Published online by Cambridge University Press: 21 February 2018
While Nozick and his sympathizers assume there is a widespread anti-hedonist intuition to prefer reality to an experience machine, hedonists have marshalled empirical evidence that shows such an assumption to be unfounded. Results of several experience machine variants indicate there is no widespread anti-hedonist intuition. From these findings, hedonists claim Nozick's argument fails as an objection to hedonism. This article suggests the argument surrounding experience machines has been misconceived. Rather than eliciting intuitions about what is prudentially valuable, these intuitive judgements are instead calculations about prudential pay-offs and trade-offs. This position can help explain the divergence of intuitions people have about experience machines.
1 Nozick, R., Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford, 1974), p. 42Google Scholar.
2 For example, see Brülde, B., ‘Happiness Theories of the Good life’, Journal of Happiness Studies 8 (2007), pp. 15–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Feldman, F., Pleasure and the Good Life (Oxford, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Finnis, J., Natural Law and Natural Rights, 2nd edn. (Oxford, 2011), pp. 95–6Google Scholar; Griffin, J., Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance (Oxford, 1986), pp. 9–10Google Scholar; Haybron, D., Pursuit of Unhappiness: The Elusive Psychology of Well-Being (Oxford, 2008), p. 21Google Scholar; Hooker, B., Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality (New York, 2000), p. 39Google Scholar; Hurka, T., The Best Things in Life: A Guide to What Really Matters (Oxford, 2011), pp. 68–70Google Scholar; Jollimore, T., ‘Meaningless Happiness and Meaningful Suffering’, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 42 (2004), pp. 333–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kagan, S., Normative Ethics (Boulder, CO, 1998), pp. 34–6Google Scholar; Kagan, S., ‘Well-Being as Enjoying the Good’, Philosophical Perspective: Ethics 23 (2009), pp. 253–72, at 253CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Keller, S., ‘Welfare as Success’, Noûs 43 (2009), pp. 656–84, at 657CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kraut, R., What is Good and Why: The Ethics of Well-Being (Cambridge 2007), pp. 124–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kymlicka, W., Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction, 2nd edn. (New York, 2002)Google Scholar; Railton, P., Facts, Values, and Norms: Essays towards a Morality of Consequence (New York, 2003), pp. 156–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sobel, D., ‘Varieties of Hedonism’, Journal of Social Philosophy 33 (2002), pp. 240–56, at 244CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Thomson, G., Needs (New York, 1987), p. 41Google Scholar; Tiberius, V., ‘Cultural Differences and Philosophical Accounts of Well-being’, Journal of Happiness Studies 5 (2004), pp. 293–314, at 311CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
3 Barber, A., ‘Hedonism and the Experience Machine’, Philosophical Papers 40 (2011), pp. 257–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hewitt, S., ‘What Do Our Intuitions about the Experience Machine Really Tell Us about Hedonism?’, Philosophical Studies 151 (2010), pp. 331–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kawall, J., ‘The Experience Machine and Mental State Theories of Well-being’, The Journal of Value Inquiry 33 (1999), pp. 381–7CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Silverstein, M., ‘In Defense of Happiness: A Response to the Experience Machine’, Social Theory and Practice 26 (2000), pp. 279–300CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Tännsjö, T., ‘Narrow Hedonism’, Journal of Happiness Studies 8 (2007), pp. 79–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Weijers, D., ‘Nozick's Experience Machine is Dead, Long Live the Experience Machine!’, Philosophical Psychology 27 (2014), pp. 513–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
4 Lin, E., ‘How to Use the Experience Machine’, Utilitas 28 (2016), pp. 314–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
5 Nozick, Anarchy State and Utopia, p. 44.
6 Nozick, R., The Examined Life: Philosophical Medititations (New York, 1989), p. 106Google Scholar.
7 Nozick, Anarchy State and Utopia, p. 43.
8 Barber, ‘Hedonism and the Experience Machine’.
9 Substantive lists of those who agree and disagree with Nozick, yet take the intuition as the crux of his argument, can be found in nn. 2 and 3.
10 Weijers, D. and Schouten, V., ‘An Assessment of Recent Responses to the Experience Machine Objection to Hedonism’, Journal of Value Inquiry 47 (2013), pp. 461–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
11 Baber, H., ‘The Experience Machine Deconstructed’, Philosophy in the Contemporary World 15 (2008), pp. 132–7; Tännsjö, ‘Narrow Hedonism’CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
12 Feldman, F., ‘What We Learn from the Experience Machine’, The Cambridge Companion to Nozick's ‘Anarchy, State, and Utopia’, ed. Bader, R. M. and Meadowcroft, J. (Cambridge, 2011), pp. 59–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hewitt, ‘Intuitions about the Experience Machine’.
13 Barber, ‘Hedonism and the Experience Machine’; Feldman, ‘What We Learn from the Experience Machine’. Both Barber and Feldman mean that even if hedonism were true, we would still refuse to plug into an experience machine if we believe that hedonism is false. And as they point out, just because we believe some view or proposition to be false does not mean that the view or proposition is actually false, as our beliefs do not determine their truth-value.
14 Weijers and Schouten, ‘Responses to the Experience Machine’, p. 471.
15 Weijers and Schouten, ‘Responses to the Experience Machine, pp. 466–7.
16 Tännsjö, ‘Narrow Hedonism’, p. 95.
17 Tännsjö, T., Hedonistic Utilitarianism (Edinburgh, 1998), p. 112Google Scholar.
18 Weijers and Schouten, ‘Responses to the Experience Machine’, p. 478.
19 Kolber, A., ‘Mental Statism and the Experience Machine’, Bard Journal of Social Sciences 3 (1995), pp. 10–17Google Scholar; De Brigard, F., ‘If You Like It, Does It Matter If It's Real?’, Philosophical Psychology 23 (2010), pp. 43–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Weijers, ‘Long Live the Experience Machine’. I wish to flag here that all of these discussed experiments only provided a binary choice to their participants: the experience machine or reality. Participants are not given the option to say that they ‘do not know’ which to choose, nor how difficult a choice it is, or how certain they are they have made the right one. I think a lack of a third option is disconcerting, and I discuss it further in section IV below.
20 Kolber, ‘Mental Statism’, p. 15.
21 De Brigard, ‘Does It Matter If It's Real?’, p. 47.
22 Weijers, ‘Long Live the Experience Machine!’.
23 Weijers, ‘Long Live the Experience Machine!’, p. 523.
24 Weijers, ‘Long Live the Experience Machine!’, p. 526.
25 Weijers, ‘Long Live the Experience Machine’, p. 529.
26 Lin, ‘How to Use the Experience Machine’.
27 Lin, ‘How to Use the Experience Machine’, pp. 320–1.
28 Lin, ‘How to Use the Experience Machine’, p. 321.
29 For further discussion, see Campbell, S., ‘The Concept of Well-being’, The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Well-being, ed. Fletcher, G. (New York, 2016), pp. 402–14Google Scholar; Hooker, B., ‘Does Moral Virtue Constitute a Benefit to the Agent?’, How Should One Live? Essays on the Virtues, ed. Crisp, R. (Oxford, 1996), pp. 141–55Google Scholar.
30 R. Kim, ‘What is this Thing called Well-being?’ (unpublished manuscript).
31 Kagan, S., ‘The Limits of Well-being’, Social Philosophy & Policy 9 (1992), pp. 169–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kagan, S., ‘Me and My Life’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series 94 (1994), pp. 309–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
32 Michalos, A. C., ‘Education, Happiness and Wellbeing’, Social Indicators Research 87 (2008), pp. 347–66, at 349–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Cf. Sirgy, M. J., Michalos, A. C., Ferriss, A. L., Easterlin, R. A., Patrick, D. and Pavot, W., ‘The Quality-of-Life (QOL) Research Movement: Past, Present, and Future’, Social Indicators Research 76 (2006), pp. 343–466CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
33 Kagan, ‘Me and My Life’, p. 321.
34 Sumner, L. W., ‘Two Theories of the Good’, The Good Life and the Human Good, ed. Paul, E. F., Paul, J. and Miller, F. D. Jr. (Cambridge, 1992), pp. 1–14, at 4Google Scholar. Sumner re-employs doing and going: ‘our concern will be with welfare in the original meaning still preserved in the term's etymology: the condition of faring or doing well. . . . what is it for a life to go well (or badly)?’ (Sumner, L. W., Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics (Oxford, 1996) p. 1)Google Scholar.
35 Ferkany, M., ‘The Objectivity of Wellbeing’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93 (2012), pp. 472–92, at 476CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
36 Alexandrova, A., ‘Doing Well in the Circumstances’, Journal of Moral Philosophy 10 (2013), pp. 307–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
37 I thank an anonymous reviewer for motivating me to give further justification for using the bipartite distinction.
38 I say particular types because other types of objective-list theories (those which did not include any subjective experience) would be incompatible with the bipartite distinction. I should also note that not all list or pluralist theories are compatible with the bipartite distinction. As I have said above, strict objective-list theories are not, but nor would subjective-list theories be either, as both pluralist theories can only account for a single dimension (doing-well for subjective-list, going-well for objective-list). For subjective-list theories, see Lin, E., ‘The Subjective List Theory of Well-being’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94 (2016), pp. 99–114CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
39 I thank an anonymous reviewer for pushing me to clarify my point here.
40 It should be noted that Nozick does not think that the question he is posing is ‘whether plugging in is preferable to extremely dire alternatives’, but rather, ‘whether plugging in would constitute the very best life, or tie for being best, because all that matters about a life is how it feels from the inside’ (Nozick, The Examined Life, p. 105).
41 Belshaw, C., ‘What's Wrong with the Experience Machine?’, European Journal of Philosophy 22 (2014), pp. 573–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Weijers and DiSilvestro have also argued for this point at length. I thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing this to my attention. See Weijers, D. and DiSilvestro, R., ‘The Morality of Experience Machines for Palliative and End of Life Care’, Experience Machines: The Philosophy of Virtual Worlds, ed. Silcox, M. (London, 2017), pp. 183–201Google Scholar.
42 As one reviewer noted, participants could have manipulated the response forms by adding this third option. Or, as in Weijers, ‘Long Live the Experience Machine’, could have stated their preference for a third option (their indecision) in the qualitative section of the response form. I hope to test my hypothesis empirically in future research.
43 I am indebted to my MA supervisor, Daniel Halliday, for his guidance and support over the years. For helpful conversations on this topic I thank Keny Nichols and James Matthews. And I extend particular thanks to the two anonymous referees for their helpful comments and feedback. This article was written with the support of an Australian Government Research Training Program Scholarship.