage frequencies of William Prynne, who appeared to be categorically conservative in possessive contexts before the age of thirty-six but fully turned toward the progressive variant after the age of fifty-six.Footnote 17 Thus, both Heylyn and Prynne may have categorically switched to the progressive variant when a possessive is involved around similar ages (sixty and fifty-six respectively), and times (in 1659 and 1664).

Given these results, the question arises whether the observed trends can be understood as a full constraint change, where these individuals categorically switch from exclusively using a conservative variant to exclusively using the progressive variant under a given grammatical condition.Footnote 18 An interesting question with respect to such possible (partial or full) constraint changes is whether an author's apparent adoption of a new system (under a particular constraint) also involves a rejection of the old system, which would be even stronger evidence for a qualitative change. However, unless we find metalinguistic comments in their works (which we have not so far), this will remain an open question.Footnote 19 With respect to direction, it appears that all (possible) constraint changes are in accordance with the larger population-level development (loss of ing-OF in bare and possessive contexts).

Discussion: inter- and intraindividual variation and change

What emerges from the results is that, while neither full nor partial inventory changes (where an individual ceases to use ing-OF and/or adopts ing-Ø) occur, we do observe a fair number of frequency and (to a lesser extent) constraint-based age effects. Additionally, the vast majority of observable quantitative shifts across all grammatical contexts appear to be in the direction of the larger population-level development, showing an increase of ing-Ø.

There are, however, two “retrograde” changers (Wagner & Sankoff, Reference Wagner and Sankoff2011). The first is John Bunyan, who appears to become incrementally more conservative than his peers (Age coefficient estimate: −0.54 [95% CI: −0.78 −0.32]). The second is George Fox, who similarly turns to making more conservative choices (Age coefficient estimate: −0.35 [95% CI: −0.58 −0.13]). These results corroborate earlier findings on interindividual variation in linguistic lifespan change trajectories: the frequency with which individuals use variants need not but can change, and when it does, it commonly is, but need not be, in line with the population-level development (e.g., progressive as well as retrograde change attested in panel studies by Wagner & Sankoff [Reference Wagner and Sankoff2011] for inflected futures in Montreal French; Buchstaller [Reference Buchstaller2015] for quotative be like in Tyneside English; Standing [Reference Standing2021:360-72] for cleft constructions in Early Modern English; also see Anthonissen [Reference Anthonissen2020:247]). What is discussed somewhat less commonly than interindividual variation in lifespan trajectories is that there may also be intraindividual variation in this respect: for many authors where frequency-based change is attested, this change may be restricted to only a few grammatical contexts. Furthermore, an interesting example in our data set is George Fox, who becomes more conservative if the ing-nominal is not preceded by a determiner, while his choices following possessives likely concur with the population-level pattern.Footnote 20

In other words, while it may be uncommon, individuals need not consistently develop toward or away from the community trend in every respect (also see Buchstaller et al., Reference Buchstaller, Krause-Lerche, Mechler, Beaman and Buchstaller2021). Such intraindividual variation thus may not only be attestable across the sets of variants an individual employs (Bergs, Reference Bergs2005:255-56), but also across the grammatical contexts that condition a single variable set.

Confronted with these figures, the question arises whether labile linguistic behavior can somehow be linked to the contextual metainformation included in the corpus. With respect to stable speakers and speakers who adapted (slightly) in the direction of the community trend, there appear to be no striking differences in terms of social or geographical (in)stability. By way of illustration, Tillotson and Dryden were born one year apart, belonged both to the upper class, and both went to Cambridge University in the early 1650s. After their studies, they both moved to London around the same time (1656 and 1657 respectively). Virtually all of their published work was written while they lived there. Yet, while Dryden shows a frequency (and possibly even a constraint) shift along the lines of the community trend, Tillotson is stable throughout his life. More generally, this could either mean that the differences can be explained by some unidentified factor or that some speakers are simply more likely to model their usage rates to the perceived community trend later in life (due to different ”cognitive learning styles,” see for example Riding & Rayner, Reference Riding and Rayner1998).

Regarding the two individuals who become more conservative, George Fox and John Bunyan, there are some striking similarities between them that may go some way in explaining their retrograde behavior (see Sankoff [Reference Sankoff2018] and [Reference Sankoff2019] for an overview of studies attesting retrograde change). First, after a relatively uneventful youth spent in small countryside communities, both experienced a more diversified social life.Footnote 21 Fox spent about a year in London at the age of nineteen, whereas Bunyan enlisted in the Parliamentary army between the age of sixteen and nineteen. This may have led them to accommodate to language use in more urban settings and establish the grammar shown in their first published work. However, some years later they were both cut off from society, being repeatedly imprisoned for their dissenting religious views and actions. Fox was in prison at least ten times (between 1649 and 1675), adding up to a total of more than six and a half years, or about 15% of his writing career. Bunyan was in prison uninterrupted (though he was allowed outside occasionally) for twelve years from 1660 until 1672, and another half year in 1676 (almost 40% of his writing career). While early modern prisons were rather “porous” and brimming with short-term inmates and visitors, normal social life was nevertheless sincerely disrupted, and prisoners were confined to their own cells in poor conditions for much of their time (Murray [Reference Murray2009:147, 152]). When in such relative isolation, one may fall back, due to the lack of sustained input from a more constructive social network structure, on entrenched language patterns such as they knew from youth (see the conservative behavior of the English poet Browning living in Italy [Arnaud, Reference Arnaud1998:132-33]). Fox and Bunyan's inmates, most of them from a lower class origin, may have been an additional conservative influence (see also the linguistic stagnation in prison documented in Baugh [Reference Baugh, Guy, Crawford, Schiffrin and Baugh1996:408-9], where this is interpreted as a case of covert prestige). The lower classes were typically less mobile and therefore less influenced by London life, which played a central role in many linguistic changes at the time, including the shift from ing-OF to ing-Ø (Nevalainen, Reference Nevalainen2015:288).Footnote 22

Besides Fox and Bunyan, there is one other speaker, William Prynne, who was incarcerated for about ten years or one fifth of his writing career. He was transported to the island of Jersey, where he was kept “incommunicado,” not even allowed a pen and paper (Cressy, Reference Cressy2018:741). His isolation was therefore more severe than in either Fox's or Bunyan's case. This period of seclusion may have slowed down his accommodation to ongoing change, similar to Fox and Bunyan. However, while he was imprisoned first around the same age (thirty-three) as Bunyan's (thirty-two), the majority of his time in prison (seven out of ten years) occurred in the first half of his career (between 1633-1640). After 1640, Prynne remained productive and mostly free until 1668 and was generally well-connected, even becoming MP in 1648. While reconnecting to the speech community again, Prynne caught up on the ongoing changes, which might partly explain his more radical shift in preferences (in line with the community trend) in possessive contexts (also see Petré et al. [Reference Petré, Anthonissen, Budts, Manjavacas, Silva, Standing and Strik2019:110] on a similar shift in the language of Margaret Cavendish after her return from exile). Prynne's political success and general well-connectedness after his seclusion distinguishes him from Fox and Bunyan.

Finally, together with Nathaniel Crouch, Fox and Bunyan are the only authors in our sample who did not grow up in an upper-class family, instead being the sons of middle class artisans. They are also the only ones that did not attend university. Yet, what sets Fox and Bunyan apart from Crouch is that they were by far the least connected to “society” in its sense of the aggregate of fashionable, wealthy, or otherwise prominent people. Nathaniel Crouch, as a successful London-based publisher, was in the middle of buzzing London city life. By contrast, Fox spent most of his time preaching throughout the country, experiencing relatively few periods of stable participation in large-scale weak-tied urban communities such as London. Bunyan, in turn, was a poor man for most of his life and, as a result, bound to the countryside of Bedfordshire. It is interesting to note that Bunyan, who is arguably the author with the smallest social network, becomes more conservative across the board, whereas Fox may pick up at least on the innovation in possessive contexts. Yet overall, the similarity of their life paths (extended period of isolation, class background, lack of university attendance) seem to provide a plausible group of explanations for their shared retrograde behavior.

To tentatively explore whether these effects could help explain interauthor variation with respect to age effects, the selected model (ing ~ age_sd + det + age_sd*det|author) could be further extended with the parameters “incarcerated” (levels: yes/no, indicating whether a given author has spent more than five years imprisoned) and “university” (levels: yes/no, indicating whether the author has attended university).Footnote 23 These factors should be understood as groupings that introduce slope variance with respect to the factor age. As such, they are modeled as group-level effects with varying age slopes. The resulting models were submitted to a WAIC model comparison, presented in Table 7.Footnote 24

Table 7. WAIC estimates and WAIC weight (rounded to 0.0000001) for additional models, ranked by WAIC score (ascending)

While the highest weight is assigned to the model including incarceration, it does not bring about a substantial reduction in the WAIC estimate. Considering the fact that the scores are near identical for each model, it remains undetermined whether the extended incarceration model indeed yields a better fit. We do, however, invite readers to extend our analysis to a new sample of authors that is more nicely balanced with respect to isolation versus connectedness, middle versus upper class, and/or (lack of) university education, or to explore alternative social dimensions by adapting our analysis scripts for use on the openly released data.

