Published online by Cambridge University Press: 08 January 2010
I have been arguing, for almost thirty years now, that emotions have been unduly neglected in philosophy. Back in the seventies, it was an argument that attracted little sympathy. I have also been arguing that emotions are a ripe for philosophical analysis, a view that, as evidenced by the Manchester 2001 conference and a large number of excellent publications, has now become mainstream. My own analysis of emotion, first published in 1973, challenged the sharp divide between emotions and rationality, insisted that we reject the established notion that the emotions are involuntary, and argued, in a brief slogan, that ‘emotions are judgments.’ Since then, although the specific term ‘judgment’ has come under considerable fire and my voluntarist thesis continues to attract incredulousness the general approach I took to emotions has been widely accepted in both philosophy and the social sciences. When Paul Griffiths took on what he misleadingly characterized as ‘propositional attitude’ theories of emotion as the enemy of all that was true and scientifically worthy, I knew that we had made it. Such ferocious abuse is surely a sign that we had shifted, in Kuhnian terms, from being revolutionary to becoming the ‘normal’ paradigm. The current counter-revolution of affect programmes and neuro-reductionism says a lot about who we are and how far we have come. (Progress in philosophy is moved more by this drama of one outrageous thesis after another—once called ‘dialectic’—than by cautious, careful argument.)
1 Griffiths, P., What Emotions Really Are (Chicago, 1998).Google Scholar
2 Lane, R. and Nadel, L., The Cognitive Neuroscience of Emotion (Oxford, 1999).Google Scholar
3 Neu, Jerome, Emotion, Thought & Therapy (Routledge, 1978).Google Scholar
4 Calhoun, C., ‘Cognitive Emotions?’ in Calhoun, C. and Solomon, R., What is an Emotion? (Oxford University Press, 1984)Google Scholar; Roberts, Robert, ‘Propositions and Animal Emotion’ Philosophy 71, 147–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
5 E.g. Ortony, A., Clore, G. L. and Collins, A., The Cognitive Structure of Emotions (Cambridge University Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gordon, Robert, The Structure of Emotions: Investigations in Cognitive Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 1987)Google Scholar.
6 Lazarus, R., Averill, J. and Opton, E. ‘Towards a Cognitive Theory of Emotion’, in Feelings and Emotions, Arnold, Magda B. (Academic Press, 1970).Google Scholar
7 Kenny, A., Action, Emotion and Will (London: Routledge, 1963).Google Scholar
8 Greenspan, P., Emotions and Reasons: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification (New York: Routledge, 1988)Google Scholar.
9 Stocker, M., with Hegeman, E., Valuing Emotions (Cambridge University Press, 1996)Google Scholar.
10 Nietzsche, F., Beyond Good and Evil (New York: Random House, 1967)Google Scholar.
11 Damasio, A., Descartes' Error (London: Macmillan, 1994)Google ScholarPubMed.
12 Davidson, Donald (1977) ‘Hume's Cognitive Theory of Pride’Google Scholar reprinted in Davidson (1980) Essays on Actions an Events (Oxford University Press), 277#90. Davidson‘s view was taken very seriously by many philosophers who never showed any interest in emotion, much less in any cognitive theory of emotion. But what gets left out of Davidson's reconstruction— as Hume himself clearly recognized—was pride, that is, the emotion. See Baier, Annette, ‘Hume's Analysis of Pride’, Journal of Philosophy, 75 (1978), pp. 27–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
13 Calhoun, C. and Solomon, R., What is an Emotion? (Oxford University Press 1984)Google Scholar.
14 Ortony et. al. (1988).
15 Downing, George, ‘Emotion Theory Revisited’, in Heidegger, Coping, and Cognitive Science: a Festschhrift for Hubert Dreyfus, Vol. 2 (M.I.T. Press, 2001), pp. 245–70.Google Scholar
16 The line is from William Henley's ‘Invictus,’ which has been forever tarnished by mass-murderer Timothy McVeigh, who quoted it immediately before his execution (June 2001).