Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T12:50:02.439Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Must We Always Pursue Economic Growth?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 November 2023

Jeffrey Carroll*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Bowling Green State University, Bowling Green, OH, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Must we always pursue economic growth? Kogelmann answers yes. Not only should poor countries pursue growth, but rich countries should as well. Kogelmann aims to provide a wealth-insensitive argument – one demonstrating all countries should pursue growth regardless of their wealth. His central argument – the no halting growth (NHG) argument – says no country experiencing growth should stop it, because doing so requires undermining the conditions causing it and those conditions are independently morally desirable, so they should not be undermined. For countries not growing, he may argue that they have an obligation to implement the conditions that cause growth because they are independently morally desirable. Call this the implementation argument. I contend that neither argument is wealth-insensitive as each fails to establish an obligation to pursue growth. I attempt to diagnose how this could be and propose that it is a product of attempting to answer three questions about growth simultaneously.

Type
Replies
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Whether or not Gordon Gekko was right that greed is good, growth is good (Wall Street 1987). This is obviously true for poor countries. But Brian Kogelmann (Reference Kogelmann2022) has recently argued in an important essay that economic growth is good for rich countries as well.Footnote 1 Pace the likes of John Stuart Mill (Reference Mill2008), John Maynard Keynes (Reference Keynes, Pecchi and Piga2010), and John Rawls (Reference Rawls1999) who give wealth-sensitive arguments for growth – arguments that advocate growth only for countries that fall below a certain threshold of wealth – Kogelmann (Reference Kogelmann2022: 478) makes a wealth-insensitive argument – an argument that establishes “that all countries should pursue growth regardless [of] their current level of wealth.”Footnote 2 Rich or poor, we must always pursue economic growth.

This essay argues that Kogelmann's considered view is not wealth-insensitive, by his own lights. His central argument – the no halting growth (NHG) argument – is not wealth-insensitive as it cannot be soundly made by all countries. The countries unable to soundly make the NHG argument are those experiencing growth. For stagnating or shrinking countries, Kogelmann may offer what I call the implementation argument. We may understand Kogelmann's considered view to be the disjunction of these two arguments. Unfortunately, neither establishes an obligation to pursue growth. Hence, Kogelmann's considered view fails to be wealth-insensitive.

The paper proceeds as follows. In Section 2, I introduce Kogelmann's conception of wealth-insensitivity, understood as an argument having the properties of being universal and prescriptive. In Section 3, I state the NHG argument. In Section 4, I note that the NHG argument is not universal. However, when paired with the implementation argument, the resulting view would be. So, let us understand Kogelmann's considered view to be the disjunction of the two. In Section 5, I argue that neither argument is Prescriptive, so his considered view is not wealth-insensitive. In Section 6, Tyler Cowen's argument for growth is used as an illustration of a genuinely wealth-insensitive argument. In Section 7, I identify where Kogelmann's argument goes wrong and suggest to what question he is giving the right answer. Finally, in Section 8, I conclude by contrasting Cowen and Kogelmann's positions in terms of a common analogy.

2. Wealth-insensitivity

An argument is wealth-insensitive on Kogelmann's account when it is both universal and prescriptive.

Universal: For every country, C, an argument, A, can be soundly made by C.

All 197 countries in the world must be able to soundly make A for it to be universal. It does not matter whether C refers to a rich country like the United States or a poor country like Somalia.

Prescriptive: The conclusion of an argument, A, obligates the pursuit of growth by the country, C, making it.

If A is sound, C is obligated to pursue growth.

What would motivate one to want to provide an argument that is both universal and prescriptive? One answer is to show that growth is good for all. Existing explanations for why growth is good include (i) because it leads to an increase in happiness understood as subjective well-being, (ii) because it leads to an increase in objective well-being, or (iii) because it allows for the persistence of democracy which is itself a good thing. While each of these answers can say why growth is good for some (i.e., poor) countries, none, according to Kogelmann (Reference Kogelmann2022: 479–83), are able to say why growth is good for all (in particular, rich) countries as economic growth does not (i) correlate to increased happiness after a satiation point of wealth has been reached, (ii) guarantee that citizens in countries that become rich will, as a result, attain a greater share of the goods on the objective well-being list; indeed, they may end up with a lesser share of them, or (iii) contribute to the achievement or maintenance of democracy after a country reaches a certain level of wealth.Footnote 3

In short, the happiness, objective well-being, and democracy arguments all fail to be universal. If the goal is to show that economic growth is good for all countries, a different argument is needed.

3. Kogelmann's NHG argument

To this end, Kogelmann provides an “indirect” argument that does not argue for economic growth itself, but rather against halting growth when it is occurring. His argument can be summarized as follows:

Growth premise: Economic growth is occurring.

Intervention premise: Halting growth would require altering the conditions that cause growth.

Causal premise: The conditions that cause growth are inclusive institutions (Acemoglu and Robinson Reference Acemoglu and Robinson2013; see also North Reference North1990 and North et al. Reference North, Wallis and Weingast2013), open inquiry (Mokyr Reference Mokyr2018), and bourgeois dignity (McCloskey Reference McCloskey2016; McCloskey and Carden Reference McCloskey and Carden2022).Footnote 4

Moral premise: Inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity are morally desirable independent of their effect on growth.Footnote 5

Prohibition premise: Independently morally desirable conditions should not be altered unless there is all-things-considered reason to do so.

Empirical premise: There is not all-things-considered reason to do so.Footnote 6

Conclusion: Economic growth should not be halted.

Call this the NHG argument. If it is sound, the economy should be allowed to continue to “grow like a weed” (Kogelmann Reference Kogelmann2022: 483).

The NHG argument is different from the happiness, objective well-being, and democracy arguments in that the soundness of the argument does not turn on whether it is made by a rich or poor country. No matter how wealthy a country becomes, the argument is not falsified because countries should not alter independently morally desirable conditions like inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity unless there is all-things-considered reason to do so, which is not the case.

4. What about countries not economically growing?

For the NHG argument to be wealth-insensitive, it must be universal. But there are a non-trivial number of countries for which the growth premise will be false as a result of economic growth not occurring. The NHG argument is growth-sensitive: only countries experiencing growth can soundly make it. Countries not growing cannot soundly make it. Hence, the NHG argument is not universal and, thereby, not wealth-insensitive.

How might Kogelmann respond to the charge that his argument does not show that stagnating or shrinking countries should pursue growth? A potential response would be to say that such countries have an obligation to implement inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity which will almost certainly lead to growth.Footnote 7 While this is not a direct argument to pursue growth, it is an argument to perform some action φ where the consequence of φ-ing will almost surely be growth.

What this amounts to, argumentatively, is eliminating the growth and intervention premises, swapping out the prohibition premise for the implementation premise and modifying the empirical premise.

Causal premise: The conditions that cause growth are inclusive institutions (Acemoglu and Robinson Reference Acemoglu and Robinson2013; see also North Reference North1990 and North et al. Reference North, Wallis and Weingast2013), open inquiry (Mokyr Reference Mokyr2018), and bourgeois dignity (McCloskey Reference McCloskey2016; McCloskey and Carden Reference McCloskey and Carden2022).

Moral premise: Inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity are morally desirable independent of their effect on growth.

Implementation premise: Independently morally desirable conditions should be implemented unless there is all-things-considered reason not to do so.

Empirical premise*: There is not all-things-considered reason not to do so.

Conclusion: Inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity should be implemented.

Call this the implementation argument.

Kogelmann's position, so understood, would be disjunctive: either a country is growing in which case it is obligated to not stop growth on the basis of the NHG argument, or a country is not growing in which case it is obligated to implement inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity on the basis of the implementation argument.Footnote 8 Let this be understood as Kogelmann's considered view.

5. Is Kogelmann's considered view prescriptive?

If both arguments are sound, then Kogelmann's considered view is universal. To be wealth-insensitive, it must also be prescriptive – the conclusion of the argument must obligate the pursuit of growth by the country making it. However, as I will argue, the conclusion of neither the NHG nor implementation argument obligates a country to pursue growth.

To begin, compare two ways Kogelmann formulates the thesis of his essay. The first formulation is what we can call the argumentative thesis.

