Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T22:03:24.643Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Contextual Abductive Reasoning with Side-Effects

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 July 2014

LUÍS MONIZ PEREIRA*
Affiliation:
Centro de Inteligência Artificial (CENTRIA), Departamento de Informática, Faculdade de Ciências e Tecnologia, Universidade Nova de Lisboa, 2829-516 Caparica, Portugal
EMMANUELLE-ANNA DIETZ*
Affiliation:
Centro de Inteligência Artificial (CENTRIA), Departamento de Informática, Faculdade de Ciências e Tecnologia, Universidade Nova de Lisboa, 2829-516 Caparica, Portugal International Center for Computational Logic, TU Dresden, D-01062 Dresden, Germany
STEFFEN HÖLLDOBLER*
Affiliation:
International Center for Computational Logic, TU Dresden, D-01062 Dresden, Germany

Abstract

The belief bias effect is a phenomenon which occurs when we think that we judge an argument based on our reasoning, but are actually influenced by our beliefs and prior knowledge. Evans, Barston and Pollard carried out a psychological syllogistic reasoning task to prove this effect. Participants were asked whether they would accept or reject a given syllogism. We discuss one specific case which is commonly assumed to be believable but which is actually not logically valid. By introducing abnormalities, abduction and background knowledge, we adequately model this case under the weak completion semantics. Our formalization reveals new questions about possible extensions in abductive reasoning. For instance, observations and their explanations might include some relevant prior abductive contextual information concerning some side-effect or leading to a contestable or refutable side-effect. A weaker notion indicates the support of some relevant consequences by a prior abductive context. Yet another definition describes jointly supported relevant consequences, which captures the idea of two observations containing mutually supportive side-effects. Though motivated with and exemplified by the running psychology application, the various new general abductive context definitions are introduced here and given a declarative semantics for the first time, and have a much wider scope of application. Inspection points, a concept introduced by Pereira and Pinto, allows us to express these definitions syntactically and intertwine them into an operational semantics.

Type
Regular Papers
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Apt, K. R. and van Emden, M. H. 1982. Contributions to the theory of logic programming. Journal of the ACM 29, 3, 841862.Google Scholar
Byrne, R. M. J. 1989. Suppressing valid inferences with conditionals. Cognition 31, 6183.Google Scholar
Clark, K. L. 1978. Negation as failure. In Logic and Data Bases, Gallaire, H. and Minker, J., Eds. Vol. 1. Plenum Press, New York, NY, 293322.Google Scholar
Dietz, E.-A., Hölldobler, S., and Ragni, M. 2012. A computational logic approach to the suppression task. In Proceedings of the 34th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, CogSci 2013, Miyake, N., Peebles, D., and Cooper, R. P., Eds. Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society, 15001505.Google Scholar
Dietz, E.-A., Hölldobler, S., and Ragni, M. 2013. A computational logic approach to the abstract and the social case of the selection task. In Proceedings of the 11th International Symposium on Logical Formalizations of Commonsense Reasoning, COMMONSENSE 2013. Aeya Nappa, Cyprus.Google Scholar
Dietz, E.-A., Hölldobler, S., and Wernhard, C. 2013. Modeling the suppression task under weak completion and well-founded semantics. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics.Google Scholar
Evans, J. 2010. Reasoning and imagination. In Thinking Twice: Two Minds in One Brain. OUP Oxford.Google Scholar
Evans, J. 2012. Biases in deductive reasoning. In Cognitive Illusions: A Handbook on Fallacies and Biases in Thinking, Judgement and Memory, Pohl, R., Ed. Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Evans, J., Barston, J. L., and Pollard, P. 1983. On the conflict between logic and belief in syllogistic reasoning. Memory & Cognition 11, 3, 295306.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1966. Philosophy of Natural Science. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.Google Scholar
Hölldobler, S. and Kencana Ramli, C. D. 2009a. Logic programs under three-valued Łukasiewicz semantics. In Logic Programming, 25th International Conference, ICLP 2009, Hill, P. M. and Warren, D. S., Eds. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 5649. Springer, Heidelberg, 464478.Google Scholar
Hölldobler, S. and Kencana Ramli, C. D. 2009b. Logics and networks for human reasoning. In International Conference on Artificial Neural Networks, ICANN 2009, Part II, Alippi, C., Polycarpou, M. M., Panayiotou, C. G., and Ellinas, G., Eds. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 5769. Springer, Heidelberg, 8594.Google Scholar
Hölldobler, S., Philipp, T., and Wernhard, C. 2011. An abductive model for human reasoning. In Logical Formalizations of Commonsense Reasoning, Papers from the AAAI 2011 Spring Symposium. AAAI Spring Symposium Series Technical Reports. AAAI Press, Cambridge, MA, 135138.Google Scholar
Kakas, A. C., Kowalski, R. A., and Toni, F. 1993. Abductive logic programming. Journal of Logic and Computation 2, 6, 719770.Google Scholar
Kowalski, R. 2011. Computational Logic and Human Thinking: How to be Artificially Intelligent. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Łukasiewicz, J. 1920. O logice trójwartoś.ciowej. Ruch Filozoficzny 5, 169–171. English translation: On three-valued logic. In: Łukasiewicz J. and Borkowski L. (ed.). (1990). Selected Works, Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 87–88.Google Scholar
Pereira, L. M., Aparício, J. N., and Alferes, J. J. 1991. Hypothetical reasoning with well founded semantics. In Scandinavian Conference on Artificial Intelligence: Proc. of the SCAI'91, Mayoh, B., Ed. IOS Press, Amsterdam, 289300.Google Scholar
Pereira, L. M. and Pinto, A. M. 2011. Inspecting side-effects of abduction in logic programs. In Logic Programming, Knowledge Representation, and Nonmonotonic Reasoning: Essays in honour of Michael Gelfond, Balduccini, M. and Son, T. C., Eds. LNAI, vol. 6565. Springer, 148163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saptawijaya, A. and Pereira, L. M. 2013. Tabled abduction in logic programs. Theory and Practice of Logic Programming 13, 4-5-Online-Supplement.Google Scholar
Stenning, K. and van Lambalgen, M. 2005. Semantic interpretation as computation in nonmonotonic logic: The real meaning of the suppression task. Cognitive Science 6, 29, 916960.Google Scholar
Stenning, K. and van Lambalgen, M. 2008. Human Reasoning and Cognitive Science. A Bradford Book. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Torasso, P., Console, L., Portinale, L., and Dupré, D. T. 1991. On the relationship between abduction and deduction. Journal of Logic and Computation 1, 5, 661690.Google Scholar
Van Gelder, A., Ross, K. A., and Schlipf, J. S. 1991. The well-founded semantics for general logic programs. Journal of the ACM 38, 3, 619649.Google Scholar
Wason, P. 1968. Reasoning about a rule. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 20, 3, 273281.Google Scholar