Published online by Cambridge University Press: 29 July 2016
The French Franciscan, Peter Aureoli, was born shortly before 1280 near Cahors in the south of France. He studied in Paris, but the date of his arrival there, 1304, quite likely would have made him too late to hear the lectures of Duns Scotus on books 1 and 4 of the Sentences. After teaching at Bologna (1312) and Toulouse (1314), Peter finally returned to Paris where he lectured from 1316–20. In July 1318, his friend John XXII sponsored him for the licentiate in Theology. The request was granted and Aureoli took the oath of Magister actu regens on 13 November 1318. Elected provincial of the Aquitaine Franciscans toward the end of 1320, he was nominated archbishop of Aix-en-Provence before he exercised the former office. Pope John XXII consecrated him on 14 June 1321, but before Peter could settle into his new task he died, probably on 10 January 1322.
1 The life, writings and teaching of Aureoli have been described in detail by A. Teetaert in his article, “Pierre Auriol,” in DThC12/2 (Paris, 1935): cols. 1810–81. In this article Teetaert has summarized in admirable fashion all the literature touching our author up to the year 1931. The starting point of any study of Aureoli, it must be used cautiously since new studies have appeared. E. M. Buytaert (Peter Aureoli. Scriptum super Primum Sententiarum, 2 vols. [St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1953–56]) has brought the materials on the life and writings of Aureoli up to the year 1952 in the introduction to his edition, 1:vii-xxi. On the question of Scotus as the teacher of Aureoli, see the clarifications noted by V. Heynck in Franziskanische Studien 35 (1953), 469–70, and Franziskanische Studien 46 (1964), 179.Google Scholar
2 For a doctrinal study of the various positions on the topic ‘Unity of Being,’ see Brown, S. F., “Avicenna and the Unity of the Concept of Being: The Interpretations of Henry of Ghent, Duns Scotus, Gerard of Bologna and Peter Aureoli,” Franciscan Studies 25 (1965): 117–50. For a defense of Henry of Ghent's position, see idem, “Richard of Conington and the Analogy of the Concept of Being,” Franziskanische Studien 48 (1966): 297–307. For defenders of Scotus's theory of univocity against the criticisms of Aureoli, see Fitzpatrick, N., “Walter Chatton on the Univocity of Being: A Reaction to Peter Aureoli and William of Ockham,” Franciscan Studies 31 (1971): 88–177, and S. D. Dumont, “The Univocity of the Concept of Being in the Fourteenth Century: II. The De ente of Peter Thomae,” Mediaeval Studies 50 (1988): 186–256, esp. 193, 218–21, 238–47. For the position of Gerard of Bologna, see Brown, S. F., “Gerard of Bologna's Quodlibet I, qu. 1: On the Analogy of Being,” Carmelus 31 (1984): 143–79. For a defense of Aureoli's position, see Boulnois, O., “Une question inédite sur l'univocité,” Archives d'Histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen-âge (AHDL) 60 (1993): 293–331.Google Scholar
3 Commentariorum in I Sententiarum pars prima, auctore Petro Aureolo Verberio, O.M. (Rome, 1596) and Buytaert, Peter Aureoli, Scriptum, 2:471–523.Google Scholar
4 Valois, N., “Pierre Auriol, Frère Mineur” in Histoire littéraire de la France (Paris, 1886), 33:527.Google Scholar
5 Dreiling, R., Der Konzeptualismus in der Universalienlehre des Franziskanererzbischofs Petrus Aureoli, BGPhMA 11/6 (Münster, 1913), 214–17.Google Scholar
6 Valois, “Pierre Auriol,” 500–01.Google Scholar
7 J. a Trittenhem, Catalogus scriptorum ecclesiasticorum (Cologne, 1581), fol. 101v; Dreiling, Der Konzeptualismus, 20, n. 6.Google Scholar
