Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T19:25:26.202Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Irrealism about Grounding

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 July 2018

Naomi Thompson*
Affiliation:
University of Southampton and Göteborgs Universitet

Abstract

Grounding talk has become increasingly familiar in contemporary philosophical discussion. Most discussants of grounding think that grounding talk is useful, intelligible, and accurately describes metaphysical reality. Call them realists about grounding. Some dissenters reject grounding talk on the grounds that it is unintelligible, or unmotivated. They would prefer to eliminate grounding talk from philosophy, so we can call them eliminitivists about grounding. This paper outlines a new position in the debate about grounding, defending the view that grounding talk is (or at least can be) intelligible and useful. Grounding talk does not, however, provide a literal and veridical description of mind-independent metaphysical reality. This (non-eliminative) irrealism about grounding treads a path between realism and eliminativism.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See Schaffer, , ‘On What Grounds What’ in Chalmers, D., Manley, D., & Wasserman, R., Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 347383Google Scholar.

2 See e.g. Schaffer, ‘On What Grounds What’, 363–4; Rosen, Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction’ in Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 109136, 113Google Scholar.

3 For a defence of the former conception see e.g. Audi, , ‘A Clarification and Defense of the Notion of Ground’ in Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 101121CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Audi, , ‘Grounding: Toward a Theory of the In-Virtue-Of Relation’, Journal of Philosophy 109 (2012), 685711CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fine, , ‘The Question of Realism’, Philosopher's Imprint 1:1 (2001), 130Google Scholar; Fine, ‘A Guide to Ground’, in Metaphysical Grounding, 37–80. In defence of the latter conception see e.g. Schaffer, , ‘On What Grounds What’ and ‘Monism: The Priority of the Whole’, Philosophical Review 119 (2009), 3176CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 See e.g. Fine, ‘The Question of Realism’; ‘A Guide to Ground’; Schaffer, ‘On What Grounds What’; Sider, , Writing the Book of the World (Oxford: OUP, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Trogdon, An Introduction to Grounding’ in Varieties of Dependence (Munich: Philosophia Verlag, 2012), 97122Google Scholar.

5 See Schaffer, ‘Grounding, Transitivity, and Contrastivity’ in Metaphysical Grounding, 112–138 on transitivity; Jenkins, , ‘Is Metaphysical Dependence Irreflexive?’, The Monist 94 (2011), 267–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar on irreflexivity, and Thompson, Metaphysical Interdependence’ in Jago, (ed.) Reality Making (Oxford, OUP, 2016), 3855CrossRefGoogle Scholar on asymmetry. Rodriguez-Pereyra, argues in ‘Grounding is not a Strict Order’, Journal of the APA 1/3 (2015), 517534Google Scholar argues grounding is neither transitive, nor asymmetric, nor irreflexive.

6 See e.g. Correia, , ‘Grounding and Truth FunctionsLogique et Analyse 53 (2010), 251279Google Scholar; deRossett, ‘Better Semantics for the Pure Logic of Ground’, Analytic Philosophy (forthcoming); Krämer & Roski, , ‘A Note on the Worldly Logic of Ground’, Thought 4/1 (2015), 5968Google Scholar; Fine, Some Puzzles of Ground’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51, 97118CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 For that, see Clark, and Liggins, , ‘Recent Work on Grounding’, Analysis 72 (2012), 812823CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Correia and Schnieder, Metaphysical Grounding; Trogdon, ‘An Introduction to Grounding’; Bliss and Trogdon, ‘Metaphysical Grounding’, available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/grounding/ (2014); and Raven, , ‘GroundPhilosophy Compass 10/5 (2015), 322333CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 This is a rough and ready characterisation, but it will do for present purposes.

9 For the former strategy see Daly, ‘Scepticism about Grounding’, Metaphysical Grounding, 81–100 and Hofweber, ‘Ambitious, Yet Modest, Metaphysics’, Metametaphysics, 280–289; Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics (Oxford University Press, 2016)Google Scholar, Chapter 13. For the latter see Wilson, , ‘No Work for a Theory of Grounding’, Inquiry 57 (2014), 145CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Kosliki, , ‘The Coarse-Grainedness of Grounding’ in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics (Oxford University Press, 2015), 306344CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Explanation is generally considered to be transitive, asymmetric, irreflexive, non-monotonic and hyperintensional.

11 This is the strategy taken by Rosen in ‘Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction’, and by Trogdon in ‘An Introduction to Grounding’, amongst others.

12 See Audi, ‘A Clarification and Defence of the Notion of Ground’.

13 Rosen, ‘Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction’, 110.

14 Lewis, , On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986), 203Google Scholar.

15 Hofweber, ‘Ambitious, Yet Modest, Metaphysics’, 267.

16 Wilson, ‘No Work for a Theory of Grounding’, 549.

17 Koslicki, ‘The Coarse-Grainedness of Grounding’ makes a similar point.

18 Wilson, ‘No Work for a Theory of Grounding’, 554–7.

19 E.g. Dasgupta, S., ‘The Possibility of Physicalism’, The Journal of Philosophy 111/9 (2014), 557592CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fine, ‘A Guide to Ground’; Raven, M., ‘In Defence of Ground’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90/4 (2012), 687701CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rosen ‘Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction’.

20 Fine, ‘A Guide to Ground’.

21 Raven, ‘Ground’, 326.

22 Thompson, N., ‘Grounding and Metaphysical Explanation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 116/3 (2016), 396403CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Kim, J., ‘Explanatory Knowledge and Metaphysical Dependence’, Philosophical Issues 5 (1994), 5169CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 See e.g. Trogdon, K., ‘Grounding: Necessary or Contingent?’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94 (2013), 465485CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 I assume here that irrealists about grounding will maintain that it is at least sometimes appropriate to make a claim about grounding (I think they might also take such claims sometimes to be true). I defend this claim in sections 3 and 4.

26 Wallace, D., ‘Decoherence and Ontology: or, How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love FAPP’ in Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory, and Reality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 69Google Scholar.

27 Mackie, J., Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (New York: Penguin, 1977)Google Scholar.

28 Kim, ‘Explanatory Knowledge and Metaphysical Dependence’, 54.

29 Fine, ‘A Guide to Ground’, 39.

30 For those who think causation is a primitive relation, the cases are much more similar. Knowledge of primitive causal relations would be hard to come by.

31 Rosen, ‘Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction’, 110.

32 Ibid., 134.

33 Of course, not all sentences about grounding are false according to the error theorist. Sentences like ‘there are no grounding relations’, ‘A doesn't ground B’ and ‘B is ungrounded’ might all be true (because they don't commit us to the existence of grounding relations). As is standard, I describe the error theorist's commitment as being to the systematic falsity of grounding sentences in order to circumvent this complication.

34 This terminology is borrowed from Kalderon, , Moral Fictionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Chapter 3.

35 Lewis, D., ‘Truth in fiction’, American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (1978), 3746Google Scholar.

36 Cf. Kalderon, Moral Fictionalism, 121–123.

37 Walton, K., Mimesis and Make-Believe (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990)Google Scholar.

38 Kalderon, Moral Fictionalism, 124.

39 This view is developed in detail in my ‘Getting the Story Straight: Fictionalism about Grounding’ (in progress).

40 See my ‘Getting the Story Straight: Fictionalism about Grounding’ for more details.

41 This is arguably the position of Field in Science Without Numbers (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980)Google Scholar, where he defends the view that there are compelling instrumentalist justifications for continuing to engage in mathematical discourse, but declines to say what, if anything, mathematical utterances might be used to assert.

42 Field, Science Without Numbers.

43 See Wilson, ‘No Work for a Theory of Grounding’, 557.

44 Ibid.

45 Fine, ‘The Question of Realism’.

46 See Fine, ‘The Question of Realism’ for the details of the proposal.

47 Fine, ‘A Guide to Ground’, 39.

48 Fine, ‘The Question of Realism’, 16.

49 Price, H., ‘Expressivism for Two Voices’ in Knowles, J. and Rydenfelt, H. (eds) Pragmatism, Science, and Naturalism (Peter Lang, 2011)Google Scholar.

50 Gibbard, A., Thinking How to Live (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2003)Google Scholar.

51 Thanks to Darragh Byrne, Uriah Kriegal, David Liggins, Alastair Wilson and audiences in Nottingham, Hamburg, Birmingham, Southampton, and Barcelona for discussion and helpful comments.