No CrossRef data available.
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 08 January 2010
Cartesian accounts of the mental make it axiomatic that consciousness is transparent: what I feel, I know I feel, however many errors I may make about its cause. ‘I’ names a simple, unextended, irreducible substance, created ex nihilo or eternally existent, and only associated with the complete, extended, dissoluble substance or pretend-substance that is ‘my’ body by divine fiat. Good moderns take it for granted that ‘we’ now realize how shifting, foggy and deconstructible are the boundaries of the self; ‘we’ know that our own motives, feelings and intentions constantly escape us; ‘I’ names only the current speaker, or the momentarily dominant self among many fluid identities.
2 Wilkes, Kathleen V., Real People (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988).Google Scholar
3 See Churchland, Patricia S., ‘Replies to Critics’, Inquiry 29 (1986), 241–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
4 Wilkes, op. cit. (n. 1); Brennan, Andrew ‘Fragmented Selves and the Problem of Ownership’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1989–1990), 143–58.Google Scholar
5 Plotinus, , Ennead VI 7. 41, 22f.Google Scholar
6 Armstrong, A. H.Enneads (London: Heinemann, Loeb Classical Library, 1988), vol. 7, 78.Google Scholar
7 Palmer, G. E. H., Sherrard, P. and Ware, K. (eds), Philokalia (London: Faber & Faber, 1979), 186.Google Scholar
8 Thigpen, Corbett and Cleckley, Harvey M. ‘A case of Multiple Personality’, Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 49 (1954), 135–51CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (reprinted in Sarason, I. G. (ed.), Contemporary Research in Personality (Princeton: Van Nostrand, 1962), 367–83Google Scholar; see also The Three Faces of Eve (London: Seeker & Warburg, 1957), 50.Google Scholar
9 McDougall, W., ‘The Case of Sally Beauchamp’, Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research 19 (1905–1907), 410–31.Google Scholar
10 Sidis, B. and Goodhart, S. P., Multiple Personality (New York: Appleton & Co., 1909), 65.Google Scholar
11 Cory, C. E., ‘Spanish Maria’, Journal of Abnormal Psychology 14 (1920)Google Scholar: Crabtree, A., Multiple Man (Eastbourne: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1985), 41f.Google Scholar
12 Cory, , Psychological Review 26 (1919).Google Scholar
13 Prince, M., The Dissociation of a Personality (New York: Longmans, Greene & Co., 1908), 78ff.Google Scholar
14 Crabtree, , op. cit. (n. 11), 39ff.Google Scholar
15 Hawthorn, J., Multiple Personality and the Disintegration of Literary Character (London: Edward Arnold, 1983).Google Scholar
16 Prince, , op. cit. (n. 13), 147ff.Google Scholar
17 Prince, , op. cit. (n. 16), 489.Google Scholar
18 Hawthorn, , op. cit. (n. 15), 18.Google Scholar
19 Ibid. 8.
20 Wilkes, , op. cit. (n. 1), 110.Google Scholar
21 Spanos, N. P., Weekes, J. R. and Bertrand, L. D., Journal of Abnormal Psychology 94 (1985), 362–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
22 Thigpen, and Cleckley, , op. cit. (n. 8), 165.Google Scholar
23 Crabtree, , op. cit. (n. 11), 211f.Google Scholar
24 Wilkes, , op. cit. (n. 1), 111.Google Scholar
25 See Hawthorn, , op. cit. (n. 15), 11ff.Google Scholar It is also widely claimed that such ‘multiples’ were often or always victims of sexual and other abuse as children. It is not surprising that such victims should exaggerate the normal tendency to forget unpleasant or disgraceful episodes.
26 See Lewis, I. M., Ecstatic Religion (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1971).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
27 Spanos, et al. , op. cit. (n. 21).Google Scholar
28 Thigpen, and Cleckley, , op. cit. (n. 8), 195.Google Scholar
29 Aldridge-Morris, Ray, Multiple Personality: an Exercise in Deception (London: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1989)Google Scholar, cited by Snedegar, Jean, The Independent, 20 03 1990, p. 15.Google Scholar
30 Thigpen, and Cleckley, , op. cit. (n. 8), 271.Google Scholar It may be they have other, better, reasons for their conclusions: how could we tell?
31 Plath, Sylvia, The Bell Jar (London: Faber & Faber, 1966), 80Google Scholar; cited by Hawthorn, , op. cit. (n. 15), 117.Google Scholar
32 Dunne, J. S., The City of Gods (London: Sheldon Press, 1974), 125.Google Scholar
33 Prince, , op. cit. (n. 16), 560.Google Scholar
34 Ibid. 514.
35 Guin, Wyman, Beyond Bedlam (London: Sphere Books, 1973), 15Off.Google Scholar
36 As Eve White apparently thought: Thigpen and Cleckley, , op. cit. (n. 8), 206.Google Scholar
37 Keyes, Daniel, who wrote The Minds of Billy Milligan (New York: Random House, 1981)Google Scholar, is better known as the author of the science fiction story, Flowers for Algernon. They are both touching stories, but I prefer the latter.
38 Taylor, Charles, Sources of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 34.Google Scholar
39 See ‘On Wishing there were Unicorns’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1989–1990), 247–65.Google Scholar
40 McDougall, W., Outline of Abnormal Psychology (London: Methuen, 1926), 541f.Google Scholar
41 Ibid. 546ff.
42 Sidis, and Goodhart, , op. cit. (n. 10), 4.Google Scholar
43 McDougall, , op. cit. (n. 40), 546f.Google Scholar
44 Prince, , op. cit. (n. 13), 186–240.Google Scholar
45 Ibid. 399.
46 Crabtree, , op. cit. (n. 11), 52Google Scholar, after Keyes, op. cit. (n. 37).
47 It is a clumsy methodological error to suppose that—if there are real multiples at all—they must all end up requiring therapy. It is therefore quite wrong to claim that we know that all or most multiples (if they exist) must have been abused as children.
48 Sidis, and Goodhart, , op. cit. (n. 10), 193.Google Scholar
49 Ibid. 199.
50 Ibid. 364.
51 During discussion at the Conference I inflicted this elementary exercise on my audience, and concluded (from their unanimous failure to achieve a tensecond thought) that we could hardly be said to control our thoughts at all. İlham Dilman responded that he had at least thought of the thing I had asked them to, and so must have controlled his thinking at least for a moment. True enough: but now (if you control your thoughts) don't think of a white mare.
52 Philo, , On Cherubim, 114f.Google Scholar: Collected Works, trans. Colson, F. H., Whitaker, G. H. et al. (London: Heinemann, Loeb Classical Library, 1929), vol. II, 77.Google Scholar
53 Philo, , De Mutatione, 293fGoogle Scholar: ibid., vol. V, 265f.
54 Sangarakshita, , Survey of Buddhism, 6th ed. (London: Tharpa Publications, 1987), 196f.Google Scholar
55 Midgley, Mary, Wickedness (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984), 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
56 I have discussed some of the difficulties in attempts to explain the existence or nature of consciousness by referring only to such things as can supposedly exist without consciousness in From Athens to Jerusalem (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), ch. 7.Google Scholar
57 Hawthorn, , op. cit. (n. 15), 34.Google Scholar
58 Potts, T. C., Conscience in Mediaeval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
59 Allison, R., Mind in Many Pieces (New York: Rawson, Wade, 1980).Google Scholar
60 Sally: Prince, , op. cit. (n. 13), 166.Google Scholar
61 As ibid. 150.
62 BI: ibid. 209.
63 As in Stapledon, Olaf, Last Men in London (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1972; first published 1932).Google Scholar
64 Anquttara-Nikaya 1, 10Google Scholar: cited by Sangarakshita, , op. cit. (n. 54), 104.Google Scholar Edward Conze emphasizes that Humean comparisons are deeply misleading: whereas Hume ‘understood our personality after the image of inanimate objects, which also have no “self”, or true inwardness of any kind… the Buddhist doctrine of anatta invites us to search for the super-personal’ (Thirty Years of Buddhist Studies (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1967), 239f).Google Scholar
65 Prince, , op. cit. (n. 13), 316.Google Scholar
66 Ibid. 152; see also 221.
67 Ibid. 234.
68 Ibid. 238.
69 See Merlan, Philip, Monopsychism Mysticism Metaconsciousness (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1963).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
70 See Robinson, H. M., ‘Aristotelian Dualism’, in Annas, J. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, vol. I (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983).Google Scholar
71 Plotinus, , Enneads IIIGoogle Scholar 4.3; see my ‘Reason as Daimon’ in Gill, C. (ed), The Person and the Human Mind (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 187–206.Google Scholar
72 Evans, C. O., The Subject of Consciousness (London: Allen & Unwin, 1970), 144.Google Scholar
73 Prince, , op. cit. (n. 13), 525.Google Scholar
74 Blake, W., ‘Jerusalem’, 49.72fGoogle Scholar, in Keynes, G. (ed.), Collected Works (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966), 680.Google Scholar
75 See Suzuki, D. T. (ed.), Manual of Zen Buddhism (New York: Grove Press, 1960).Google Scholar
76 There is a related doctrine in Augustine, on which see Nash, R. H.The Light of Knowledge (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1969), 94ff.Google Scholar
77 See my ‘Is Humanity a Natural Kind?’, in Ingold, Tim (ed.), What is an Animal? (London: Unwin Hyman, 1988), 17–34.Google Scholar