Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T03:35:28.835Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Tacit Bargaining and Arms Control

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 June 2011

Get access

Extract

Astate bargains tacitly with another state when it attempts to manipulate the latter's policy choices through its behavior rather than by relying on formal or informal diplomatic exchanges. The process is tacit because actions rather than rhetoric constitute the critical medium of communication; it is bargaining and not coercion because the actions are aimed at influencing an outcome that can only be achieved through some measure of joint, voluntary behavior. Obviously, states rarely rely on either purely tacit or purely formal negotiation. However, the theory of tacit bargaining does not become totally inapplicable when there is verbal or written communication between the principals. It simply becomes increasingly relevant as states rely more on actions than on conventional negotiation. Examples of tacit bargaining are plentiful in international relations: a retaliatory tariff is announced in response to trade barriers; a state at war refrains from using chemical weapons or from bombing nonmilitary targets in the hope that its opponent will behave similarly; an austerity program is implemented by a financially troubled government in order to convince foreign banks that they should continue to extend credit.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Trustees of Princeton University 1977

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Adelman, , “Arms Control with and without Agreements,” Foreign Affairs 63 (Winter 1984/85), 240–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Garwin, , “Is There a Way Out?” (symposium), Harpers (June 1985), 35–47Google Scholar. Specifically, Garwin suggested the following:

The United States ought to build 400 Midgetmen, the small, not very accurate, singlewarhead missile proposed by the Scowcroft Commission, and put them in Minuteman II silos. Meanwhile, we should reduce our forces temporarily by 50 percent—send half our submarines to cruise in the Antarctic, pile 20 meters of earth over half our minuteman silos, and put half our strategic bombers in mothballs. Then we should invite the Soviet Union to follow suit within six weeks, and if it does, we should make the arrangement permanent (p. 44).

3 Schelling, , The Strategy of Conflict (New York: Oxford University Press, 1963)Google Scholar. See also Schelling, Thomas and Halperin, Morton, Strategy and Arms Control (New York: Twentieth Century Fund, 1961)Google Scholar.

4 Osgood, , An Alternative to War or Surrender (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1962)Google Scholar.

5 Axelrod, , The Evolution of Cooperation (New York: Basic Books, 1984)Google Scholar; Axelrod, Robert, “The Emergence of Cooperation Among Egoists,” American Political Science Review 75 (June 1981), 306–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Axelrod, Robert and Hamilton, William D., “The Evolution of Cooperation,” Science, No. 211 (March 1981), 1390–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Axelrod (fn. 5), 181.

7 Downs, George W. et al., “Arms Races and Cooperation,” World Politics 38 (October 1985), 118–46, at 139–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar, reprinted in Oye, Kenneth A., ed., Cooperation under Anarchy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986)Google Scholar.

8 Formally, the only requirement for an arms race is that each side prefer mutual escalation to unilateral reduction. This leaves open the possibility that a given arms race could be motivated by a wide variety of games. Of course, each participant in an arms race may have a different set of preferences and may thus be playing a different game.

9 Cobden, Richard, The Political Writings of Richard Cobden (London: William Ridgway, 1868)Google Scholar; Hirst, F. W., The Six Panics (London: Methuen, 1913)Google Scholar; Gooch, G. P., Franco-German Relations, 1817–1914 (London: Longmans, 1923)Google Scholar.

10 Lee, William T., Understanding the Soviet Military Threat (New York: National Strategy Information Center, 1977)Google Scholar.

11 Ross, Michael and Sicoly, Fiore, “Egocentric Biases in Availability and Attribution,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37 (March 1979), 322–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Finlay, David Holsti, Ole, and Fagan, Richard, Enemies in Politics (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1967), 60Google Scholar.

13 Ross, Lee and Anderson, Craig, “Shortcomings in the Attribution Process: On the Origins and Maintenance of Erroneous Social Assessments,” in Kahneman, Daniel et al., eds., Judgment Under Uncertainty (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 129–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Jervis, Robert, “Cooperation under the Security Dilemma,” World Politics 30 (January 1978), 167214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15 Nisbett, Richard E. and Ross, Lee, Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1980), 170Google Scholar.

16 For simplicity, in the simulation the rival states were assumed already to be proceeding at their individually optimal rate. This means that substantial deterioration could not occur. Had we started the simulation at a lower rate, it would clearly have reinforced our conclusions at the cost of some additional complexity of presentation.

17 Box, George E. P., Hunter, William G., and Hunter, J. Stuart, Statistics for Experimenters (New York: John Wiley, 1975)Google Scholar. In the simulation, we examine the effects of three parameters. In order to simplify the presentation, we use a base case and three sensitivity analysis cases that vary one parameter at a time. A full factorial design was not used because of the difficulty of grasping eight charts simultaneously.

18 Formally, we suppose that a state achieves a net benefit of

when arms are increased, and

when arms are decreased, where TA and TB are the new levels of arms for the two sides, and A is the last turn's arms level for side A. The cost function is quadratic for arms increases, to represent the difficulties that the industrial infrastructure and the political system have with arbitrarily large increases. Values used in the simulation are b = 1.0, c = 1.0, and d = 0.5 in all cases, with a = 6 in the Base Case and a = 3 in the Low-Benefit Case. It is easily seen that the “optimal” increase of arms for side A is given by

regardless of the level chosen by side B. Thus, the simulation is begun by assuming that the arms race has been proceeding at this “optimal” level for some time. Note that it is possible for A to choose an arms increase greater that Although it might seem irrational, some punishment-based strategies could have this result.

19 Downs et al. (fn. 7), 123.

20 In the first case, when B employs a reciprocal strategy, the increase will be

A — T*A

matching A's increase (or decrease) from last time, where the o and * superscripts refer to the last move and the one before that. In the second case, B will continue its past build-up no matter what, so the increase will be

A — T*B

Thus, the current increase is exactly the same as the last turn's increase. In modeling cautious reciprocity, we imagine that B examines A's change last time compared to B's own change two turns ago. If A were playing a reciprocal strategy, these two quantities would be identical. If they are, or if A's move is larger, then B plays reciprocally, subject to staying below the optimal increase; otherwise, B makes an increase midway between A's last move and B's own last move. Although this strategy seems complex, it only amounts to following up a cooperative gesture with a smaller cooperative gesture.

21 A larger bias makes tacit bargaining almost impossible; anything less would be historically naive.

22 The numbers were calculated from simulations run separately for the case in which the opponent is playing Deadlock and the case in which the opponent is employing the reciprocal strategy.

23 If the payoff for making no cooperative gesture is Po and the payoff for making a cooperative gesture of size G is PG, then the quantity graphed against G is (PG — Po)/Po. The required numbers were estimated by simulation.

24 Payoffs were calculated by simulation for each of the seven strategies against each of the opponent's strategies for each environment. A typical point (p1, p2, p3) in the triangle represents an estimated probability of p, that State B is playing its first strategy, etc. The expected payoff to a given strategy is a weighted average, by p1, p2, and p3, of the outcomes against the three possible strategies of State B. From the payoff formula for each strategy at each point, the areas of optimality for each strategy within the triangle were easily computed.

25 For a list and discussion of these arms races, see Huntington, Samuel, “Arms Races: Prerequisites and Results,” Public Policy 8 (1958), 4186Google Scholar; Kennedy, Paul, Strategy and Diplomacy (Aylesbury, England: Fontana, 1984), 163–78Google Scholar; Downs et al. (fn. 7), 119–21. For one viewpoint on the role of cooperation-based tacit bargaining in the U.S.-Soviet arms race, see Adelman (fn. 1).