Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T15:32:04.618Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

INCOMPATIBILITY OF GENERIC HUGENESS PRINCIPLES

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 February 2023

MONROE ESKEW*
Affiliation:
KURT GÖDEL RESEARCH CENTER INSTITUT FÜR MATHEMATIK, UNIVERSITÄT WIEN KOLINGASSE 14-16 1090 WIEN, AUSTRIA E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We show that the weakest versions of Foreman’s minimal generic hugeness axioms cannot hold simultaneously on adjacent cardinals. Moreover, conventional forcing techniques cannot produce a model of one of these axioms.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

In [Reference Foreman5Reference Foreman8], Foreman proposed generic large cardinals as new axioms for mathematics. These principles are similar to strong kinds of traditional large cardinal axioms but speak directly about small uncountable objects like $\omega _1,\omega _2$ , etc. Because of this, they are able to answer many classical questions that are not settled by ZFC plus traditional large cardinals. For example, if $\omega _1$ is minimally generically huge, then the Continuum Hypothesis holds and there is a Suslin line [Reference Foreman8].

For a poset $\mathbb {P}$ , let us say that a cardinal $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically huge if $\mathbb {P}$ forces that there is an elementary embedding $j : V \to M \subseteq V[G]$ with critical point $\kappa $ , where M is a transitive class closed under $j(\kappa )$ -sequences from $V[G]$ . If $\mathbb {P}$ forces that $j(\kappa ) = \lambda $ , we call $\lambda $ the target. We say that $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically n-huge when the requirement on M is strengthened to closure under $j^n(\kappa )$ -sequences (where $j^n$ is the composition of j with itself n times), and we say $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically almost-huge if the requirement is weakened to closure under ${<}j(\kappa )$ -sequences. We say that a cardinal $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically measurable if $\mathbb {P}$ forces that there is an elementary embedding $j : V \to M \subseteq V[G]$ with critical point $\kappa $ , where M is transitive.

If $\kappa $ is the successor of an infinite cardinal $\mu $ , we say that $\kappa $ is minimally generically n-huge if it is $\operatorname {\mathrm {Col}}(\mu ,\kappa )$ -generically n-huge, where $\operatorname {\mathrm {Col}}(\mu ,\kappa )$ is the poset of functions from initial segments of $\mu $ into $\kappa $ ordered by end-extension. The main result of this note is that for a successor cardinal $\kappa $ , it is inconsistent for both $\kappa $ and $\kappa ^+$ to be minimally generically huge.

Theorem 1. Suppose $0<m\leq n$ and $\kappa $ is a regular cardinal that is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically n-huge with target $\lambda $ , where $\mathbb {P}$ is nontrivial and strongly $\lambda $ -c.c. Then $\kappa ^{+m}$ is not $\mathbb {Q}$ -generically measurable for any $\kappa $ -closed $\mathbb {Q}$ .

Here, “nontrivial” means that forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ necessarily adds a new set. Usuba [Reference Usuba12] introduced the strong $\lambda $ -chain condition (strong $\lambda $ -c.c.), which means that $\mathbb {P}$ has no antichain of size $\lambda $ and forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ does not add branches to $\lambda $ -Suslin trees. As Usuba observed, $\mathbb {P}$ having the strong $\lambda $ -c.c. is implied by $\mathbb {P}$ having the $\mu $ -c.c. for $\mu <\lambda $ and by $\mathbb {P} \times \mathbb {P}$ having the $\lambda $ -c.c. In particular, if $\theta = \kappa ^{<\mu }$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Col}}(\mu ,\kappa )$ collapses $\theta $ to $\mu $ and is strongly $\theta ^+$ -c.c. Let us also remark that in Theorem 1, $\kappa $ -closure can be weakened to $\kappa $ -strategic-closure without change to the arguments.

Regarding the history: Woodin proved, in unpublished work mentioned in [Reference Foreman8, p. 1126], that it is inconsistent for $\omega _1$ to be minimally generically 3-huge while $\omega _3$ is minimally generically 1-huge. Subsequently, the author [Reference Eskew3] improved this to show the inconsistency of a successor cardinal $\kappa $ being minimally generically n-huge while $\kappa ^{+m}$ is minimally generically almost-huge, where $0 < m < n$ . The weakening of the hypothesis to $\kappa $ being only generically 1-huge uses an idea from the author’s work with Cox [Reference Cox and Eskew1].

In contrast to Theorem 1, Foreman [Reference Foreman4] exhibited a model where for all $n>0$ , $\omega _n$ is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically almost-huge with target $\omega _{n+1}$ for some $\omega _{n-1}$ -closed, strongly $\omega _{n+1}$ -c.c. poset $\mathbb {P}$ . A simplified construction was given by Shioya [Reference Shioya11].

We prove Theorem 1 in Section 2 via a generalization that is less elegant to state. In Section 3, we discuss what is known about the consistency of generic hugeness by itself and present a corollary of Theorem 1 showing that the usual forcing strategies cannot produce models where $\omega _1$ is generically huge with target $\omega _2$ by a strongly $\omega _2$ -c.c. poset. Our notations and terminology are standard. We assume the reader is familiar with the basics of forcing and elementary embeddings.

2 Generic huge embeddings and approximation

The relevance of the strong $\kappa $ -c.c. is its connection to the approximation property of Hamkins [Reference Hamkins9]. Suppose $\mathcal {F} \subseteq \mathcal {P}(\lambda )$ . We say that a set $X \subseteq \lambda $ is approximated by $\mathcal {F}$ when $X \cap z \in \mathcal {F}$ for all $z \in \mathcal {F}$ . If $V \subseteq W$ are models of set theory, then we say that the pair $(V,W)$ satisfies the $\kappa $ -approximation property for a V-cardinal $\kappa $ when for all $\lambda \in V$ and all $X \subseteq \lambda $ in W, if X is approximated by $\mathcal {P}_\kappa (\lambda )^V$ , then $X \in V$ . We say that a forcing $\mathbb {P}$ has the $\kappa $ -approximation property when the $\kappa $ -approximation property is forced to hold of the pair $(V,V[G])$ . The following result appears as Lemma 1.5 and Note 1.11 in [Reference Usuba12]:

Theorem 2 (Usuba).

If $\mathbb {P}$ is a nontrivial $\kappa $ -c.c. forcing and $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ is a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a $\kappa $ -closed forcing, then $\mathbb {P} * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ has the $\kappa $ -approximation property if and only if $\mathbb {P}$ has the strong $\kappa $ -c.c.

Theorem 1 will follow from the more general lemma below.

Lemma 3. The following hypotheses are jointly inconsistent:

  1. (1) $\kappa _0\leq \kappa _1$ and $\lambda _0\leq \lambda _1$ are regular cardinals.

  2. (2) $\mathbb {P}$ is a nontrivial strongly $\lambda _0$ -c.c. poset that forces an elementary embedding $j : V \to M \subseteq V[G]$ with $j(\kappa _0) = \lambda _0$ , $j(\kappa _1) = \lambda _1$ , $\mathcal {P}(\lambda _1)^V \subseteq M$ , and $M^{<\lambda _0} \cap V[G] \subseteq M$ .

  3. (3) $\kappa _1^+$ is $\mathbb {Q}$ -generically measurable for a $\kappa _0$ -closed $\mathbb {Q}$ .

Proof We will need a first-order version of (3) that can be carried through the embedding of (2). Replace it by the (possibly weaker) hypothesis that $\mathbb {Q}$ is a $\kappa _0$ -closed poset and for some $\theta \gg \lambda _1$ , $\mathbb {Q}$ forces an elementary embedding $j : H_\theta ^V \to N$ with critical point $\kappa _1^+$ , where $N \in V^{\mathbb {Q}}$ is a transitive set.

Claim 4. $\kappa _1^{<\kappa _0} = \kappa _1$ .

Proof Let $G \subseteq \mathbb {Q}$ be generic over V, and let $j : H_\theta ^V \to N$ be an elementary embedding with critical point $\kappa _1^+$ , where $N \in V[G]$ is a transitive set. By ${<}\kappa _0$ -distributivity, $\mathcal {P}_{\kappa _0}(\kappa _1)^{N} \subseteq \mathcal {P}_{\kappa _0}(\kappa _1)^{V}$ , so the cardinality of $\mathcal {P}_{\kappa _0}(\kappa _1)^V$ must be below the critical point of j.

Claim 5. $\lambda _1^{<\lambda _0} = \lambda _1$ .

Proof Let $G \subseteq \mathbb {P}$ be generic over V, and let $j : V \to M$ be as hypothesized in (2). By the closure of M, $\mathcal {P}_{\lambda _0}(\lambda _1)^M = \mathcal {P}_{\lambda _0}(\lambda _1)^{V[G]}$ . By elementarity and Claim 4, $M \models \lambda _1^{<\lambda _0} = \lambda _1$ . Thus M has a surjection $f : \lambda _1 \to \mathcal {P}_{\lambda _0}(\lambda _1)^{V[G]} \supseteq \mathcal {P}_{\lambda _0}(\lambda _1)^V$ . If $\lambda _1^{<\lambda _0}> \lambda _1$ in V, then f would witnesses a collapse of $\lambda _1^+$ , contrary to the $\lambda _0$ -c.c.

Now let $\mathcal {F} = \mathcal {P}_{\lambda _0}(\lambda _1)^V$ . Let $j : V \to M \subseteq V[G]$ be as in hypothesis (2). Claim 5 implies that $\mathcal {F}$ is coded by a single subset of $\lambda _1$ in V, so $\mathcal {F} \in M$ . In M, let $\mathcal {A}$ be the collection of subsets of $\lambda _1$ that are approximated by $\mathcal {F}$ . Since $\mathcal {P}(\lambda _1)^V \subseteq M$ , it is clear that $\mathcal {P}(\lambda _1)^V \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ .

For each $\alpha <\lambda _1^+$ , there exists an $X \in \mathcal {A} \cap V$ that codes a surjection from $\lambda _1$ to $\alpha $ in some canonical way. Working in M, choose for each $\alpha <\lambda _1^+$ an $X_\alpha \in \mathcal {A}$ that codes a surjection from $\lambda _1$ to $\alpha $ .

By elementarity, $\lambda _1^+$ is $j(\mathbb {Q})$ -generically measurable in M, witnessed by generic embeddings with domain $H^M_{j(\theta )}$ . By the closure of M, $j(\mathbb {Q})$ is $\lambda _0$ -closed in $V[G]$ . Let $H \subseteq j(\mathbb {Q})$ be generic over $V[G]$ . Let $i : H^M_{j(\theta )} \to N \in M[H]\subseteq V[G][H]$ be given by the $j(\mathbb {Q})$ -generic measurability of $\lambda _1^+$ in M, with $\operatorname {\mathrm {crit}}(i) = \delta = \lambda _1^+$ .

Let $\langle X^{\prime }_\alpha : \alpha < i(\delta ) \rangle = i(\langle X_\alpha : \alpha < \delta \rangle )$ . By elementarity, $X^{\prime }_\delta $ is approximated by $i(\mathcal {F}) = \mathcal {F}$ . Since $\mathbb {P} * j(\dot {\mathbb {Q}})$ is a nontrivial strongly $\lambda _0$ -c.c. forcing followed by a $\lambda _0$ -closed forcing, it has the $\lambda _0$ -approximation property by Usuba’s theorem. Therefore, $X^{\prime }_\delta \in V$ . But this is a contradiction, since $X^{\prime }_\delta $ codes a surjection from $\lambda _1$ to $(\lambda _1^+)^V$ .

Let us now complete the proof of Theorem 1. Suppose $n\geq 1$ , $\kappa <\lambda $ , $\mathbb {P}$ is strongly $\lambda $ -c.c., and $\mathbb {P}$ forces an embedding $j : V \to M \subseteq V[G]$ such that $j(\kappa ) = \lambda $ and M is closed under $j^n(\kappa )$ -sequences from $V[G]$ . By the $\lambda $ -c.c. of $\mathbb {P}$ and the $\lambda $ -closure of M, $(\lambda ^+)^M = (\lambda ^+)^V$ . Suppose inductively that $i<n$ and $(\lambda ^{+i})^M = (\lambda ^{+i})^V \leq j^{i+1}(\kappa )$ . Again, by the chain condition and the $j^{i+1}(\kappa )$ -closure of M, $(\lambda ^{+i+1})^M = (\lambda ^{+i+1})^V$ . Since $\kappa ^{+i}<\lambda ^{+i} = j(\kappa ^{+i})$ , $j(\lambda ^{+i})$ must be an M-cardinal greater than $\lambda ^{+i}$ , so $\lambda ^{+i+1} \leq j(\lambda ^{+i})$ . By elementarity applied to the induction hypothesis, $j(\lambda ^{+i}) \leq j^{i+2}(\kappa )$ . Thus the induction hypothesis carries through up to n. Now suppose $0<m\leq n$ and set $\kappa _0=\kappa $ , $\lambda _0 = \lambda $ , $\kappa _1 = \kappa ^{+m-1}$ , and $\lambda _1 = \lambda _0^{+m-1}$ . Then we have $j(\kappa _0)=\lambda _0$ and $j(\kappa _1) = \lambda _1 \leq j^n(\kappa )$ . If $\kappa ^{+m}$ is also generically measurable by a $\kappa $ -closed forcing, then this assignment of variables satisfies the hypotheses of the lemma, which we have shown to be inconsistent.

Remark 6. Suppose $\omega _1$ is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically almost-huge and $\omega _2$ is $\mathbb {Q}$ -generically measurable, where $\mathbb {P}$ is strongly $\omega _2$ -c.c. and $\mathbb {Q}$ is countably closed. This holds, for example, in Foreman’s model [Reference Foreman4]. Let $j : V \to M$ be an embedding witnessing the $\mathbb {P}$ -generic almost-hugeness of $\omega _1$ . Put $\kappa _0=\kappa _1=\omega _1$ and $\lambda _0=\lambda _1=\omega _2$ . The only hypothesis of Lemma 3 that fails is $\mathcal {P}(\omega _2)^V \subseteq M$ .

3 On the consistency of generic hugeness

It is not known whether any successor cardinal can be minimally generically huge. Moreover, it is not known whether $\omega _1$ can be $\mathbb {P}$ -generically huge with target $\omega _2$ for an $\omega _2$ -c.c. forcing $\mathbb {P}$ . But we do not think that Theorem 1 is evidence that this hypothesis by itself is inconsistent, since there are other versions of generic hugeness for $\omega _1$ that satisfy the hypothesis of Theorem 1 and are known to be consistent relative to huge cardinals. Magidor [Reference Magidor10] showed that if there is a huge cardinal, then in a generic extension, $\omega _1$ is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically huge with target $\omega _3$ , where $\mathbb {P}$ is strongly $\omega _3$ -c.c. Shioya [Reference Shioya11] observed that if $\kappa $ is huge with target $\lambda $ , then Magidor’s result can be obtained from a two-step iteration of Easton collapses, $\mathbb {E}(\omega ,\kappa ) * \dot {\mathbb {E}}(\kappa ^+,\lambda )$ . An easier argument shows that after the first step of the iteration, or even in the extension by the Levy collapse $\operatorname {\mathrm {Col}}(\omega ,{<}\kappa )$ , $\omega _1$ is $\mathbb {P}$ -generically huge with target $\lambda $ by a strongly $\lambda $ -c.c. forcing $\mathbb {P}$ .

Theorem 1 shows that in these models, $\omega _2$ is not $\mathbb {Q}$ -generically measurable for a countably closed $\mathbb {Q}$ . It also shows that if it is consistent for $\omega _1$ to be generically huge with target $\omega _2$ by a strongly $\omega _2$ -c.c. forcing, then this cannot be demonstrated by a standard method resembling Magidor’s:

Corollary 7. Suppose $\kappa $ is a huge cardinal with target $\lambda $ . Suppose $\mathbb {P}$ is such that $:$

  1. (1) $\mathbb {P}$ is $\lambda $ -c.c. and contained in $V_\lambda $ .

  2. (2) $\mathbb {P}$ preserves $\kappa $ and collapses $\lambda $ to become $\kappa ^+$ .

  3. (3) For all sufficiently large $\alpha <\lambda $ (for example, all Mahlo $\alpha $ beyond a certain point), $\mathbb {P} \cong (\mathbb {P} \cap V_\alpha ) * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha $ , where $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha $ is forced to be $\kappa $ -closed.

Then in any generic extension by $\mathbb {P}$ , $\kappa $ is not generically huge with target $\lambda $ by a strongly $\lambda $ -c.c. forcing.

Furthermore, suppose $\lambda $ is supercompact in V, and (3) is strengthened to:

  1. (4) For all sufficiently large $\alpha <\beta <\lambda $ , $\mathbb {P} \cong (\mathbb {P} \cap V_\alpha ) * \dot {\mathrm {Col}}(\kappa ,\beta )* \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\alpha ,\beta }$ , where $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_ {\alpha ,\beta }$ is forced to be $\kappa $ -closed.

Then $\kappa $ is not generically huge with target $\lambda $ by a strongly $\lambda $ -c.c. forcing in any $\lambda $ -directed-closed forcing extension of $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ .

Proof Let $j : V \to M$ witness that $\kappa $ is huge with target $\lambda $ . By elementarity and the fact that $\mathcal {P}(\lambda ) \subseteq M$ , $\lambda $ is measurable in V. Let $\mathcal {U}$ be a normal ultrafilter on $\lambda $ , and let $i : V \to N$ be the ultrapower embedding.

Since the decomposition of (3) holds for all “sufficiently large” $\alpha $ , $N \models i(\mathbb {P}) \cong \mathbb {P} * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ , where $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ is forced to be $\kappa $ -closed. By the closure of N, V also believes that $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ is forced by $\mathbb {P}$ to be $\kappa $ -closed. Thus if we take $G \subseteq \mathbb {P}$ generic over V, then the embedding i can be lifted by forcing with $\mathbb {Q}$ . This means that in $V[G]$ , $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {Q}$ -generically measurable, $\mathbb {Q}$ is $\kappa $ -closed, and $\lambda = \kappa ^+$ . Theorem 1 implies that in $V[G]$ , $\kappa $ cannot be generically huge with target $\lambda $ by a strongly $\lambda $ -c.c. forcing.

For the final claim, suppose $\lambda $ is supercompact in V, and let $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a $\lambda $ -directed-closed forcing. Let $\gamma $ be such that $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} |\dot {\mathbb {R}}| \leq \gamma $ . By [Reference Cummings2, Theorem 14.1], $\operatorname {\mathrm {Col}}(\kappa ,\gamma ) \cong \operatorname {\mathrm {Col}}(\kappa ,\gamma ) \times \mathbb {R}$ in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ . Let $i : V \to N$ be an elementary embedding such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {crit}}(i) = \lambda $ , $i(\lambda )> \gamma $ , and $N^\gamma \subseteq N$ . By applying (4) in N, there is in N a complete embedding of $\mathbb {P} * \dot {\mathbb {R}}$ into $i(\mathbb {P})$ , such that the quotient forcing is equivalent to something of the form $\operatorname {\mathrm {Col}}(\kappa ,\gamma )*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\lambda ,\gamma }$ , where $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\lambda ,\gamma }$ is forced to be $\kappa $ -closed in $N^{\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {R}} * \dot {\mathrm {Col}}(\kappa ,\gamma )}$ . By the closure of N, the quotient is forced to be $\kappa $ -closed in $V^{\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}}$ .

Let $G * H \subseteq \mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be generic. Further $\kappa $ -closed forcing yields a generic $G' \subseteq i(\mathbb {P})$ that projects to $G*H$ . We can lift the embedding to $i : V[G] \to N[G']$ . By elementarity, $i(\mathbb {R})$ is $i(\lambda )$ -directed-closed in $N[G']$ . Thus $i[H]$ has a lower bound $r \in i(\mathbb {R})$ . By the closure of N, $i(\mathbb {R})$ is at least $\kappa $ -closed in $V[G']$ . Forcing below r yields a generic $H' \subseteq i(\mathbb {R})$ and a lifted embedding $i : V[G*H] \to N[G'*H']$ . Hence in $V[G*H]$ , $\lambda $ is generically measurable via a $\kappa $ -closed forcing. Theorem 1 implies that $\kappa $ cannot be generically huge with target $\lambda $ by a strongly $\lambda $ -c.c. forcing.

Funding

The author wishes to thank the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) for the generous support through grants P34603 and START Y1012-N35 (PI: Vera Fischer).

References

Cox, S. and Eskew, M., Compactness versus hugeness at successor cardinals. Journal of Mathematical Logic. vol. 23 (2023), no. 1, 2250016.Google Scholar
Cummings, J., Iterated forcing and elementary embeddings , Handbook of Set Theory (M. Foreman and A. Kanamori, editors), Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 775883.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eskew, M., Generic large cardinals as axioms . Review of Symbolic Logic , vol. 13 (2020), no. 2, pp. 375387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M., More saturated ideals, Cabal Seminar 79–81 (A. S. Kechris, D. A. Martin, and Y. N. Maschovakis, editors), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1019, Springer, Dordrecht, 1983, pp. 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M., Potent axioms . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 294 (1986), no. 1, pp. 128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M., Generic large cardinals: New axioms for mathematics? Documenta Mathematica , vol. II (1998), pp. 1121.Google Scholar
Foreman, M., Has the continuum hypothesis been settled? Lecture Notes in Logic , vol. 24 (2006), pp. 5675.Google Scholar
Foreman, M., Ideals and generic elementary embeddings, Handbook of Set Theory (M. Foreman and A. Kanamori, editors), Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 8851147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamkins, J. D., Extensions with the approximation and cover properties have no new large cardinals . Fundamenta Mathematicae , vol. 180 (2003), no. 3, pp. 257277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magidor, M., On the existence of nonregular ultrafilters and the cardinality of ultrapowers . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 249 (1979), no. 1, pp. 97111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shioya, M., Easton collapses and a strongly saturated filter . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 59 (2020), nos. 7–8, pp. 10271036.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Usuba, T., The approximation property and the chain condition . Research Institute for Mathematical Sciences Kokyuroku , vol. 1895 (2014), pp. 103107.Google Scholar