Conclusion

In recent years, a growing number of studies have indicated that an individual's grammar is not necessarily a fixed system and may be subject to change even after what is traditionally understood as the critical acquisition period. This has been amply shown for gradual shifts in pronunciation and morphophonology (e.g., Bowie & Yaeger-Dror, Reference Bowie, Yaeger-Dror, Honeybone and Salmons2015; Harrington, Palethorpe, & Watson, Reference Harrington, Palethorpe and Watson2000; MacKenzie, Reference MacKenzie2017; Nahkola & Saanilahti, Reference Nahkola and Saanilahti2004; Sankoff & Blondeau, Reference Sankoff and Blondeau2007). Recent studies have moreover shown that it also applies to morphosyntactic constructions, which may be adopted (Anthonissen & Petré, Reference Anthonissen and Petré2019; Petré & Anthonissen, Reference Petré and Anthonissen2020; Petré & Van de Velde, Reference Petré and Van de Velde2018), significantly expanded (Anthonissen, Reference Anthonissen2020; Neels, Reference Neels2020), or changed (Buchstaller, Reference Buchstaller2015, Reference Buchstaller2016; Standing & Petré, Reference Standing, Petré, Beaman and Buchstaller2021) beyond the critical period. Similarly, lifespan change has also been attested in contexts where a choice between morphosyntatic variants needs to be made (e.g., Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg2005, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Nevala and Palander-Collin2009; Raumolin-Brunberg & Nurmi, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Narrog and Heine2011). While several of these changes may be regarded as stochastic shifts in preference, some changes do appear to result in a rejection of one of the variants, which could ultimately point to qualitative change, and stochastic shift also cannot explain cases where a language user starts to adopt grammatical innovations later in life. What may set such changes apart from grammatical change rooted in child language acquisition is that changes later in life may involve more (top-down) explicit learning (similar to second-language learning, see Anthonissen & Petré, Reference Anthonissen and Petré2019:3; Dąbrowska, Reference Dąbrowska, Dąbrowska and Divjak2015:661), but the resulting shifts in representation may arguably be just as “qualitative.”

Our study corroborates earlier findings that individuals can change the rate by which they use the competing morphosyntactic structures across their lifespan (see, among others, Buchstaller, Reference Buchstaller2015; Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg2005, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Nevala and Palander-Collin2009; Raumolin-Brunberg & Nurmi, Reference Raumolin-Brunberg, Nurmi, Narrog and Heine2011; Wagner & Sankoff, Reference Wagner and Sankoff2011), and, for the majority of individuals, this change proceeds in the direction of the ongoing change in the rest of the community. Yet, in line with Baxter and Croft's (Reference Baxter and Croft2016) suggestion that individual speakers may differ in their inclination to adjust their behavior to the community (also see Anthonissen, Reference Anthonissen2020), we also found nontrivial interindividual variation regarding the extent to which these usage rates change, as well as the direction in which they change (with retrograde changers such as John Bunyan opposing the general, community-directed patterns of change, which may partly be the result of their particular life trajectories).

We additionally established that there is intraindividual variation in the slopes and direction of change under different grammatical conditions. As such, we further extend Bergs’ (Reference Bergs2005:255) study on intraindividual variation, which demonstrates that individuals need not be consistently progressive or conservative in all aspects of their grammar. While Bergs considered the choices of individuals with respect to multiple morphosyntactic variables without factoring in grammatical constraints, we suggest that, even with respect to a single variable (ing-OF versus ing-Ø), individuals can also become more progressive over time with respect to some grammatical contexts while remaining stable or even becoming more conservative in others. That the rate of change attested need not be constant across grammatical contexts in the linguistic output of individuals (as it is assumed to be at the community level, see Kroch's [Reference Kroch1989] Constant Rate Hypothesis) does, however, call for further empirical inquiry.

Finally, we also probed into the question of whether individuals may also “participate” in qualitative change by reaching a more advanced stage of the community grammar during their lifespan. In a recent study with panel data, Buchstaller et al. (Reference Buchstaller, Krause-Lerche, Mechler, Beaman and Buchstaller2021:32-3) suggested that “evidence of inventory change is rare and difficult to come by,” and “speakers are less likely to change the constraints that govern the use of a variable than they are to change proportional use of a variant” (also see MacKenzie, Reference MacKenzie2019). Finding evidence of full (and even partial) inventory changes in real-time corpus data may be equally difficult or even impossible, particularly with protracted changes such as the one examined in the present study (Nevalainen et al., Reference Nevalainen, Ramoulin-Brunberg and Manilla2011). Yet, when taking a constraint-based definition of qualitative change (which is facilitated by large-scale individual-oriented corpora such as EMMA) and identifying an appropriate time window (e.g., when the population-level patterns these individuals model themselves toward are sufficiently unstable to allow for more radical adjustments), we may in fact attest cases where individuals allow novel variants to diffuse to (and/or take over in) new grammatical contexts, albeit indeed to a lesser extent than frequency-based changes.

Footnotes

1. Note that structures such as the killing an usurper are no longer current in Present-day English (see Fanego, Reference Fanego2004). Furthermore, the extent to which there is distributional overlap between ing-Ø and ing-OF has been reduced substantially after the eighteenth century. See Maekelberghe (Reference Maekelberghe2017) for a discussion of whether the variants ing-OF and ing-Ø can still be considered a morphosyntactic alternation pair in Present-day English.

2. The higher number of authors in the second generation is due to the fact that, overall, the number of relevant tokens per author is smaller than in the first and third generation. Besides Aphra Behn, the only other woman in the corpus did not produce any relevant tokens for the selected genres.

3. The full annotated data set and R code to replicate the analysis is accessible in an online repository: https://github.com/LFonteyn/LVC_lifespan.

4. Issues related to separation in response classes have previously been described as “knockouts” (Rousseau & Sankoff, Reference Rousseau, Sankoff and Sankoff1978; Sankoff & Labov, Reference Sankoff and Labov1979) and “empty cells” (Tagliamonte & Baayen, Reference Tagliamonte and Baayen2012:24).

5. A description of why frequentist models struggle with estimating maximum likelihood values when there is (quasi-)separation can be found in Kimball et al. (Reference Kimball, Shantz, Eager and Roy2019). On convergence errors more generally, see Bates, Kliegl, Vasishth, and Baayen (Reference Bates, Kliegl, Vasishth and Baayen2018).

6. For a very detailed tutorial on using the brms package, see Nalborczyk, Batailler, Lœvenbruck, Vilain, and Bürkner (Reference Nalborczyk, Batailler, Lœvenbruck, Vilain and Bürkner2019).

7. More specifically, the priors for the fixed effects were distributed around a mean of zero, with a standard deviation of one. The intercept priors were also set as normally distributed, with a mean at zero and a standard deviation of five. The varying author intercepts were modeled using a Half-Cauchy (long-tail distribution) with zero mean and a standard deviation of two.

8. The simple intercept model estimates the posterior predictive probability of the incoming variant at 0.713 [95% CI: 0.706-0.721], while the varying intercept model puts the estimate at 0.723 [95% CI: 0.661-0.776].

9. The extent of interindividual variation can also be expressed when examining the “group-level” standard deviation estimate (0.66), for which we can state with 95% confidence that this value lies between 0.47 and 0.94. The closer this value is to zero, the smaller the relevance of interindividual variation.

10. Vehtari, Gelman, and Gabry (Reference Vehtari, Gelman and Gabry2017) pointed out that WAIC estimates may be inaccurate with weak priors or influential observations. They recommend using Approximate Leave-One-Out cross-validation with Pareto-smoothed importance sampling (PSIS-LOO). Repeating the entire model comparison with PSIS-LOO rather than WAIC yielded similar estimates. Results of PSIS-LOO can be found and compared in the R notebook included in the online repository.

11. WAIC weights were obtained with model_weights (Bürkner, Reference Bürkner2017, Reference Bürkner2018). Further model evaluation involved examining the models’ trace plots and Rhat statistic. If the Rhat exceeds one, the algorithm has not yet converged. In such cases, more iterations are needed (possibly along with more informative priors).

