Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T17:35:58.916Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Albert algebras over $\mathbb {Z}$ and other rings

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2023

Skip Garibaldi
Affiliation:
IDA Center for Communications Research-La Jolla, 4320 Westerra Ct, San Diego, CA 92121, USA; E-mail: [email protected]
Holger P. Petersson
Affiliation:
Fakultät für Mathematik und Informatik, FernUniversität in Hagen, D-58084 Hagen, Germany; E-mail: [email protected]
Michel L. Racine
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Ottawa, 150 Louis-Pasteur Pvt, Ottawa, ON, K1N 6N5, Canada; E-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

Albert algebras, a specific kind of Jordan algebra, are naturally distinguished objects among commutative nonassociative algebras and also arise naturally in the context of simple affine group schemes of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ , $\mathsf {E}_6$ , or $\mathsf {E}_7$ . We study these objects over an arbitrary base ring R, with particular attention to the case $R = \mathbb {Z}$ . We prove in this generality results previously in the literature in the special case where R is a field of characteristic different from 2 and 3.

Type
Algebra
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

1 Introduction

Albert algebras, which are a specific kind of Jordan algebra, are naturally distinguished objects among commutative nonassociative algebras and also arise naturally in the context of simple affine group schemes of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ , $\mathsf {E}_6$ , or $\mathsf {E}_7$ . We study these objects over an arbitrary base ring R, with particular attention to the case $R = \mathbb {Z}$ . We prove in this generality results previously in the literature in the special case where R is a field of characteristic different from 2 and 3.

Why Albert algebras?

In the setting of semisimple algebraic groups over a field, a standard technique for computing with elements of a group — especially an anisotropic group — is to interpret the group in terms of automorphisms of some algebraic structure, such as viewing an adjoint group of type $\mathsf {B}_n$ as the special orthogonal group of a quadratic form of dimension $2n+1$ , or an adjoint group of inner type $\mathsf {A}_n$ as the automorphism group of an Azumaya algebra of rank $(n+1)^2$ . This approach can be seen in many references, from [Reference WeilWeil], through [Reference Knus, Merkurjev, Rost and TignolKnMRT] and [Reference ConradConrad]. In this vein, Albert algebras appear as a natural tool for computations related to $\mathsf {F}_4$ , $\mathsf {E}_6$ , and $\mathsf {E}_7$ groups, as we do below.

In the setting of nonassociative algebras, Albert algebras also arise naturally. Among commutative not-necessarily-associative algebras under additional mild hypotheses (the field has characteristic $\ne 2, 3, 5$ and the algebra is metrized), every algebra satisfying a polynomial identity of degree $\le 4$ is a Jordan algebra (see [Reference Chayet and GaribaldiChG, Proposition A.8]). Jordan algebras have an analogue of the Wedderburn-Artin theory for associative algebras [Reference JacobsonJ68, p. 201, Corollary 2], and one finds that all the simple Jordan algebras are closely related to associative algebras (more precisely, “are special”) except for one kind, the Albert algebras (see, for example [Reference JacobsonJ68, p. 210, Theorem 11] or [Reference McCrimmon and Zel’manovMcCZ]).

Our contribution

In the setting of nonassociative algebras, we prove a classification of Albert algebras over $\mathbb {Z}$ (Theorem 14.3), which was viewed as an open question in the context of nonassociative algebra; here, we see that it is equivalent to the classification of groups of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ , which was known (see [Reference ConradConrad], which leverages [Reference GrossGr] and [Reference Elkies and GrossElkiesGr]). We also prove new results about ideals in Albert algebras (Theorem 8.2), about isotopy of Albert algebras over semilocal rings (Theorem 13.3), and about the number of generators of an Albert algebra (Proposition 12.1). We have not seen Lemma 15.1 in the literature, even in the case of a base field of characteristic different from 2 and 3.

In the setting of affine group schemes, the language of Albert algebras provides a way to give concrete descriptions of the affine group schemes over $\mathbb {Z}$ (see Section 18). In that language, a clever computation in [Reference Elkies and GrossElkiesGr] appears as an example of a general mechanism known as isotopy (see Definition 14.1). To facilitate these applications, we present the definition of Albert algebras in a streamlined way (see Definition 7.1). Note that they are defined as a type of what was formerly called a “quadratic” Jordan algebra — because instead of a bilinear multiplication, one has a quadratic map, the U-operator — and that the definition makes sense whether or not 2 is invertible in the base ring. Applying the definition here allows one to replace, in some proofs, “global” computations over $\mathbb {Z}$ as one finds in [Reference ConradConrad] with “local” computations over an algebraically closed field that exist in several places in the literature (see, for example, the proof of Lemma 9.1 and Section 18).

A different definition

The definition of Albert algebra over a ring R given here (Definition 7.2) is in the context of para-quadratic algebras as recalled at the beginning of Section 5 — such an algebra is an R-module M with a distinguished element $1_M$ and a quadratic map $U \!: M \to \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_R(M)$ such that $U_{1_M} = \operatorname {\mathrm {Id}}_M$ . There are no other axioms to check. We then define a specific para-quadratic algebra, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R))$ , in Definition 6.7, and define an Albert R-algebra J to be a para-quadratic R-algebra such that $J \otimes S \cong \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R)) \otimes S$ for some faithfully flat R-algebra S.

A different approach is taken by references such as [Reference PeterssonPe19, Section 6.1] or [Reference AlsaodyAls21]. They define an Albert R-algebra to be a cubic Jordan R-algebra (Definition 6.2) J whose underlying R-module is projective of rank 27 and $J \otimes F$ is a simple algebra for every homomorphism from R to a field F. This definition involves axioms that in principle need to be verified over all R-algebras. The two definitions give the same objects. Theorem 17 in [Reference PeterssonPe19] states that an Albert algebra in the sense of that paper is an Albert algebra in the sense of this paper by proving the existence of the required faithfully flat R-algebra; a detailed proof has not been published but closely follows an argument for octonion algebras from [Reference Loos, Petersson and RacineLoPR]. For the converse, an Albert algebra in the sense of this paper has a projective underlying module (because $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R))$ does), is a cubic Jordan algebra (Proposition 10.1), and satisfies the simplicity condition (Corollary 8.5).

2 Notation

Rings, by definition, have a 1. We put ${\mathbb {Z}\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ for the category of commutative rings, where $\mathbb {Z}$ is an initial object. For any $R \in {\mathbb {Z}\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ , we put ${R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ for the category of pairs $(S, f)$ with $S \in {\mathbb {Z}\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ and $f \!: R \to S$ , that is, the coslice category $R \downarrow {\mathbb {Z}\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ . Below, R will typically denote an element of ${\mathbb {Z}\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ . (The interested reader is invited to mentally replace R by a base scheme $\mathbf {X}$ , ${R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ with the category of schemes over $\mathbf {X}$ , finitely generated projective R-modules with vector bundles over $\mathbf {X}$ , etc., thereby translating results below into a language closer to that in [Reference Calmès and FaselCalF].) An R-algebra S is said to be fppf if it is faithfully flat and finitely presented.

We write $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_n(R)$ for the ring of n-by-n matrices with entries from R, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Id}}$ for the identity matrix, and ${\left \langle {\alpha _1, \ldots , \alpha _n}\right \rangle } \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_n(R)$ for the diagonal matrix whose $(i,i)$ -entry is $\alpha _i$ . The transpose of a matrix x is denoted $x^{\intercal }$ . We write $\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}_n(R)$ for the group of invertible elements in $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_n(R)$ .

Suppose now that $\mathbf {G}$ is a finitely presented group scheme over R. For each fppf $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ , we write $H^1(S/R, \mathbf {G})$ for Čech cohomology of the sheaf of groups $\mathbf {G}$ relative to $R \to S$ (see, for example [Reference GiraudGir, Section III.3.6] or [Reference WaterhouseWa, Chapter 17]). The set $H^1(S/R, \mathbf {G})$ does not depend on the choice of structure homomorphism $R \to S$ , and more is true: Every morphism $S \to T$ in ${k\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ gives a morphism $H^1(S/R, \mathbf {G}) \to H^1(T/R, \mathbf {G})$ that is injective and does not depend on the choice of arrow $S \to T$ [Reference GiraudGir, Remark III.3.6.5]. The subcategory of fppf elements of ${R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ has a small skeleton, so the colimit

$$\begin{align*}H^1(R, \mathbf{G}) := \varinjlim_{\text{fppf } S \in {R\text{-}\textbf{alg}}} H^1(S/R, \mathbf{G}) \end{align*}$$

is a set. We call it the nonabelian fppf cohomology of $\mathbf {G}$ . In case $\mathbf {G}$ is smooth, it agrees with étale $H^1$ . If additionally R is a field, then it agrees with the nonabelian Galois cohomology defined in, for example, [Reference SerreSerre].

Unimodular elements

Let M be an R-module. An element $m \in M$ is said to be unimodular if $Rm$ is a free R-module of rank 1 and a direct summand of M, equivalently, if there is some $\lambda \in M^*$ (the dual of M) such that $\lambda (m) = 1$ . When M is finitely generated projective, this is equivalent to: $m \otimes 1$ is not zero in $M \otimes F$ for every field $F \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ (see, for example [Reference LoosLo, 0.3]). If $m \in M$ is unimodular, then so is $m \otimes 1 \in M \otimes S$ for every $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ . In the opposite direction, if M is finitely generated projective, S is a Zariski cover of R (i.e., $\operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} S \to \operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} R$ is surjective), and $m \otimes 1$ is unimodular in $M \otimes S$ , it follows that m is unimodular as an element of M.

3 Background on polynomial laws

We may identify an R-module M with a functor $\mathbf {W}(M)$ from ${R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ to the category of sets defined via $S \mapsto M \otimes S$ . For R-modules M, N, a polynomial law (in the sense of [Reference RobyRoby] or [Reference BourbakiBouA2, Section IV.5, Exercise 9]) $f \colon \mathbf {W}(M) \to \mathbf {W}(N)$ is a morphism of functors, that is, a collection of set maps $f_S \colon M \otimes S \to N \otimes S$ varying functorially with S. We put $\mathscr {P}_R(M, N)$ for the collection of polynomial laws $\mathbf {W}(M) \to \mathbf {W}(N)$ , omitting the subscript R when it is understood. Note that $\mathscr {P}_R(M, N)$ is an R-module.

Lemma 3.1. Let M be a finitely generated projective R-module, and suppose $f \in \mathscr {P}(M, N)$ is such that $f_R(0) = 0$ . If $m \in M$ has $f_R(m)$ unimodular in N, then m is unimodular.

In the case $N = R$ , the condition that $f_R(m)$ is unimodular means that $f_R(m) \in R^{\times }$ .

Proof. Replacing f with $\lambda f$ , where $\lambda \in N^*$ is such that $\lambda (f_R(m)) = 1$ , we may assume $N = R$ and $f_R(m) = 1$ . If m is not unimodular, then there is a field $F \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ , such that $m \otimes 1 = 0$ in $M \otimes F$ , and $f_F(m \otimes 1) = 0$ , whence $f_R(m)$ belongs to the kernel of $R \to F$ a contradiction.

A polynomial law is homogeneous of degree $d \ge 0$ if $f_S(sx) = s^d f_S(x)$ for every $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ , $s \in S$ , and $x \in M \otimes S$ (see [Reference RobyRoby, p. 226]). We put $\mathscr {P}^d_R(M, N)$ for the submodule of $\mathscr {P}_R(M, N)$ of polynomial laws that are homogeneous of degree d. The polynomial laws that are homogeneous of degree 0 are constants, and those of degree 1 are linear transformations, that is, the natural maps

$$\begin{align*}N \to \mathscr{P}_R^0(M, N) \quad \text{and} \quad \operatorname{\mathrm{Hom}}_R(M, N) \to \mathscr{P}_R^1(M, N) \end{align*}$$

are isomorphisms (see [Reference RobyRoby, pp. 230, 231]). For degree $2$ , $\mathscr {P}_R^2(M,N)$ is canonically identified with the maps $f \colon M \to N$ that are quadratic in the sense that $f(rm) = r^2f(m)$ and the map $M\times M \to N$ defined by $f(m_1,m_2) := f(m_1 + m_2) - f(m_1) - f(m_2)$ is bilinear [Reference RobyRoby, p. 236, Proposition II.1]. A form of degree d on M is a polynomial law $\mathbf {W}(M) \to \mathbf {W}(R)$ that is homogeneous of degree d. The forms of degree 2 are commonly known as quadratic forms on M.

Directional derivatives

For $f \in \mathscr {P}(M, N)$ , $v \in M$ , t an indeterminate, and $n \ge 0$ , we define a polynomial law $\nabla _v^n f$ as follows. For $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ and $x \in M \otimes S$ , $f_{S[t]}(x + v \otimes t)$ is an element of $N \otimes S[t]$ , and we define $\nabla _v^n f_S(x) \in N \otimes S$ to be the coefficient of $t^n$ . This defines a polynomial law called the n-th directional derivative $\nabla _v^n f$ of f in the direction v. One finds that $\nabla ^0_v f = f$ regardless of v. We abbreviate $\nabla _v f := \nabla _v^1 f$ ; it is linear in v.

If f is homogeneous of degree d and $0 \le n \le d$ , then $\nabla _v^n f(x)$ is homogeneous of degree $d - n$ in x and degree n in v. The symmetry implicit in the definition of the directional derivative gives $\nabla _v^n f(x) = \nabla _x^{d-n} f(v)$ for $x \in M$ .

Lemma 3.2. Suppose M, N are R-modules and A is a unital associative R-algebra and $g \in \mathscr {P}(M , A)$ is a polynomial law such that there is an element $m \in M$ such that $g_R(m) \in A$ is invertible. If $f \in \mathscr {P}^d(M, N)$ satisfies

$$\begin{align*}g_S(x) \in (A \otimes S)^{\times} \Rightarrow f_S(x) = 0 \end{align*}$$

for all $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ and $x \in M \otimes S$ , then $f = 0$ .

Proof. Since the hypotheses are stable under base change, it suffices to show that $f(v) = 0$ for all $v \in M$ . Replacing g by $L \circ g \in \mathscr {P}(M, A)$ , where $L \in \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_R(A)$ is multiplication in A on the left by the inverse of $g_R(m)$ , we may assume $g_R(m) = 1_A$ . Set $S := R[\varepsilon ]/(\varepsilon ^{d+1})$ . For $v \in M$ , the element

$$\begin{align*}g_S(m + \varepsilon v) = 1_A + \sum_{n=1}^d \varepsilon^n \nabla_v^n g_R(m) \end{align*}$$

is invertible in $A_S$ , so by hypothesis,

$$\begin{align*}0 = f_S(m+\varepsilon v) = \sum_{n = 0}^d \varepsilon^n \nabla_v^n f_R(m). \end{align*}$$

Focusing on the coefficient of $\varepsilon ^d$ in that equation gives

$$\begin{align*}0 = \nabla_v^d f_R(m) = \nabla_m^0 f_R(v) = f_R(v), \end{align*}$$

as required.

While Lemma 3.2 has some similarity with the principle of extension of algebraic identities as in [Reference BourbakiBouA2, Section IV.2.3], that result imposes some hypothesis on R.

The module of polynomial laws

In the following, we write $\mathsf {S}^n M$ for the n-th symmetric power of M, that is, the R-module $\otimes ^n M$ modulo the submodule generated by elements $x - \sigma (x)$ for $x \in \otimes ^n M$ and $\sigma $ a permutation of the n factors.

Lemma 3.3. Let M and N be finitely generated projective R-modules. Then for each $d \ge 0$ :

  1. 1. $\mathscr {P}^d(M, N)$ is a finitely generated projective R-module.

  2. 2. If $T \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ is flat, the natural map $\mathscr {P}^d_R(M, N) \otimes T \to \mathscr {P}^d_T(M \otimes T, N \otimes T)$ is an isomorphism.

  3. 3. The natural map $\mathsf {S}^d(M^*) \otimes N \to \mathscr {P}^d(M, N)$ is an isomorphism.

  4. 4. The natural map $\mathscr {P}^d(M, R) \otimes N \to \mathscr {P}^d(M, N)$ is an isomorphism.

Proof. To establish notation, we write $R = \prod _{i=0}^n R_i$ for some n such that $M = \prod _i M_i$ and $N = \prod _i N_i$ with each $M_i$ , $N_i$ an $R_i$ -module of finite constant rank.

Next write $\Gamma _d(M)$ for the module of degree d divided powers on M as defined in [Reference BourbakiBouA2, Section IV.5, Exercise 2]. We claim that it is finitely generated projective, and therefore, by [Stacks, Tag 00NX], finitely presented. If M is free, then $\Gamma _d(M)$ is free. If M is projective of constant rank, then there exists $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ faithfully flat such that $M \otimes S$ is free. Because $\Gamma _d$ commutes with base change [Reference BourbakiBouA2, Section IV.5, Exercise 7], $\Gamma _d(M) \otimes S \cong \Gamma _d(M \otimes S)$ is free, and we again find that $\Gamma _d(M)$ is finitely generated projective [Stacks, Tags 03C4, 05A9]. In the general case, $\Gamma _d(M) = \prod _i \Gamma _d(M_i)$ , and the claim is verified.

To verify (2), we note that $\mathscr {P}^d_R(M, N)$ is naturally isomorphic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_R(\Gamma _d(M), N)$ by [Reference RobyRoby, Theorem IV.1]. Then $\mathscr {P}^d_R(M, N) \otimes T \cong \operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_R(\Gamma _d(M), N) \otimes T$ , which in turn is $\operatorname {\mathrm {Hom}}_T(\Gamma _d(M) \otimes T, N \otimes T)$ because T is flat and $\Gamma _d(M)$ is finitely presented [Reference BourbakiBouCA, Section I.2.10, Proposition 11]. Since $\Gamma _d$ commutes with base change, we have verified (2).

(3): If M and N are free modules, then the map is an isomorphism by [Reference RobyRoby, p. 232]. If M and N have constant rank, then there is a faithfully flat $T \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ such that $M \otimes T$ and $N \otimes T$ are free. Since (3) holds over T by the free case, (2) and faithfully flat descent give that (3) holds. In the general case, $\mathscr {P}^d(M, N) = \prod \mathscr {P}^d(M_i, N_i)$ and $\mathsf {S}^d(M^*) \otimes N = \prod (\mathsf {S}^d(M_i^*) \otimes N_i)$ and the claim follows by the constant rank case.

(4) follows trivially from (3). For (1), note that $M^*$ is finitely generated projective, so are $\mathsf {S}^d(M^*)$ and the tensor product $\mathsf {S}^d(M^*) \otimes N$ . Applying (3) gives the claim.

One can create new polynomial laws from old by twisting by a line bundle, that is, by a rank 1 projective module.

Lemma 3.4. Let M and N be finitely generated projective R-modules. Then for every $d \ge 0$ and every line bundle L, we have:

  1. 1. There is a natural isomorphism $\mathscr {P}^d(M, N) \otimes (L^*)^{\otimes d} \to \mathscr {P}^d(M \otimes L, N)$ .

  2. 2. There is a natural isomorphism $\mathscr {P}^d(M, N) \cong \mathscr {P}^d(M \otimes L, N \otimes L^{\otimes d})$ .

Proof. For (1), since $L^*$ is a line bundle, the natural map $(L^*)^{\otimes d} \to \mathsf {S}^d(L^*)$ is an isomorphism because it is so after faithfully flat base change. Since $\mathsf {S}^d(M^*) \otimes \mathsf {S}^d(L^*)$ is naturally identified with $\mathsf {S}^d((M \otimes L)^*)$ , combining Lemma 3.3(3),(4) then gives (1).

For (2), there are isomorphisms $\mathscr {P}^d(M \otimes L, N \otimes L^{\otimes d}) \xrightarrow {\sim } \mathscr {P}^d(M, N) \otimes (L^*)^{\otimes d} \otimes L^{\otimes d}$ by (1) and Lemma 3.3(4). Since $L^{\otimes d} \otimes (L^*)^{\otimes d} \cong R$ , the claim follows.

Example 3.5. (References: [Stacks, Tag 03PK], [Reference Calmès and FaselCalF, Section 2.4.3], [Reference KnusKn, Section III.3]) Suppose L is a line bundle and there is an isomorphism $h \colon L^{\otimes d} \to R$ for some $d \ge 1$ . We call such a pair $[L, h]$ a d-trivialized line bundle. (In the case $d = 2$ , they are sometimes called discriminant modules.) Applying h to identify $N \otimes L^{\otimes d} \xrightarrow {\sim } N$ in Lemma 3.4(2) gives a construction that takes $f \in \mathscr {P}^d(M, N)$ and gives an element of $\mathscr {P}^d(M \otimes L, N)$ , which we denote by $[L, h] \cdot (M, f)$ .

For example, for each $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ , define ${\left \langle {\alpha }\right \rangle }$ to be $[L, h]$ as in the preceding paragraph, where $L = R$ and h is defined by $h(\ell _1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \ell _d) = \alpha \prod \ell _i$ . Clearly, ${\left \langle {\alpha \beta ^d}\right \rangle } \cong {\left \langle {\alpha }\right \rangle }$ for all $\alpha , \beta \in R^{\times }$ . Applying the construction in the previous paragraph, we find ${\left \langle {\alpha }\right \rangle } \cdot (M, f) \cong (M, \alpha f)$ .

Every $[L, h]$ with $L = R$ is necessarily isomorphic to ${\left \langle {\alpha }\right \rangle }$ for some $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ . In particular, if $\operatorname {\mathrm {Pic}}(R)$ has no d-torsion elements other than zero — for example, if R is a semilocal ring or a UFD [Stacks, Tags 0BCH, 02M9] — then each $[L, h]$ is isomorphic to ${\left \langle {\alpha }\right \rangle }$ for some $\alpha $ . The group scheme $\mu _d$ of d-th roots of unity is the automorphism group of each $[L, h]$ , where $\mu _d$ acts by multiplication on L. The group $H^1(R, \mu _d)$ classifies pairs $[L, h]$ up to isomorphism.

We say that homogeneous polynomial laws related by the isomorphism in Lemma 3.4(2) are projectively similar, imitating the language from [Reference Auel, Bernardara and BolognesiAuBB, Section 1.2] for the case of quadratic forms ( $d = 2$ ). (This relationship was called “lax-similarity” in [Reference Balmer and CalmèsBC].) We say that homogeneous degree d laws f and $[L, h] \cdot f$ for $[L, h] \in H^1(R, \mu _d)$ as in the preceding example are similar. If $\operatorname {\mathrm {Pic}}(R)$ is d-torsion, the two notions coincide.

