No CrossRef data available.
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 08 January 2010
As a rule we treat people as responsible for what they do. We admonish them if they behave badly, praise them if they do well. We punish people. And we reward them.
There are exceptions, of course. For example, we do not punish someone for doing something he has been compelled to do, perhaps by having a gun in his back. And we even recognize such a thing as psychological compulsion, as in the case of kleptomania.
1 Hobbes, T., Leviathan (London: Dent, 1914).Google Scholar
2 Locke, J., An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Nidditch, P. H. (ed.) (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975).Google Scholar
3 Locke, , op. cit. III, ii, i.Google Scholar
4 Pohlenz, M., Die Stoa (Gottinghen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1959)Google Scholar; Long, A. A., Problems in Stoicism (London: Athlone, 1971).Google Scholar
5 Descartes, R., The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, tr. Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R. and Murdoch, D. (Cambridge University Press, 1985), 343.Google Scholar
6 Descartes, , op. cit. 205.Google Scholar
7 Plato, , The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Hamilton, E. and Cairns, H. (eds) (New York: Pantheon, 1961).Google Scholar
8 Ibid.
9 Chisholm, R. M., ‘Human Freedom and the Self’, in Watson, G. (ed.) Free Will (Oxford University Press, 1982)Google Scholar; Davidson, D., ‘Agency’, in D. Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)Google Scholar; Kolnai, A., ‘Agency and Freedom’, in Vesey, G. (ed.), The Human Agent, Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, Vol. 1, 1966/7 (London: Macmillan), 20–46 Google Scholar; Taylor, R., Action and Purpose (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1966)Google Scholar; Thalberg, I., ‘Do We Cause Our Own Actions?, Analysis 27 (1967), 196–201 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Yolton, J., ‘Agent Causality’, American Philosophical Quarterly 3 (1966), 14–26.Google Scholar
10 Aristotle, , The Basic Works of Aristotle Google Scholar, edited and with an introduction by R. McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941).
11 Danto, A., ‘What We Can Do’, Journal of Philosophy 60 (1963), 435–445 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; ‘Basic Actions’, American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (1965), 141–148 Google Scholar; Brand, M., ‘Danto on Basic Actions’, Nous (1968)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Stoutland, F., ‘Basic Actions and Causality’, Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968), 467–475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
12 James, W., The Principles of Psychology (London: Macmillan, 1891).Google Scholar
13 Descartes, , op. cit. II, 113–114.Google Scholar
14 James, , op. cit. II, 560.Google Scholar
15 Descartes, , op. cit. I, 315, 341, 343–345.Google Scholar
16 Descartes, , op. cit. I, 206.Google Scholar
17 Ibid.
18 Kenny, A. (tr. and ed.), Descartes: Philosophical Letters (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970), 94.Google Scholar
19 Descartes, , op. cit. II, 39.Google Scholar
20 Hume, D., ‘An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding’, in Hume's Enquiries, Selby-Bigge, L. A. (ed.), with revisions by P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), 82.Google Scholar
21 Hartley, D., Observations on Man, His Frame, His Duty and His Expectations (Hildesheim: Ohms, 1967).Google Scholar
22 Hume, D., A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd edn, Selby-Bigge, L. A. (ed.), revised by P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), I, i, 4.Google Scholar
23 Hartley, D., op. cit.Google Scholar
24 Mill, J. S., A System of Logic: Ratiocinative and Inductive, Robson, (ed.), in Collected Works of John Stuart Mill (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1974), VI, ii, 1.Google Scholar
25 Ibid. VI, ii, 2.
26 Ibid. VI, ii, 3.
27 Tucker, A., The Light of Nature Pursued (London: Thomas Tegg, 1837), I, 39–40.Google Scholar
28 Huxley, T. H., ‘On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and its History’, in Huxley, T. H., Collected Essays, Vol. I, Methods and Results (London: Macmillan, 1912), 240, 243–244.Google Scholar