12. The WAIC weight of the varying intercept model, which closely approximates one (as opposed to the WAIC weight of the simple intercept model, which approximates zero), corroborates that there are nontrivial differences between authors. Note that the weights are distributed between the models that are included in the comparison only. Neither the simple nor the varying intercept base model illustrated here will receive any weight when more complex models are included in the comparison.

14. Apart from modeling lifespan trends by looking at the author's age of production, we can also examine age effects by modeling the author's date of birth. In EMMA, authors have been grouped into generations based on their date of birth. Adding the author's generation category as an additional variable increases the WAIC estimate slightly (by approximately 0.2). The WAIC weight of a model that only includes age is estimated at 0.384, which is slightly higher than that of a model with age and generation added as fixed effects (0.323) and a model that includes the interaction between age and generation (0.292).

15. It should be noted that the WAIC mean estimates of the six models with the lowest WAIC estimates are very similar (see Figure A in the online repository). This indicates some uncertainty in the model comparison. Ultimately, the WAIC weight estimation seems to be in favor of the model where the interaction between age and determiner is not included as a population-level effect.

16. Crucially, failure to attest linguistic change is not the same as confirming stability—claims that involve the independence of time/age effects “are not testable and may only be assumed true” (see Paolillo, Reference Paolillo2011:271).

17. The only late instance of the conservative variant (in 1664) is found in what turns out to be a reprint of a text first printed in 1655 and therefore should have been excluded.

18. For both Heylyn and Prynne, the lower bound of the leftmost (i.e., earliest) posterior probability estimate's 95% credible interval approaches zero, and the upper bound of the rightmost (i.e., latest) estimate approaches one. Exact values can be consulted in the Appendix.

19. Additionally, it would be interesting to consider whether the rejection of the old system was inspired by prescriptivist comments. As pointed out by Fanego (Reference Fanego2004), eighteenth and nineteenth century prescriptivists advised against the combination of definite articles with ing-Ø, possibly halting the diffusion of the innovative variant in those contexts. The developments described here predate such prescriptivist comments.

20. To be considered a retrograde trend, the lower bound of the credible interval of the leftmost (i.e., earliest) probability estimate of bare ing-forms must be higher than the upper bound of the rightmost (i.e., latest) probability estimate. Conversely, to be considered a progressive trend, the upper bound of the leftmost estimate of possessive ing-forms must be lower than the lower bound of the rightmost estimate. For bare forms, a retrograde trend can be established at the 95% credible interval (0.84-0.81) as well as the 89% credible interval (0.85-0.79). For possessive forms, the 95% CI still includes a retrograde trend (0.64-0.57), but these values should be considered unlikely. At the 89%, the bounds suggest a positive trend (0.58-0.63).

21. Drayton-in-the-clay (today known as Fenny Drayton) and Elstow respectively. Biographical data was taken from the EMMA corpus metadata (Petré et al., Reference Petré, Anthonissen, Budts, Manjavacas, Silva, Standing and Strik2019).

22. One other explanatory factor that has been identified with respect to retrograde change is ascent upon the social ladder, which has been found to correlate with more conservative behavior in Early Modern England (particularly Nevalainen & Raumolin-Brunberg, Reference Nevalainen and Raumolin-Brunberg2016:143). While it is true that Fox and Bunyan both gradually became influencers in their own ways, the first as the leader of the Quaker movement, the latter as an influential preacher, there is no evidence that their social status went up among the establishment, nor that they had aspirations in that direction. We therefore suggest that isolation from the speech community where the change is taking place is a more likely factor and in line with what is known about the role of social networks (Sharma & Dodsworth, Reference Sharma and Dodsworth2020).

23. We cannot distinguish the influence of class from the influence of university attendance, as the subset of authors who did not attend university (George Fox, John Bunyan and Nathaniel Crouch) is the same as the subset of authors with a middle-class background.

24. PSIS-LOO yielded similar estimates and weights.

References

Anderson, Stephen R. (2016). Synchronic versus diachronic explanation and the nature of the language faculty. Annual Review of Linguistics 2:1131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anthonissen, Lynn. (2020). Special Passives across the Lifespan: Cognitive and Social Mechanisms. Doctoral dissertation, University of Antwerp and Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München.Google Scholar
Anthonissen, Lynn & Petré, Peter. (2019). Grammaticalization and the linguistic individual: new avenues in lifespan research. Linguistics Vanguard 5:112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arnaud, René. (1998). The development of the progressive in 19th century English: A quantitative survey. Language Variation and Change 10:123–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barlow, Michael. (2013). Individual differences and usage-based grammar. International Journal of Corpus Linguistics 18:443–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bates, Douglas, Kliegl, Reinhold, Vasishth, Shravan & Baayen, Harald. (2018). Parsimonious Mixed Models. https://arxiv.org/pdf/1506.04967.pdfGoogle Scholar
Baugh, John. (1996). Dimensions of a theory of econolinguistics. In Guy, G., Crawford, F., Schiffrin, D. & Baugh, J. (Eds.), Towards a social science of language, vol. I. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. 397419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baxter, Gareth & Croft, William. (2016). Modeling language change across the lifespan: Individual trajectories in community change. Language Variation and Change 28:129–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckner, Clay, Blythe, Richard, Bybee, Joan, Christiansen, Morten H., Croft, William, Ellis, Nick C., Holland, John, Ke, Jinyun, Larsen-Freeman, Diane & Schoenemann, Tom. (2009). Language is a complex adaptive system. Language Learning 59:126.Google Scholar
Bergs, Alexander. (2005). Social networks and historical socio-linguistics: studies in morphosyntactic variation in the Paston Letters (1421–1503). Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowie, David & Yaeger-Dror, Malcah. (2015). Phonological change in real time. In Honeybone, P. & Salmons, J. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of historical phonology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 603–18.Google Scholar
Buchstaller, Isabelle. (2015). Exploring linguistic malleability across the life span: Age-specific patterns in quotative use. Language in Society 44:457–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchstaller, Isabelle. (2016). Investigating the effect of socio-cognitive salience and speaker-based factors in morpho-syntactic life-span change. Journal of English Linguistics 44:199229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchstaller, Isabelle, Krause-Lerche, Anne & Mechler, Johanna. (2021). Exploring the effect of linguistic architecture and heuristic method in panel analysis. In Beaman, K. & Buchstaller, I. (Eds.), Language variation and language change across the lifespan: Theoretical and Empirical Perspectives from Panel Studies. New York: Routledge. 185208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bürkner, Paul-Christian. (2017). brms: An R Package for Bayesian Multilevel Models Using Stan. Journal of Statistical Software 80(1):128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bürkner, Paul-Christian. (2018). Advanced Bayesian Multilevel Modeling with the R Package brms. The R Journal 10(1):395411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bybee, Joan L. (2006). From Usage to Grammar: The Mind's Response to Repetition. Language 82:711–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cressy, David. (2018). Puritan Martyrs in Island Prisons. Journal of British Studies 57:736754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Croft, William. (2000). Explaining Language Change: An Evolutionary Approach, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dąbrowska, Ewa. (2015). Individual differences in grammatical knowledge. In Dąbrowska, E. & Divjak, D. (Eds.), Handbook of cognitive linguistics. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton. 649–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Denison, David. (2002). Log(ist)ic and simplistic S-curves. In Hickey, R. (Ed.), Motives for Language Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 5470.Google Scholar
De Smet, Hendrik. (2008). Functional motivations in the development of nominal and verbal gerunds in Middle and Early Modern English. English Language and Linguistics 12:55102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Smet, Hendrik. (2016). How gradual change progresses: The interaction between convention and innovation. Language Variation and Change 28:83102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diessel, Holger. (2019). The Grammar Network: How linguistic structure is shaped by language use. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fanego, Teresa. (2004). On reanalysis and actualization in syntactic change: The rise and development of English verbal gerunds. Diachronica 21:555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelman, Andrew, Hwang, Jessica & Vethari, Aki. (2014). Understanding predictive information criteria for Bayesian models. Statistics and Computing 24:9971016.Google Scholar
Harrington, Jonathan, Palethorpe, Sallyanne & Watson, Catherine I.. (2000). Does the Queen speak the Queen's English? Nature 408:927–28.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Houston, Ann. (1989). The English gerund: syntactic change and discourse function. In Fasold, R. & Schiffrin, D. (Eds.), Language change and variation. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. 173–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kerswill, Paul. (1996). Children, adolescents, and language change. Language Variation and Change 8:177202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimball, Amelia E., Shantz, Kailen, Eager, Christopher & Roy, Joseph. (2019). Confronting Quasi-Separation in Logistic Mixed Effects for Linguistic Data: A Bayesian Approach. Journal of Quantitative Linguistics 26:231–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kroch, Anthony. (1989). Reflexes of grammar in patterns of language change. Language Variation and Change 1:199244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Labov, William. (1994). Principles of linguistic change: Internal factors. Vol 1. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Labov, William. (2001). Principles of Linguistic Change: Social Factors. Vol. 2. Malden and Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lightfoot, David. (2019). Chomsky's I-languages: Rethinking catastrophic changes. Acta Linguistica Academica 66:349–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
López-Couso, María José. (2017). Transferring insights from child language acquisition to diachronic change (and vice versa). In Hundt, M., Mollin, S. & Pfenninger, S. E. (Eds.), The changing English language: Psycholinguistic perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 332–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacKenzie, Laurel. (2017). Frequency effects over the lifespan: A case study of Attenborough's r's. Linguistics Vanguard 3:112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacKenzie, Laurel. (2019). Perturbing the community grammar: Individual differences and community-level constraints on sociolinguistic variation. Glossa 4:123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maekelberghe, Charlotte. (2017). The use of nominal and verbal gerunds in Present-day English. A multifunctional comparative analysis. Doctoral dissertation, KU Leuven.Google Scholar
Meisel, Jurgen, Elsig, Martin & Rinke, Esther. (2013). Language acquisition and change: A morphosyntactic perspective. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Murray, Molly. (2009). Measured Sentences: Forming Literature in the Early Modern Prison. Huntington Library Quarterly 72:147–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nahkola, Kari & Saanilahti, Marja. (2004). Mapping language changes in real time: A panel study on Finnish. Language Variation and Change 16:7592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nalborczyk, Ladislas, Batailler, Cédric, Lœvenbruck, Hélène, Vilain, Anne & Bürkner, Paul-Christian. (2019). An Introduction to Bayesian Multilevel Models Using brms: A Case Study of Gender Effects on Vowel Variability in Standard Indonesian. Journal of Speech, Language, and Hearing Research 62:1225–42.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Neels, Jakob. (2020). Lifespan change in grammaticalisation as frequency-sensitive automation: William Faulkner and the let alone construction. Cognitive Linguistics 31:339–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nevalainen, Terttu, Ramoulin-Brunberg, Helena & Manilla, Heikki. (2011). The diffusion of language change in real time: Progressive and conservative individuals and the time depth of change. Language Variation and Change 23:143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nevalainen, Terttu. (2015). Social networks and language change in Tudor and Stuart London-only connect? English Language and Linguistics 19:269–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nevalainen, Terttu & Raumolin-Brunberg, Helena. (2016). Historical sociolinguistics. Language change in Tudor and Stuart England, 2nd edn. London & New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paolillo, John. (2011). Independence claims in linguistics. Language Variation and Change 23:257–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petré, Peter, Anthonissen, Lynn, Budts, Sara, Manjavacas, Enrique, Silva, Emma-Louise, Standing, William & Strik, Odile A.O.. (2019). Early Modern Multiloquent Authors (EMMA): Designing a large-scale corpus of individuals’ languages. ICAME Journal 43:83122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petré, Peter & Anthonissen, Lynn. (2020). Individuality in complex systems: A constructionist approach. Cognitive Linguistics 31:185212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petré, Peter & Van de Velde, Freek. (2018). The real-time dynamics of the individual and the community in grammaticalization. Language 94:867901.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
R Core Team. (2021). R: A language and environment for statistical computing. R Foundation for Statistical Computing, Vienna, Austria. https://www.R-project.org/.Google Scholar
Raumolin-Brunberg, Helena. (2005). Language change in adulthood: Historical letters as evidence. European Journal of English Studies 9:3751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raumolin-Brunberg, Helena. (2009). Lifespan changes in the language of three early modern gentlemen. In Nurmi, A., Nevala, M. & Palander-Collin, M. (Eds.), The Language of Daily Life in England (1400–1800). Amsterdam: John Benjamins. 165–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raumolin-Brunberg, Helena & Nurmi, Arja. (2011). Grammaticalization and language change in the individual. In Narrog, H. & Heine, B. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of grammaticalization. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 251–62.Google Scholar
Riding, Richard & Rayner, Stephen. (1998). Cognitive styles and learning strategies: Understanding style differences in learning and behavior. London: Fulton.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Pascale & Sankoff, David. (1978). A solution to the problem of grouping speakers. In Sankoff, D. (Ed.), Linguistic variation: Models and methods, 97117. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Rutten, Gijsbert & van der Wal, Marijke. (2014). Social and constructional diffusion: Relative clauses in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century Dutch. In Boogaert, R., Colleman, T. & Rutten, G. (Eds.), Extending the scope of construction grammar, 181206. Berlin: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sankoff, David & Labov, William. (1979). On the uses of variable rules. Language in Society 8(2–3): 189222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sankoff, Gillian & Blondeau, Hélène. (2007). Language change across the lifespan: /r/ in Montreal French. Language 83:560–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sankoff, Gillian. (2018). Language change across the lifespan. Annual Review of Linguistics 4:297316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sankoff, Gillian. (2019). Language change across the lifespan: three trajectory types. Language 95(2). 197229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharma, Devyani, Bresnan, Joan, & Deo, Ashwini. (2008). Variation and change in the individual: Evidence from the Survey of English Dialects. In Cooper, R. & Kempson, R. (Eds.), Language in flux: Dialogue coordination, language variation, change and evolution. London: College Publications. 265321.Google Scholar
Sharma, Devyani & Dodsworth, Robin. (2020). Language variation and social networks. Annual Review of Linguistics 6:341–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smirnova, Elena. (2015). Constructionalization and constructional change: the role of context in the development of constructions. In Barđdal, J., Smirnova, E., Sommerer, L. & Gildea, S. (Eds.), Diachronic Construction Grammar. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. 81106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Standing, William. (2021). It-cleft change across the lifespan in Early Modern Authors. Doctoral dissertation, University of Antwerp.Google Scholar
Standing, William & Petré, Peter. (2021). Exploiting convention: Lifespan change and generational incrementation in the development of cleft constructions. In Beaman, K. & Buchstaller, I. (Eds.), Language variation and language change across the lifespan: Theoretical and Empirical Perspectives from Panel Studies. New York: Routledge. 141–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tagliamonte, Sali A. & D'Arcy, Alexandra. (2007). Frequency and variation in the community grammar: Tracking a new change through the generations. Language Variation and Change 19:199217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tagliamonte, Sali A. & Baayen, Harald. (2012). Models, forests and trees of York English: was/were variation as a case study for statistical practice. Language Variation and Change 24(2):135–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tagliamonte, Sali A. & Denis, Derek. (2016). The changing FUTURE: competition, specialization and reorganization in the contemporary English future temporal reference system. English Language and Linguistics 22:403–30.Google Scholar
Traugott, Elisabeth C. & Trousdale, Graeme. (2013). Constructionalization and Constructional Changes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vehtari, Aki, Gelman, Andrew & Gabry, Jonah. (2017). Practical Bayesian model evaluation using leave-one-out cross-validation and WAIC. Statistics and Computing 2017 27:1413–32.Google Scholar
Wagner, Suzanne Evans, & Sankoff, Gillian. (2011). Age grading in the Montréal French inflected future. Language Variation and Change 23:275313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watanabe, Sumio. (2010). Asymptotic Equivalence of Bayes Cross Validation and Widely Applicable Information Criterion in Singular Learning Theory. Journal of Machine Learning Research 11:3571–94.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Absolute and relative frequencies of ing-OF and ing-Ø per author

Figure 1

Table 2. Overlap and quasi-separation in the data set

Figure 2

Table 3. Model comparison of simple intercept model, predicting the posterior probability of the dependent variable at the population level, and varying author intercept model predicting the posterior probability of the dependent variable and correcting the population estimate for differences between individuals (group level effects). Number of observations = 16629, chains = 4, iterations = 4000, warmup = 1000, thin = 1

Figure 3

Figure 1. WAIC estimates and standard error of simple intercept model and varying author intercept model.

Figure 4

Table 4. WAIC and WAIC weight (rounded to 0.000001) for all models, ranked by WAIC score (ascending)

Figure 5

Figure 2. Effect plots of varying intercept model and varying slope model (n = 500).

Figure 6

Table 5. For each parameter, we provide the population-level mean estimate coefficient (Estimate), the standard deviation of the posterior distribution of the estimate (Est.Error), and the 95% Credible intervals (CI lower bound and CI upper bound). Rhat helps evaluate the estimate the posterior distribution of the parameter (Rhat = 1.0 indicates convergence). The covariance matrix of group-level effects can be found in the online repository

Figure 7

Figure 3. Effect plots of interaction effect: age*det|author.

Figure 8

Table 6. Observed changes and metadata per author (excluding Aphra Behn and George Swinnock)

Figure 9

Table 7. WAIC estimates and WAIC weight (rounded to 0.0000001) for additional models, ranked by WAIC score (ascending)