The argumentative thesis: We must not halt economic growth.

Or, as Kogelmann (Reference Kogelmann2022: 479) puts it, “Halting growth requires that we alter [the conditions that cause growth], but we ought not do this.”

The second formulation is what we can call the titular thesis.

The titular thesis: We must always pursue economic growth.

Calling it the titular thesis does not mean that it does not appear in the text. For instance, Kogelmann (Reference Kogelmann2022: 479) writes, “I shall argue that all countries, irrespective of their current level of wealth, have reason to pursue economic growth.”

For an argument to be prescriptive, it is the titular thesis that must be vindicated. However, the NHG argument only establishes the argumentative thesis. One strategy for vindicating the titular thesis would be to show that the two theses are logically equivalent. If it is the case that the NHG argument can establish the argumentative thesis and the argumentative thesis is logically equivalent to the titular thesis, then the NHG argument can be rightfully described as prescriptive. However, if the two are not equivalent, then the NHG argument would not be prescriptive.

What we need to determine is whether NHG is synonymous with pursuing growth. To do this, we need to know what it is to pursue growth. Depending on whether growth is already occurring, pursuing growth can mean one of the two things. If it is not, pursuing growth involves seeking ways of bringing it about. Call this creating growth. If it is occurring, pursuing growth involves amplifying the rate at which it is occurring. Call this increasing growth.

Since the NHG argument is premised on growth occurring, increasing growth is germane. But the NHG argument does not advocate amplifying growth. It merely requires not interrupting it. The growth rate could remain constant (or even decrease). On the basis of the NHG argument alone, one has no reason to prefer an increasing growth rate to a constant growth rate. Hence, NHG is not synonymous with increasing growth. The implication is that the NHG argument is not prescriptive.

The route the implementation argument takes to the titular thesis is more direct. At issue is just whether it can show that we must always pursue growth. Since the implementation argument drops the growth premise, creating growth is germane. What needs to be shown is that there is always an obligation to bring about growth when it is not already occurring. Unlike the NHG argument, the implementation argument does advocate bringing about something; namely, inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity. And these conditions happen to be ones that tend to lead to economic growth. While it is conceptually possible that growth-fostering conditions do not lead to growth, Kogelmann's argument is one of nonideal theory and the facts in the actual world are such that there is a strong presumption in favor of growth-fostering conditions creating growth.

I do not disagree that growth-fostering conditions tend to lead to growth. But there are two reasons – one structural, the other substantive – for thinking that the implementation argument does not vindicate the titular thesis. Structurally, the implementation argument does not advocate bringing about growth; it advocates bringing about particular moral conditions. The reason the conditions are advocated for is not because they tend to lead to growth, but because they are independently morally desirable. The implementation argument is growth-indifferent – the argument can be sound without obligating that growth be pursued.

To illustrate this, consider the following argument that mirrors the structure of the implementation argument.

The ingredients needed to make a peanut butter and banana sandwich are peanut butter, banana, and bread. These three ingredients are each delicious independent of being combined to make a peanut butter and banana sandwich. Independently delicious ingredients should be bought, unless there is all-things-considered reason not to. There is not all-things-considered reason not to buy them. Therefore, peanut butter, banana, and bread should be bought.

I do not dispute the validity of this argument. Depending on the context and the balance of reasons (on which a great deal hangs), it may even be sound. But it is not an argument showing that you have an obligation to make a peanut butter and banana sandwich.

Likewise, the implementation argument is not an argument to create growth. It is an argument to attain the conditions as they are independently valuable. Just like we should have peanut butter, banana, and bread in our pantry even if we are not making a sandwich, we should want inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity even if they did not cause growth. The fact that they tend to is no more relevant than any other causal implication of bringing about those conditions.

The second reason to doubt the ability of the implementation argument to establish the titular thesis is substantive. The argument, even if it had the appropriate structure, may just not be sound. Of relevance are the implementation premise and empirical premise*. These premises contend, respectively, that independently morally desirable conditions should be implemented unless there is reason not to and that there is no reason not to.

But there very well may be all-things-considered reason not to implement independently morally desirable conditions because doing so may involve significant moral costs and potentially yield a morally worse state of affairs. Take, for instance, an independently morally desirable condition like inclusive institutions. If there is an obligation to implement inclusive institutions for non-growing countries, what this practically amounts to is something like the economic version of the Bush Doctrine. This is a highly demanding result and history has shown us how this type of interventionist approach can go awry. Kogelmann could defend such a radical approach, but doing so would be a significant departure from the non-interventionist motivations underlying the NHG argument. For this reason, I am hesitant to attribute an argument with such implications to Kogelmann. However, if we do not, his view is straightforwardly not universal.

This leaves Kogelmann with a dilemma. Either he can only embrace the NHG argument (which is quite plausible) but acknowledge that it is not wealth-insensitive as it is neither universal nor prescriptive, or he can remain committed to giving a wealth-insensitive argument and try to show that his considered view actually is both universal and prescriptive, despite the preceding objections. I believe the first horn is the best route forward as neither the NHG argument nor the implementation argument can establish the titular thesis. For an argument to be able to vindicate the titular thesis requires an unequivocal commitment to growth. We turn to what such an argument would look like in the next section.

6. A genuinely wealth-insensitive argument

Tyler Cowen's (Reference Cowen2018: 28) argument in Stubborn Attachments is a promising candidate for a wealth-insensitive argument. Cowen makes an analogical argument for pursuing growth that commences by introducing Frank Knight's (Reference Knight1944) Crusonia plant – “a mythical, automatically growing crop which generates more output each period.” Were we to compare a Crusonia plant with a non-Crusonia plant that dies after a normal amount of time, we may find the non-Crusonia plant preferable to the Crusonia along various dimensions like, say, beauty and smell. But, if we were to make an all-things-considered evaluation, we should prefer the Crusonia plant because at “some point the sheer accretion of value from the ongoing growth … dominates the comparison” (Cowen Reference Cowen2018: 28). No matter how beautiful and fragrant the non-Crusonia plant is for its life, the perpetual growth of the Crusonia will yield so much value that it will ultimately be the better choice.

Cowen (Reference Cowen2018: 28) thinks policy decisions are no different: we should “choose the Crusonia plant.” To choose the Crusonia plant is to choose policies that “give rise to the equivalent of the Crusonia plant's unceasing yield, namely ongoing and self-sustaining surges in value” (Cowen Reference Cowen2018: 29). In practice, this means choosing policies that lead to economic growth while giving appropriate due to sustainability and leisure.Footnote 9 Cowen labels the value that such policies select for Wealth Plus and advocates maximizing it conditional upon the pursuit to do so not destabilizing the broader society.Footnote 10 If Cowen's argument is sound, then policy decisions should be made in accordance with the following principle.

The principle of growth: We should maximize the rate of sustainable economic growth, defined in terms of a concept such as Wealth Plus.Footnote 11

Cowen's argument for the principle of growth is the type that can vindicate the titular thesis. If growth is not occurring, then Cowen would be in favor of creating growth. If growth is already occurring, then he would advocate increasing growth. In either case, the right course of action is to maximize the rate of growth.

7. What question about growth does Kogelmann's argument answer?

How could Cowen's argument be wealth-insensitive, while Kogelmann's own argument not be? The answer, I believe, is a product of Kogelmann addressing three important questions about economic growth simultaneously that is better addressed discretely. Call these, respectively, the prescriptive question, the axiological question, and the institutional question.

The prescriptive question: Should a country (always) pursue economic growth?

The axiological question: Is economic growth (always) good for a country?

The institutional question: Can achieving a stationary (or steady) state (ever) justify a country stopping economic growth?

The prescriptive question asks about what a country should do for growth, the axiological question asks about the value of growth, and the institutional question asks about a macro-economic end-state justifying stopping growth.

The question that motivates Kogelmann's essay and the one his argument can provide a clear and compelling answer to is the institutional question. The paper commences by citing the trio of famous Johns who, in varying ways and to varying degrees, view a stationary state as an aspirational macro-economic goal. Pace Keynes, Mill and Rawls, the NHG argument seeks to establish that the answer to the institutional question is no.Footnote 12

By contrast, Cowen can answer both the prescriptive question and the axiological question. His view is that the answer to the axiological question is yes. Growth is unequivocally good for a country in all but the most farfetched counterfactual circumstances. This renders the answer to the prescriptive question also yes. If growth is unequivocally good, then there is decisive reason to create it if it is not occurring or amplify it if it is.