8 Birkenmajer, A., Vermischte Untersuchungen zur Geschichte der mittelalterlichen Philosophie, BGPhMA 20/5 (Münster, 1922), 220–25.Google Scholar
9 Cf. Pelster's, F. review of Birkenmajer's book in Theologische Revue 23 (1924), 448ff. The manuscript he pointed to is cod. 292 in the library of St. Anthony in Padua.Google Scholar
10 Pelster, F., “Estudios sobre la transmisión manuscrita de algunas obras de Pedro Aureoli O.F.M. († 1322),” Estudios eclesiásticos 9 (1930): 462–79; 10 (1931): 449–74.Google Scholar
11 A. Maier (“Zu einigen Sentenzenkommentaren des 14. Jahrhunderts,” in Archivum Franciscanum Historicum 51 [1958], 371), says that Pelster overlooked the fact that the endings differ. This contradicts Pelster's own words (“Estudios” 466). Pelster's article was already written before he had a chance to see Borghese cod. ms. 123. Before the article was printed, however, he had the time to jot down what he considered the essentials, noted the difference in endings, added a list of question-titles from book 1, and did not push the matter further.Google Scholar
12 Maier, A., “Literarhistorische Notizen über Petrus Aureoli, Durandus und den ‘Cancellarius,’” Gregorianum 29 (1948): 218–20.Google Scholar
13 Maier, “Zu einigen Sentenzenkommentaren,” 269–93.Google Scholar
14 The prologue and distinctions 1–8 have been edited in a new edition, based mainly on Vat. lat. cod. 329: Buytaert, Peter Aureoli. Scriptum (n. 1 above).Google Scholar
15 Ehrle, F., Historia Bibliothecae Romanorum Pontificum tum Bonifatianae tum Avenionensis (Rome, 1890), 1:319.Google Scholar
16 Maier, A., Codices Burghesiani Bibliothecae Vaticanae, Studi e Testi, 170 (Vatican City, 1952), 161.Google Scholar
17 Maier, “Zu einigen Sentenzenkommentaren,” 369–409.Google Scholar
18 Pelster, “Estudios sobre la transmisión,” 469–79.Google Scholar
19 Minciotti, L., Catalogo dei Codici manoscritti esistenti nella Biblioteca di Sant’ Antonio di Padova (Padua, 1842), 83 and A. Iosa, I Codici manoscritti della Biblioteca Antoniana (Padua, 1886), 185.Google Scholar
20 Maier, A., “Zu einigen Sentenzenkommentaren,” 392–93.Google Scholar
21 This argument from style and format is based on a parallel argument concerning the redaction problem of book 3 of Aureoli's Sentences formulated by V. Heynck in his review of L. Rosato's Doctrina de immaculata B.V.M. conceptione secundum Petrum Aureoli in Franziskanische Studien 41 (1959), 433.Google Scholar
22 Maier indicated that she did not examine the tabula quaestionum of Toulouse, cod. 243 herself, but accepted Pelster's declaration that the table corresponds to the Padua and Berlin manuscripts. The tabula quaestionum for all four books is found in Toulouse, cod. 243, fols. 124rb–127vb. The date, partially erased but readable, is found on fol. 127vb. A comparison of the tabulae of Borghese, cod. 123 and Toulouse, cod. 243 reveals their independence. The number and type of variants attest to this independence.Google Scholar
23 See, e.g., dist. 3, q. 4 (fol. 56vb): “Responsio. Hic fuit magna pugna inter Hieronymum et Augustinum, et hoc in duobus punctis. Primus punctus erat quoad licentiam legalium, utrum fuerint statim post Pentecosten prohibita. Et dicebat Hieronymus quod sic …” (lacuna of six lines). Then: “Sed Augustinus contra eum, quia …” (lacuna of about 45 lines). (Cf. IV Sent. [ed. 1605], 45b). In dist. 12, p. 2, q. 1 (fol. 79ra) the case is the same: “Sed oppositum est, quia sensus attingit illa accidentia separata, igitur et intellectus, quia plus potest quam sensus …” (lacuna equal to 27 lines of omitted text: cf. ibid., 114ab). Here, then, are the same kind of omissions and blanks in a reportatio manuscript. Other instances of such omissions may be found in fols. 62vb, 63va, 66va, 113ra. In the printed edition of 1605 these blanks and omissions are not present. Our search, however, does show that reportatio manuscripts of Aureoli do have similar omissions.Google Scholar
24 Cf. Buytaert, E., Peter Aureoli. Scriptum, 1:xviii-xxi.Google Scholar
25 One important question to be examined is the date of the Reportatio on books 1 and 2 found in Vat. lat. cod. 6768. Maier, using the Quodlibet of Wylton as a measure, has set it after 1316 at Paris. Is her argument solid? Does its location in a codex with a number of Bologna masters not rather point to its earlier origin when Aureoli himself was at Bologna (1312)? Also, why does this text find itself used in the Berlin and Padua manuscripts after distinction 32?Google Scholar
26 Cf. Buytaert, Peter Aureoli. Scriptum, 2:469–523.Google Scholar
27 Padua, Bibl. di Università, cod. 1580, fols. 167r–79r; Padua, Bibl. di Sant’ Antonio, cod. 173, fols. 47r–49r. The latter manuscript does not give the complete text.Google Scholar
28 Pelster says that Cardinal Ehrle told him that he had heard of another manuscript at Wolfenbüttel. The librarian there says no such work exists. Maier also indicated in correspondence that she was unable to track down this manuscript.Google Scholar
29 Maier, , Codices Burghesiani (n. 16 above), 161.Google Scholar
30 Ehrle, , Historia Bibliothecae Romanorum Pontificum (n. 15 above), 1:319.Google Scholar
31 Maier, “Zu einigen Sentenzenkommentaren,” 374–76.Google Scholar
32 Cf. Minciotti, Catalogo dei Codici, 83; Iosa, I Codici (n. 19 above), 185.Google Scholar
33 Cod. 572, fol. 16: “Item, primus Aureoli super sententias cum tabulis copertus corio albo.” The catalogue dates from 1397.Google Scholar
34 The lacunae are found on fols. 31vb–32ra, fols. 58vb and 73va.Google Scholar
a Petrus Lombardus Sententiae in IV libris distinctae 1, dist. 2, cap. 1 (ed. I. Brady [Grottaferrata, 1971], 1:2, 61). Cf. Augustinus De Trinitate 1.2.4 (PL 42:822; CCL 50:31).Google Scholar
b Aristot. Praedicamenta 4.1b25–28.Google Scholar
c Aristot. Metaph. 4.2.1003a32–b12.Google Scholar
d Aristot. Metaph. 5.7.1017a23–29.Google Scholar
e Aristot. Physica 1.2.185a20–23.Google Scholar
f Aristot. Metaph. 5.1.1012b34–1013a20.Google Scholar
g Aristot. Metaph. 5.1.1012b34–1013a20.Google Scholar
h Aristot. Metaph. 5.1.1013a17–19.Google Scholar
i Aristot. Physica 1.3.186a10–15.Google Scholar
j Aristot. Metaph. 5.2.1013a24–35.Google Scholar
k Aristot. Anal. Poster. 1.4.73b32–74a3.Google Scholar
l Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 12, com. 4 (ed. Iuntina [Venice, 1562–74], 8:292DE).Google Scholar
m Aristot. De anima 3.8.431b20–23.Google Scholar
n August. De Trinitate 15.2.nn. 2–3 (PL 42:1057–58; CCL 50A:462).Google Scholar
o Avicenna Metaph. 1.6 (ed. S. Van Riet, 1:31–32; ed. Venetiis, , 1508, fol. 72rb): “Dicemus igitur quod res et ens et necesse talia sunt quod statim imprimuntur in anima prima impressione, quae non acquiritur ex aliis notioribus se, sicut credulitas quae habet prima principia …”Google Scholar
p Aristot. Physica 1.1.184a 17–21.Google Scholar
q Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 12, com. 51 (ed. Iuntina, 8:337AB).Google Scholar
r Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 12, com. 2 (Ibid., 8:291HI).Google Scholar
s Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 10, com. 8 (Ibid., 8:257FG).Google Scholar
t Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 3, com. 10 (Ibid., 8:49BC).Google Scholar
u Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 3, com. 10 (Ibid., 8:49BC).Google Scholar
v Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 5, com. 14 (Ibid, 8:117G).Google Scholar
w Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 4, com. 2 (Ibid., 8:66DE).Google Scholar
x Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
y Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
z Cf. Duns Scotus, Ioannes Ordinatio 1, dist. 3, p. 1, q. 3 nn. 131–33 (ed. Vaticana, 3:81–83).Google Scholar
a2 Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
b2 Cf. Aristot, . Physica 3.4.249a22–23.Google Scholar
c2 Aristot. Historia Animalium 1.6.491a19–24.Google Scholar
d2 Aristot. Metaph. 10.2.1053b28–33.Google Scholar
e2 Aristot. Metaph. 4.4.1006b8.Google Scholar
f2 Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
g2 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 3, com. 10 (ed. Iuntina, 8:49BC).Google Scholar
h2 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 3, com. 10 (Ibid., 8:49B-D).Google Scholar
i2 Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
j2 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 3, com. 10 (ed. Iuntuna, 8:49B-D).Google Scholar
k2 Aristot. Metaph. 7.13.1039ab.Google Scholar
l2 Aristot. Metaph. 9.1.1045b35.Google Scholar
m2 Cf. Duns Scotus, Ioannes Ordinatio 1, dist. 3, p. 1, q. 3, nn. 134–36 (ed. Vaticana, 3:83–85).Google Scholar
n2 Aristot. Metaph. 7.1.1028b14.Google Scholar
o2 Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
p2 Cf. Duns Scotus, Ioannes Ordinatio 1, dist. 3, p. 1, q. 3, n. 161 (ed. Vaticana, 3:99–100).Google Scholar
q2 Cf. Duns Scotus, Ioannes Ordinatio 1, dist. 3, p. 1, q. 3, nn. 132–33, 159–61 (Ibid., 3:81–83, 97–100), et praesertim Ordinatio 2, d. 3, p. 1, qq. 5–6, nn. 170–75 (Ibid., 7:475–78).Google Scholar
r2 Cf. Andreas, Antonius In Sententias 1, dist. 3, q. 2 (cod. Vat. lat. 1113, fol. 57ra): “Ad aliam, cum dicitur quod ‘si conceptus entis esset unus unitate determinatae rationis, tunc rationes speciales entium adderent aliquid ei quod non esset, et ita essent nihil’, solutum fuit prius. Dico tamen quod non addunt aliquid differens realiter ab ente; addunt tamen rationes speciales quae sunt aliae a ratione entis non alietate oppositionis vel disparationis sed alietate determinationis et inadequationis, sicut inferius dicitur esse aliud a superiori. Et ex hoc non sequitur quod sint non-ens, quia idem argumentum potest fieri de speciebus respectu generis.”Google Scholar
s2 Cf. de Alnwick, Guillemus In Primum Sententiarum q. 8 (ed. Stephen D. Dumont, Mediaeval Studies 49 (1987), 69–70: “Ad hoc ad primam probationem, cum dicitur omne univocum ad aliqua seipso non descendit in illa, dicendum quod verum est ‘seipso’ in universali accepto, sed vel per differentias vel per modos intrinsecos perfectionis, qui non sunt proprie aliqua addita enti sed gradus intrinseci entis.” Cf. etiam Antonius Andreas Quaestiones subtilissimae super duodecim libros Metaphysicae Aristotelis 1, q. 1, a. 3 (ed. Venetiis, 1495), fol. 3vb: “Sed hoc non obstante conveniunt in aliquo conceptu reali imperfecto et inadequato realitati, cuiusmodi conceptus entis qui ut sic abstrahitur ab omni modo intrinseco realitatis Dei et creaturae qui sunt finitum et infinitum. Unde conceptus entis formaliter non est finitus nec infinitus positive, sed communis utrique, abstrahens ab utroque.” Cf. etiam Ioannes Duns Scotus Ordinatio 1, dist. 8, p. 1, q. 3, nn. 108, 139–50 (ed. Vaticana, 4:202–03, 222–27).Google Scholar
t2 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 2, com. 11 (ed. Iuntina, 8:33KL).Google Scholar
u2 Aristot. Metaph 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
v2 Aristot. Metaph. 8.3.1043b28–33.Google Scholar
w2 Avicenna Metaph. 5.6 (ed. Van Riet, 2:281; ed. Venetiis, ., fol. 90va).Google Scholar
x2 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 10, com. 1 (ed. Iuntina, 8:250AB).Google Scholar
y2 Averroes In Aristot. De anima 1, com. 8 (ed. F. S. Crawford [Cambridge, MA, 1953], 12).Google Scholar
z2 Averroes In Aristot. De anima 1, com. 8 (Ibid., 12).Google Scholar
a3 Avicenna Metaph. 5.2 (ed. S. Van Riet, 2:245; ed. Venetiis, , fol. 87vb).Google Scholar
b3 Aristot. Metaph. 4.1.1003a21–22.Google Scholar
c3 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 4, com. 1 et 2 (ed. Iuntina, 8:64D-65G).Google Scholar
d3 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 9, com. 1 (Ibid., 8:226A).Google Scholar
e3 Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
f3 Aristot. Topica 6.6.144a9.Google Scholar
g3 Aristot. Anal. Poster. 1.4.73a37–73b5.Google Scholar
h3 Aristot. Topica 6.6.144a9.Google Scholar
i3 Avicenna Metaph. 5.6 (ed. Van Riet, 2:281; Venetiis, fol. 90va).Google Scholar
j3 Avicenna Metaph. 5.5 (ed. Van Riet, 2:269; Venetiis, fol. 89va).Google Scholar
k3 Avicenna Metaph. 5.5 (ed. Van Riet, 2:269; Venetiis, fol. 89va).Google Scholar
l3 Aristot. Praedicamenta 5.3b 10–17.Google Scholar
m3 Aristot. Anal. Poster. 1.4.73a37–73b5.Google Scholar
n3 Ibid.Google Scholar
o3 Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–27.Google Scholar
p3 Aristot. Metaph. 9.8.1049b4–1051a3.Google Scholar
q3 Aristot. Metaph. 3.3.998b23–37.Google Scholar
r3 Liber de causis prop. 5 (6), nn. 57 et 61 (ed. A. Pattin, Tijdschrift voor Philosophie 28 [1966], 147–48): “Causa prima superior est omni narratione…. Quod est quia narratio non fit nisi per loquelam, et loquela per intelligentiam, et intelligentia per cogitationem, et cogitatio per meditationem, et meditatio per sensum. Causa autem prima est supra res omnes, quoniam est causa eis; propter illud ergo fit quod ipsa non cadit sub sensu et meditatione et cogitatione et intelligentia et loquela; non est ergo narrabilis.”Google Scholar
s3 Pseudo-Dionysius De divinis nominibus 1, n. 5 (PG 3:594): “Illam igitur divinam supraquam substantiam quodcunque est illa supraquam essentia bonitatis, quae supra bonitatem est….”Google Scholar
t3 Aristot. Anal. Poster. 1.2.72a28–29.Google Scholar
u3 Aristot. Metaph. 2.1.993b30–31.Google Scholar
v3 Averroes In Aristot. De anima 3, com. 19 (ed. Crawford, 441).Google Scholar
w3 Augustinus De Trinitate 8.3 (CCL 50:272; PL 42:949).Google Scholar
x3 Eustratius In Aristot. Ethicorum 4 (ed. H. Paul F. Merken, The Greek Commentaries on the Nicomachaean Ethics of Aristotle [Leiden, 1973] 1:49–50).Google Scholar
y3 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 12, com. 51 (ed. Iuntina, 8:337AB).Google Scholar
z3 Averroes In Arist. Metaph. 12, com. 36 (Ibid., 8:318B-319D).Google Scholar
a4 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 12, com. 51 (Ibid., 8:337AB).Google Scholar
b4 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 12, com. 36 (Ibid., 8:318F–319D).Google Scholar
c4 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 12, com. 18 (Ibid., 8:305DE).Google Scholar
d4 Aristot. Metaph. 1.9.990a33–993a10.Google Scholar
e4 Averroes In Aristot. Metaph. 13, com. 4–5 (1078b7–1080a12).Google Scholar
f4 Aristot. Metaph. 13.4–5.1078b–1080a 12.Google Scholar
g4 Aristot., Metaph. 14.1–6.1087a28–1093b29.Google Scholar
h4 Extravagantes 1.1.2 (ed. A. Friedberg, Corpus Iuris Canonici, 2:, col. 6–7); Enchiridion Symbolorum [ed. Denzinger-Schönmetzer, 1976], 433): “Reprobamus etiam et condemnamus perversissimum dogma impii Almarici cuius mentem sic pater mendacii excaecavit, ut eius doctrina non tam haeretica censenda sit, quam insana.”Google Scholar