Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T04:39:02.130Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Welfarism and Utilitarianism: A Rehabilitation*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 January 2009

Extract

Utilitarianism seems to be going out of fashion, amidst increasing concerns for issues of freedom, equality, and justice. At least, anti-utilitarian and non-utilitarian moral philosophers have been very active. This paper is a very modest attempt to defend utilitarianism in particular and welfarism (i.e., general utilitarianism or utilitarianism without the sum-ranking aspect) in general. Section I provides an axiomatic defence of welfarism and utilitarianism. Section II discusses the divergences between individual preferences and individual welfares and argues in favour of welfare utilitarianism. Section III criticizes some non-utilitarian principles, including knowledge as intrinsically good, rights-based ethics, and Rawls's second principle. Section IV argues that most objections to welfarism are probably based on the confusion of non-ultimate considerations with basic values. This is discussed with reference to some recent philosophical writings which abound with such confusion. Section V argues that the acceptance of utilitarianism may be facilitated by the distinction between ideal morality and self-interest which also resolves the dilemma of average versus total utility maximization in optimal population theory.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

I am grateful to Peter Singer for commenting on the first draft.

References

1 In this section, we ignore the question what individual utilities stand for. In particular, whether they refer to individual preferences or individual happiness (discussed in section II); whether non-human sentients like animals are included in the relevant set of individuals. See Ng, Y. K., ‘Some Broader Issues in Social Welfare’, in Pattanaik, P. K. and Salles, M. eds., Social Choice and Welfare, Amsterdam, 1983.Google Scholar

2 I use ‘welfarism’ as a synonym for ‘general utilitarianism’, see Sen, A. K., ‘Personal Utilities and Public Judgements’, Economic Journal, lxxxix (1979), 537–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar. However, some readers may prefer to use welfarism as w = w(w1, w2, …, w2) where w1 = welfare or happiness of individual 1. To be precise, w = w(u1, u2, …, un) is preference welfarism, w = w(w1, w2, …, wn) is welfare welfarism.

3 Radford, C., ‘Utilitarianism and the Noble Art’, Philosophy, lxiii (1988), 6381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 However, perception and affective feelings evolved simultaneously. As I hope to argue elsewhere, perception without affective feelings also serves no evolutionary purposes. Here, perception is defined as involving subjective consciousness, not just in the wider sense ‘reception and interpretation of signals from the environment’, regarded as evidenced in the bacterium E. coli, see Delbruik, M., Mind from Matter? An Essay on Evolutionary Epistemology, Oxford, 1986.Google Scholar

5 Harsanyi, J. C., ‘Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparison of Utility’, Journal of Political Economy, lxviii (1955), 309–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Ng, Y. K., ‘Bentham or Bergson? Finite Sensibility, Utility Functions, and Social Welfare Functions’, Review of Economic Studies, xlii (1975), 545–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 d'Aspremont, C. and Gevers, L., ‘Equity and the Informational Basis of Collective Choice’, Review of Economic Studies, xliv (1977), 199209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 Fleming's result is also positive but he established only separability, i.e., w = f2 (u2) + …, +fn (un), but using very reasonable axioms. Fleming, M., ‘A Cardinal Concept of Welfare’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, lxvi (1952), 366–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 See Lyons, D., ‘Human Rights and the General Welfare’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, vi (1976), 113–29Google Scholar; Hardin, R., ‘The Utilitarian Logic of Liberalism’, Ethics, xcvii (1986), 4774CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Kuflik, A., ‘The Utilitarian Logic of Inalienable Rights’, Ethics, xcvii (1986), 7587CrossRefGoogle Scholar on the consistency of utilitarianism with certain inalienable rights. However, the preference for certain counter-efficiency rights may be based on the ignorance of economics; see Ng, Y. K., ‘Economic Efficiency versus Egalitarian Rights’, Kyklos, xli (1988), 215–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 For some more realistic circumstances where the exercise of rights leads to disastrous outcomes, see Sen, A. K., ‘The Moral Standing of the Market’, in Paul, E. F. et al. eds., Ethics and Economics, Oxford, 1985, p. 6.Google Scholar

11 Gibbard, A., ‘Inchoately Utilitarian Common Sense’, in Miller, H. B. and Williams, W. H. eds., The Limits of Utilitarianism, Minnesota, 1982, p. 83.Google Scholar

12 Ng, Y. K., ‘Individual Irrationality and Social Welfare’, Social Choice and Welfare, vi (1989), 87102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 Rawls, J., A Theory of Justice, Oxford, 1972, pp. 150–61.Google Scholar

14 It is true that Rawls would argue that freedom to rape is not a basic liberty while the right to non-violation of the body is. However, how do we determine what are basic liberties? Either it is based on the utilitarian principle or it is open to the objection of the last subsection on the unacceptability of rights-based ethics.

15 Temkin, L. S., ‘Inequality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, xv (1986), p. 109.Google Scholar

16 Allais, M. and Hagen, O., The Expected Utility Hypothesis and the Allais Paradox, Dordrecht, 1979CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Harsanyi, J., Essays on Ethics, Social Behaviour and Scientific Explanation, Dordrecht, 1976CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Ng, Y. K., ‘Expected Subjective Utility: Is the Neumann-Morganstern Utility Index the same as the Neoclassical's?’, Social Choice and Welfare, i (1984), 177–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 For example, Locke's asymetric utilitarian solution to Parfit's population problem is open to the same objection; see Locke, D., ‘The Parfit Population Problem’, Philosophy, lxii (1987), 131–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 Temkin, L. S., ‘Intransitivity and the Mere Addition Paradox’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, xi (1987), 172.Google Scholar

19 Ibid., 172–3.

20 Ibid., 155.

22 The preference for equality in Welfare as such may well be due to ‘utility illusion’, the double discounting of the incomes of the well-off; see Ng, Y. K., ‘Bentham or Bergson?’, pp. 545–70.Google Scholar

23 Dworkin, R., ‘What is Equality?’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, x (1981), 201–4.Google Scholar

24 Alexander, L. and Schwartzchild, M., ‘Liberalism, Neutrality, and Equality of Welfare vs. Equality of Resources’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, xvi (1987), 90.Google Scholar

25 Some people may take the (I think naive) position that a right or principle is either fully observed or not at all. In that case, the degree of observance assumes a value of either one or zero.

26 For simplicity, the possible dependence 0t Ot on variables at times other than t is ignored.

27 If the individual concerned does not like this sum-ranking method, we may just define vi = vi (w1, w2, …, wi–1, wi+1 …, wn) which is whatever function he uses for the welfares of other individuals.

28 Narveson, J., ‘Moral Problems of Population’, The Monist, lvii (1973), 80.Google Scholar

29 Parfit, D., Reasons and Persons, Oxford, 1984.Google Scholar

30 Narveson, , p. 80.Google Scholar

31 For the argument that, in this perspective, the Repugnant Conclusion is not repugnant at all and that Parfit's ideal theory X either does not exist or violates the compelling Non-Antiegalitarianism, see Ng, Y. K., ‘What Should we do About Future Generations?’, Economics and Philosophy, v (1989), 235–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

32 Ng, , ‘What Should we do About Future Generations?’Google Scholar

33 See Harsanyi, J. C., ‘Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparison of Utility’, Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, B., Utilitarianism: For and Against, Cambridge, 1973Google Scholar; Hare, R. M., ‘Ethical Theory and Utilitarianism’, in H. D. Lewis, Contemporary British Philosophy, London 1976Google Scholar; and Riley, J., Liberal Utilitarianism: Social Choice Theory and J. S. Mill's Philosophy, Cambridge, 1988.Google Scholar