Of course, this does not mean that Cowen gives the right answer to either question. An absolute commitment to maximizing growth presents problems. For instance, if rich countries are obligated to maximize growth, then this may require committing morally objectionable acts in pursuit of it, such as buying morally tarnished products (like oil) from oppressive regimes to spur growth, and, in doing so, support and legitimize oppressive, totalitarian regimes (Wenar Reference Wenar2015).

What is relevant for present purposes is not the evaluation of Cowen's argument, but that his argument can be seen as answering yes to the prescriptive question. The NHG argument is best understood as answering a different question. Not answering every question is not a problem. But it is important to be clear about what question an argument does answer.

8. On horticulture

Both Kogelmann and Cowen analogize economic growth to plant growth. But they disagree about our horticultural obligations. For Kogelmann, if we have a plant that is growing, we have an obligation to not start meddling with the soil. Just keep letting it grow. We do not have an obligation to add fertilizer and nutrients to improve the soil so that the plant can grow even better. If our plant is not growing, only then do we have an obligation to add fertilizer and nutrients. But that obligation exists because fertilizer and nutrients are independently good, not because they spur growth. Our horticultural obligations are sensitive to the state of the plant.

For Cowen, our obligations are insensitive to the state of the plant. If the soil does not presently permit of growth, then we have an obligation to improve it to the point that it does. If the soil already allows for growth, then we have an obligation to add fertilizer to amplify the growth. In either case, we are obligated to pursue growth.

The point of this essay is not that Cowen is right and Kogelmann wrong. It is that to make a wealth-insensitive argument, on Kogelmann's definition, requires an argument for growth that is as unequivocal as Cowen's. Kogelmann's considered view is not such an argument. But, to just the institutional question, the NHG argument provides a compelling answer and perhaps even is sound.

Acknowledgements

The author thanks the editor and the anonymous reviewers for very helpful comments on the paper.

Footnotes

1 On the difference between economic growth and economic progress, see Holcombe (Reference Holcombe2006).

2 Kogelmann's argument is at the country level (see also Moller Reference Moller, Queralt and van der Vossen2019). For a wealth-insensitive argument at the individual level, see Flanigan and Freiman (Reference Flanigan and Freiman2022).

3 One could respond by trying to show that one of these arguments actually is wealth-insensitive. To focus on Kogelmann's positive argument, let us grant his critical project.

4 Koglemann is claiming neither that these three conditions are individually necessary, nor that they are jointly sufficient for causing economic growth. Rather, the claim is that when inclusive institutions, open inquiry, and bourgeois dignity are present, there is a very strong likelihood that growth will occur. For an excellent overview of the causes of growth throughout history, see Koyama and Rubin (Reference Koyama and Rubin2022).

5 I follow Kogelmann in being ecumenical in understanding moral desirability.

6 This premise is unstated, but crucial to the validity of the argument. Despite being unstated and undefended, let us accept its truth to focus on whether the NHG argument is wealth-insensitive at all.

7 Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for comments that ultimately led to this reframing.

8 Kogelmann does not state his argument disjunctively, but I believe it is the best and most charitable interpretation. Importantly, it makes his position no longer growth-sensitive.

9 This does not mean that rules and rights are absent from the story. In a world with a largely unknowable future, they provide the parameters that allow for the principle of growth to be acted upon. See also Cowen (Reference Cowen2006).

10 Cowen's justification for maximizing Wealth Plus is that it makes us objectively better off and subjectively happier. On the former, Friedman (Reference Friedman2006) shows how many modern virtues depend on ongoing economic growth and Moller (Reference Moller2011) argues that there is reason to pursue growth even when it does n't lead to happiness. On the latter, Deaton (Reference Deaton2008) and Stevenson and Wolfers (Reference Stevenson and Wolfers2008, Reference Stevenson and Wolfers2013) find that increases in income boosts happiness.

Recall that Kogelmann provides reason to be skeptical of grounding a wealth-insensitive argument in such considerations. My aim is not to say that Cowen's argument is sound. It is to say that if it is sound, then he provides an example of a wealth-insensitive argument. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on this point.

11 Cowen's final statement says inviolable rights should constrain the quest for growth. He admits, though, that even “inviolable” rights can be violable in sufficiently radical scenarios.

12 Recent work has been done on how Mill (McCabe Reference McCabe2021; see also Turner Reference Turner2023) and Rawls (Edmundson Reference Edmundson2017) answer the institutional question.

References

Acemoglu, Daron, and Robinson, James A.. 2013. Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity, and Poverty (New York: Currency).Google Scholar
Cowen, Tyler. 2006. ‘The Epistemic Problem Does Not Refute Consequentialism’, Utilitas, 18.4: 383–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cowen, Tyler. 2018. Stubborn Attachments: A Vision for a Society of Free, Prosperous, and Responsible Individuals (San Francisco: Stripe Press).Google Scholar
Deaton, Angus. 2008. ‘Income, Health, and Well-Being around the World: Evidence from the Gallup World Poll’, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 22.2: 5372.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Edmundson, William A. 2017. John Rawls: Reticent Socialist (New York: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanigan, Jessica, and Freiman, Christopher. 2022. ‘Wealth Without Limits: In Defense of Billionaires’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 25.5: 755–75.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Friedman, Benjamin M. 2006. The Moral Consequences of Economic Growth (New York, NY: Vintage).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holcombe, Randall. 2006. Entrepreneurship and Economic Progress (New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Keynes, John Maynard. 2010. ‘Economic Possibilities for Our Grandchildren’, in Revisiting Keynes: Economic Possibilities for Our Grandchildren, ed. by Pecchi, Lorenzo and Piga, Gustavo (Cambridge: MIT Press), pp. 1726.Google Scholar
Knight, Frank H. 1944. ‘Diminishing Returns from Investment’, Journal of Political Economy, 52.1: 2647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kogelmann, Brian. 2022. ‘We Must Always Pursue Economic Growth’, Utilitas, 34.4: 478–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koyama, Mark, and Rubin, Jared. 2022. How the World Became Rich: The Historical Origins of Economic Growth (Medford, MA: Polity).Google Scholar
McCabe, Helen. 2021. John Stuart Mill, Socialist (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen's University Press).Google Scholar
McCloskey, Deirdre. 2016. Bourgeois Equality: How Ideas, Not Capital or Institutions, Enriched the World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, Deirdre, and Carden, Art. 2022. Leave Me Alone and I'll Make You Rich: How the Bourgeois Deal Enriched the World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 2008. Principles of Political Economy and Chapters on Socialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Mokyr, Joel. 2018. A Culture of Growth: The Origins of the Modern Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Moller, Dan. 2011. ‘Wealth, Disability, and Happiness’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 39.2: 177206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moller, Dan. 2019. ‘Global Justice and Economic Growth: Ignoring the Only Thing That Works’, in Economic Liberties and Human Rights, ed. by Queralt, Jahel and van der Vossen, Bas (London: Routledge), pp. 95–113.Google Scholar
North, Douglass C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance (New York: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, Douglass C., Wallis, John Joseph, and Weingast, Barry. 2013. Violence and Social Order: A Conceptual Framework for Interpreting Recorded Human History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, Betsey, and Wolfers, Justin. 2008. ‘Economic Growth and Subjective Well-Being: Reassessing the Easterlin Paradox’, Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 39. Spring: 1102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, Betsey, and Wolfers, Justin. 2013. ‘Subjective Well-Being and Income: Is There Any Evidence of Satiation?’, The American Economic Review, 103.3: 598604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, Piers Norris. 2023. ‘Book Review: Helen McCabe, John Stuart Mill, Socialist’, Utilitas, 35.2: 167–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall Street. 1987. dir. by Oliver Stone (Twentieth Century Fox).Google Scholar
Wenar, Leif. 2015. Blood Oil: Tyrants, Violence, and the Rules That Run the World (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar