Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T22:32:49.283Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Innocent Before God: Politics, Morality and the Case of Billy Budd1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 April 2017

Extract

I begin with the story told by Herman Melville in his short novel, Billy Budd. The year is 1797. Britain is engaged in a long and bitter war against France, and the British war effort has been threatened by two naval mutinies: the Nore Mutiny and the mutiny at Spithead. The scene is His Majesty's Ship, the Indomitable, and the central character is Billy Budd, sailor. Billy Budd is a young man of exceptional beauty, both physical and moral, whose only flaw is a stammer. He is loved by all his fellow sailors except the master-at-arms, John Claggart. The incarnation of evil, Claggart recognises in Billy the incarnation of goodness, and is consumed by a jealousy which leads him to accuse Billy (falsely) of inciting the crew to mutiny. Alone with Claggart and the ship's Captain, Edward Vere, Billy hears the lying charge against him. He is enraged, but his stammer prevents him from responding in words. He strikes Claggart, and the blow is fatal. Billy Budd, sailor, has killed the master-at-arms of one of His Majesty's ships on active service, and the penalty for this is death.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

2 All references are to McCall, Dan (ed.) Melville's Short Novels (New York: Norton, 2002).Google Scholar

3 Op. cit., 148.

4 See the critical essays in McCall, Dan (ed.) Melville's Short NovelsGoogle Scholar for some examples of the range of critical responses to the novel.

5 Arendt, Hannah, On RevolutionGoogle Scholar as quoted in McCall, (ed.) Melville's Short Novels, op. cit., 397.Google Scholar

6 Billy Budd, 156.Google Scholar

7 StMatthew, 27:24.Google Scholar

8 Winch, Peter, ‘The Universalizability of Moral Judgements’Google Scholar in Winch, , Ethics and Action, (London: Routledge, 1972), 163.Google Scholar

9 Op. cit., 164.

10 Thompson, Dennis, Political Ethics and Public Office (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1987), 64.Google Scholar

11 Stephen, James Fitzjames, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967), 114115.Google Scholar

12 Hollis, Martin, ‘Dirty Hands’, in Reason in Action: Essays in the philosophy of social science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 143.Google Scholar

13 Wiggins, David, ‘Truth and Truth as Predicated of Moral Judgements’, in Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987), 180.Google Scholar

14 Twain, Mark, Huckleberry Finn (London: Dent, 1950), chapter xvi.Google Scholar

16 For an illuminating discussion of this case see Bennett, Jonathan, ‘The Conscience of Huckleberry Finn’, Philosophy, 49, (1974), 123–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 Rawls, John, Political Liberalism, (New York: Columbia University, 1993), xvi.Google Scholar

18 Mill, John Stuart, On Liberty, (London: Penguin, 1974), 132–3.Google Scholar

19 Rawls, John, op. cit., 58.Google Scholar

20 In making this claim I am, of course, assuming that a distinction between the right and the good can be drawn, and that the fact of pluralism is confined to pluralism about the good. This claim is contestable—see, for example, Waldron, Jeremy, ‘Rawls's Political LiberalismGoogle Scholar, in Waldron, , Law and Disagreement, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 149–63.Google Scholar

21 Stephen, James Fitzjames, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967), 114115.Google Scholar

22 Billy Budd, op. cit, 168.Google Scholar