For $f \in \mathscr {P}^d(M, N)$ , we define $\operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}(f)$ to be the subgroup of $\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(M)$ consisting of elements g such that $fg = f$ as polynomial laws. In case M and N are finitely generated projective, so is $\mathscr {P}^d(M, N)$ , whence the functor $\mathbf {Aut}(f)$ from ${R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ to groups defined by $\mathbf {Aut}(f)(T) = \operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}(f_T)$ is a closed sub-group-scheme of $\mathbf {GL}(M)$ .

Lemma 3.6. Let f and $f'$ be homogeneous polynomial laws on finitely generated projective modules. If f and $f'$ are projectively similar, then their automorphism groups are isomorphic.

Proof. By hypothesis, $f \in \mathscr {P}^d(M, N)$ and $f' \in \mathscr {P}^d(M \otimes L, N \otimes L^{\otimes d})$ for some modules M and N, line bundle L, and $d \ge 0$ . The group scheme $\mathbf {Aut}(f)$ is the closed sub-group-scheme of $\mathbf {GL}(M)$ stabilizing the element f in $\mathsf {S}^d(M^*) \otimes N$ . Now, any element of $\mathbf {GL}(M)$ acts on $\mathsf {S}^d((M \otimes L)^*) \otimes (N \otimes L^{\otimes d})$ by defining it to act as the identity on L. In this way, we find a homomorphism $\mathbf {Aut}(f) \to \mathbf {Aut}(f')$ . Viewing M as $(M \otimes L) \otimes L^*$ and N as $(N \otimes L^{\otimes d}) \otimes (L^*)^{\otimes d}$ , and repeating this construction, we find an inverse mapping $\mathbf {Aut}(f') \to \mathbf {Aut}(f)$ .

4 Background on composition algebras

A not-necessarily-associative R-algebra C is an R-module with an R-linear map $C \otimes _R C \to C$ , which we view as a multiplication and write as juxtaposition. Such a C is unital if it has an element $1_C \in C$ such that $1_C c = c 1_C = c$ for all $c \in C$ (see, for example, [Reference SchaferSch]). A composition R-algebra as in [Reference PeterssonPe93] is such a C that is finitely generated projective as an R-module, is unital, and has a quadratic form $n_C \!: C \to R$ that allows composition (that is, such that $n_C(xy) = n_C(x)n_C(y)$ for all $x, y \in C$ ), satisfies $n_C(1_C) = 1$ , and whose bilinearization defined by $n_C(x, y) := n_C(x+y) - n_C(x) - n_C(y)$ gives an isomorphism $C \to C^*$ via $x \mapsto n_C(x, \cdot )$ . We say that a symmetric bilinear form with this property is regular. The quadratic form $n_C$ (which is unique by Proposition 4.3 below) is called the norm of C.

Remark 4.1. In the definition above, one can swap the condition $n_C(1_C) = 1$ with the requirement that the rank of C is nowhere zero, that is, $C \otimes F \ne 0$ for every field $F \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ .

We put $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C(x) := n_C(x, 1_C)$ , a linear map $C \to R$ , called the trace of C. Trivially, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C(1_C) = 2$ . Lemma 3.1 gives that $1_C$ is unimodular, so we may identify R with $R1_C$ , and C is a faithful R-module. The unimodularity of $1_C$ is equivalent to the existence of some $\lambda \in C^*$ such that $\lambda (1_C) = 1$ , that is, some $x \in C$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C(x) = 1$ , whence $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C \colon C \to R$ is surjective.

The class of composition algebras is stable under base change. That is, if C is a composition R-algebra with norm $n_C$ , then for every $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ , $C \otimes S$ is a composition S-algebra with norm $n_C \otimes S$ . The following two results are essentially well known [Reference PeterssonPe93, 1.2 $-$ 1.4]. For convenience, we include their proof.

Lemma 4.2 (“Cayley-Hamilton”)

Let C be a composition algebra with norm $n_C$ , and define $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C$ as above. Then

$$\begin{align*}x^2 - \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_C(x) x + n_C(x) 1_C = 0 \end{align*}$$

for all $x \in C$ .

Proof. Linearizing the composition law $n_C(xy) = n_C(x) n_C(y)$ , we find

(4.1) $$ \begin{align} n_C(xy, x) = n_C(x) \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_C(y) \quad \text{and} \end{align} $$
(4.2) $$ \begin{align} n_C(xy, wz) + n_C(wy, xz) = n_C(x,w) n_C(y,z) \end{align} $$

for all $x, y, z, w \in C$ . Setting $z = x$ and $w = 1_C$ in (4.2), we find:

$$\begin{align*}n_C(xy, x) + n_C(y, x^2) = \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_C(x) n_C(x, y). \end{align*}$$

Combining these with (4.1), we find:

$$\begin{align*}n_C(x^2 - \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_C(x) x + n_C(x) 1_C, y) = 0 \quad \text{for all } x, y \in C. \end{align*}$$

Since the bilinear form $n_C$ is regular, the claim follows.

A priori, a composition algebra is a unital algebra together with a quadratic form, the norm. The next result shows that these data are redundant.

Proposition 4.3. If C is a composition algebra, then the norm $n_C$ is uniquely determined by the algebra structure of C.

Proof. Let $n' \colon C \to R$ be any quadratic form making C a composition algebra, and write $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}'$ for the corresponding trace $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}'(x) := n'(x + 1_C) - n'(x) - n'(1_C)$ . Then $\lambda := \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C - \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}'$ (respectively, $q := n_C - n'$ ) is a linear (respectively, quadratic) form on C and the Cayley-Hamilton property yields

(4.3) $$ \begin{align} \lambda(x) x = q(x) 1_C \quad \text{for all } x \in C. \end{align} $$

We aim to prove that $q = 0$ . Because $1_C$ is unimodular, it suffices to prove $\lambda = 0$ . This can be checked locally, so we may assume that R is local and, in particular, $C = R1_C \oplus M$ for a free module M. Now, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C(1_C) = 2 = \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}'(1_C)$ , so $\lambda (1_C) = 0$ . For $m \in M$ a basis vector, $\lambda (m)m$ belongs to $M \cap R1_C$ by (4.3), so it is zero, whence $\lambda (m) = 0$ , proving the claim.

Corollary 4.4. Let C be a unital R-algebra. If there is a faithfully flat $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ such that $C \otimes S$ is a composition S-algebra, then C is a composition algebra over R.

Proof. Because the norm $n_{C \otimes S}$ of $C \otimes S$ is uniquely determined by the algebra structure, one obtains by faithfully flat descent a quadratic form $n_C \colon C \to R$ such that $n_C \otimes S = n_{C \otimes S}$ . Because $n_{C \otimes S}$ satisfies the properties required to make $C \otimes S$ a composition algebra and S is faithfully flat over R, it follows that the same properties hold for $n_C$ .

The following facts are standard, see, for example [Reference KnusKn, Section V.7]: Composition algebras are alternative algebras. The map $\bar {\ } \!: C \to C$ defined by $\overline {x} := \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C(x)1_C - x$ is an involution, that is, an R-linear antiautomorphism of period 2.

Composition algebras of constant rank

In case R is connected — that is, $R \not \cong R_1 \times R_2$ , where neither $R_1$ nor $R_2$ are the zero ring — a composition R-algebra has rank $2^e$ for $e \in \{ 0, 1, 2, 3 \}$ [Reference KnusKn, p. 206, Theorem V.7.1.6]. Therefore, specifying a composition R-algebra C is equivalent to writing

(4.4) $$ \begin{align} R = \prod_{e=0}^3 R_e \quad \text{and} \quad C = \prod_{e=0}^3 C_e, \end{align} $$

where $C_e$ is a composition $R_e$ -algebra of constant rank $2^e$ .

If C is a composition algebra of rank 1, then since $1_C$ is unimodular, C is equal to R. The bilinear form $n_C(\cdot , \cdot )$ gives an isomorphism $C \to C^*$ and $n_C(1_C, \alpha 1_C) = 2\alpha $ , and we deduce that $2$ is invertible in R. Conversely, if 2 is invertible, then R is a composition algebra by setting $n_C(\alpha ) = \alpha ^2$ ; in this case, we say that R is a split composition algebra.

A composition algebra whose rank is 2 is not just an associative and commutative ring, it is an étale algebra [Reference KnusKn, p. 43, Theorem I.7.3.6]. Conversely, every rank 2 étale algebra is a composition algebra. Among rank 2 étale algebras, there is a distinguished one, $R \times R$ , which is said to be split.

A composition algebra whose rank is 4 is associative and is an Azumaya algebra, commonly known as a quaternion algebra. (Note that our notion of quaternion algebra is more restrictive than the one in the books [Reference KnusKn, see p. 43] and [Reference VoightVo].) Among quaternion R-algebras, there is a distinguished one, the 2-by-2 matrices $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_2(R)$ , which is said to be split.

A composition algebras whose rank is 8 is known as an octonion algebra. Among octonion R-algebras, there is a distinguished one that is said to be split, called the Zorn vector matrices and denoted $\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R)$ (see [Reference Loos, Petersson and RacineLoPR, 4.2]). As a module, we view it as $\left ( \begin {smallmatrix} R & R^3 \\ R^3 & R \end {smallmatrix} \right )$ with multiplication

$$\begin{align*}\left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & u \\ x & \alpha_2 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \beta_1 & v \\ y & \beta_2 \end{smallmatrix} \right) = \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 \beta_1 - u^{\intercal} y & \alpha_1 v + \beta_2 u + x \times y \\ \beta_1 x + \alpha_2 y + u \times v & {-x^{\intercal} v + \alpha_2 \beta_2}\end{smallmatrix} \right), \end{align*}$$

where $\times $ is the ordinary cross product on $R^3$ . The quadratic form is

$$\begin{align*}n_{\operatorname{\mathrm{Zor}}(R)}\left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & u \\ x & \alpha_2 \end{smallmatrix} \right) = \alpha_1 \alpha_2 + u^{\intercal} x. \end{align*}$$

One says that a composition R-algebra C is split if, when we write R and C as in (4.4), $C_e$ is isomorphic to the split composition $R_e$ -algebra for $e \ge 1$ .

It is well known in the case where $R = \mathbb {R}$ , the real numbers, that a composition algebra is determined up to isomorphism by its dimension and whether it is split. That is, there are only seven isomorphism classes of composition $\mathbb {R}$ -algebras, consisting of four split ones and four division algebras, namely, $\mathbb {R}$ , $\mathbb {C}$ , $\mathbb {H}$ , and $\mathbb {O}$ ; note that both collections of four contain $\mathbb {R}$ .

Example 4.5. The real octonions $\mathbb {O}$ are a composition $\mathbb {R}$ -algebra with basis $1_{\mathbb {O}}$ , $e_1$ , $e_2$ , $\ldots $ , $e_7$ which is orthonormal with respect to the quadratic form $n_{\mathbb {O}}$ with multiplication table

$$\begin{align*}e_r^2 = -1 \quad \text{and} \quad e_r e_{r+1} e_{r+3} = -1 \end{align*}$$

for all r with subscripts taken modulo 7, and the displayed triple product is associative.

The $\mathbb {Z}$ -sublattice $\mathcal {O}$ of $\mathbb {O}$ spanned by $1_{\mathbb {O}}$ , the $e_r$ , and

$$ \begin{align*} h_1 = (1 + e_1 + e_2 + e_4)/2, \quad h_2 = (1 + e_1 + e_3 + e_7)/2, \\ h_3 = (1 + e_1 + e_5 + e_6)/2 \quad \text{and} \quad h_4 = (e_1 + e_2 + e_3 + e_5)/2 \end{align*} $$

is a composition $\mathbb {Z}$ -algebra. It is a maximal order in $\mathcal {O} \otimes \mathbb {Q}$ , and all such are conjugate under the automorphism group of $\mathcal {O} \otimes \mathbb {Q}$ . (As a consequence, there is some choice in the way one presents this algebra. We have followed [Reference Elkies and GrossElkiesGr].) As a subring of $\mathbb {O}$ , it has no zero divisors. For more on this, see [Reference DicksonDi, Section 19], [Reference CoxeterCox], [Reference Conway and SmithConwS, Section 9], or [Reference ConradConrad, Section 5]. The nonuniqueness of this choice of maximal order and its relationship to other orders like $\mathbb {Z} \oplus \mathbb {Z} e_1 \oplus \cdots \oplus \mathbb {Z} e_7$ can be understood in terms of the Bruhat-Tits building of the group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Q}_2))$ of type $\mathsf {G}_2$ over the 2-adic numbers, compare [Reference Gan and YuGanY, Section 9].

5 Background on Jordan algebras

Para-quadratic algebras

A (unital) para-quadratic algebra over a ring R is an R-module J together with a quadratic map $U \colon J \to \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_R(J)$ — that is, U is an element of $\mathscr {P}^2(J, \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_R(J))$ — called the U-operator, and a distinguished element $1_J \in J$ such that $U_{1_J} = \operatorname {\mathrm {Id}}_J$ . A homomorphism $\phi \colon J \to J'$ of para-quadratic R-algebras is an R-linear map such that $\phi (1_J) = 1_{J'}$ and $U^{\prime }_{\phi (x)} \phi (y) = \phi (U_x y)$ for all $x, y \in J$ , where $U'$ denotes the U-operator in $J'$ .

Jordan algebras

As a notational convenience, we define a linear map $J \otimes J \otimes J \to J$ denoted $x \otimes y \otimes z \mapsto \{ xyz\}$ via

(5.1) $$ \begin{align} \{ x y z \} := (U_{x+z} - U_x - U_z)y. \end{align} $$

Evidently, $\{ x y z \} = \{ z y x \}$ for all $x, y, z \in J$ . A para-quadratic R-algebra J is a Jordan R-algebra if the identities

(5.2) $$ \begin{align} U_{U_x y} = U_x U_y U_x \quad \text{and} \quad U_x \{ yxz \} = \{ (U_xy) z x \} \end{align} $$

hold for all $x, y, z \in J\otimes S$ for all $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ . (Alternatively, one can define a Jordan R-algebra entirely in terms of identities concerning elements of J, avoiding the “for all $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ ”, at the cost of requiring a longer list of identities (see [Reference McCrimmonMcC66, Section 1]).) Note that if J is a Jordan R-algebra, then $J \otimes T$ is a Jordan T-algebra for every $T \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ (“Jordan algebras are closed under base change”). If J is a para-quadratic algebra and $J \otimes T$ is Jordan for some faithfully flat $T \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ , then J is Jordan.

For x in a Jordan algebra J and $n \ge 0$ , we define the n-th power $x^n$ via

(5.3) $$ \begin{align} x^0 := 1_J, \quad x^1 := x, \quad x^n = U_x x^{n-2} \ \text{for } n \ge 2. \end{align} $$

An element $x \in J$ is invertible with inverse y if $U_x y = x$ and $U_x y^2 = 1$ [Reference McCrimmonMcC66, Section 5]. It turns out that x is invertible if and only if $U_x$ is invertible if and only if $1$ is in the image of $U_x$ ; when these hold, the inverse of x is $y = U_x^{-1} x$ , which we denote by $x^{-1}$ . It follows from (5.2) that $x,y \in J$ are both invertible if and only if $U_xy$ is invertible, and in this case, $(U_xy)^{-1} = U_{x^{-1}}y^{-1}$ .

Example 5.1. Let A be an associative and unital R-algebra. Define $U_xy := xyx$ for $x, y \in A$ . Then $\{ xyz\} = xyz + zyx$ and A endowed with this U-operator is a Jordan algebra denoted by $A^+$ . Note that for $x \in A$ and $n \ge 0$ , the n-th powers of x in A and $A^+$ are the same.

Relations with other kinds of algebras

Suppose for this paragraph and the next that 2 is invertible in R. Given a para-quadratic algebra J as in the preceding paragraph, one can define a commutative (bilinear) product $\bullet $ on J via

(5.4) $$ \begin{align} x \bullet y := \frac12 \{x1_Jy \} \quad \text{for } x, y \in J. \end{align} $$

(In the case where J is constructed from an associative algebra as in Example 5.1, one finds that $x \bullet y = \frac 12 (xy + yx)$ . If, additionally, the associative algebra is commutative, $\bullet $ equals the product in that associative algebra.) If J is Jordan, then $\bullet $ satisfies

(5.5) $$ \begin{align} (x \bullet y) \bullet (x \bullet x) = x \bullet (y \bullet (x \bullet x)), \end{align} $$

which is the axiom classically called the “Jordan identity”.

In the opposite direction, given an R-module J with a commutative product $\bullet $ with identity element $1_J$ , we obtain a para-quadratic algebra by setting

(5.6) $$ \begin{align} U_x y := 2x \bullet (x \bullet y) - (x \bullet x) \bullet y \quad \text{for } x, y \in J. \end{align} $$

If the original product satisfied the Jordan identity, then the para-quadratic algebra so obtained satisfies (5.2), that is, is a Jordan algebra in our sense (see, for example [Reference JacobsonJ69, Section 1.4]).

Definition 5.2 (hermitian matrix algebras)

Let C be a composition R-algebra and $\Gamma = {\left \langle {\gamma _1, \gamma _2, \gamma _3}\right \rangle } \in \operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}_3(R)$ . We define $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ to be the R-submodule of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(C)$ consisting of elements fixed by the involution $x \mapsto \Gamma ^{-1} \bar {x}^{\intercal } \Gamma $ and with diagonal entries in R. Note that, as an R-module, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ is a sum of three copies of C and three copies of R, so it is finitely generated projective.

In the special case where 2 is invertible in R, one can define a multiplication $\bullet $ on $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ via $x \bullet y := \frac 12 (xy + yx)$ , where juxtaposition denotes the usual product of matrices in $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(C)$ . It satisfies the Jordan identity [Reference JacobsonJ68, p. 61, Corollary], and therefore, the U-operator defined via (5.6) makes $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ into a Jordan algebra.

6 Cubic Jordan algebras

In this section, we define cubic Jordan algebras and the closely related notion of cubic norm structure. They provide a useful alternative language for computation.

Definition 6.1. Following [Reference McCrimmonMcC69] (see [Reference Petersson and RacinePeR86a, p. 212] for the terminology), we define a cubic norm R-structure as a quadruple $\mathbf {M} = (M,1_{\mathbf {M}},\sharp ,N_{\mathbf {M}})$ consisting of an R-module M; a distinguished element $1_{\mathbf {M}} \in M$ (the base point); a quadratic map $\sharp \colon M \to M$ , written $x \mapsto x^{\sharp }$ (the adjoint) with (symmetric bilinear) polarization $x \times y := (x + y)^{\sharp } - x^{\sharp } - y^{\sharp };$ and a cubic form $N_{\mathbf {M}}\colon M \to R$ (the norm) such that the following axioms are fulfilled. Define a bilinear form $T_{\mathbf {M}}\colon M \times M \to R$ by

(6.1) $$ \begin{align} T_{\mathbf{M}}(x,y) := (\nabla_xN_{\mathbf{M}})(1_{\mathbf{M}})(\nabla_yN_{\mathbf{M}})(1_{\mathbf{M}}) - (\nabla_x\nabla_yN_{\mathbf{M}})(1_{\mathbf{M}}) \end{align} $$

(the bilinear trace), which is symmetric since the directional derivatives $\nabla _x$ , $\nabla _y$ commute [Reference RobyRoby, p. 241, Proposition II.5], and a linear form $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_{\mathbf {M}}\colon M \to R$ by

(6.2) $$ \begin{align} \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_{\mathbf{M}}(x) := T_{\mathbf{M}}(x,1_{\mathbf{M}}) \end{align} $$

(the linear trace). For $\mathbf {M}$ to be a cubic norm structure, we require that the identities

(6.3) $$ \begin{align} 1_{\mathbf{M}}^{\sharp} = 1_{\mathbf{M}}, \quad N_{\mathbf{M}}(1_{\mathbf{M}}) = 1, \end{align} $$
(6.4) $$ \begin{align} 1_{\mathbf{M}} \times x = \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_{\mathbf{M}}(x)1_{\mathbf{M}} - x,\; (\nabla_yN_{\mathbf{M}})(x) = T_{\mathbf{M}}(x^{\sharp},y),\:x^{\sharp\sharp} = N_{\mathbf{M}}(x)x \end{align} $$

hold in all scalar extensions $M \otimes S$ , $S\in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ .

For such a cubic norm structure $\mathbf {M}$ , we then define a U-operator by

(6.5) $$ \begin{align} U_xy := T_{\mathbf{M}}(x,y)x - x^{\sharp} \times y, \end{align} $$

which together with $1_{\mathbf {M}}$ converts the R-module M into a Jordan R-algebra $J = J(\mathbf {M})$ [Reference McCrimmonMcC69, Theorem 1]. In the sequel, we rarely distinguish carefully between the cubic norm structure $\mathbf {M}$ and the Jordan algebra $J(\mathbf {M})$ . By abuse of notation, we write $1_J = 1_{\mathbf {M}}$ , $N_J = N_{\mathbf {M}}$ , $T_J = T_{\mathbf {M}}$ , and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_J:= \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_{\mathbf {M}}$ if there is no danger of confusion, even though, in general, J does not determine $\mathbf {M}$ uniquely [Reference Petersson and RacinePeR86a, p. 216].

Definition 6.2. A Jordan R-algebra J is said to be cubic if there exists a cubic norm R-structure $\mathbf {M}$ as in Definition 6.1 such that (i) $J = J(\mathbf {M})$ and (ii) $J = M$ is a finitely generated projective R-module. With the quadratic form $S_J\colon M \to R$ defined by $S_J(x) := \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_J(x^{\sharp })$ for $x \in J$ (the quadratic trace), the cubic Jordan algebra J satisfies the identities

(6.6) $$ \begin{align} (U_xy)^{\sharp} = U_{x^{\sharp}}y^{\sharp}, \quad N_J(U_xy)U_xy = N_J(x)^2N_J(y)U_xy, \end{align} $$
(6.7) $$ \begin{align} U_xx^{\sharp} = N_J(x)x, \quad U_x(x^{\sharp})^2 = N_J(x)^21_J, \end{align} $$
(6.8) $$ \begin{align} x^{\sharp} = x^2 - \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_J(x)x + S_J(x)1_J \quad \text{and} \end{align} $$
(6.9) $$ \begin{align} x^3 - \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_J(x)x^2 + S_J(x)x - N_J(x)1_J = 0 = x^4 - \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_J(x)x^3 + S_J(x)x^2 - N_J(x)x \end{align} $$

for all $x \in J$ . For (6.6)–(6.8) and the first equation of (6.9), see [Reference McCrimmonMcC69, p. 499], while the second equation of (6.9) follows from the first, (6.7), and (6.8) via $x^4 = U_xx^2 = U_xx^{\sharp } + \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_J(x)U_xx - S_J(x)U_x1_J = \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_J(x)x^3 - S_J(x)x^2 + N_J(x)x$ .

