Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T20:21:57.209Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Science and Sovietology: Bridging the Methods Gap in Soviet Foreign Policy Studies

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 June 2011

Jack Snyder
Affiliation:
Columbia University
Get access

Abstract

Specialists in the study of Soviet foreign policy increasingly feel torn between the positivist culture of political science departments and the holistic traditions of the Soviet area-studies programs. In fact, these approaches are largely complementary. Examples taken from literature on Soviet security policy and on the domestic sources of Soviet expansionism show how positivist theories and methods can be used to clarify holist (or traditionalist) arguments, to sharpen debates, to suggest more telling tests, and to invigorate the field's research agenda.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Trustees of Princeton University 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 These are ideal types. Real scholars often use both approaches in varying combinations or proportions. For example, some positivist scholars, like Kenneth Waltz, look at whole systems or, like Robert Jervis, try to explain the subjective understandings of actors. Despite these qualifications, I would contend that the above distinctions capture the most important lines of epistemological cleavage. The term “holism” is unsatisfactory, but alternatives like “traditionalism” or “non-positivism” are even more problematic. For further discussion, see Diesing, Paul, Patterns of Discovery in the Social Sciences (New York: Aldine, 1971)Google Scholar, and Polkinghorne, Donald, Methodology for the Human Sciences (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1983)Google Scholar.

2 Snyder, Jack, “Richness, Rigor, and Relevance in the Study of Soviet Foreign Policy,” International Security 9 (Winter 19841985), 89108CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 For elaboration and qualifications, see Snyder (fn. 2) and Diesing (fn. 1).

4 Jervis, Robert, “Cooperation under the Security Dilemma,” World Politics 30 (January 1978), 167214CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Levy, Jack S., “The Offensive/Defensive Balance of Military Technology: A Theoretical and Historical Analysis,” International Studies Quarterly 28 (Summer 1984), 219–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Jervis, Robert, Perception and Misperception in International Politics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1976)Google Scholar, chap. 6, illustrates how to detect spurious causal inferences.

7 Jervis (fn. 4).

8 Legvold, Robert, “Military Power in International Politics: Soviet Doctrine on Its Centrality and Instrumentality,” in Nerlich, Uwe, ed., Soviet Power and Western Negotiating Strategies (Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1983), 124Google Scholar, quoting Hoffmann, Stanley, “Perception, Reality, and the Franco-American Conflict,” Journal of International Affairs 21 (No. 1, 1967), 57Google Scholar.

9 Legvold (fn. 8), 125, 123, and passim. I will return to Legvold's study in order to suggest how it might be recast in positivist terms.

10 Diesing (fn. 1.)

11 Shulman, Marshall, Stalin's Foreign Policy Reappraised (New York: Atheneum, 1969)Google Scholar; Talbott, Strobe, Endgame (New York: Harper Colophon, 1980), 80Google Scholar.

12 Shulman (fn. 11), 3, 50, 259, and passim.

13 Ibid., 8, 14, 123, and passim.

14 Ibid., 8, comes close to doing this, citing a few instances of Soviet attempts to buy time during periods of weakness.

15 On Zhdanov and Molotov, see Ibid., 14–15, 117–18. Suslov's militancy, however, is linked to the argument that the correlation of forces was turning in favor of socialism; see Ibid., 119.

16 See especially the discussion of Malenkov, Ibid., 111–17.

17 On cybernetic decision making and how it differs from analytic rationality, see Steinbruner, John, The Cybernetic Theory of Decision (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974)Google Scholar.

18 Shulman (fn. 11), 3–9, 263–71.

19 , Gelman, The Brezhnev Politburo and the Decline ofDetente (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1984)Google Scholar. On the problem of a priori underdetermination and a posteriori overdeter-mination, see Kurth, James, “United States Foreign Policy and Latin American Military Rule,” in Schmitter, Phillippe, ed., Military Rule in Latin America (Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 1973). 244322Google Scholar.

20 lbld., 83.

21 Ibid., 46, 52–58.

22 Breslauer, George, Khrushchev and Brezhnev as Leaders (London: Allen & Unwin, 1982)Google Scholar, conclusion, esp. 280, 284–90.

23 Riker, William H. and Brams, Steven J., “The Paradox of Vote Trading,” American Political Science Review 67 (December 1973), 1235–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Gelman (fn. 19), 73; also 79, 90, 114.

25 Waltz, Kenneth, Theory of International Politics (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1979), 50Google Scholar, used this phrase to characterize earlier systems theories.

26 Jervis (fn. 6), 128–42.

27 The last hypothesis, omitted in most accounts of the links between totalitarianism and foreign policy, is based on Gerschenkron, Alexander, Economic Backwardness in Historical Perspective (Cambridge, MA: Belknap, 1962)Google Scholar. For other arguments, see Friedrich, Carl and Brzezinski, Zbigniew, Totalitarian Dictatorship and Autocracy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1956)Google Scholar, and Brzezinski, Zbigniew, Ideology and Power in Soviet Politics (New York: Praeger, 1962)Google Scholar.

28 See Toulmin, Stephen, Human Understanding (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1972)Google Scholar.

29 A recent example of work done in this tradition is the special issue of World Politics 38 (October 1985), also published as Cooperation under Anarchy, Oye, Kenneth A., ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985)Google Scholar.

30 See, for example, Kratochwil, Friedrich and Ruggiel, John“International Organization: A State of the Art on an Art of the State,” International Organization 40 (Fall, 1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31 “A Garthoff-Pipes Debate on Soviet Strategic Doctrine,” Strategic Review 10 (Fall 1982), 3663Google Scholar.

32 Schelling, Thomas C., Arms and Influence (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966)Google Scholar, chaps. 2 and 3; , Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (London: Oxford University Press, 1960)Google Scholar, chap. 2.

33 , Jervis, “Why Nuclear Superiority Doesn't Matter,” Political Science Quarterly 94 (Winter 19791980), 617–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

34 Schelling (fn. 32, 1966), 106.

35 Strategic Review (fn. 31), 57.

36 McConnell, James M., “The ‘Rules of the Game’: A Theory on the Practice of Superpower Naval Diplomacy,” in Dismukes, Bradford and McConnell, James, eds., Soviet Naval Diplomacy (New York: Pergamon, 1979)Google Scholar.

37 For example, the argument (Ibid., 265–66) that the United States was the defender in the mining of Haiphong Harbor, though not unreasonable, makes use of ad hoc criteria that place more weight on American statements linking the action to the defense of South Vietnam than on the pritnafacie offensive character of U.S. behavior.

38 See also Blechman, Barry and Kaplan, Stephen, Force without War (Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution, 1978), 127–29Google Scholar.

39 For this point, and qualifications to it, see McConnell (fn. 36), 244.

40 Ibid., 247–48.

41 Ibid., 265.

42 McConnell's own conclusions from these cases are somewhat more complex. See ibid., 246, 267–76.

43 Betts, Richard K., “Elusive Equivalence: The Political and Military Meaning of the Nuclear Balance,” in Huntington, Samuel P., The Strategic Imperative (Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1982), 108Google Scholar, draws attention to this question. See also Betts, Richard, Nuclear Blackmail and Nuclear Balance (Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution, 1987)Google Scholar, which carries out detailed, sophisticated tests similar to those described above.

44 Schelling (fn. 32, 1966), 46–47. This vignette seems to be a conflation of several Khrushchev remarks. For an example of the invocation of uncontrollable risk, see Slusser, Robert, The Berlin Crisis of 1961 (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973), 9899Google Scholar; for asymmetry in motivation, Adomeit, Hannes, Soviet Risk-Taking and Crisis Behavior (London: Allen & Unwin, 1982), 207Google Scholar, and Schick, Jack, The Berlin Crisis, 1958–1962 (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971), 178CrossRefGoogle Scholar; for the onus of the last clear chance, Talbott, Strobe, ed., Khrushchev Remembers: The Last Testament (New York: Bantam, 1974), 575Google Scholar. For more examples and for some qualifications to this view, see Hope Harrison, “Was Khrushchev a Student of Thomas Schelling?: Khrushchev's Coercive Diplomacy in the 1958–1961 Berlin Crisis,” unpub. (Harriman Institute, Columbia University, 1987).

45 Leites, Nathan, A Study of Bolshevism (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1953)Google Scholar; George, Alexander, “The ‘Operational Code’: A Neglected Approach to the Study of Political Leaders and Decision-Making,” in Hoffmann, Erik and Fleron, Frederic, eds., The Conduct of Soviet Foreign Policy, 2d ed. (New York: Aldine, 1980), 191212Google Scholar.

46 Polkinghorne (fn. 1), 107 and passim.

47 Zimmerman, William and Axelrod, Robert, “The ‘Lessons’ of Vietnam and Soviet Foreign Policy,” World Politics 34 (October 1981), 124CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

48 Ibid., 10–11.

49 Ibid., 8.

50 Polkinghorne (fn. 1), 117–18; Lakatos, Imre, “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes,” in Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge: Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, London, 1965, Vol. IV (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51 Legvold (fn. 8), 131.

52 MccGwire, Michael, Military Objectives in Soviet Foreign Policy (Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution, 1987)Google Scholar.