Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T04:36:49.381Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Utilitarianism and Self-Respect*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 January 2009

Extract

Modern utilitarianism has largely abandoned the view that human well-being consists solely in pleasurable sensations. Too much was wanting in that view for it to withstand the critique of a more refined philosophical psychology than was available to Bentham and Mill. The objections are by now familiar and need no detailed rehearsal. The older view failed to characterize adequately the structure of human satisfactions, forgetting that we can care about things that will happen after we are dead, that we generally prefer to be told a distasteful truth to a comforting lie, and that we wish to be actors in our own lives (with all the struggle and strife which that implies) and not merely passive recipients of pleasures from external sources. The extent to which a life is a flourishing one cannot be determined by summing the pleasures and pains, and calculating the balance. Nor, indeed, can it be determined by summing anything else. A life that is happy or eudaimon in the Aristotelian sense is an organic unity in which the significance of its parts rests on their contribution to the meaning of the whole. Nur im Zusammenhange eines Lebens hat ein Erlebnis Bedeutung. Utilitarianism needs to find a way of incorporating an organic view of human satisfaction.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

I am grateful to an anonymous referee for Utilitas for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

1 For some substantial progress towards this end, see Griffin, James, Well-Being, Oxford, 1986Google Scholar. Some aspects of an organic view of happiness are illustrated in my parable, ‘The Second Book of Job’, Cogito. v (1991), 92–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 Aristotle, , Nicomachean Ethics. 1172bGoogle Scholar (W. D. Ross's translation).

3 Cicero, , De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum. translated by Rackham, H., Cambridge, Mass., 1967, p. 59; I. xvii.Google Scholar

4 Quoted by Fitzgerald, C. P. in, China: A Short Cultural History. 3rd. edn., London, 1961, p. 432.Google Scholar

5 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice. Oxford, 1972, p. 62.Google Scholar

6 See, for example, Williams, Bernard, ‘A Critique of Utilitarianism’, in Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, Bernard, Utilitarianism For and Against. Cambridge, 1973, pp. 75155.Google Scholar

7 Juvenal, , Satires. xGoogle Scholar. For a good short account of the Roman games, see Grant, Michael, Gladiators. London, 1967.Google Scholar

8 Smart, J. J. C., ‘An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics’Google Scholar, in Smart, and Williams, , p. 25.Google Scholar

9 Ibid., pp. 25–6.

10 Seneca, , Letters. viiGoogle Scholar. I have quoted Michael Grant's translation of this sometimes mistranslated passage, from Grant, , p. 118.Google Scholar

11 Baldwin, James, The Fire Next Time. Harmondsworth, 1964, p. 73.Google Scholar

12 Rawls, ibid., section 67.

13 Ibid., p. 440.

14 Williams, , in Smart, and Williams, , pp. 98–9Google Scholar. Note that a utilitarian faced with this dilemma will have strong feelings of compunction about shooting the hostages, even though he feels no guilt (given the fact that if he refuses to shoot, the consequences for that humanity which he values and respects will he much more calamitous still).

15 See Harris, John, ‘The Survival Lottery’, Philosophy, 1. (1975), 81CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16 Erasmus of Rotterdam, Preface to The Paraphrase Upon the Gospell of Sainct Marke, translated by Key, Thomas, London, 1548, fo. iiir.Google Scholar