Remark 6.3. Note that the second equality of (6.9) derives from the first through formal multiplication by x. But, due to the para-quadratic character of Jordan algebras, this is not a legitimate operation unless $2$ is invertible in R. In fact, cubic Jordan algebras exist that contain elements x satisfying $x^2 = 0 \neq x^3$ [Reference JacobsonJ69, 1.31–1.32].

Example 6.4 (3-by-3 matrices)

We claim that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(R)^+$ is a cubic Jordan algebra, in particular, it is $J(\mathbf {M})$ for $\mathbf {M} := (\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(R), \operatorname {\mathrm {Id}}, \sharp , \det )$ , where $\sharp $ denotes the classical adjoint. We first verify that $\mathbf {M}$ is a cubic norm structure. Computing directly from the definition (6.1), we find that $T_{\mathbf {M}}(x,y) = \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_{\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(R)}(xy)$ , where the juxtaposition on the right is usual matrix multiplication. The formulas in (6.3) are obvious. For (6.4), the first two equations can be verified directly and the third equation is a standard property of the classical adjoint, completing the proof that $\mathbf {M}$ is a cubic norm structure. Similarly, one can check directly that the U-operator defined from the cubic norm structure by (6.5) equals the U-operator defined from the usual matrix product in Example 5.1, that is, $J(\mathbf {M}) = \operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(R)^+$ .

Lemma 6.5. Let J be a cubic Jordan R-algebra and $x,y \in J$ .

  1. 1. x is invertible in J if and only if $N_J(x)$ is invertible in R. In this case

    $$\begin{align*} x^{-1} = N_J(x)^{-1}x^{\sharp} \quad \text{and} \quad N_J(x^{-1}) = N_J(x)^{-1}. \end{align*}$$
  2. 2. Invertible elements of J are unimodular.

  3. 3. $N_J(U_xy) = N_J(x)^2N_J(y)$ and $N_J(x^2) = N_J(x)^2 = N_J(x^{\sharp })$ .

Proof. (1): If $N_J(x)$ is invertible in R, then (6.7) shows that so is x, with inverse $x^{-1} = N_J(x)^{-1}x^{\sharp }$ . Conversely, assume x is invertible in J. Then $y := (x^{-1})^2$ satisfies $U_xy = 1_J$ , and (6.6) yields $1_J = N_J(U_xy)U_xy = N_J(x)^2N_J(y)1_J$ , hence

$$\begin{align*}N_J(x)^2N_J(y) = 1 \end{align*}$$

since $1_J$ is unimodular by Lemma 3.1 and (6.3). Thus, $N_J(x) \in R^{\times }$ . Before proving the final formula of (1), we deal with (2), (3).

(2) follows immediately from Lemma 3.1 combined with the first part of (1).

(3): Applying Lemma 3.2 to the polynomial law $g\colon J \times J \to \operatorname {\mathrm {End}}_R(J)$ defined by $g(x,y) := U_{U_xy}$ in all scalar extensions, we may assume that $U_xy$ is invertible. By (2), therefore, $U_xy$ is unimodular, and the first equality follows from (6.6). The second equality follows from the first for $y = 1_J$ , while in the third equality, we may again assume that x is invertible, hence, unimodular. Then (6.7) combines with the first equality to imply $N_J(x)^4 = N_J(N_J(x)x) = N_J(U_xx^{\sharp }) = N_J(x)^2N_J(x^{\sharp })$ , as desired.

Now the second equality of (1) follows from the first and (3) via

$$\begin{align*}N_J(x^{-1}) = N_J(x)^{-3}N_J(x^{\sharp}) = N_J(x)^{-1}.\end{align*}$$

Without the assumption that J is finitely generated projective as an R-module, Lemma 6.5 would be false [Reference Petersson and RacinePeR85, Theorem 10].

Example 6.6. We endow the R-module $M := \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C,\Gamma )$ from Definition 5.2 with a cubic norm R-structure $\mathbf {M}= (M,1_{\mathbf {M}},\sharp ,N_{\mathbf {M}})$ , where $1_{\mathbf {M}}$ is the 3-by-3 identity matrix. An element $x \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ may be written as

$$\begin{align*}x = \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & \gamma_2 c_3 & \gamma_3 \bar{c}_2 \\ \gamma_1 \bar{c}_3 & \alpha_2 & \gamma_3 c_1 \\ \gamma_1 c_2 & \gamma_2 \bar{c}_1 & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \end{align*}$$

for $\alpha _i \in R$ and $c_i \in C$ . Because three of the entries are determined by symmetry, we may denote such an element by

(6.10) $$ \begin{align} x := \sum\nolimits_{i=1}^3 \left( \alpha_i \varepsilon_i + \delta_i^{\Gamma}(c_i) \right), \end{align} $$

where $\varepsilon _i$ has a 1 in the $(i, i)$ entry and zeros elsewhere, and $\delta _i^{\Gamma }(c)$ has $\gamma _{i+2}c$ in the $(i+1, i+2)$ entry — where the symbols $i+1$ and $i+2$ are taken modulo 3 — and zeros in the other entries not determined by symmetry. In the literature on Jordan algebras, one finds the notation $c[(i+1)(i+2)]$ for what we denote $\delta _i^{\Gamma }(c)$ . We define the adjoint $\sharp $ by

$$\begin{align*}x^{\sharp} := \sum\nolimits_{i=1}^3\Big(\big(\alpha_{i+1}\alpha_{i+2} - \gamma_{i+1}\gamma_{i+2}n_C(c_i)\big)\varepsilon_i + \delta_i^{\Gamma}\big({-\alpha_ic_i} + \gamma_i\overline{c_{i+1}c_{i+2}}\big)\Big) \end{align*}$$

with indices modulo (mod) 3, and the norm $N_{\mathbf {M}}$ by

(6.11) $$ \begin{align} N_{\mathbf{M}}(x) := \alpha_1\alpha_2\alpha_3 - \sum\nolimits_{i=1}^3\gamma_{i+1}\gamma_{i+2}\alpha_in_C(c_i) + \gamma_1\gamma_2\gamma_3\mathrm{Tr}_C(c_1c_2c_3) \end{align} $$

in all scalar extensions, where the last summand on the right of (6.11) is unambiguous since $\mathrm {Tr}_C((c_1c_2)c_3) = \mathrm {Tr}_C(c_1(c_2c_3))$ [Reference McCrimmonMcC85, Theorem 3.5]. By [Reference McCrimmonMcC69, Theorem 3], $\mathbf {M}$ is indeed a cubic norm structure. The corresponding cubic Jordan algebra will again be denoted by $J := \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C,\Gamma ) := J(\mathbf {M})$ .

(In case 2 is invertible in R, the commutative product $\bullet $ on $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ defined from the U-operator by (5.4) equals the product $x \bullet y := \frac 12 (xy + yx)$ from Definition 5.2. In order to see this, it suffices to note that the square of $x \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ as defined in (5.3) is the same as the square of x in the matrix algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(C)$ . This in turn follows immediately from (6.8), (6.11), and the definition of the adjoint.)

For x as above and $y = \sum (\beta _i\varepsilon _i + \delta _i^{\Gamma }(d_i))$ , with $\beta _i \in R$ , $d_i \in C$ , evaluating the bilinear trace at $x,y$ yields

(6.12) $$ \begin{align} T_J(x,y) = \sum\nolimits_{i=1}^3 \big(\alpha_i\beta_i + \gamma_{i+1}\gamma_{i+2}n_C(c_i, d_i)\big). \end{align} $$

Since the bilinearization of $n_C$ is regular, so is $T_J$ .

Here is an important special case.

Definition 6.7. For the special case where $\Gamma = \operatorname {\mathrm {Id}}$ , we define $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C) := \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \operatorname {\mathrm {Id}})$ and write $\delta _i$ for $\delta _i^{\Gamma }$ . It can be useful to write elements of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ as

$$\begin{align*}\left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & c_3 & \cdot \\ \cdot & \alpha_2 & c_1 \\ c_2 & \cdot & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right), \end{align*}$$

where $\cdot $ denotes an entry that is omitted because it is determined by symmetry. As an example of the triple product defined from (5.1) and (6.5), we mention that for $x = \sum \alpha _i \varepsilon _i$ diagonal, we have

(6.13) $$ \begin{align} \{ \delta_i(a) \delta_{i+1}(b) x \} = \delta_{i+2}(\overline{ab}) \alpha_i \quad \text{and} \quad \{ \delta_{i+1}(b) \delta_i(a) x \} = \delta_{i+2}(\overline{ab}) \alpha_{i+1} \end{align} $$

for $i \in 1, 2, 3$ taken mod 3 and $a, b \in C$ .

Note that, for the Jordan algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ , if we multiply $\Gamma $ by an element of $R^{\times }$ or any entry in $\Gamma $ by the square of an element of $R^{\times }$ , we obtain an algebra isomorphic to the original. Therefore, replacing $\Gamma $ by ${\left \langle { (\det \Gamma )^{-1} \gamma _1, (\det \Gamma )^{-1} \gamma _2, (\det \Gamma ) \gamma _3}\right \rangle }$ does not change the isomorphism class of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ , and we may assume that $\gamma _1 \gamma _2 \gamma _3 = 1$ .

Example 6.8. When studying the Jordan R-algebras $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ in the special case $R = \mathbb {R}$ , the preceding paragraph shows that it is sufficient to consider two choices for $\Gamma $ , namely, ${\left \langle {1, s, s}\right \rangle }$ for $s = \pm 1$ . We compute $T_{\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )}$ for each choice of C and $\Gamma $ . Regular symmetric bilinear forms over $\mathbb {R}$ are classified by their dimension and signature (an integer), so it suffices to specify the signature. If $C = \mathbb {R}$ , $\mathbb {C}$ , $\mathbb {H}$ , or $\mathbb {O}$ , the signature of $n_C$ is $2^r$ for $r = 0$ , 1, 2, 3, respectively. By (6.12), $T_J$ has signature $3(1 + 2^r)$ for $J = \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ and $3 - 2^r$ for $J = \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, {\left \langle {1, -1, -1}\right \rangle })$ . For $C$ the split composition algebra of rank $2^r$ for $r = 1$ , 2, or 3 and any $\Gamma$ , the signature of $n_C$ is 0 and the signature of $T_{\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma)}$ is 3.

Remark 6.9. Alternatively, one could define the Jordan algebra structure on $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ for an arbitrary ring R without referring to cubic norm structures as follows. Writing out the formulas for the U-operator from Definition 5.2 in case $R = \mathbb {Q}$ , one finds that the formulas do not involve any denominators other than $\gamma _i$ terms and therefore make sense for any R regardless of whether 2 is invertible. This makes $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ a para-quadratic algebra. Because it is a Jordan algebra in case $R = \mathbb {Q}$ as in Definition 5.2, we conclude that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ is a Jordan algebra with no hypothesis on R by extension of identities [Reference BourbakiBouA2, Section IV.2.3, Theorem 2]. This alternative definition gives the same objects but is much harder to work with.

7 Albert algebras are Freudenthal algebras are Jordan algebras

Definition 7.1. A split Freudenthal R-algebra is a Jordan algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ as in Definition 6.7 for some split composition R-algebra C. Because split composition algebras are determined up to isomorphism by their rank function, so are split Freudenthal algebras.

A para-quadratic R-algebra J is a Freudenthal algebra if $J \otimes S$ is a split Freudenthal S-algebra for some faithfully flat $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ . It is immediate that every Freudenthal algebra is a Jordan algebra. Since every split Freudenthal R-algebra is finitely generated projective as an R-module for every R, the same is true for every Freudenthal R-algebra J, and by the same reasoning, we see that the identity element $1_J$ is unimodular. Because the rank of a composition algebra takes values in $\{ 1, 2, 4, 8 \}$ , the rank of a Freudenthal algebra takes values in $\{ 6, 9, 15, 27 \}$ .

We are now prepared to define the objects named in the title of this paper.

Definition 7.2. An Albert R-algebra is a Freudenthal R-algebra of rank 27.

We continue to prove results about Freudenthal algebras, rather than merely Albert algebras. The extra generality comes at a low cost.

Proposition 7.3. For every composition R-algebra C and every $\Gamma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}_3(R)$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ is a Freudenthal algebra.

Proof. Replacing R with $R_e$ as in (4.4), we may assume that C has constant rank. There is a faithfully flat $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ such that $C \otimes S$ is a split composition algebra.

Consider $T := S[t_1, t_2, t_3] / (t_1^2 - \gamma _1, t_2^2 - \gamma _2, t_3^2 - \gamma _3)$ . It is a free S-module, so faithfully flat. Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma ) \otimes T$ is isomorphic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C \otimes T)$ as Jordan algebras, and the latter is a split Freudenthal algebra.

A Freudenthal algebra is said to be reduced if it is isomorphic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ for some C and $\Gamma $ .

Example 7.4. Let J be a Freudenthal R-algebra. If $x \in J$ has $U_x = \operatorname {\mathrm {Id}}_J$ , then $x = \zeta 1_J$ for some $\zeta \in R$ such that $\zeta ^2 = 1$ . To see this, first suppose that J is $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ for some composition algebra C and write $x = \sum (\alpha _i \varepsilon _i + \delta _i(c_i))$ for $\alpha _i \in R$ and $c_i \in C$ . We find

$$\begin{align*}U_x \varepsilon_i = \alpha_i^2 \varepsilon_i + \delta_{i+2}(\alpha_i c_{i+2}) + \cdots \end{align*}$$

for each i, so $\alpha _i^2 = 1$ and $c_{i+2} = 0$ for all i. Then

$$\begin{align*}U_x \delta_i(1_C) = \delta_i(\alpha_{i+1} \alpha_{i+2} 1_C). \end{align*}$$

Since $1_C$ is unimodular, $\alpha _{i+1} \alpha _{i+2} = 1$ for all i, proving the claim for this J.

For general J, let $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ be faithfully flat such that $J \otimes S$ is split. Then $x \in J$ maps to an element of $R1_J \otimes S \subseteq J \otimes S$ and so belongs to $R1_J \subseteq J$ . Since $U_{\zeta 1_J} = \zeta ^2 \operatorname {\mathrm {Id}}_J$ for $\zeta \in R$ , the claim follows.

The following result is well known when R is a field or perhaps a local ring (see, for example [Reference PeterssonPe19, Proposition 20]). We impose no hypothesis on R.

Proposition 7.5. Suppose C is a split composition R-algebra of constant rank at least 2, that is, C is $R \times R$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_2(R)$ , or $\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R)$ . Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma ) \cong \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ for all $\Gamma $ .

Proof. Define $\gamma _i$ via $\Gamma = {\left \langle {\gamma _1, \gamma _2, \gamma _3}\right \rangle }$ . We may assume $\gamma _1\gamma _2\gamma _3 = 1$ . Since $n_C$ is universal, there are invertible $p, q \in C$ such that $\gamma _2 = n_C(q^{-1})$ and $\gamma _3 = n_C(p^{-1})$ , so $\gamma _1 = n_C(pq)$ . We define $C^{(p,q)}$ to be a not-necessarily-associative R-algebra with the same underlying R-module structure and with multiplication $\cdot _{(p,q)}$ defined by

$$\begin{align*}x \cdot_{(p,q)} y := (xp)(qy), \end{align*}$$

where the multiplication on the right is the multiplication in C. Certainly $(pq)^{-1}$ is an identity element in $C^{(p,q)}$ . The algebra $C^{(p,q)}$ is called an isotope of C and is studied in [Reference McCrimmonMcC71a], where it is proved to be alternative. One checks that it is a composition algebra with quadratic form $n_{C^{(p,q)}} = n_C(pq) n_C$ (see [Reference McCrimmonMcC71a, Proposition 5] for a more general statement in case R is a field).

Define $\phi \!: \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C^{(p,q)}) \to \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ via $\phi (\sum x_i \varepsilon _i + \delta _i(c_i)) = \sum x_i \varepsilon _i + \delta _i^{\Gamma }(c^{\prime }_i)$ , where

$$\begin{align*}c^{\prime}_1 = (pq) c_1 (pq), \quad c^{\prime}_2 = c_2p, \quad \text{and} \quad c^{\prime}_3 = qc_3. \end{align*}$$

It is evidently an isomorphism of R-modules, and one checks that it is an isomorphism of Jordan algebras, compare [Reference McCrimmonMcC71a, Theorem 3]. Therefore, we are reduced to verifying that $C^{(p,q)}$ is split.

If C is associative, then the R-linear map

$$\begin{align*}L_{pq} \colon C^{(p,q)} \to C\text{ such that} \quad L_{pq}(x) = pqx \end{align*}$$

is an isomorphism of R-algebras. So assume $C = \operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R)$ .

At the beginning, when we chose p and q, we were free to pick $\xi _i, \eta _i \in R^{\times }$ such that $p = \left ( \begin {smallmatrix} \xi _1 & 0 \\ 0 & \xi _2 \end {smallmatrix} \right )$ and $q = \left ( \begin {smallmatrix} \eta _1 & 0 \\ 0 & \eta _2 \end {smallmatrix} \right )$ . Let $A \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(R)$ be any matrix such that $\det A = (\xi _1 \xi _2^2 \eta _1^2 \eta )^{-1}$ and put $B := \xi _2 \eta _1 (A^{\sharp })^{\intercal }$ , where $\sharp $ denotes the classical adjoint. With $\zeta _i := (\xi _i \eta _i)^{-1}$ , one checks, using the formula $(Sx) \times (Sy) = (S^{\sharp })^{\intercal }(x \times y)$ for $\times $ the usual cross product in $R^3$ , that the assignment

$$\begin{align*}\left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & u_1 \\ u_2 & \alpha_2 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \mapsto \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \zeta_1 \alpha_1 & Au_1 \\ Bu_2 & \zeta_2 \alpha_2 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \end{align*}$$

defines an isomorphism $C \xrightarrow {\sim } C^{(p,q)}$ .

8 The ideal structure of Freudenthal algebras

It is a standard exercise to show that every (two-sided) ideal in the matrix algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_n(R)$ is of the form $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_n(\mathfrak {a})$ for some ideal $\mathfrak {a}$ in R. More generally, every ideal in an Azumaya R-algebra A is of the form $\mathfrak {a} A$ some ideal $\mathfrak {a}$ of R [Reference Knus and OjangurenKnO, p. 95, Corollary III.5.2].

A similar result holds for every octonion R-algebra C: Every one-sided ideal in C is a two-sided ideal that is stable under the involution on C. The maps $I \mapsto I \cap R$ and are bijections between the set of ideals of C and ideals in R. See [Reference PeterssonPe21, Section 4] for a proof in this generality and the references therein for earlier results of this type going back to [Reference MahlerMa].

We now prove a similar result for Freudenthal algebras.

Definition 8.1. An ideal in a para-quadratic R-algebra J is the kernel of a homomorphism, that is, an R-submodule I such that

$$\begin{align*}U_I J + U_J I + \{ J J I \} = I, \end{align*}$$

where we have written $U_I J$ for the R-span of $U_x y$ with $x \in I$ and $y \in J$ . (This is sometimes written with a $\subseteq $ instead of $=$ , but the two are equivalent since $U_J I \supseteq U_{1_J} I = I$ .) An R-submodule I is an outer ideal if

(8.1) $$ \begin{align} U_J I + \{ J J I \} = I. \end{align} $$

Here are some observations about outer ideals:

  1. 1. Every ideal is an outer ideal.

  2. 2. If 2 is invertible in R, then for every $x \in I$ and $y \in J$ , $U_x y = \frac 12 \{ xyx \} \in \{ J J I \}$ , so the notions of ideal and outer ideal coincide, and both agree with the notion of ideal for the commutative bilinear product $\bullet $ defined in (5.4).

  3. 3. For every ideal $\mathfrak {a}$ in R, the R-submodule $\mathfrak {a} J$ is an ideal of J.

  4. 4. If $1_J$ is unimodular, then for every outer ideal I of J, $I \cap R1_J$ is an ideal in R, for the trivial reason that I is an R-module.

  5. 5. If $\mathfrak {a}$ is an ideal in R and $1_J$ is unimodular, then $\mathfrak {a} 1_J = (\mathfrak {a} J) \cap R 1_J$ . The containment $\subseteq $ is clear. To see the opposite containment, suppose $\alpha 1_J \in \mathfrak {a} J \cap R1_J$ for some $\alpha \in R$ and write $\alpha 1_J = \sum \alpha _i y_i$ with $\alpha _i \in \mathfrak {a}$ and $y_i \in J$ . There is some R-linear $\lambda \!: J \to R$ such that $\lambda (1_J) = 1$ . Then $\alpha = \lambda (\alpha 1_J) = \sum \alpha _i \lambda (y_i)$ is in $\mathfrak {a}$ .

Theorem 8.2. Let J be a Freudenthal R-algebra. Every outer ideal of J is an ideal. The maps $I \mapsto I \cap R1_J$ and are bijections between the set of outer ideals of J and the set of ideals of R.

Proof. It suffices to show that the stated maps are bijections, because then observation (3) implies that every outer ideal is of the form $\mathfrak {a} J$ and therefore an ideal. In view of (5) (noting that $1_J$ is unimodular), it suffices to verify that $(I \cap R1_J)J = I$ for every outer ideal I. First suppose that $J = \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ for some composition R-algebra C and write $\mathfrak {a} := I \cap R1_J$ . The Peirce projections relative to the diagonal frame of J, that is, $U_{\varepsilon _i}$ and $x \mapsto \{\varepsilon _j x \varepsilon _l \}$ for $i, j, l = 1, 2, 3$ [Reference McCrimmonMcC66, p. 1074] stabilize I, and we find

$$\begin{align*}I = \sum_i (I \cap R\varepsilon_i) + (I \cap \delta_i(C)). \end{align*}$$

Set $B := \{ c \in C \mid \delta _1(c) \in I \}$ . We claim that B is an ideal in C. Note that $U_{\delta _1(1_C)} \delta _1(b) = \delta _1(\bar {b})$ , so B is stable under the involution.

We leverage (6.13). Repeatedly applying this with $a = 1_C$ and using that B is stable under the involution, we conclude that $\delta _i(B) = I \cap \delta _i(C)$ for all i. For $c \in C$ and $b \in B$ , I contains $\{ 1_J \delta _2(\bar {c}) \delta _1(\bar {b}) \} = \delta _3(c b)$ , so $cB \subseteq B$ , that is, B is an ideal in C and therefore $B = \mathfrak {a} C$ for some ideal $\mathfrak {a}$ of R.

For $c \in C$ , I contains $\{ \delta _i(1_C) \varepsilon _{i+1} \delta _i(\mathfrak {a} c) \} = \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C(\mathfrak {a} c) \varepsilon _{i+2}$ . Since $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_C$ is surjective, $\mathfrak {a} \varepsilon _j \subseteq I$ for all j.

In the other direction, if $\alpha _i \varepsilon _i \in I$ , then so is

$$\begin{align*}\{ \delta_{i+1}(1_C) 1_J (\alpha_i \varepsilon_i) \} = \delta_{i+1}(\alpha_i 1_C). \end{align*}$$

It follows that $I \cap R\varepsilon _i = \mathfrak {a} R$ for all i and, in particular, $I \cap R1_J = \mathfrak {a} R$ and $I = \mathfrak {a} J$ .

We now treat the general case. Suppose I is an outer ideal in a Freudenthal R-algebra J. There is a faithfully flat $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ , such that $J \otimes S$ is a split Freudenthal algebra. We have

$$\begin{align*}((I \cap R1_J) J) \otimes S = ((I \otimes S) \cap S1_J) (J \otimes S) = I \otimes S, \end{align*}$$

where the first equality is because S is flat and the second is by the previous case, since $I \otimes S$ is an outer ideal. It follows that $I = (I \cap R1_J)J$ as desired.

Remark 8.3. In the proof above, the inclusion $(I \cap R1_J) J \subseteq I$ could instead have been argued as follows. Define $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sq}}(J)$ as the R-submodule of J generated by $x^2$ for $x \in J$ . Since $1_J$ is unimodular, one finds that $(I \cap R1_J) \operatorname {\mathrm {Sq}}(J) \subseteq I$ . Then, one argues that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sq}}(J) = J$ for a split Freudenthal algebra, and that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sq}}(J \otimes S) = \operatorname {\mathrm {Sq}}(J) \otimes S$ for all flat $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ .

Corollary 8.4. Let $\phi \colon J \to A$ be a homomorphism of para-quadratic R algebras. If J is a Freudenthal algebra and $1_A$ is unimodular in A, then $\phi $ is injective.

In particular, the corollary applies to every homomorphism between Freudenthal R-algebras.

Proof. The kernel of $\phi $ is an ideal of J and therefore $\mathfrak {a} J$ for some ideal $\mathfrak {a}$ of R. For $\alpha \in \mathfrak {a}$ , we have $0 = \phi (\alpha 1_J) = \alpha \phi (1_J) = \alpha 1_A$ , so $\alpha = 0$ because $1_{A}$ is unimodular.

Because a Freudenthal algebra J is a projective R-module of rank $\ge 3$ , the corollary says that there is no homomorphism of para-quadratic R-algebras $J \to R^+$ . This might be stated as J is not augmented or J has no counit.

A para-quadratic algebra J is said to be simple if the underlying module is not the zero module and if every ideal in J equals 0 or J. Theorem 8.2 immediately gives:

Corollary 8.5. If J is a Freudenthal R-algebra and R is a field, then J is simple. $\Box $

Remark 8.6. There is also the notion of an inner ideal in a Jordan algebra (see [Reference McCrimmonMcC71b, Theorem 8] for a description of them for $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R))$ ). The inner ideals are related to the projective homogeneous varieties associated with the group of isometries described in Section 15 and “outer automorphisms” relating these varieties (see [Reference RacineRac] and [Reference Carr and GaribaldiCarrG]).

9 Groups of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ and $\mathsf {C}_3$

In the following, for a Jordan R-algebra J, we write $\operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}(J)$ for the ordinary group of R-linear automorphisms of J and $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ for the functor from ${R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ to groups such that $S \mapsto \operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}(J \otimes S)$ . Recall that for every simple root datum, there is a unique simple group scheme over $\mathbb {Z}$ called a Chevalley group [Reference Demazure and GrothendieckDemG, Corollary XXIII.5.4], and every split simple algebraic group over a field is obtained from a unique Chevalley group by base change [Reference MilneMilne, Section 23g].

Lemma 9.1. Let J be a Freudenthal algebra of rank 15 or 27 over a ring R. Then $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ is a semisimple R-group scheme that is adjoint (i.e., its center is the trivial group scheme). Its root system has type $\mathsf {C}_3$ if J has rank 15 and type $\mathsf {F}_4$ if J has rank 27. If J is the split Freudenthal algebra, then the group scheme $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ is obtained from the Chevalley group over $\mathbb {Z}$ by base change.

Proof. First suppose that $R = \mathbb {Z}$ and J is split. If J has rank 15, then the proof of 14.19 in [Reference SpringerSp73] shows that the automorphisms of $J \otimes F$ for every field F are exactly the automorphisms of the algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_6(F)$ with the split symplectic involution, which is the split adjoint group $\operatorname {\mathrm {PGSp}}_6$ of type $\mathsf {C}_3$ . For J of rank 27, $\mathbf {Aut}(J) \times F$ is split of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ by [Reference JacobsonJ71, Section 6] (written for Lie algebras), [Reference FreudenthalFr85, Satz 4.11] (written for $\mathbb {R}$ ), [Reference Springer and VeldkampSpV, Theorem 7.2.1] (if $\operatorname {\mathrm {char}} F \ne 2, 3$ ), or [Reference SpringerSp73, 14.24] in general.

Note that $\mathbf {Aut}(J) \times F$ is connected and smooth as a group scheme over F, and $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ is finitely presented (because $\mathbb {Z}$ is noetherian and J is a finitely generated module), so it follows by [Reference Gan and YuGanY, Proposition 6.1] or [Reference Alsaody and GilleAlsG, Lemma B.1] that $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ is smooth as a scheme over the Dedekind domain $\mathbb {Z}$ . In summary, $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ is semisimple and adjoint of the specified type. Moreover, because $\mathbf {Aut}(J) \times \mathbb {Q}$ is split, $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ is a Chevalley group [Reference ConradConrad, Theorem 1.4].

In the case of general R and J, let $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ be faithfully flat such that $J \otimes S$ is split. Then $\mathbf {Aut}(J) \times S$ is semisimple adjoint of the specified type. Certainly, $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ is also smooth. Moreover, for each $\mathfrak {p} \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} R$ , there is a $\mathfrak {q} \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} S$ such that $\mathfrak {q} \cap R = \mathfrak {p}$ . Then the field of fractions $R(\mathfrak {p})$ of $R/\mathfrak {p}$ embeds in the field $S(\mathfrak {q})$ , so the algebraic closure $\overline {R(\mathfrak {p})}$ includes in the algebraic closure $\overline {S(\mathfrak {q})}$ . Because $\mathbf {Aut}(J) \times \overline {S(\mathfrak {q})}$ is adjoint semisimple of the specified type and this property is unchanged by replacing one algebraically closed field by a smaller one, the same holds over $\overline {R(\mathfrak {p})}$ . Since this holds for every $\mathfrak {p}$ , the claim is verified.

Remark 9.2. In case R is a field, the automorphism group of the split Freudenthal algebra of rank 6 or 9 can be deduced in a similar manner, referring to 14.17 and 14.16 in [Reference SpringerSp73]. The automorphism group of the split Freudenthal algebra of rank 9 is $\operatorname {\mathrm {PGL}}_3 \rtimes \mathbb {Z}/2$ . The automorphism group of the split Freudenthal algebra of rank 6 is the special orthogonal group of the quadratic form $x^2 + y^2 + z^2$ , that is, the group commonly denoted $\mathrm {SO}(3)$ . In particular, it is not smooth when R is a field of characteristic 2, and indeed, one can give examples of Freudenthal algebras of rank 6 over a field F of characteristic 2 that are not split by any separable field extension of F. (From this, it follows that such an algebra is not split by any étale F-algebra R.)

Suppose J, $J_0$ are Jordan R-algebras and there is an fppf $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ and an isomorphism $f \colon J \otimes S \to J_0 \otimes S$ . The isomorphism f gives a class in $H^1(S/R, \mathbf {Aut}(J_0))$ that depends only on the isomorphism class of J as a Jordan R-algebra. Analogous statements apply when the role of Jordan algebras is replaced with affine group schemes. This is the source of the diagonal arrows in the theorem below.

Theorem 9.3. Let $J_0$ be a Freudenthal R-algebra of rank $r = 15$ or 27. In the diagram

all arrows are bijections that are functorial in R.

Proof. The top arrow has the claimed codomain by Lemma 9.1.

Every Freudenthal algebra is split by some faithfully flat R-algebra by definition, so the discussion preceding the theorem of the statement yields the lower left arrow.

As another consequence of Lemma 9.1, the conjugation map $\mathbf {Aut}(J_0) \to \mathbf {Aut}(\mathbf {Aut}(J_0))$ is an isomorphism that we use to identify $H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(J_0)) \xrightarrow {\sim } H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(\mathbf {Aut}(J_0)))$ . Every semisimple group scheme is split by some faithfully flat R-algebra (even an étale cover) [Reference Demazure and GrothendieckDemG, Corollary XXIV.4.1.6], and the remarks before the statement of the theorem now define the lower right arrow.

The facts that the diagram commutes and that the diagonal arrows are bijective are general features of the machinery of descent as in [Reference WaterhouseWa, Theorem 17.6] or see [Reference Calmès and FaselCalF, 2.2.4.5].

The machinery of descent shows a more refined statement, where each of the boxes in the theorem are replaced by groupoids and the arrows are equivalences of groupoids. In that statement, the bottom box is replaced by the groupoid of $\mathbf {Aut}(J_0)$ -torsors and the diagonal arrows are provided by [Reference GiraudGir, p. 151, Theorem III.2.5.1].

In the theorem, the set $H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(J_0))$ is naturally a pointed set and the bijections are actually of pointed sets, where the distinguished elements are $J_0$ in the upper left and $\mathbf {Aut}(J_0)$ in the upper right.

In case R is a field of characteristic different from 2, 3 and $r = 27$ , the theorem goes back to [Reference HijikataHij]. Or see [Reference Knus, Merkurjev, Rost and TignolKnMRT, 26.18]. The statement of the theorem is similar to various statements over a field that can be found in [Reference SerreSerre, Section III.1].

Corollary 9.4. For each Freudenthal R-algebra J of rank 15 or 27, there is an étale cover $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ such that $J \otimes S$ is a split Freudenthal algebra.

Proof. Let $J_0$ be the split Freudenthal R-algebra of the same rank as J. The image $\mathbf {Iso}(J, J_0)$ of J in $H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(J_0))$ is an $\mathbf {Aut}(J_0)$ -torsor. Since $\mathbf {Aut}(J_0)$ is smooth (Lemma 9.1), there is an étale cover of R that trivializes $\mathbf {Iso}(J, J_0)$ .

Note that exactly the same kind of argument gives analogues of Lemma 9.1 and Theorem 9.3 for composition algebras, where $r = 4$ or 8, and the group is of type $\mathsf {A}_1$ or $\mathsf {G}_2$ , respectively.

10 Generic minimal polynomial of a Freudenthal algebra

Polynomials with polynomial-law coefficients

Let J be a Jordan R-algebra, $\mathscr {P}(J, R)$ the R-algebra of polynomial laws from J to R, and t a variable. Consider a polynomial $\mathbf {p}(t) = \sum _{i=0}^n f_it^i$ with $f_i \in \mathscr {P}(J, R)$ for $0 \leq i \leq n$ . For $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ , $x \in J \otimes S$ , we have $\mathbf {p}(t,x) := \sum _{i=0}^nf_{iS}(x)t^i \in S[t]$ , and we define

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{p}(x,x) := \sum_{i=0}^nf_{iS}(x)x^i \quad \in J \otimes S. \end{align*}$$

The algebra J is said to satisfy $\mathbf {p}$ if $\mathbf {p}(x,x) = 0 = (t\mathbf {p})(x,x)$ for all $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ and $x \in J \otimes S$ . Note that the second equation follows from the first if $2$ is invertible in R but not in general (see Remark 6.3).

The generic minimal polynomial

Let $J := \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ as in Example 6.6. With a variable t, we recall from (6.9) that J satisfies the monic polynomial

(10.1) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{m}_J = t^3 - \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_J\cdot t^2 + S_J\cdot t - N_J \quad \in \mathscr{P}(J, R)[t]. \end{align} $$

More precisely, by [Reference LoosLo, 2.4(b)], J is generically algebraic of degree $3$ in the sense of [Reference LoosLo, 2.2] and $\mathbf {m}_J$ is the generic minimal polynomial of J, that is, the unique monic polynomial in $\mathscr {P}(J,R)[t]$ of minimal degree satisfied by J [Reference LoosLo, 2.7]. It follows that the Jordan algebra J determines the polynomial $\mathbf {m}_J$ uniquely. In particular, the generic norm $N_J$ , the generic trace $T_J$ (or $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_J$ ) and, in fact, the cubic norm structure underlying J in the sense of Definition 6.2 are uniquely determined by J as a Jordan algebra. By faithfully flat descent, every Freudenthal algebra J has a uniquely determined generic minimal polynomial of the form (10.1), and a uniquely determined underlying cubic norm structure. We conclude:

Proposition 10.1. Every Freudenthal algebra J is a cubic Jordan algebra and the bilinear trace form $T_J$ is regular. $\Box $

The preceding discussion shows that, for a Freudenthal R-algebra J, the Jordan algebra structure of J alone (ignoring that J is a cubic Jordan algebra) determines the bilinear form $T_J$ . (For example, the 11 Freudenthal $\mathbb {R}$ -algebras discussed in Example 6.8 have distinct trace forms and therefore are distinct.) When R is a field of characteristic $\ne 2, 3$ and J and $J'$ are reduced Freudenthal algebras, Springer proved that the converse also holds, that is, $J \cong J'$ if and only if $T_J \cong T_{J'}$ [Reference Springer and VeldkampSpV, Theorem 5.8.1]. We do not use Springer’s result in this paper.

The following result can also be found in [Reference PeterssonPe19, Corollary 18(b)], based on the definition of Albert algebra appearing there.

Lemma 10.2. Let J and $J'$ be Freudenthal R-algebras. An R-linear map $\phi \!: J \to J'$ is an isomorphism of para-quadratic algebras if and only if $\phi $ is surjective, $\phi (1_J) = 1_{J'}$ , and $N_{J'} = N_J \phi $ as polynomial laws.

Proof. The “only if” direction follows from the uniqueness of the generic minimal polynomial as in (10.1), so we show “if”. The equality $N_{J'} = N_J \phi $ of polynomial laws and the definition of the directional derivative in Section 3 gives formulas, such as

$$\begin{align*}\nabla_y N_J(x) = \nabla_{\phi(y)} N_{J'}(\phi(x)). \end{align*}$$

Since $\phi (1_J) = 1_{J'}$ , the definition of the bilinear forms $T_J$ and $T_{J'}$ in (6.1) give:

$$\begin{align*}T_{J'}(\phi (x), \phi (y)) = T_J(x, y) \end{align*}$$

for all $x, y$ . Therefore, on the one hand we have

$$\begin{align*}\nabla_y N_J(x) = T_J(x^{\sharp}, y) = T_{J'}(\phi(x^{\sharp}), \phi(y)). \end{align*}$$

On the other hand, we have

$$\begin{align*}\nabla_y N_J(x) = \nabla_{\phi(y)} N_{J'}(\phi(x)) = T_{J'}((\phi(x))^{\sharp}, \phi(y)). \end{align*}$$

Therefore, $\phi (x^{\sharp }) = \phi (x)^{\sharp }$ for all x. In summary, $\phi $ commutes with $\sharp $ and preserves $T_J$ . Therefore, by (6.5), $\phi $ is a homomorphism of Jordan algebras.

Suppose that x is in $\ker \phi $ . Then for all $y \in J$ , $T_J(x, y) = T_{J'}(\phi (x), \phi (y)) = 0$ , so $x = 0$ since the bilinear form $T_J$ is regular. Since $\phi $ is both surjective and injective, it is an isomorphism.

Example 10.3. We claim that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(R \times R)$ , the split Freudenthal algebra of rank 9, is isomorphic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(R)^+$ . To see this, define $\pi _i \!: R \times R \to R$ to be the projection on the i-th coordinate and define $\phi \colon \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(R \times R) \to \operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(R)^+$ by sending

$$\begin{align*}\left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & c_3 & \cdot \\ \cdot & \alpha_2 & c_1 \\ c_2 & \cdot & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \mapsto \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & \pi_1(c_3) & \pi_2(c_2)\\ \pi_2(c_3) & \alpha_2 & \pi_1(c_1) \\ \pi_1(c_2) & \pi_2(c_2) & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \quad \text{for } \alpha_i \in R \text{ and } c_i \in R \times R. \end{align*}$$

This map is obviously R-linear and surjective and sends the identity to the identity. One checks directly that $\phi $ preserves norms, that is, that $\det (\phi (x))$ equals $N(x)$ according to (6.11). Because $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(R \times R)$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(R)^+$ are both cubic Jordan algebras with regular trace bilinear forms, the proof of the “if” direction of Lemma 10.2 shows that $\varphi $ is an isomorphism of Jordan algebras.

11 Basic classification results for Albert algebras

In the case where R is a field, such as the real numbers, a finite field, a local field, or a global field, one can find in many places in the literature classifications of Albert algebras proved using techniques involving algebras as in [Reference Springer and VeldkampSpV, Section 5.8]. For such an R, groups of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ can be classified using techniques from algebraic groups, such as in [Reference Platonov and RapinchukPlRap, Chapter 6] or [Reference GilleGil19]. The two approaches are equivalent by Theorem 9.3.

Example 11.1 (Albert algebras over $\mathbb {R}$ )

Up to isomorphism, there are three Albert $\mathbb {R}$ -algebras, namely, the split one $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {R}))$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathbb {O}, {\left \langle {1, -1, -1}\right \rangle })$ , and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathbb {O})$ . Rather than proving this in the language of Jordan algebras as in [Reference Albert and JacobsonAlbJ, Theorem 10], one may leverage Theorem 9.3 as follows. The three algebras are pairwise nonisomorphic because their trace forms are (Example 6.8). At the same time, a computation in the Weyl group of $\mathsf {F}_4$ as in [Reference SerreSerre, Section III.4.5], [Reference Borovoi and EvenorBorE, 14.1], or [Reference Adams and TaïbiAdT, Table 3] shows that $H^1(\mathbb {R}, \mathbf {Aut}(\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {R}))))$ has three elements. That is, there are exactly three isomorphism classes of simple affine group schemes over $\mathbb {R}$ of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ , so we have found all of them.

Example 11.2 (Albert algebras over global fields)

Let A be an Albert F-algebra for F a global field. Put $\Omega $ for the (finite) set of inequivalent embeddings $\omega \colon F \hookrightarrow \mathbb {R}$ . Since $\mathbf {Aut}(A)$ is a simple and simply connected affine group scheme, the natural map

$$\begin{align*}H^1(F, \mathbf{Aut}(A)) \xrightarrow{\prod \omega} \prod_{\omega \in \Omega} H^1(\mathbb{R}, \mathbf{Aut}(A)) \end{align*}$$

is a bijection by [Reference HarderHa66] or [Reference Platonov and RapinchukPlRap, p. 286, Theorem 6.6]. Because $H^1(\mathbb {R}, \mathbf {Aut}(A))$ has three elements by the preceding example, there are exactly $3^{|\Omega |}$ isomorphism classes of Albert F-algebras. This result, for number fields and with a proof in the language of Albert algebras, dates back to [Reference Albert and JacobsonAlbJ, p. 417, Corollary of Theorem 12].

The same argument goes through for octonion algebras, and one finds that there are $2^{|\Omega |}$ isomorphism classes of octonion F-algebras. This result, for number fields and with a proof in the language of octonion algebras, dates back to [Reference ZornZ, p. 400].

In the special case where F has a unique real embedding (e.g., $F = \mathbb {Q}$ ), the two isomorphism classes of octonion algebras are $\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(F)$ and $\mathcal {O} \otimes F$ , and the three isomorphism classes of Albert algebras are $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(F))$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O} \otimes F, {\left \langle {1, s, s}\right \rangle })$ for $s = \pm 1$ .

Below, we will focus our attention on classification results in the case where R is not a field. We translate known results about cohomology of affine group schemes into the language of Albert algebras.

Proposition 11.3. If R is: (1) a complete discrete valuation ring whose residue field is finite or (2) a finite ring, then every Freudenthal R-algebra of rank 15 or 27 and every quaternion or octonion R-algebra is split.

Proof. In view of Theorem 9.3 and its analogue for composition algebras, it suffices to prove that $H^1(R, \mathbf {G}) = 0$ for $\mathbf {G}$ a simple R-group scheme of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ or $\mathsf {C}_3$ obtained by base change from a Chevalley group over $\mathbb {Z}$ . In case (1), this is [Reference ConradConrad, Proposition 3.10]. In case (2), we apply the following lemma.

Lemma 11.4. If R is a finite ring and $\mathbf {G}$ is a smooth connected R-group scheme, then $H^1(R, \mathbf {G}) = 0$ .

Proof. If R is not connected, then it is a finite product $R = \prod R_i$ , where each ring $R_i$ is finite, so $H^1(R, \mathbf {G}) = \prod H^1(R_i, \mathbf {G} \times R_i)$ . Therefore, it suffices to assume that R is connected.

Suppose $\mathbf {X}$ is a $\mathbf {G}$ -torsor. Our aim is to show that $\mathbf {X}$ is the trivial torsor, that is, $\mathbf {X}(R)$ is nonempty. Put $\mathfrak {a}$ for the nil radical $\operatorname {\mathrm {Nil}}(R)$ of R. Because R is finite, there is some minimal $m \ge 1$ such that $\mathfrak {a}^m = 0$ . We proceed by induction on m. If $m = 1$ , then R is reduced and connected, so it is a finite field and $H^1(R, \mathbf {G}) = 0$ by Lang’s theorem. For the case $m \ge 2$ , put $I := \mathfrak {a}^{m-1}$ . The ring $R/I$ has $\operatorname {\mathrm {Nil}}(R/I)^{m-1} = (\operatorname {\mathrm {Nil}}(R)/I)^{m-1} = 0$ , so by induction, $\mathbf {X}(R/I)$ is nonempty. On the other hand, $I^2 = \mathfrak {a}^{2m-2} = \mathfrak {a}^m \cdot \mathfrak {a}^{m-2} = 0$ and $\mathbf {X}$ is smooth, so the natural map $\mathbf {X}(R) \to \mathbf {X}(R/I)$ is surjective.

Example 11.5. Suppose R is a Dedekind domain, and write F for its field of fractions. For $\mathbf {G}$ a Chevalley group of type $\mathsf {G}_2$ , $\mathsf {F}_4$ , or $\mathsf {E}_8$ , the map $H^1(R, \mathbf {G}) \to H^1(F, \mathbf {G})$ has zero kernel [Reference HarderHa67, Satz 3.3]. Consequently, if A is an Albert or octonion R-algebra and $A \otimes F$ is split, then the R-algebra A is split.

In particular, if F is a global field with no real embeddings, then every Albert or octonion F-algebra is split, so every Albert or octonion R-algebra is split.

In the case where F is a number field with a real embedding, we provide the following partial result, which relies on Example 11.1.

Proposition 11.6. Suppose F is a number field and R is a localization of its ring of integers at finitely many primes. If A is an Albert (respectively, octonion) F-algebra such that $A \otimes \mathbb {R}$ is not isomorphic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathbb {O})$ (respectively, $\mathbb {O}$ ) for every embedding $F \hookrightarrow \mathbb {R}$ , then there is an Albert (respectively, octonion) R-algebra B such that $B \otimes F \cong A$ and B is uniquely determined up to R-isomorphism.

Proof. Write $\mathbf {G}$ for the automorphism group of the split Albert (respectively, octonion) F-algebra. Write $H^1_{\mathrm {ind}}(R, \mathbf {G}) \subseteq H^1(R, \mathbf {G})$ for the isomorphism classes of R-algebras B such that $B \otimes F_v$ is not $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathbb {O})$ (respectively, $\mathbb {O}$ ), that is, such that $\mathbf {Aut}(B) \times F_v$ is not compact, for all real places v of F. Since $\mathbf {G}$ is simply connected, Strong Approximation gives that the natural map $H^1_{\mathrm {ind}}(R, \mathbf {G}) \to H^1_{\mathrm {ind}}(F, \mathbf {G})$ is an isomorphism [Reference HarderHa67, Satz 4.2.4], which is what is claimed.

12 The number of generators of an Albert algebra

The goal of this section is to prove Proposition 12.1, which is inspired by the work of First-Reichstein [Reference First and ReichsteinFiR] generalizing the Forster-Swan theorem. Let J be a para-quadratic R-algebra. By a (para-quadratic) subalgebra of J, we mean a submodule $J' \subseteq J$ containing $1_J$ and closed under the U-operator, that is, such that $U_x y \in J'$ for all $x,y \in J'$ . For any subset $S \subseteq J$ , the smallest subalgebra of J containing S is called the subalgebra generated by S; if this subalgebra is all of J, we say that S generates J.

Proposition 12.1. For every noetherian ring R, every Albert R-algebra can be generated in the sense of the preceding paragraph by $3 + \dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Max}} R$ elements.

In the statement, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Max}} R$ is the topological space whose points are the maximal ideals of R, endowed with the subspace topology inherited from $\operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} R$ . It is evident that $\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Max}} R \le \dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} R$ , also known as the Krull dimension. Beyond this inequality, the two numbers may be quite different (e.g., for a local ring, $\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Max}} R = 0$ and $\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Spec}} R$ can be any number).

If 2 is invertible in R, the bound in the proposition is Corollary 4.2c in [Reference First and ReichsteinFiR]. The contribution here is to remove the hypothesis on 2. In the special case where R contains an infinite field of characteristic $\ne 2$ , a different (and possibly smaller) upper bound is given in [Reference First, Reichstein and WilliamsFiRW, Section 13].

The results in [Reference First and ReichsteinFiR] reduce the proof of the proposition to the case where R is a field. For a field of characteristic not $2$ , a proof may be read off from [Reference McCrimmonMcC04, p. 112]; we give a characteristic-free proof using the first Tits construction of cubic Jordan algebras [Reference McCrimmonMcC69, pp. 507–509]. We briefly recall its details.

The first Tits construction

Let A be a (finite-dimensional) separable associative algebra of degree $3$ over a field F, so its generic norm $N_A$ is a cubic form on A and its trace $T_A\colon A \times A \to F$ defined as in (6.1) is a nondegenerate symmetric bilinear form. Given any nonzero scalar $\mu \in F$ , we obtain a cubic norm structure

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{M}:= (A \times A \times A,1_{\mathbf{M}},\sharp,N_{\mathbf{M}}) \end{align*}$$

by defining

(12.1) $$ \begin{align} 1_{\mathbf{M}}:= (1_A,0,0), \end{align} $$
(12.2) $$ \begin{align} x^{\sharp} := (x_0^{\sharp} - x_1x_2,\mu^{-1}x_2^{\sharp} - x_0x_1,\mu x_1^{\sharp} - x_2x_0) \quad \text{and} \end{align} $$
(12.3) $$ \begin{align} N_{\mathbf{M}}(x) := N_A(x_0) + \mu N_A(x_1) + \mu^{-1}N_A(x_2) - T_A(x_0x_1x_2) \end{align} $$

for all $x = (x_0,x_1,x_2)$ in all scalar extensions of $A \times A \times A$ . By [Reference McCrimmonMcC69, Theorem 6], $\mathbf {M}$ is a cubic norm structure, so $J(\mathbf {M})$ is a cubic Jordan F-algebra which we denote by $J(A, \mu )$ .

Example 12.2. (a): Let E be a cubic étale F-algebra. If E is either split — that is, isomorphic to $F \times F \times F$ — or a cyclic cubic field extension of F, then $J(E,1) \cong \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(F \times F, {\left \langle {1, -1, -1}\right \rangle })$ [Reference Petersson and RacinePeR84b, Theorem 3], that is, is the split Freudenthal algebra of rank 9 (Proposition 7.5), which is $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(F)^+$ by Example 10.3.

(b): Let A be a central simple associative F-algebra of degree $3$ . Then $J(A,1)$ is a split Albert algebra [Reference Petersson and RacinePeR84a, Corollary 4.2].

Lemma 12.3. Let A be a separable associative F-algebra of degree $3$ and $\mu \in F^{\times }$ . Then the first Tits construction $J(A,\mu )$ is generated by $A^+$ (identified in $J(A,\mu )$ through the initial summand) and $(0,1_A,0)$ .

Proof. Let $J'$ be the subalgebra of $J(A, \mu )$ generated by $A^+$ and $w := (0,1_A,0)$ . As a subalgebra, it is closed under $\sharp $ by (6.8), that is, $x^{\sharp } \in J'$ and $x \times y \in J'$ for all $x, y \in J'$ . Since $w^{\sharp } = \mu (0,0,1_A)$ and $x_0 \times (0,x_1,x_2) = (0,-x_0x_1,-x_2x_0)$ for all $x_i \in A$ by (12.2), it follows that $J'$ must be all of $J(A, \mu )$ .

Proof of Proposition 12.1

Theorem 1.2 in [Reference First and ReichsteinFiR] reduces the proof to the case where R is a field F, in which case $\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Max}} R = 0$ , so the task is to prove that three elements suffice to generate an Albert algebra J. If F is infinite, then Proposition 4.1 in [Reference First and ReichsteinFiR] reduces us to considering the case where J is split. If F is finite, then J is split by Proposition 11.3.

If $F \ne \mathbb {F}_2$ , then the split cubic étale F-algebra $E := F \times F \times F$ can be generated by a single element x as an associative algebra. On the other hand, if $F = \mathbb {F}_2$ , let $E := \mathbb {F}_8$ be the cyclic cubic extension of F, which is again generated by one element, call it x. In either case, x also generates the Jordan algebra $E^+$ , because the powers of x in $E^+$ and E are the same.

Hence, Example 12.2 (a) and Lemma 12.3 show that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(F)^+$ is generated by two elements. Lemma 12.3 combined with Example 12.2 (b) shows that the split Albert algebra $J(\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(F),1)$ is generated by three elements.

Remark 12.4. That the Jordan algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_3(F)^+$ , for any field F, is generated by two elements doesn’t seem too surprising, but one should keep in mind that the analogous result for 2-by-2 matrices is false: the minimal number of generators for the Jordan algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Mat}}_2(F)^+$ is three.

Remark 12.5 (dichotomy of fields and the Tits construction)

The classification of Albert algebras over a field F of characteristic $\ne 3$ has a fundamentally different flavor depending on whether or not $H^3(F, \mathbb {Z}/3)$ is zero, as indicated by [Reference RostRost], [Reference Petersson and RacinePeR96], or [Reference GaribaldiGar09, Section 8]. If $H^3(F, \mathbb {Z}/3) = 0$ — as is the case for global fields, p-adic fields, and the real numbers — every Albert F-algebra is reduced, that is, of the form $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ for some C and $\Gamma $ , and is not a division algebra. (It is natural to speculate that this is the reason it took many years after Albert algebras were defined — all the way until 1958 — for the first Albert division algebra to be exhibited in [Reference AlbertAlb58].) In the other case, when $H^3(F, \mathbb {Z}/3) \ne 0$ , as happens when $F = \mathbb {Q}(t)$ , for example, one can construct an Albert division algebra via the first Tits construction described above as $J(A \otimes \mathbb {Q}(t), t)$ for A an associative division algebra of dimension 9 over $\mathbb {Q}$ .

It is known that every Albert algebra over a field is obtained by the first Tits construction or second Tits construction (which we have not described here) (see [Reference McCrimmonMcC70, Theorem 10] or [Reference Petersson and RacinePeR86b, Theorem 3.1(i)]). Both constructions have been extended from the case of algebras over a field to an arbitrary base ring [Reference Petersson and RacinePeR86a]. However, in this more general setting, the Tits constructions do not produce all Albert algebras [Reference Parimala, Sridharan and ThakurPaST].

13 Isotopy

The aim of this section is to discuss the notion of isotopy of Jordan algebras, which will pay off later in the paper when we discuss groups of type $\mathsf {E}_6$ in Section 15 and $\mathsf {E}_7$ in Section 17. We include this material at this point in the paper because Corollary 13.6 is needed in the following section.

Definition 13.1. Let J be a Jordan R-algebra, and suppose $u \in J$ is invertible. We define a Jordan algebra $J^{(u)}$ with the same underlying R-module, with U-operator $U^{(u)}_x := U_x U_u$ (where the unadorned U on the right denotes the U-operator in J), and with identity element $1^{(u)} := u^{-1}$ . One checks that $J^{(u)}$ is indeed a Jordan algebra, and for $u, v$ invertible, we have $(J^{(u)})^{(v)} = J^{(U_u v)}$ . A Jordan R-algebra $J'$ is an isotope of J if it is isomorphic to $J^{(u)}$ for some invertible $u \in J$ ; equivalently, one says that J and $J'$ are isotopic. This defines an equivalence relation on Jordan algebras that is a priori weaker than isomorphism.

We have presented the notion of isotopy for Jordan algebras. However, there are analogous notions for other classes of algebras, which go back at least to [Reference AlbertAlb42]. For associative algebras, isotopy is the same as isomorphism. For octonion algebras, isotopy amounts to norm equivalence [Reference Alsaody and GilleAlsG, Corollary 6.7], which is a weaker condition than isomorphism (see [Reference GilleGil14] and [Reference Asok, Hoyois and WendtAsHW]).

Isotopes of cubic Jordan algebras

If J is a cubic Jordan R-algebra and $u \in J$ is invertible, then [Reference McCrimmonMcC69, Theorem 2] and its proof show that the isotope $J^{(u)}$ is a cubic Jordan algebra as well whose identity element, adjoint and norm are given by

(13.1) $$ \begin{align} 1_{J^{(u)}} = u^{-1}, \quad x^{\sharp(u)} = N_J(u)U_u^{-1}x^{\sharp}, \quad N_{J^{(u)}}(x) = N_J(u)N_J(x). \end{align} $$

Moreover, the (bi-)linear and quadratic trace of $J^{(u)}$ have the form

(13.2) $$ \begin{align} T_{J^{(u)}}(x,y) = T_J(U_ux,y), \quad \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_{J^{(u)}}(x) = T_J(u,x), \quad S_{J^{(u)}}(x) = T_J(u^{\sharp},x^{\sharp}). \end{align} $$

The first equation of (13.2) is in [Reference McCrimmonMcC69, p. 500], while the second one follows from (13.1), the first, and Lemma 6.5 (1) via $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_{J^{(u)}}(x) = T_{J^{(u)}}(u^{-1},x) = T_J(U_uu^{-1},x) = T_J(u,x)$ . Similarly,

$$\begin{align*}S_{J^{(u)}}(x) = \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_{J^{(u)}}(x^{\sharp(u)}) = T_J(u,N_J(u)U_u^{-1}x^{\sharp}) = T_J(N_J(u)U_u^{-1}u,x^{\sharp}) = T_J(u^{\sharp},x^{\sharp}). \end{align*}$$

Example 13.2. $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ is isotopic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ for every $\Gamma $ . Indeed, for

$$\begin{align*}u := \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \gamma_1 & 0 & 0 \\ 0 & \gamma_2 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 & \gamma_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \quad \in \operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C, \Gamma), \end{align*}$$

the map $\phi \!: \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )^{(u)} \to \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ defined by

$$\begin{align*}\phi \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & \gamma_2 c_3 & \gamma_3 \bar{c}_2 \\ \gamma_1 \bar{c}_3 & \alpha_2 & \gamma_3 c_1 \\ \gamma_1 c_2 & \gamma_2 \bar{c}_1 & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) = \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \gamma_1 \alpha_1 & \gamma_1 \gamma_2 c_3 & \cdot \\ \cdot & \gamma_2 \alpha_2 & \gamma_2 \gamma_3 c_1 \\ \gamma_1 \gamma_3 c_2 & \cdot & \gamma_3 \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \end{align*}$$

is an isomorphism of Jordan algebras. One can also turn this around:

$$\begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C,\Gamma) = (\operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C,\Gamma)^{(u)})^{(u^{-2})} \cong \operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C)^{(\phi(u^{-2}))} = \operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C)^{(u^{-1})}. \end{align*}$$

Jordan algebras isotopic to a reduced Freudenthal algebra

In the special case where R is a field, a Jordan algebra that is isotopic to the split Albert algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R))$ is necessarily isomorphic to it (see, for example [Reference JacobsonJ71, p. 53, Theorem 9]). This need not hold for general R: Alsaody has shown in [Reference AlsaodyAls21, Theorem 2.7] that there exists a ring R finitely generated over $\mathbb {C}$ and an Albert R-algebra that is isotopic to the split Albert R-algebra but is not isomorphic to it. Here we show that it is sufficient to assume that R is a semilocal ring (Corollary 13.4), as a consequence of a more general result (Theorem 13.3) from which we also obtain the key Corollary 13.6.

We work in a slightly more general context than semilocal rings. For the following statements, see [Reference Estes and GuralnickEsG] and [Reference McDonald and WaterhouseMcDW]. We say that R is an LG ring if whenever a polynomial $f \in R[x_1, \ldots , x_n]$ represents a unit over $R_{\mathfrak {m}}$ for every maximal ideal $\mathfrak {m}$ of R, then f represents a unit over R. Every semilocal ring is an LG ring. It is easy to see that rings $R_1$ , $R_2$ are both LG if and only if their product $R_1 \times R_2$ is LG. The ring of all algebraic integers and the ring of all real algebraic integers are LG rings. Every integral extension of an LG ring is LG [Reference Estes and GuralnickEsG, Corollary 2.3].

Theorem 13.3. Suppose J is a Jordan R-algebra that is isotopic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ for some composition R-algebra C and some $\Gamma $ . If R is an LG ring, then J is isomorphic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma ')$ for some $\Gamma '$ .

Proof. As in previous proofs, we reduce to the case where C has constant rank.

In view of Example 13.2, J is isotopic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ , that is, $J \cong \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)^{(u^{-1})}$ for some invertible $u \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ . The same example shows we are done if u is diagonal.

Write N for the cubic form on $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ . In case u is not diagonal, we will apply successive elements $\eta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C))$ such that $N \eta = N$ as polynomial laws. (In the notation of Section 15 below, $\eta \in \mathbf {Isom}(\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C))(R)$ .) Note that each such $\eta $ defines an isomorphism of R-modules

(13.3) $$ \begin{align} \eta \colon \operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C)^{(u^{-1})} \to \operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C)^{(\eta(u)^{-1})}. \end{align} $$

We have

$$\begin{align*}N(\eta(u)^{-1}) = N(\eta(u))^{-1} = N(u)^{-1} = N(u^{-1}), \end{align*}$$

so we have by (13.1) that

$$\begin{align*}N_{\operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C)^{(u^{-1})}} = N(u)^{-1} N = N(\eta(u)^{-1}) N \eta = N_{\operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(C)^{(\eta(u)^{-1})}}\eta. \end{align*}$$

Since $\eta $ is a norm isometry that maps the identity element $u^{-1}$ in the domain of (13.3) to the identity element in the codomain, it is an isomorphism of algebras by Lemma 10.2. Thus, if successive elements $\eta $ transform u into a diagonal element, the proof will be complete.

We employ the transformation $\tau _{st}(q)$ for $1 \le s \ne t \le 3$ and $q \in C$ defined by

$$\begin{align*}\tau_{st}(q) \colon A \mapsto (I_3 + q E_{st}) A (I_3 + \bar{q} E_{ts}), \end{align*}$$

where $I_3$ is the identity matrix, $E_{st}$ is the 3-by-3 matrix with a 1 in the $(s, t)$ -entry and 0 elsewhere, and juxtaposition defines naive multiplication of 3-by-3 matrices with entries in C. For example,

$$\begin{align*}\tau_{12}(q) \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & c_3 & \cdot \\ \cdot & \alpha_2 & c_1 \\ c_2 & \cdot & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) = \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1+n_C(q, c_3) + \alpha_2 n_C(q) & c_3 + \alpha_2 q & \cdot \\ \cdot & \alpha_2 & c_1 \\ c_2 + \bar{c}_1\bar{q} & \cdot & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right). \end{align*}$$

These transformations appear in [Reference JacobsonJ61, Section 5] and [Reference KrutelevichKr02, Section 2]; the argument in either reference shows that $\tau _{st}(q)$ preserves N for all choices of s, t, and q. For $e = 2, 3$ , define polynomial functions $\nu _e$ from $C^e$ to the group scheme $\mathbf {G}$ of linear transformations stabilizing the norm N via

$$\begin{align*}\nu_3(q_1, q_2, q_3) = \tau_{31}(q_3) \tau_{21}(q_2) \tau_{12}(q_1) \quad \text{and} \quad \nu_2(q_1, q_2) = \tau_{32}(q_2) \tau_{23}(q_1). \end{align*}$$

Additionally, for every permutation $\pi $ of $\{ 1, 2, 3 \}$ , there is a linear transformation of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ that we denote also by $\pi $ , for example, the transposition $(1\,2)$ acts via

(13.4) $$ \begin{align} \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & c_3 & \cdot \\ \cdot & \alpha_2 & c_1 \\ c_2 & \cdot & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \mapsto \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_2 & \bar{c}_3 & \cdot \\ \cdot & \alpha_1 & \bar{c}_2 \\ \bar{c}_1 & \cdot & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \end{align} $$

(see, for example, [Reference KrutelevichKr02, p. 282]). The other transpositions are constructed analogously and each evidently preserves the norm. In this way, we obtain a representation of the permutation group on $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ .

Case: R is local: We collect some observations in the case where R is a local ring. Write

$$\begin{align*}u = \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha_1 & c_3 & \cdot \\ \cdot & \alpha_2 & c_1 \\ c_2 & \cdot & \alpha_3 \end{smallmatrix} \right). \end{align*}$$

By hypothesis, $N(u)$ is invertible, that is, does not lie in the maximal ideal $\mathfrak {m}$ of R.

If $\alpha _1 \in R^{\times }$ or $\alpha _2, \alpha _3 \notin R^{\times }$ , then after modifying u by a transformation in the image of $\nu _3$ , we may assume that $\alpha _1 \in R^{\times }$ and $c_2 = c_3 = 0$ . Indeed, if $\alpha _1 \notin R^{\times }$ , then by (6.11) we have

$$\begin{align*}N(u) \equiv \operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_C(c_1 c_2 c_3) \bmod \mathfrak{m}, \end{align*}$$

whence $c_3 \notin \mathfrak {m} C$ . Since $n_C$ continues to be regular when changing scalars to $R/\mathfrak {m}$ , some $q \in C$ has $n_C(q,c_3) \notin \mathfrak {m}$ . Applying $\tau _{12}(q)$ , we may arrange $\alpha _1 \in R^{\times }$ . Then note that $\tau _{21}(q) \left ( \begin {smallmatrix} \alpha _1 & c_3 & \cdot \\ \cdot & \alpha _2 & c_1 \\ c_2 & \cdot & \alpha _3 \end {smallmatrix} \right )$ has top row entries $\alpha _1$ , $c_3 + \alpha _1 \bar {q}$ , $\bar {c_2}$ . Taking $q = -\bar {c}_3 \alpha _1^{-1}$ shows that we may assume $c_3 = 0$ . The argument that we may assume $c_2 = 0$ is similar, with the role of $\tau _{21}$ replaced by $\tau _{31}$ .

Now suppose that $\alpha _1 \in R^{\times }$ and $c_2 = c_3 = 0$ . If $\alpha _2 \in R^{\times }$ or $\alpha _3 \notin R^{\times }$ , then after modifying u by a transformation in the image of $\nu _2$ , we may assume that u is diagonal. Indeed, since u has norm $\alpha _1 (\alpha _2 \alpha _3 - n_C(c_1)) \not \in \mathfrak {m}$ , at least one of $\alpha _2$ , $\alpha _3$ , or $n_C(c_1)$ is not in $\mathfrak {m}$ . The same argument as in the preceding paragraph, with $\tau _{12}$ replaced by $\tau _{23}$ , shows that we may assume that $\alpha _2 \not \in \mathfrak {m}$ . The same argument as in the preceding paragraph, with $\tau _{21}$ replaced by $\tau _{32}$ , shows that we may assume that $c_1 = 0$ . Thus, we have transformed u into a diagonal element, as required.

General case: Return to the setting of R as in the statement of the theorem. We combine the transformations $\nu _3$ , $\nu _2$ , and permutations together into a polynomial function $C^{21} \to \mathbf {G}$ , namely

(13.5) $$ \begin{align} \left( \nu_2 \, (2\,3)\, \nu_2 \nu_3 \,(1\,3) \right)\left( \nu_2 \, (2\,3)\, \nu_2 \nu_3 \,(1\,3) \right) \left( \nu_2 \, (2\,3)\, \nu_2 \nu_3 \right), \end{align} $$

where the arguments to the various $\nu _2$ , $\nu _3$ are assigned independently. Combining this with the polynomial function on $\mathbf {G}$ that sends $g \in \mathbf {G}(R)$ to the product of the diagonal entries of $gu$ , we obtain a polynomial law in $\mathscr {P}(C^{21}, R)$ . But more is true. Because R is LG and C is projective of constant rank, C is a free module (see [Reference Estes and GuralnickEsG, Theorem 2.10] or [Reference McDonald and WaterhouseMcDW, p. 457]). Choosing a basis for C expresses this polynomial law as a polynomial with coefficients in R.

We claim that this polynomial represents a unit over $R_{\mathfrak {m}}$ for every maximal ideal $\mathfrak {m}$ of R. For a given $\mathfrak {m}$ , here is how to pick the element of $C^{21}$ that produces a unit. If $\alpha _1 \in R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ or $\alpha _2, \alpha _3 \notin R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ , applying $\nu _3$ to u, with arguments chosen as in the second paragraph of the local case, we obtain an element with $\alpha _1 \in R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ and $c_3 = c_2 = 0$ . We take this to be the rightmost term in (13.5). If that element has $\alpha _2 \in R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ or $\alpha _3 \notin R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ , the next $\nu _2$ term can be chosen to produce a diagonal u; one takes the remaining $\nu $ terms in (13.5) to have argument 0. Otherwise, $\alpha _3$ is invertible in $R_{\mathfrak {m}}$ , and we plug 0 into the rightmost $\nu _2$ , pick the argument for the next $\nu _2$ as in the proof of the local case, and plug 0 into the remaining $\nu $ terms to the left in (13.5). The claim is verified if $\alpha _1 \in R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ or $\alpha _2, \alpha _3 \notin R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ .

The next case of the claim is where $\alpha _2 \in R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ . In that case, we plug 0 into the rightmost three $\nu $ terms in (13.5). After applying the permutation $(2\,3)$ and then $(1\,3)$ , we obtain an element of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ with $\alpha _1$ invertible, and a well-chosen argument for the next $\nu _3$ term will assure that $c_3 = c_2 = 0$ . As in the preceding paragraph, choosing the arguments for the leftmost two $\nu _2$ terms in the middle product in (13.5) suffices to transform u into a diagonal element, verifying the claim in this case.

The last case of the claim is when $\alpha _3 \in R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ . Plug 0 in the $\nu $ terms in the middle and right parenthetical expressions in (13.5). After applying all permutations in (13.5) besides the leftmost transposition to u, we obtain an element of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ with $\alpha _1 \in R_{\mathfrak {m}}^{\times }$ and the argument in the preceding paragraph, again, transforms u into a diagonal element, completing the proof of the claim.

Since R is an LG ring, the claim provides an element $g \in \mathbf {G}(R)$ such that $gu$ has $(1,1)$ -entry a unit. That is, we may assume that in the element u, $\alpha _1$ is invertible. Applying now $\tau _{21}(q)$ and $\tau _{31}(q)$ to u for values of q chosen as in the local case, we may assume that $c_3 = c_2 = 0$ .

Applying now an argument as in the preceding five paragraphs, with the function

$$\begin{align*}\nu_2 \, (2\,3) \, \nu_2 \colon C^4 \to \mathbf{G}, \end{align*}$$

we conclude that we may transform u to further assume that $\alpha _2$ is invertible, and therefore, apply a transformation $\tau _{32}(q)$ to transform it into a diagonal element, as required.

Corollary 13.4. Suppose J is a Jordan R-algebra over an LG ring R. If J is isotopic to a split Freudenthal algebra whose rank does not take the value 6, then J is itself a split Freudenthal algebra.

Proof. As in previous proofs, one is reduced to the case where J has constant rank, which is not 6. The theorem and Proposition 7.5 give the claim.

The hypothesis that the rank is not 6 is necessary, because $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathbb {R}, {\left \langle {1, -1, -1}\right \rangle })$ is isotopic to the split Freudenthal algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathbb {R})$ (Example 13.2) but is not isomorphic to it (Example 6.8).

Example 13.5 (isotopy over global fields)

For $F = \mathbb {R}$ or a global field, there is a bijection between the isomorphism classes of octonion algebras and isotopy classes of Albert algebras given by $C \leftrightarrow \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ . Indeed, every Albert F-algebra is reduced (Example 11.2), so $C \mapsto \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)$ touches every isotopy class. For injectivity, if $C, C'$ are distinct octonion algebras, there is a real embedding $F \hookrightarrow \mathbb {R}$ such that $C \otimes \mathbb {R} \not \cong C' \otimes \mathbb {R}$ , and Corollary 13.4 shows that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C) \otimes \mathbb {R}$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C') \otimes \mathbb {R}$ are not isotopic.

Corollary 13.6. Every isotope of a Freudenthal algebra is itself a Freudenthal algebra.

Proof. Suppose J is an isotope of a Freudenthal algebra. After base change to a faithfully flat extension, J is an isotope of a split Freudenthal algebra.

The R-algebra $S := \prod _{\mathfrak {m}} R_{\mathfrak {m}}$ , where $\mathfrak {m}$ ranges over maximal ideals of R, is faithfully flat. For each $\mathfrak {m}$ , $J \otimes R_{\mathfrak {m}}$ is $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ for C a split composition $R_{\mathfrak {m}}$ -algebra and some $\Gamma $ by Theorem 13.3. By Proposition 7.3, there is a faithfully flat $R_{\mathfrak {m}}$ -algebra T such that $J \otimes T$ is a split Freudenthal algebra. The product of these T’s is a faithfully flat R-algebra over which J is the split Freudenthal algebra.

We close this section by making explicit the relationship between isotopy and norm similarity between Freudenthal algebras, extending Lemma 10.2.

Proposition 13.7. Let J and $J'$ be Freudenthal R-algebras. For an R-linear map $\phi \!: J \to J'$ , the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. $\phi $ is an isomorphism $J \to (J')^{(u)}$ for some invertible $u \in J'$ (“ $\phi $ is an isotopy”).

  2. 2. $N_{J'} \phi = \alpha N_J$ as polynomial laws for some $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ , and $\phi $ is surjective (“ $\phi $ is a norm similarity”).

Proof. Since $(J^{\prime })^{(u)}$ is a Freudenthal algebra by Corollary 13.6, condition (2) follows from (1) by Lemma 10.2 and (13.1). Conversely, we assume (2) and prove (1). Because $N_{J'}(\phi (1_J)) = \alpha $ , the element $\phi (1_J)$ is invertible in $J'$ . We set $u := \phi (1_J)^{-1}$ and $J'' := (J')^{(u)}$ . We have

$$\begin{align*}\phi(1_J) = u^{-1} = 1_{J''}. \end{align*}$$

Also, $N_{J'}(u) = N_{J'}(\phi (1_J))^{-1} = \alpha ^{-1}$ . Then

$$\begin{align*}N_{J''} \phi = N_{J'}(u) N_{J'} \phi = N_J \end{align*}$$

as polynomial laws. Lemma 10.2 implies that $\phi $ is an isomorphism $J \xrightarrow {\sim } J''$ , as desired.

14 Classification of Albert algebras over $\mathbb {Z}$

In this section, we study Albert algebras over the integers.

Definition 14.1. In the notation of Example 4.5, consider the element

$$\begin{align*}\beta := (-1 + e_1 + e_2 + \cdots + e_7)/2 = h_1 + h_2 + h_3 - (2 + e_1) \quad \in \mathcal{O}, \end{align*}$$

as was done in [Reference Elkies and GrossElkiesGr, (5.2)]. That element has

$$\begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Tr}}_{\mathcal{O}}(\beta) = -1, \quad n_{\mathcal{O}}(\beta) = 2 \quad \text{and} \quad \beta^2 + \beta + 2 = 0. \end{align*}$$

Put

$$\begin{align*}v := \left( \begin{smallmatrix} 2 & \beta & \cdot \\ \cdot & 2 & \beta \\ \beta & \cdot & 2 \end{smallmatrix} \right) \quad \in \operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(\mathcal{O}). \end{align*}$$

Since $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_{\mathcal {O}}(\beta ^3) = 5$ , we find that $N_{\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})}(v) = 1$ . In particular, v is invertible with inverse $v^{\sharp }$ . We define $\Lambda := \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})^{(v)}$ ; it is an Albert algebra by Corollary 13.6.

Proposition 14.2. $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O}) \not \cong \Lambda $ as Jordan $\mathbb {Z}$ -algebras, but $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O}) \otimes \mathbb {Q} \cong \Lambda \otimes \mathbb {Q}$ as Jordan $\mathbb {Q}$ -algebras.

Proof. We first prove the claim over $\mathbb {Z}$ , which amounts to a computation from [Reference Elkies and GrossElkiesGr]. The isomorphism class of a Freudenthal algebra determines its cubic norm form and also its trace linear form. From (13.1), we deduce for $x \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})$ that $x^{\sharp (v)} = 0$ if and only if $x^{\sharp } = 0$ . Hence, [Reference Elkies and GrossElkiesGr, Proposition 5.5] says that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})$ contains exactly three elements x such that $x^{\sharp } = 0$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_{\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})}(x) = 1$ , whereas $\Lambda $ has no elements x such that $x^{\sharp (v)} = 0$ and

$$\begin{align*}T_{\operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(\mathcal{O})}(v, x) = 1, \end{align*}$$

where the left side is $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}_{\Lambda }(x)$ by (13.2). This proves that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O}) \not \cong \Lambda $ .

Now consider $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O}) \otimes \mathbb {R}$ . It is called a “euclidean” Jordan algebra or, in older references, a “formally real” Jordan algebra, because every sum of nonzero squares is not zero [Reference Braun and KoecherBrK, p. 331]. The element v has generic minimal polynomial, in the sense of (10.1), $(t-1)(t^2 - 5t + 1)$ , which has three positive real roots. Therefore, there is some $u \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O}) \otimes \mathbb {R}$ such that $u^2 = v$ [Reference Braun and KoecherBrK, Section XI.3, S. 3.6 and 3.7]. From this, it is trivial to see that

$$\begin{align*}\Lambda \otimes \mathbb{R} \cong (\operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(\mathcal{O}) \otimes \mathbb{R})^{(v)} \cong \operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(\mathcal{O}) \otimes \mathbb{R}, \end{align*}$$

and Example 11.2 gives that $\Lambda \otimes \mathbb {Q} \cong \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O}) \otimes \mathbb {Q}$ .

Theorem 14.3. Over $\mathbb {Z}$ :

  1. a. There are exactly two isomorphism classes of octonion algebras: $\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z})$ and $\mathcal {O}$ .

  2. b. There are exactly four isomorphism classes of Albert algebras: $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z}))$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O}, {\left \langle {1, -1, -1}\right \rangle })$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})$ , and $\Lambda $ .

  3. c. There are exactly two isotopy classes of Albert algebras: $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z}))$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})$ .

Proof. We first prove (a) and (b). No pair of the algebras listed are isomorphic to each other. For $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})$ and $\Lambda $ , this is Proposition 14.2. For any other pair, base change to $\mathbb {Q}$ yields nonisomorphic $\mathbb {Q}$ -algebras. To complete the proof, it suffices to show that every octonion or Albert $\mathbb {Z}$ -algebra B is isomorphic to one of the ones listed.

If B is indefinite — that is, $B \otimes \mathbb {R}$ is not isomorphic to $\mathbb {O}$ nor $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathbb {O})$ — then the isomorphism class of B is determined by $B \otimes \mathbb {Q}$ as a $\mathbb {Q}$ -algebra (Proposition 11.6). Since the indefinite octonion or Albert $\mathbb {Q}$ -algebras are $\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Q})$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Q}))$ , and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O} \otimes \mathbb {Q}, {\left \langle {1, -1, -1}\right \rangle })$ by Example 11.2, B is isomorphic to one of the algebras listed in the statement.

If B is definite, then $\mathbf {Aut}(B)$ is a $\mathbb {Z}$ -form of the compact real group of type $\mathsf {G}_2$ or $\mathsf {F}_4$ . Gross’s mass formula [Reference GrossGr, Proposition 5.3] shows that, up to $\mathbb {Z}$ -isomorphism, there is only one group of type $\mathsf {G}_2$ and two groups of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ with this property. Using the equivalence between these groups and octonion or Albert algebras (Theorem 9.3), we conclude that up to isomorphism $\mathcal {O}$ is the unique definite octonion $\mathbb {Z}$ -algebra and $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})$ and $\Lambda $ are the two isomorphism classes of definite Albert $\mathbb {Z}$ -algebras, completing the proof of (a) and (b).

For (c), note that the three algebras in (b) that are not $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z}))$ are all isotopic, see Example 13.2, so the two algebras listed in (c) represent all of the isotopy classes of Albert $\mathbb {Z}$ -algebras. The base change of these two algebras to $\mathbb {Q}$ are not isotopic (Example 13.5), so they are not isotopic as $\mathbb {Z}$ -algebras.

Note that part (a) of the theorem can be proved entirely in the language of octonion algebras (see [Reference van der Blij and SpringervdBS]).

In view of Theorem 9.3, part (b) is equivalent to a classification of the group schemes of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ over $\mathbb {Z}$ , which was done in Sections 6 and 7 of [Reference ConradConrad], especially Examples 6.7 and 7.4. The innovation, here, is that we can use the language of Albert algebras also in the case of $\mathbb {Z}$ where $2$ is not invertible. Because of this extra flexibility, we can substitute results from the literature over algebraically closed fields (including characteristic 2) for some of the computations over $\mathbb {Z}$ done in [Reference ConradConrad].

Part (c) corresponds to the classification of groups of type $\mathsf {E}_6$ over $\mathbb {Z}$ up to isogeny (see Section 18).

15 Groups of type $\mathsf {E}_6$

Roundness of the norm

We note that the cubic norm of a Freudenthal algebra has the following special property. A quadratic form with this property is called “round” (see [Reference Elman, Karpenko and MerkurjevElKM, Section 9.A]).

Lemma 15.1 (roundness)

For every Freudenthal R-algebra J,

$$\begin{align*}\{ \alpha \in R^{\times} \mid \alpha N_J \cong N_J \} = \{ N_J(x) \in R^{\times} \mid x \text{ invertible in } J \}. \end{align*}$$

Proof. If $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ and $\phi \in \operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(J)$ are such that $\alpha N_J = N_J \phi $ , then for $x := \phi (1_J)$ , we have $N_J(x) = \alpha $ . Conversely, if x is invertible in J, put $\alpha := N_J(x)$ and define $\phi := \alpha U_{x^{-1}}$ . Then $N_J \phi = \alpha ^3 N_J(x^{-1})^2 N_J$ by Lemma 6.5(3), so $N_J \phi = \alpha N_J$ .

Example 15.2. For $J = \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C, \Gamma )$ , the sets displayed in Lemma 15.1 equal $R^{\times }$ . To see this for the right side, take $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ and note that $N_J(\alpha \varepsilon _1 + \varepsilon _2 + \varepsilon _3) = \alpha $ . For the left side, consider $\phi \in \operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(J)$ defined by

$$ \begin{align*} \phi(\varepsilon_i) = \alpha \varepsilon_i \quad \text{and} \quad \phi(\delta_i(c)) = \delta_i(c) \quad \text{for } i = 1, 2, \\ \phi(\varepsilon_3) = \alpha^{-1} \varepsilon_3 \quad \text{and} \quad \phi(\delta_3(c)) = \delta_3(\alpha c). \end{align*} $$

Then $N_J \phi = \alpha N_J$ as polynomial laws.

Example 15.3. In contrast to the preceding example, we now show that the sets displayed in Lemma 15.1 may be properly contained in $R^{\times }$ . Suppose F is a field and J is a Freudenthal F-algebra such that $N_J$ is anisotropic, that is, $N_J(x) = 0$ if and only if $x = 0$ . (For example, such a J exists if F is Laurent series or rational functions in one variable over a global field, see Remark 12.5.) We claim that, for t an indeterminate, every nonzero element in the image of $N_{J \otimes F((t))}$ has lowest term of degree divisible by 3. Because the norm is a homogeneous form, it suffices to prove this claim for $J \otimes F[[t]]$ .

Let $x \in J \otimes F[[t]]$ be nonzero, so $x = \sum _{j \ge j_0} x_j t^j$ for some $j_0 \ge 0$ with $x_{j_0} \ne 0$ . Since $N_J$ is anisotropic, $N_J(x_{j_0}) \ne 0$ . If $j_0 = 0$ , then the homomorphism $F[[t]] \to F$ such that $t \mapsto 0$ sends $x \mapsto x_0$ and $N_{J\otimes F[[t]]}(x) \mapsto N_J(x_0) \ne 0$ , therefore $N_{J \otimes F[[t]]}(x)$ has lowest degree term $N_J(x_0)t^0$ . If $j_0> 0$ , then

$$\begin{align*}N_{J \otimes F[[t]]}(x) = N_{J \otimes F[[t]]}(t^{j_0} (xt^{-j_0})) = t^{3j_0} (N_J(x_{j_0}) t^0 + \cdots), \end{align*}$$

proving the claim.

Corollary 15.4. For Freudenthal R-algebras J and $J'$ , the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. J and $J'$ are isotopic.

  2. 2. $N_J \cong \alpha N_{J'}$ for some $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ .

  3. 3. $N_J \cong N_{J'}$ .

Proof. The equivalence of (1) and (2) is Proposition 13.7.

Supposing (2), let $\phi \colon J' \to J$ be an R-module isomorphism such that $\alpha N_{J'} = N_J \phi $ . Take $x := \phi (1_{J'})$ . Since $N_J(x) = \alpha $ , Lemma 15.1 gives that $\alpha N_J \cong N_J$ . As $N_J$ is also isomorphic to $\alpha N_{J'}$ , we conclude (3). The converse is trivial.

In the corollary, the inclusion of (3) seems to be new, even in the case where R is a field. Omitting that, in the special case where R is a field of characteristic $\ne 2, 3$ , the equivalence of (1) and (2) and Proposition 15.6 below can be found as Theorems 7 and 10 in [Reference JacobsonJ71].

Albert algebras and groups of type $\mathsf {E}_6$

The stabilizer of the cubic form $N_J$ in $\mathbf {GL}(J)$ is a closed sub-group-scheme denoted $\mathbf {Isom}(J)$ . It contains $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ as a natural sub-group-scheme, namely, it is the stabilizer of $1_J$ by Lemma 10.2. Arguing as in the proof of Lemma 9.1, one finds that $\mathbf {Isom}(J)$ is a simple affine group scheme that is simply connected of type $\mathsf {E}_6$ . (In the case where R is an algebraically closed field, this claim is verified in [Reference SpringerSp73, 11.20, 12.4], or see [Reference Springer and VeldkampSpV, Theorem 7.3.2] for the case where R is a field of characteristic different from 2, 3.) Compare [Reference AlsaodyAls21, Lemma 2.3] or [Reference ConradConrad, Appendix C]. Moreover, $\mathbf {Isom}(J)$ is a “pure inner form” in the sense of [Reference ConradConrad, Section 3], respectively, “strongly inner” in [Reference Calmès and FaselCalF, Definition 2.2.4.9], meaning that it is an inner twist of $\mathbf {Isom}(J_0)$ for the split Albert algebra $J_0$ . We note that the center of $\mathbf {Isom}(J)$ is the group scheme $\mu _3$ of cube roots of unity operating on J by scalar multiplication.

Faithfully flat descent shows that the set $H^1(R, \mathbf {Isom}(J))$ is in bijection with isomorphism classes of pairs $(M, f)$ , where M is a projective module of the same rank as J and f is a cubic form on M — that is, an element of $\mathsf {S}^3(M^*)$ — such that $f \otimes S$ is isomorphic to the norm on $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(S))$ for some faithfully flat $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ . For every Albert R-algebra J and every $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ , $(J, \alpha N_J)$ is such a pair by Example 15.2. In the special case where R is a field, every such pair $(M, f)$ — that is, every element of $H^1(R, \mathbf {Isom}(J))$ — is of the form $(J, \alpha N_J)$ for some J and $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ (see [Reference GaribaldiGar09, 9.12] in general or [Reference SpringerSp62] for the case of characteristic $\ne 2, 3$ ).

Outer automorphism of $\mathbf {Isom}(J)$

Suppose J and $J'$ are Freudenthal R-algebras and $\phi \colon J \to J'$ is an isomorphism of R-modules. Since the bilinear form $T_{J'}$ is regular, there is a unique R-linear map $\phi ^{\dagger } \colon J \to J'$ such that $T_{J'}(\phi x, \phi ^{\dagger } y) = T_J(x, y)$ for all $x, y \in J$ . Because $T_J$ and $T_{J'}$ are symmetric, we have $(\phi ^{\dagger })^{\dagger } = \phi $ for all $\phi $ . If $J''$ is another Freudenthal R-algebra and $\psi \colon J' \to J''$ is an R-linear bijection, then $(\phi \psi )^{\dagger } = \phi ^{\dagger } \psi ^{\dagger }$ .

Proposition 15.5. Let J be a Freudenthal R-algebra.

  1. 1. If $\phi \in \operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(J)$ is such that $N_J \phi = \alpha N_J$ for some $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ , then $N_J \phi ^{\dagger } = \alpha ^{-1} N_J$ .

  2. 2. The map $\phi \mapsto \phi ^{\dagger }$ is an automorphism of $\mathbf {Isom}(J)$ of order 2 that is not an inner automorphism.

  3. 3. For $\phi $ as in (1) or in $\mathbf {Isom}(J)(R)$ , $\phi ^{\dagger } = \phi $ if and only if $\phi $ is an automorphism of J.

Proof. (1): Put $u := \phi (1_J)^{-1}$ . On the one hand,

$$\begin{align*}T_J(x,y) = T_{J^{(u)}}(\phi(x), \phi(y)) \end{align*}$$

for all $x, y \in J$ , because $\phi $ is an isomorphism $J \to J^{(u)}$ by Proposition 13.7. On the other hand, (13.2) yields

$$\begin{align*}T_{J^{(u)}}(\phi(x), \phi(y)) = T_J(U_u \phi(x), \phi(y)). \end{align*}$$

Therefore,

(15.1) $$ \begin{align} \phi^{\dagger} = U_{\phi(1_J)^{-1}} \phi. \end{align} $$

To complete the proof of (1), we note by Lemma 6.5(3) that

$$\begin{align*}N_J \phi^{\dagger} = N_J U_u \phi = N_J(u)^2 N_J \phi = \alpha^{-1} N_J. \end{align*}$$

For (2), we only have to check that the map is not an inner automorphism. Let $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ be such that there exists $\zeta \in \mu _3(S)$ such that $\zeta \ne 1$ . Then $\zeta ^{\dagger } = \zeta ^{-1} \ne \zeta $ and $\zeta $ is in the center of $\mathbf {Iso}(J)(R)$ , proving that the automorphism is not inner (and not the identity).

For (3), suppose $\phi ^{\dagger } = \phi $ . Then $N_J \phi = N_J$ . By (15.1), $U_{\phi (1_J)^{-1}} = \operatorname {\mathrm {Id}}_J$ , so $\phi (1_J) = \zeta 1_J$ for some $\zeta \in R$ with $\zeta ^2 = 1$ (Example 7.4). Yet $1 = N_J(1_J) = N_J \phi (1_J)$ , so $\zeta ^3$ also equals 1, whence $\phi (1_J) = 1_J$ . Lemma 10.2 shows that $\phi $ is an automorphism of J. Conversely, if $\phi $ is an automorphism of J, then $u = 1_J$ , so $\phi ^{\dagger } = \phi $ by (15.1).

Proposition 15.6. Let J and $J'$ be Albert R-algebras. Among the statements

  1. 1. $\mathbf {Isom}(J) \cong \mathbf {Isom}(J')$ ,

  2. 2. There is a line bundle L and isomorphism $h \colon L^{\otimes 3} \to R$ such that $(J', N_{J'}) \cong [L, h] \cdot (J, N_J)$ for $\cdot $ as defined in Section 3,

  3. 3. J and $J'$ are isotopic,

we have the implications (1) $\Leftrightarrow $ (2) $\Leftarrow $ (3). If $\operatorname {\mathrm {Pic}} R$ has no 3-torsion other than zero, then all three statements are equivalent.

Proof. Suppose (1); we prove (2). We may assume R is connected.

The conjugation action gives a homomorphism $\mathbf {Isom}(J) \to \mathbf {Aut}(\mathbf {Isom}(J))$ , which gives a map of pointed sets

(15.2) $$ \begin{align} H^1(R, \mathbf{Isom}(J)) \to H^1(R, \mathbf{Aut}(\mathbf{Isom}(J))), \end{align} $$

where the second set is in bijection with isomorphism classes of R-group schemes that become isomorphic to $\mathbf {Isom}(J)$ after base change to an fppf R-algebra. By hypothesis, the class of $N_{J'} \in H^1(R, \mathbf {Isom}(J))$ is in the kernel of (15.2).

There is an exact sequence

$$\begin{align*}1 \to \mathbf{Isom}(J) / \mu_3 \to \mathbf{Aut}(\mathbf{Isom}(J)) \to \mathbb{Z}/2 \to 1 \end{align*}$$

of fppf sheaves by [Reference Demazure and GrothendieckDemG, Theorem XXIV.1.3]. Since R is connected, $(\mathbb {Z}/2)(R)$ has one nonidentity element, and it is the image of the map $\dagger $ from Lemma 15.5. That is, in the exact sequence

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{Aut}(\mathbf{Isom}(J))(R) \to (\mathbb{Z}/2)(R) \to H^1(R, \mathbf{Isom}(J)/\mu_3) \to H^1(R, \mathbf{Aut}(\mathbf{Isom}(J))), \end{align*}$$

the first map is surjective, so the third map has zero kernel, and we deduce that the image of $N_{J'}$ in $H^1(R, \mathbf {Isom}(J)/\mu _3)$ is the zero class. It follows that $N_{J'}$ is in the image of the map

$$\begin{align*}H^1(R, \mu_3) \to H^1(R, \mathbf{Isom}(J)), \end{align*}$$

which is the orbit of the zero class $N_J$ under the action of the group $H^1(R, \mu _3)$ , which is (2).

That (2) implies (1) is Lemma 3.6. The claimed implications between (3) and (2) are Corollary 15.4.

16 Freudenthal triple systems

In this section, we define Freudenthal triple systems, also known as FT systems. We will see in Theorem 17.4 in the next section that they play the same role relative to groups of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ that forms of the norm on an Albert algebra play for groups of type $\mathsf {E}_6$ .

For any Albert R-algebra J, define $Q(J)$ to be the rank 56 projective R-module $R \oplus R \oplus J \oplus J$ endowed with a 4-linear form $\Psi $ and an alternating bilinear form b, defined as follows.

We write an element of $Q(J)$ as $\left ( \begin {smallmatrix} \alpha & x \\ x' & \alpha ' \end {smallmatrix} \right )$ for $\alpha , \alpha ' \in R$ and $x, x' \in J$ . Define

(16.1) $$ \begin{align} b_J \left( \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha & x \\ x' & \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right), \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \beta & y \\ y' & \beta' \end{smallmatrix} \right) \right) := \alpha \beta' - \alpha' \beta + T_J(x, y') - T_J(x', y). \end{align} $$

As an intermediate step to defining $\Psi $ , define a quartic form

(16.2) $$ \begin{align} q_J \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha & x \\ x' & \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right) = -4T_J(x^{\sharp}, x^{\prime\sharp})+ 4\alpha N_J(x) + 4 \alpha' N_J(x') + (T_J(x, x') - \alpha \alpha')^2, \end{align} $$

compare [Reference BrownBrown, p. 87] or [Reference KrutelevichKr07, p. 940].

To define the 4-linear form, consider first the case $R = \mathbb {Z}$ and $J := \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z}))$ . (The following definitions are inspired by [Reference LurieLur, Section 6].) Putting $X_i$ for an element of $Q(J)$ and $t_i$ for an indeterminate, the coefficient of $t_1 t_2 t_3 t_4$ in $q(\sum t_i X_i)$ , equivalently, the 4-linear form

$$\begin{align*}(X_1, X_2, X_3, X_4) \mapsto \nabla_{X_1} \nabla_{X_2} \nabla_{X_3} q(X_4) \end{align*}$$

on $Q(J)$ , equals $2\Theta $ for a symmetric 4-linear form $\Theta $ . Define 4-linear forms $\Phi _i$ via

(16.3) $$ \begin{align} \Phi_1(X_1, X_2, X_3, X_4) &= b(X_1, X_2)\, b(X_3, X_4) \notag \\ \Phi_2(X_1, X_2, X_3, X_4) &= b(X_1, X_3)\, b(X_4, X_2) \\ \Phi_3(X_1, X_2, X_3, X_4) &= b(X_1, X_4)\, b(X_2, X_3). \notag \end{align} $$

Then $\Theta + \sum \Phi _i$ is divisible by 2 as a 4-linear function on $Q(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z}))$ , and we set

(16.4) $$ \begin{align} \Psi_{\operatorname{\mathrm{Her}}_3(\operatorname{\mathrm{Zor}}(\mathbb{Z}))} := \frac12 (\Theta + \sum \Phi_i). \end{align} $$

As $\Theta $ is symmetric, $\Psi $ is evidently stable under even permutations of its arguments, and we have:

$$\begin{align*}\Psi(X_1, X_2, X_3, X_4) - \Psi(X_2, X_1, X_3, X_4) = \sum \Phi_i. \end{align*}$$

For any ring R, we define $\Psi _{\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R))} := \Psi _{\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z}))} \otimes R$ , and we define $\Psi _J$ for an Albert R-algebra J by descent.

Definition 16.1. A Freudenthal triple system Footnote 1 or FT system $(M, \Psi , b)$ is an R-module M endowed with a 4-linear form $\Psi $ and an alternating bilinear form b such that $(M, \Psi , b) \otimes S$ is isomorphic (in an obvious sense) to $Q(J)$ for some faithfully flat $S \in {R\text {-}\textbf {alg}}$ and some Albert S-algebra J.

Comparison with other definitions

Suppose for this paragraph that 6 is invertible in R. Given an FT system $(M, \Psi , b)$ , we may define 4-linear forms $\Phi _i$ on M via (16.3) and recover $\Theta $ and q via

(16.5) $$ \begin{align} \Theta := 2 \Psi - \sum \Phi_i \quad \text{and} \quad \Theta(X,X,X,X) = 12q(X) \end{align} $$

as polynomial laws in X. (This last is a special case of the general fact that going from a homogeneous form of degree d to a d-linear form and back to a homogeneous form of degree d equals multiplication by $d!$ [Reference BourbakiBouA2, Section IV.5.8, Proposition 12(i)].) Since the form b is regular and $\Theta $ is symmetric, the equation

$$\begin{align*}\Theta(X_1, X_2, X_3, X_4) = b(X_1, t(X_2, X_3, X_4)) \end{align*}$$

implicitly defines a symmetric 3-linear form $t \colon M \times M \times M \to M$ , and $\mathbf {Aut}(M, \Psi , b)$ equals $\mathbf {Aut}(M, t, b)$ . That is, under the hypothesis that 6 is invertible in R, we would obtain an equivalent class of objects if we replaced the asymmetric 4-linear form $\Psi $ in the definition of FT systems with the quartic form q (the version studied in [Reference BrownBrown]) or with the trilinear form t (the version studied in [Reference MeybergMey]).

Similarity of FT systems

For a d-linear form f on an R-module M, that is, an R-linear map $f \colon M^{\otimes d} \to R$ , and a d-trivialized line bundle $[L, h] \in H^1(R, \mu _d)$ , we define a d-linear form $[L, h] \cdot f$ on $M \otimes L$ via the composition

$$\begin{align*}(M \otimes L)^{\otimes d} \xrightarrow{\sim} M^{\otimes d} \otimes L^{\otimes d} \xrightarrow{f \otimes h} R. \end{align*}$$

For $Q := (M, \Psi , b)$ , an FT system and a discriminant module $[L, h] \in H^1(R, \mu _2)$ , we define $[L, h] \cdot Q$ to be the triple consisting of the module $M \otimes L$ , the 4-linear form $[L, h^{\otimes 2}] \cdot \Psi $ for $[L, h^{\otimes 2}] \in H^1(R, \mu _4)$ , and the bilinear form $[L, h] \cdot b$ . Since ${\left \langle {1}\right \rangle } \cdot Q$ is Q itself, we deduce that $[L, h] \cdot Q$ is also an FT system. We say that FT systems Q, $Q'$ are similar if $Q' \cong [L, h] \cdot Q$ for some $[L, h] \in H^1(R, \mu _2)$ . For example, for any FT system $(M, \Psi , b)$ and any $\alpha \in R^{\times }$ , $(M, \Psi , b)$ and $(M, \alpha ^2 \Psi , \alpha b)$ are similar.

Example 16.2. Suppose $(M, \Psi , b) = Q(J)$ for some Albert R-algebra J. Then for every $\mu \in R^{\times }$ , the map

$$\begin{align*}\left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha & x \\ x' & \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right) \mapsto \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha/\mu & \mu x \\ x' & \mu^2 \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right) \end{align*}$$

is an isomorphism ${\left \langle {\mu }\right \rangle } \cdot Q(J) \xrightarrow {\sim } Q(J)$ . One checks this for $R = \mathbb {Z}$ and $J = \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z}))$ using (16.1) and (16.2). It follows for general R and J by base change and twisting.

17 Groups of type $\mathsf {E}_7$

We will now relate FT systems as defined in the previous section to affine group schemes of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ . Here is a tool that allows us to work with the quartic form q as in (16.2) rather than the less convenient 4-linear form $\Psi $ , while still getting results that hold when 6 is not invertible.

Lemma 17.1. Let $(M, \Psi , b)$ be an FT system over $\mathbb {Z}$ , let $\mathbf {G}$ be a closed subgroup of $\mathbf {GL}(M)$ , and let F be a field of characteristic zero. If $\mathbf {G}(F)$ is dense in $\mathbf {G}$ (which holds if $\mathbf {G}$ is connected) and $\mathbf {G}(F)$ preserves $b \otimes F$ and the quartic form q over F defined by (16.5), then $\mathbf {G}$ is a closed sub-group-scheme of $\mathbf {Aut}(M, \Psi , b)$ .

Proof. Since $\mathbf {G}(F)$ is dense in $\mathbf {G}$ , the group scheme $\mathbf {G} \times F$ preserves $b \otimes F$ and q, whence also $\Psi \otimes F$ . Viewing b and $\Psi $ as elements of the representation $V := (M^*)^{\otimes d}$ of $\mathbf {G}$ for $d = 2$ or 4, the natural map $V^{\mathbf {G}} \otimes F \to (V \otimes F)^{\mathbf {G} \times F}$ is an isomorphism because F is flat over $\mathbb {Z}$ [Reference SeshadriSes, Lemma 2], so $\mathbf {G}$ preserves b and $\Psi $ .

Corollary 17.2. For every Freudenthal R-algebra J, there is an inclusion $f \colon \mathbf {Isom}(J) \hookrightarrow \mathbf {Aut}(Q(J))$ via

$$\begin{align*}f(\phi) \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha & x \\ x' & \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right) = \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha & \phi(x) \\ \phi^{\dagger}(x') & \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right). \end{align*}$$

Proof. Consider the case $J = \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z}))$ . For $\phi \in \mathbf {Isom}(J)(\mathbb {Q})$ , it follows from the definition of $\phi ^{\dagger }$ and Proposition 15.5(1) that $f(\phi )$ is an isomorphism of the bilinear and quartic forms $b \otimes \mathbb {Q}$ and q defined by (16.2) for $J \otimes \mathbb {Q}$ . The lemma gives the claim in this case. Base change and twisting give the claim for every R and every Albert R-algebra J.

Corollary 17.3. Suppose J and $J'$ are Albert R-algebras. If J and $J'$ are isotopic, then $\mathbf {Aut}(Q(J)) \cong \mathbf {Aut}(Q(J'))$ .

Proof. The inclusions $\mathbf {Aut}(J) \hookrightarrow \mathbf {Isom}(J) \hookrightarrow \mathbf {Aut}(Q(J))$ induce maps

$$\begin{align*}H^1(R, \mathbf{Aut}(J)) \to H^1(R, \mathbf{Isom}(J)) \to H^1(R, \mathbf{Aut}(Q(J))), \end{align*}$$

where the last set classifies FT systems over R. The class of $J'$ in $H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(J))$ maps to the class of $N_{J'}$ in $H^1(R, \mathbf {Isom}(J))$ , and by hypothesis and by Proposition 15.6, this is the trivial class. Therefore, the image of $J'$ in $H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(Q(J)))$ , which is $Q(J')$ , is the trivial class.

In case R is a field of characteristic $\ne 2, 3$ , the converse of Corollary 17.3 is true by [Reference FerrarFe72, Corollary 6.9]. That is, if $Q(J) \cong Q(J')$ , then J and $J'$ are isotopic. The paper [Reference AlsaodyAls22] provides an example related to this construction over rings.

Theorem 17.4. The group scheme $\mathbf {Aut}(Q(\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R))))$ over R is obtained from the simply connected Chevalley group of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ over $\mathbb {Z}$ by base change. Every strongly inner and simply connected simple R-group scheme of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ over R is of the form $\mathbf {Aut}(Q)$ for some FT system Q. For FT systems Q and $Q'$ , $\mathbf {Aut}(Q) \cong \mathbf {Aut}(Q')$ if and only if Q and $Q'$ are similar.

Proof. Put $J_R := \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R))$ and $Q_R := Q(J_R)$ . We will show that $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_R)$ is isomorphic to the base change to R of the simply connected Chevalley group $E_7$ over $\mathbb {Z}$ .

In addition to the sub-group-scheme $\mathbf {Isom}(J_R)$ of $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_R)$ provided by Corollary 17.2, we consider a rank 1 torus $\mathbb {G}_{\mathrm {m}}$ defined by

$$\begin{align*}\beta \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha & x \\ x' & \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right) = \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \beta^{-3} \alpha & \beta x \\ \beta^{-1} x' & \beta^3 \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right) \quad \text{for } \beta \in R^{\times} \end{align*}$$

and two copies of $J_R$ (as group schemes under addition) through which an element $y \in J_R$ acts via

$$\begin{align*}y \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha & x \\ x' & \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right) = \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha + b(x', y) & x+\alpha' y \\ x' + x \times y & \alpha' \end{smallmatrix} \right) \quad \text{or} \quad \left( \begin{smallmatrix} \alpha & x+x' \times y \\ x' + \alpha y & \alpha' + b(x', y) \end{smallmatrix} \right). \end{align*}$$

These preserve b and q, see, for example, [Reference BrownBrown, p. 95] or [Reference KrutelevichKr07, p. 942], and so by Lemma 17.1 do belong to $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_R)$ . Considering the Lie algebras of $\mathbf {Isom}(J_R)$ , $\mathbb {G}_{\mathrm {m}}$ , and the two copies of J, as subalgebras of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Lie}}(\mathbf {GL}(Q_R))$ , one can identify the subalgebra $L_R$ they generate with the Lie algebra of $E_7 \times R$ by picking out specific root subalgebras and so on as in [Reference FreudenthalFr54] or [Reference SeligmanSel], or see [Reference GaribaldiGar01, Section 7] for partial information. Note that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Lie}}(\mathbf {Aut}(Q_R)) \supseteq L_R$ . For F any algebraically closed field, we may identify the smooth closed subgroup of $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F)$ generated by $\mathbf {Isom}(J_F)$ , $\mathbb {G}_{\mathrm {m}}$ , and the two copies of $J_F$ with $E_7 \times F$ .

In [Reference LurieLur], Lurie begins with $L_{\mathbb {Z}}$ and defines $L_{\mathbb {Z}}$ -invariant 4-linear forms $\Theta ^L$ , $\Phi _i^L$ , and $\Psi ^L$ and alternating bilinear form $b^L$ on the 56-dimensional Weyl module of $L_{\mathbb {Z}}$ . Over $\mathbb {C}$ , $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_{\mathbb {C}})$ is simply connected of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ by the references in the previous paragraph, so it preserves the base change of Lurie’s forms $\Theta ^L \otimes \mathbb {C}$ , etc. Because $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_{\mathbb {C}})(\mathbb {C})$ is dense in $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_{\mathbb {C}})$ , Lemma 17.1 shows that $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_{\mathbb {Z}})$ preserves $\Theta ^L$ , the $\Phi _i^L$ , $\Psi ^L$ , and $b^L$ . By the uniqueness of $E_7$ invariant bilinear and symmetric 4-linear forms on M (which follows from the uniqueness over $\mathbb {C}$ as in the proof of Lemma 17.1), we find that $b^L = \pm b$ and $\Theta ^L = \pm \Theta $ . Note that regardless of the sign on b in the preceding sentence, we find $\Phi ^L_i = \Phi _i$ for all i and $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F)$ preserves $b^L$ . Now let F be an algebraically closed field. If F has characteristic different from 2, then $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F)$ preserves $2 \Psi = \Theta + \sum \Phi _i$ and the $\Phi _i$ , so it preserves $\Theta $ , hence $\Theta ^L$ , hence $\Psi ^L$ . If F has characteristic 2, then although $\Psi ^L = \frac 12 (\pm \Theta + \sum \Phi _i)$ for some choice of sign as polynomials over $\mathbb {Z}$ , we have $\Psi ^L \otimes F = \Psi \otimes F$ . In either case, $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F)$ preserves $b^L \otimes F$ and $\Psi ^L \otimes F$ , whence so does its Lie algebra, so $\dim \operatorname {\mathrm {Lie}} \mathbf {Aut}(Q_F) \le \dim L_F$ by [Reference LurieLur, Theorem 6.2.3]. Putting this together with the previous paragraph, we see that $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F)$ , an affine group scheme over the field F, is smooth with identity component $E_7 \times F$ .

We claim that $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F)$ is connected. Since its identity component $E_7$ has no outer automorphisms, every element of $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F)(F)$ is a product of an element of $E_7(F)$ and a linear transformation centralizing $E_7$ . The action of $E_7 \times F$ on $Q_F$ is irreducible (it is the 56-dimensional minuscule representation), so the centralizer of $E_7$ consists of scalar transformations. Finally, we note that the intersection of $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F)$ and the scalar transformations is the group scheme $\mu _2$ of square roots of unity, which is contained in $E_7$ . In summary, $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_F) = E_7 \times F$ for every algebraically closed field F.

As in the proof of Lemma 9.1, it follows that $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_{\mathbb {Z}})$ is a simple affine group scheme that is simply connected of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ , and we deduce from the fact that $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_{\mathbb {R}})$ is split that $\mathbf {Aut}(Q_{\mathbb {Z}})$ is in fact the Chevalley group.

The second claim now follows by descent.

The third claim is proved in the same manner as Proposition 15.6, although the current situation is somewhat easier due to the absence of nontrivial automorphisms of the Dynkin diagram of $\mathsf {E}_7$ and therefore the absence of outer automorphisms for semisimple groups of that type. The sequence

(17.1) $$ \begin{align} H^1(R, \mu_2) \to H^1(R, \mathbf{Aut}(Q)) \to H^1(R, \mathbf{Aut}(\mathbf{Aut}(Q))) \end{align} $$

is exact, where $\mu _2$ is the center of $\mathbf {Aut}(Q)$ and $\mathbf {Aut}(\mathbf {Aut}(Q)) \cong \mathbf {Aut}(Q)/\mu _2$ is the adjoint group. We have $\mathbf {Aut}(Q') \cong \mathbf {Aut}(Q)$ if and only if the element $Q'$ in $H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(Q))$ is in the kernel of the second map in (17.1), if and only if $Q'$ is in the image of the first map. To complete the proof, it suffices to calculate by descent that the action of $H^1(R, \mu _2)$ on $H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(Q))$ is exactly by the similarity action defined in Section 16.

A partial rephrasing of the second statement of the theorem is that, for any FT system Q, the set $H^1(R, \mathbf {Aut}(Q))$ is in bijection with the set of isomorphism classes of FT systems over R.

Corollary 17.5. If R is: (1) a complete discrete valuation ring whose residue field is finite; (2) a finite ring; or (3) a Dedekind domain whose field of fractions F is a global field with no real embeddings, then the split FT system is the only one over R, up to isomorphism.

Proof. Imitate the arguments in Proposition 11.3 or Example 11.5, where $\mathbf {G}$ is the base change to R of the simply connected Chevalley group $\mathbf {Aut}(Q(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z})))$ .

Remarks 17.6. A previous work that considered groups of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ over rings is [Reference LuzgarevLuz]. Aschbacher [Reference AschbacherAsch] studied the 4-linear form in the case where R is a field of characteristic 2. The paper [Reference Mühlherr and WeissMüW] studied the case of fields of any characteristic, organized around a polynomial law $\Theta \in \mathscr {P}(Q, R)$ that is not homogeneous. For a field F of characteristic $\ne 2, 3$ , FT systems have been studied in this century in [Reference ClercCl], [Reference HeleniusHel], [Reference KrutelevichKr07], [Reference SpringerSp06], and [Reference Borsten, Duff, Ferrara, Marrani and RubensBDFMR] to name a few. They arise naturally in the context of the bottom row of the magic triangle from [Reference Deligne and GrossDelG, Table 2], in connection with the existence of extraspecial parabolic subgroups as in [Reference RöhrleRöh] or [Reference GaribaldiGar09, Section 12], or from groups with a $\mathsf {B}\mathsf {C}_1$ grading [Reference Gross and GaribaldiGrG, p. 995]. For every Albert F-algebra J, the group scheme $\mathbf {Aut}(Q(J))$ is isotropic (see, for example [Reference SpringerSp06, Lemma 5.6(i)]). Yet there exist strongly inner groups of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ that are anisotropic, see [Reference TitsT, 3.1] or [Reference GaribaldiGar09, Appendix A], and therefore, there exist FT systems Q that are not isomorphic to $Q(J)$ for any J. A construction that produces all FT systems can be obtained by considering a subgroup $\mathbf {Isom}(J) \rtimes \mu _4$ of $\mathbf {Aut}(Q(J))$ , which leads to a surjection $H^1(F, \mathbf {Isom}(J) \rtimes \mu _4) \to H^1(F, \mathbf {Aut}(Q(J)))$ (see [Reference GaribaldiGar09, 12.13], [Reference GaribaldiGar01, Lemma 4.15] or [Reference SpringerSp06, Section 4]).

18 Exceptional groups over $\mathbb {Z}$

We now record explicit descriptions of the isomorphism classes of semisimple affine group schemes over $\mathbb {Z}$ of types $\mathsf {F}_4$ , $\mathsf {G}_2$ , $\mathsf {E}_6$ , and $\mathsf {E}_7$ .

There are four such group schemes of type $\mathsf {F}_4$ , namely, $\mathbf {Aut}(J)$ for each of the four Albert $\mathbb {Z}$ -algebras listed in Theorem 14.3(b). The proof of this fact is intertwined with the proof of that theorem. Similarly, there are two such group schemes of type $\mathsf {G}_2$ , namely, $\mathbf {Aut}(C)$ for $C = \operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z})$ or $\mathcal {O}$ .

Proposition 18.1. For $R = \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mathbb {R}$ or a number field with a unique real embedding, and $J_i = \operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C_i)$ for $C_0 = \operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(R)$ and $C_1 = \mathcal {O} \otimes R$ :

  1. 1. there are exactly two isomorphism classes of R-forms of the cubic norm on $J_0$ , namely, $N_{J_i}$ for $i = 0, 1$ .

  2. 2. there are exactly two isomorphism classes of FT systems over R, namely, $Q(J_i)$ for $i = 0, 1$ .

Proof. For $n = 6$ or 7, put $E_n$ for the semisimple simply connected Chevalley group scheme over $\mathbb {Z}$ of type $\mathsf {E}_n$ . The set $H^1(\mathbb {R}, E_n)$ has two elements (see [Reference Borovoi and EvenorBorE], [Reference Borovoi and TimashevBorT, esp. Section 15] or [Reference Adams and TaïbiAdT, Table 3]). For F a number field with a unique real embedding, the map $H^1(F, E_n) \to H^1(\mathbb {R}, E_n)$ is a bijection, a fact we have already used in Example 11.2.

By [Reference ConradConrad, Remark 4.8], $\mathbb {Z}$ forms of absolutely simple and simply connected $\mathbb {Q}$ -group schemes are purely inner forms, that is, in this case they are obtained by twisting $E_n$ by a class $\xi \in H^1(\mathbb {Z}, E_n)$ . Now the compact real form of type $\mathsf {E}_n$ is not a pure inner form, so $(E_n)_{\xi } \times \mathbb {R}$ is not compact for all $\xi \in H^1(\mathbb {Z}, E_n)$ . Therefore, the natural map $H^1(\mathbb {Z}, E_n) \to H^1(\mathbb {Q}, E_n)$ is a bijection by [Reference HarderHa67, Satz 4.2.4].

We have observed that the set $H^1(R, E_n)$ has two elements for each choice of R, and we have already noted that this set is in bijection with the isomorphism classes in (1) for $n = 6$ and (2) for $n = 7$ (Theorem 17.4). It suffices to prove that the two exhibited elements are distinct, for which it suffices to consider the case $R = \mathbb {R}$ .

In case (1), $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\mathcal {O})$ is not split (Example 11.1), so it is not isotopic to $\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(\operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {R}))$ (Cor. 13.4) and the cubic norms on the two algebras are not isomorphic (Corollary 15.4). In case (2), one can invoke Ferrar’s converse to Corollary 17.3. Alternatively, one can use the methods used to calculate $H^1(\mathbb {R}, E_n)$ to observe that the nontrivial element of $H^1(\mathbb {R}, E_7)$ is in the image of $H^1(\mathbb {R}, E_6)$ .

(Apart from the case $R = \mathbb {Z}$ , the proposition is well known. Analogous statements for any number field can be deduced from the result over $\mathbb {R}$ via Harder’s local-global principle as in Example 11.2, see, for example [Reference FerrarFe76] and [Reference FerrarFe78].)

The proof provides the following corollary.

Corollary 18.2. Regarding isomorphism classes of semisimple and simply connected affine group schemes over $\mathbb {Z}$ :

  1. 1. there are two of type $\mathsf {E}_6$ , namely, $\mathbf {Isom}(\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C))$ and

  2. 2. there are two of type $\mathsf {E}_7$ , namely, $\mathbf {Aut}(Q(\operatorname {\mathrm {Her}}_3(C)))$

for $C = \operatorname {\mathrm {Zor}}(\mathbb {Z})$ or $\mathcal {O}$ . $\Box $

We have addressed now all the simple types that are usually called “exceptional”, apart from $\mathsf {E}_8$ . A classification of $\mathbb {Z}$ -groups of type $\mathsf {E}_8$ like Proposition 18.2 appears currently out of reach, because among those group schemes $\mathbf {G}$ over $\mathbb {Z}$ such that $\mathbf {G} \times \mathbb {R}$ is the compact group of type $\mathsf {E}_8$ , there are at least 13,935 distinct isomorphism classes [Reference GrossGr, Proposition 5.3]. Among those $\mathbf {G}$ over $\mathbb {Z}$ of type $\mathsf {E}_8$ such that $\mathbf {G} \times \mathbb {R}$ is not compact, the same argument as in the proof of Proposition 18.2 shows that there are two isomorphism classes.

Acknowledgments

We thank the many kind readers who provided suggestions or comments, including Asher Auel, Brian Conrad, Uriya First, Wee Teck Gan, Erhard Neher, Zinovy Reichstein, Ben Williams and anonymous referees. The development of this paper was influenced in various ways by [Reference ConradConrad], even when it is not explicitly cited. The authors have no support or funding to report.

Conflict of Interest

The authors have no conflict of interest to declare.

Footnotes

1 See p. 273 of [Reference SpringerSp06] for remarks on the history of this term.

References

Adams, J. and Taïbi, O., ‘Galois and Cartan cohomology of real groups’, Duke Math. J. 167(6) (2018), 10571097.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Albert, A. A., ‘Non-associative algebras. I. Fundamental concepts and isotopy’, Ann. of Math. (2) 43(4) (1942), 687707.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Albert, A. A., ‘A construction of exceptional Jordan division algebras’, Ann. of Math. (2) 67 (1958), 128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Albert, A. A. and Jacobson, N., ‘On reduced exceptional simple Jordan algebras’, Ann. of Math. (2) 66 (1957), 400417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alsaody, S., ‘Albert algebras over rings and related torsors’, Canad. J. Math. 73(3) (2021), 875898.Google Scholar
Alsaody, S., ‘Groups of type ${E}_6$ and ${E}_7$ over rings via Brown algebras and related torsors’, Preprint, 2022, arXiv:2210.15924.Google Scholar
Alsaody, S. and Gille, P., ‘Isotopes of octonion algebras, ${G}_2$ -torsors and triality’, Adv. Math. 343 (2019), 864909.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aschbacher, M., ‘Some multilinear forms with large isometry groups’, Geometriae Dedicata 25 (1988), 417465.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asok, A., Hoyois, M. and Wendt, M., ‘Generically split octonion algebras and ${A}^1$ -homotopy theory’, Algebra & Number Theory 13(3) (2019), 695747.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Auel, A., Bernardara, M. and Bolognesi, M., ‘Fibrations in complete intersections of quadrics, Clifford algebras, derived categories, and rationality problems’, J. Math. Pures Appl. 102 (2014), 249291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balmer, P. and Calmès, B., ‘Bases of total Witt groups and lax-similitude’, J. Algebra Appl. 11(3) (2012), 1250045.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borsten, L., Duff, M. J., Ferrara, S., Marrani, A. and Rubens, W., ‘Explicit orbit classification of reducible Jordan algebras and Freudenthal triple systems’, Comm. Math. Phys. 325 (2014), 1739.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borovoi, M. and Evenor, Z., ‘Real homogeneous spaces, Galois cohomology, and Reeder puzzles’, J. Algebra 467 (2016), 307365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borovoi, M. and Timashev, D. A., ‘Galois cohomology of real semisimple groups via Kac labelings’, Transf. Groups 26(2) (2021), 443477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourbaki, N., ‘Algebra II: Chapters 4–7’, in Elements of Mathematics (Springer-Verlag, 1988).Google Scholar
Bourbaki, N., ‘Commutative algebra. Chapters 1–7’, in Elements of Mathematics (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1998). Translated from the French. Reprint of the 1989 English translation.Google Scholar
Braun, H. and Koecher, M., Jordan-Algebren (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1966).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, R. B., ‘Groups of type ${E}_{7}$ ’, J. Reine Angew. Math. 236 (1969), 79102.Google Scholar
Calmès, B. and Fasel, J., ‘Groupes classiques’, Panoramas & Synthèses 46 (2015), 1133.Google Scholar
Carr, M. and Garibaldi, S., ‘Geometries, the principle of duality, and algebraic groups’, Expo. Math. 24 (2006), 195234.Google Scholar
Chayet, M. and Garibaldi, S., ‘A class of continuous non-associative algebras arising from algebraic groups including ${E}_8$ ’, Forum Math. Sigma 9 (2021), e6. doi:10.1017/fms.2020.66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clerc, J.-L., ‘Special prehomogeneous vector spaces associated to ${F}_4,{E}_6,{E}_7,{E}_8$ and simple Jordan algebras of rank 3’, J. Algebra 264 (2003), 98128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conrad, B., ‘Non-split reductive groups over $\boldsymbol{Z}$ ’, in Autour des Schémas en Groupes II, Panoramas et synthèses , vol. 46 (Société Mathématique de France, 2014), 193253.Google Scholar
Conway, J. H. and Smith, D. A., ‘On Quaternions and Octonions: Their Geometry, Arithmetic, and Symmetry’ (A K Peters, Ltd., Natick, MA, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coxeter, H. S. M., ‘Integral Cayley numbers’, Duke Math. J. 13 (1946), 561578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deligne, P. and Gross, B. H., ‘On the exceptional series, and its descendants’, C. R. Math. Acad. Sci. Paris 335(11) (2002), 877881.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demazure, M. and Grothendieck, A., ‘Schémas en groupes III: Structure des schemas en groupes reductifs’, in Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 153 (Springer, 1970).Google Scholar
Dickson, L. E., ‘A new simple theory of hypercomplex integers’, J. Math. Pures Appl. 29 (1923), 281326.Google Scholar
Elkies, N. D. and Gross, B. H., ‘The exceptional cone and the Leech lattice’, Internat. Math. Res. Notices 1996(14) (1996), 665698.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elman, R. S., Karpenko, N. and Merkurjev, A., ‘The algebraic and geometric theory of quadratic forms’, in Colloquium Publications, vol. 56 (American Mathematical Society, 2008).Google Scholar
Estes, D. R. and Guralnick, R. M., ‘Module equivalences: Local to global when primitive polynomials represent units’, J. Algebra 77 (1982), 138157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferrar, J. C., ‘Strictly regular elements in Freudenthal triple systems’, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 174 (1972), 313331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferrar, J. C., ‘Algebras of type ${E}_7$ over number fields’, J. Algebra 39 (1976), 1525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferrar, J. C., ‘Lie algebras of type ${E}_6$ . II’, J. Algebra 52(1) (1978), 201209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
First, U. A. and Reichstein, Z., ‘On the number of generators of an algebra’, Comptes Rendus Math. 355(1) (2017), 59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
First, U. A., Reichstein, Z. and Williams, B., ‘On the number of generators of an algebra over a commutative ring’, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 375 (2022), 72777321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freudenthal, H., ‘Beziehungen der ${E}_7$ und ${E}_8$ zur Oktavenebene. I’, Nederl. Akad. Wetensch. Proc. Ser. A 57 (1954), 218230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freudenthal, H., ‘Oktaven, Ausnahmegruppen und Oktavengeometrie’, Geom. Dedicata 19 (1985), 763 (Reprint of Utrecht Lecture Notes, 1951).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gan, W. T. and Yu, J.-K., ‘Schémas en groupes et immeubles des groupes exceptionnels sur un corps local. Première partie: Le groupe ${G}_2$ ’, Bull. Soc. Math. France 131(3) (2003), 307358.Google Scholar
Garibaldi, S., ‘Structurable algebras and groups of type ${E}_6$ and ${E}_7$ ’, J. Algebra 236(2) (2001), 651691.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garibaldi, S., ‘Cohomological invariants: Exceptional groups and spin groups’, in Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 937 (American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2009). With an appendix by Detlev W. Hoffmann.Google Scholar
Gille, P., ‘Octonion algebras over rings are not determined by their norms’, Canad. Math. Bull. 57(2) (2014), 303309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gille, P., ‘Groupes algébriques semi-simples en dimension cohomologique $\le 2$ ’, in Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 2238 (Springer, 2019).Google Scholar
Giraud, J., ‘Cohomologie non abélienne’, in Die Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften , vol. 179 (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1971).Google Scholar
Gross, B. H., ‘Groups over $\mathbf{Z}$ ’, Invent. Math. 124 (1–3) (1996), 263279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gross, B. H. and Garibaldi, S., ‘Minuscule embeddings’, Indag. Math. 32(5) (2021), 9871004.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harder, G., ‘Über die Galoiskohomologie halbeinfacher Matrizengruppen. II’, Math. Z. 92 (1966), 396415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harder, G., ‘Halbeinfache Gruppenschemata über Dedekindringen’, Invent. Math. 4 (1967), 165191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helenius, F., ‘Freudenthal triple systems by root system methods’, J. Algebra 357 (2012), 116137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hijikata, H., ‘A remark on the groups of type ${G}_2$ and ${F}_4$ ’, J. Math. Soc. Japan 15 (1963), 159164.Google Scholar
Jacobson, N., ‘Some groups of transformations defined by Jordan algebras. III’, J. Reine Angew. Math. 207 (1961), 6185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, N., ‘Structure and representations of Jordan algebras’, in Colloquium Publications, vol. 39 (American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1968).Google Scholar
Jacobson, N., ‘Lectures on quadratic Jordan algebras’, in Tata Institute of Fundamental Research Lectures on Mathematics , vol. 45 (Tata Institute of Fundamental Research, Bombay, 1969).Google Scholar
Jacobson, N., ‘Exceptional Lie algebras’, in Lecture Notes in Pure and Applied Mathematics, vol. 1 (Marcel-Dekker, New York, 1971).Google Scholar
Knus, M.-A., Quadratic and Hermitian Forms over Rings (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1991).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knus, M.-A., Merkurjev, A. S., Rost, M. and Tignol, J.-P., ‘The book of involutions’, in Colloquium Publications, vol. 44 (American Mathematical Society, 1998).Google Scholar
Knus, M.-A. and Ojanguren, M., ‘Théorie de la descente et algèbras d’Azumaya’, in Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 389 (Springer-Verlag, 1974).Google Scholar
Krutelevich, S., ‘On a canonical form of a $3\times 3$ Hermitian matrix over the ring of integral split octonions’, J. Algebra 253 (2002), 276295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krutelevich, S., ‘Jordan algebras, exceptional groups, and Bhargava composition’, J. Algebra 314(2) (2007), 924977.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loos, O., ‘Generically algebraic Jordan algebras over commutative rings’, J. Algebra 297 (2006), 474529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loos, O., Petersson, H. P. and Racine, M. L., ‘Inner derivations of alternative algebras over commutative rings’, Algebra Number Theory 2(8) (2008), 927968.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lurie, J., ‘On simply laced Lie algebras and their minuscule representations’, Comment. Math. Helv. 76 (2001), 515575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luzgarev, A. Yu., ‘Fourth-degree invariants for $G\left({E}_7,R\right)$ not depending on the characteristic’, Vestnik St. Petersburg University: Mathematics 46(1) (2013), 2934.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahler, K., ‘On ideals in the Cayley-Dickson algebra’, Proc. Roy. Irish Acad. Sect. A. 48 (1942), 123133.Google Scholar
McCrimmon, K., ‘A general theory of Jordan rings’, Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 56 (1966), 10721079.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McCrimmon, K., ‘The Freudenthal-Springer-Tits constructions of exceptional Jordan algebras’, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 139 (1969), 495510.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCrimmon, K., ‘The Freudenthal-Springer-Tits constructions revisited’, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 148 (1970), 293314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCrimmon, K., ‘Homotopes of alternative algebras’, Math. Ann. 191 (1971), 253262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCrimmon, K., ‘Inner ideals in quadratic Jordan algebras’, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 159 (1971), 445468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCrimmon, K., ‘Nonassociative algebras with scalar involution’, Pacific J. Math. 116(1) (1985), 85109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCrimmon, K., ‘A taste of Jordan algebras’, in Universitext (Springer-Verlag, New York, 2004).Google Scholar
McCrimmon, K. and Zel’manov, E.The structure of strongly prime quadratic Jordan algebras’, Adv. in Math. 69(2) (1988), 133222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDonald, B. R. and Waterhouse, W. C., Projective modules over rings with many units’, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 83(3) (1981), 455458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyberg, K., Eine Theorie der Freudenthalschen Tripelsysteme. I, II’, Nederl. Akad. Wetensch. Proc. Ser. A 71 $=$ Indag. Math. 30 (1968), 162190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milne, J. S., ‘Algebraic groups: The theory of group schemes of finite type over a field’, in Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics , vol. 170 (Cambridge University Press, 2017).Google Scholar
Mühlherr, B. and Weiss, R. M., ‘Freudenthal triple systems in arbitrary characteristic’, J. Algebra 520 (2019), 237275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parimala, R., Sridharan, R. and Thakur, M. L., ‘Tits’ constructions of Jordan algebras and ${F}_4$ bundles on the plane’, Compositio Math. 119 (1999), 1340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petersson, H. P., ‘Composition algebras over algebraic curves of genus zero’, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 337(1) (1993), 473493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petersson, H. P., ‘A survey on Albert algebras’, Transf. Groups 24(1) (2019), 219278.Google Scholar
Petersson, H. P., ‘Norm equivalences and ideals of composition algebras’, Münster J. of Math. 14 (2021), 283293.Google Scholar
Petersson, H. P. and Racine, M. L., ‘Springer forms and the first Tits construction of exceptional Jordan division algebras’, Manuscripta Math. 45 (1984), 249272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petersson, H. P. and Racine, M. L., ‘The toral Tits process of Jordan algebras’, Abh. Math. Sem. Univ. Hamburg 54 (1984), 251256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petersson, H. P. and Racine, M. L., ‘Radicals of Jordan algebras of degree $3$ ’, in Radical theory (Eger, 1982), Colloquia Mathematica Societatis János Bolyai, vol. 38 (North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1985), 349377.Google Scholar
Petersson, H. P. and Racine, M. L., ‘Jordan algebras of degree $3$ and the Tits process’, J. Algebra 98(1) (1986), 211243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petersson, H. P. and Racine, M. L., ‘Classification of algebras arising from the Tits process’, J. Algebra 98(1) (1986), 244279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petersson, H. P. and Racine, M. L., ‘An elementary approach to the Serre-Rost invariant of Albert algebras’, Indag. Math. (N.S.) 7(3) (1996), 343365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Platonov, V. P. and Rapinchuk, A., ‘Algebraic groups and number theory’, in Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics , vol. 1 (Academic Press, Boston, 1994).Google Scholar
Racine, M. L., ‘Point spaces in exceptional quadratic Jordan algebras’, J. Algebra 46 (1977), 2236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roby, N., ‘Lois polynomes et lois formelles in théorie des modules’, Ann. Sci. École Norm. Sup. (3) 80(3) (1963), 213348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Röhrle, G., ‘On extraspecial parabolic subgroups’, in Linear algebraic groups and their representations (Los Angeles, CA, 1992), Contemporary Mathematics, vol. 153 (American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1993), 143155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rost, M., ‘A (mod 3) invariant for exceptional Jordan algebras’, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris Sér. I Math. 313 (1991), 823827.Google Scholar
Schafer, R., An Introduction to Nonassociative Algebras (Dover Publications, New York, 1994).Google Scholar
Seligman, G. B., ‘On the split exceptional Lie algebra ${E}_7$ ’, dittoed notes, 28 pages, 1963.Google Scholar
Serre, J.-P., ‘Galois Cohomology’ (Springer-Verlag, 2002). Originally published as Cohomologie Galoisienne (1965).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seshadri, C. S., ‘Geometric reductivity over arbitrary base’, Adv. Math. 26 (1977), 225274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Springer, T. A., ‘Characterization of a class of cubic forms’, Nederl. Akad. Wetensch. 65 (1962), 259265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Springer, T. A., ‘Jordan algebras and algebraic groups’, in Ergebnisse der Mathematik und Ihrer Grenzgebiete , vol. 75 (Springer-Verlag, 1973).Google Scholar
Springer, T. A., ‘Some groups of type ${E}_7$ ’, Nagoya Math. J. 182 (2006), 259284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Springer, T. A. and Veldkamp, F. D., Octonions, Jordan Algebras and Exceptional Groups (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The Stacks Project Authors, Stacks project, https://stacks.math.columbia.edu, 2018.Google Scholar
Tits, J., ‘Strongly inner anisotropic forms of simple algebraic groups’, J. Algebra 131 (1990), 648677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van der Blij, F. and Springer, T. A., ‘The arithmetics of octaves and of the group ${G}_2$ ’, Nederl. Akad. Wetensch. 62 (1959), 406418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voight, J., Quaternion Algebras (Springer, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waterhouse, W. C., ‘Introduction to affine group schemes’, in Graduate Texts in Mathematics , vol. 66 (Springer, 1979).Google Scholar
Weil, A., ‘Algebras with involution and the classical groups ’, J. Indian Math. Soc. 24 (1960), 589623.Google Scholar
Zorn, M., ‘Alternativkörper und quadratische Systeme’, Abh. Math. Semin. Hamburg. Univ. 9 (1933), 395402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar