Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T03:39:17.687Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Superiority Discounting Implies the Preposterous Conclusion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 August 2022

Mitchell Barrington*
Affiliation:
University of Southern California, Los Angeles, USA Dianoia Institute of Philosophy, Australian Catholic University, Melbourne, Australia

Abstract

Many population axiologies avoid the Repugnant Conclusion (RC) by endorsing Superiority: some number of great lives is better than any number of mediocre lives. But as Nebel shows, RC follows (given plausible auxiliary assumptions) from the Intrapersonal Repugnant Conclusion (IRC): a guaranteed mediocre life is better than a sufficiently small probability of a great life. This result is concerning because IRC is plausible. Recently, Kosonen has argued that IRC can be true while RC is false if small probabilities are discounted to zero. This article details the unique problems created by combining Superiority with discounting. The resultant view, Superiority Discounting, avoids the Repugnant Conclusion only at the cost of the Preposterous Conclusion: near-certain hell for arbitrarily many people is better than near-certain heaven for arbitrarily many people.

Type
Replies
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aboodi, Ron, Borer, Adi, and Enoch, David. 2008. Deontology, Individualism, and Uncertainty: A Reply to Jackson and Smith. The Journal of Philosophy, 105: 259–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arrhenius, Gustaf, and Rabinowicz, Wlodek. 2015. Value Superiority. In Hirose, Iwao and Olson, Jonas (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory (Oxford University Press), pp. 225–48.Google Scholar
Bernoulli, Daniel. 1738. Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk. Econometrica, 22: 2336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bjorndahl, Adam, London, A. J., and Zollman, K. J. S.. 2017. Kantian Decision Making under Uncertainty: Dignity, Price, and Consistency. Philosophers' Imprint, 17, 122.Google Scholar
Borel, Emile. 1962. Probabilities and Life (New York: Dover).Google Scholar
Brentano, Franz. 2009. The Origin of Our Knowledge of Right and Wrong (London: Taylor & Francis Group).Google Scholar
Buchak, Lara. 2013. Risk and Rationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buffon, Georges-Louis Leclerc de. 1777. Essai D'arithmétique Morale. In Supplement a I'histoire Naturelle (Paris: Imprimerie royale).Google Scholar
Chalmers, Adam. 2017. An Offer You Can't (Rationally) Refuse: Systematically Exploiting Utility-Maximisers with Malicious Gambles. Honours Thesis. University of Sydney.Google Scholar
Condorcet, Jean-Antoine-Nicolas de Caritat. 1785. Essai sur l'application de l'analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix (Paris: Imprimerie royale).Google Scholar
Crisp, Roger. 1992. Utilitarianism and the Life of Virtue, The Philosophical Quarterly, 42: 139–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
d'Alembert, Jean Le Rond. 1761. Opuscules mathématiques, ou Mémoires sur différens sujets de géométrie, de Méchanique, d'optique, d'astronomie &c (Paris: David).Google Scholar
Edwards, Ren B. 1979. Pleasures and Pains: A Theory of Qualitative Hedonism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Glover, Jonathan. 1977. Causing Death and Saving Lives (New York: Penguin).Google Scholar
Griffin, James. 1986. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Haque, Adil Ahmed. 2012. Killing in the Fog of War. Southern California Law Review, 86: 63116.Google Scholar
Hawley, Patrick. 2008. Moral Absolutism Defended. Journal of Philosophy, 105: 273–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutcheson, Francis. 1755. A System of Moral Philosophy (London: A. M. Kelley).Google Scholar
Jordan, Jeff. 1994. The St. Petersburg Paradox and Pascal's Wager, Philosophia. 23: 207–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, Shelly. 1989. The Limits of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Kosonen, Petra. 2021. Discounting Small Probabilities Solves the Intrapersonal Addition Paradox. Ethics, 132: 204–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazar, Seth. 2017. Risky Killing. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 16: 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee-Stronach, Chad. 2018. Moral Priorities under Risk. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 48: 793811.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemos, Noah M. 1993. Higher Goods and the Myth of Tithonus. Journal of Philosophy, 90: 482–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1998. Utilitarianism, ed. Crisp, Roger (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Monton, Bradley. 2019. How to Avoid Maximizing Expected Utility. Philosophers' Imprint, 19: 125.Google Scholar
Nebel, Jacob M. 2019. An Intrapersonal Addition Paradox. Ethics, 129: 309–43.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 1986. Overpopulation and the Quality of Life. In Singer, Peter (ed.), Applied Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 145–64.Google Scholar
Robert, David. 2018. Expected Comparative Utility Theory: A New Theory of Rational Choice, Philosophical Forum, 49: 1937.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good: Some Problems in Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2017. 1% Skepticism. Noûs, 51: 271–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skorupski, John. 1999. Ethical Explorations (Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Smith, Nicholas J. J. 2014. Is Evaluative Compositionality a Requirement of Rationality? Mind, 123: 457502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Nicholas J. J. 2016. Infinite Decisions and Rationally Negligible Probabilities. Mind, 125: 1199–212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarsney, Christian. 2018. Moral Uncertainty for Deontologists. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21: 505–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar