Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T12:30:27.040Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Learning from a Novel

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

There is always a danger in philosophy, that what is intended initially as simply one explanation of some form of activity, should come to be regarded as the only possible form of explanation. Nor does this danger seem to be diminished where a philosopher's aim is itself that of attacking limited notions of what is possible as an explanation. This is one, though not the only, reason why it is often the case that what at first appears as a revolutionary and illuminating solution of certain philosophical difficulties, later gives rise to even more intractable problems of its own.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1972

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 23 note 1 The Concept of Mind (Hutchinson, 1949) p. 26.Google Scholar

page 24 note 1 Freedom and Reason (Oxford, 1963) ch. 9.Google Scholar

page 27 note 1 The Concept of Mind, p. 30.Google Scholar

page 28 note 1 Puddn'head Wilson (Zodiac Press, 1955) p. 37.Google Scholar

page 30 note 1 Mill, J. S., Autobiography (The World's Classics, 1924) p. 124.Google Scholar

page 32 note 1 Ballad of Hector in Hades.

page 32 note 2 An Autobiography (The Hogarth Press, 1954) p. 43.Google Scholar

page 32 note 3 On Poetry: A Discussion, in Encounter, 1954.Google Scholar

page 33 note 1 Eckermann, , Conversations of Goethe, p. 110.Google Scholar

page 34 note 1 An Autobiography, p. 144.Google Scholar

page 34 note 2 Ibid., p. 146.

page 35 note 1 An Autobiography, p. 146.Google Scholar

page 35 note 2 Art and Reality (Cambridge 1958) p. 4.Google Scholar

page 36 note 1 Quoted in Lawrence, D. H., Selected Literary Criticism (Heinemann, 1955) p. 126.Google Scholar

page 36 note 2 Seven Lectures on Shakespeare and Milton (Chapman and Hall, 1856) p. 10.Google Scholar

page 37 note 1 The matter is complicated because Muir's own explanation of the situation is partly influenced by psychoanalytic theory. But I think that my own account is nevertheless for the most part correct.

page 38 note 1 The temptation is, of course, considerably greater in respect of the visual and plastic arts, that is, when one speaks of a painter or a sculptor bringing someone to see something. I think that it is to be resisted equally strongly here, and for similar reasons.

page 38 note 2 An Autobiography, p. 189.Google Scholar

page 39 note 1 An Autobiography, p. 43.Google Scholar

page 40 note 1 Selected Literary Criticism, p. 185.Google Scholar

page 40 note 2 Art and Reality, p. 144.Google Scholar

page 41 note 1 The Works of Oscar Wilde (Collins, 1948) p. 986.Google Scholar

page 41 note 2 Cary, Joyce, Art and Reality, p. 100.Google Scholar

page 42 note 1 The Bodley Head Ford Madox Ford (Bodley Head, 19621963) vol. 3, p. 297.Google Scholar

page 42 note 2 Ibid., p. 297.

page 43 note 1 Inside the Whale and other essays (Penguin Press, 1962) p. 142.Google Scholar

page 43 note 2 P. 139.

page 44 note 1 Inside the Whale and other essays (Penguin Press, 1962) p. 140.Google Scholar

page 45 note 1 G. K. Chesterton: A Selection from his non-fictional prose (Faber and Faber, 1970) p. 86.Google Scholar