Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T21:48:55.241Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explanation in Psychology: Functional Support for Anomalous Monism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

Donald Davidson finds folk-psychological explanations anomalous due to the open-ended and constitutive conception of rationality which they employ, and yet monist because they invoke an ontology of only physical events. An eliminative materialist who thinks that the beliefs and desires of folk-psychology are mere pre-scientific fictions cannot accept these claims, but he could accept anomalous monism construed as an analysis, merely, of the ideological and ontological presumptions of folk-psychology. Of course, eliminative materialism is itself only a guess, a marker for material explanations we do not have, but it is made plausible by, inter alia, whatever difficulties we have in interpreting intentional folk-explanations realistically. And surely anomalous monism does require further explanation if it is to be accepted realistically and not dismissed as an analysis of a folk-idiom which is to be construed instrumentally at best. Some further explanation is needed of how beliefs, desires, etc. can form rational patterns which have ‘no echo in physical theory’ and yet those beliefs, desires etc. be physical events. To this end I propose to graft on to anomalous monism a modest version of functionalism.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Appiah, A. 1986. ‘Truth Conditions: A Casual Theory’, in Butterfield.Google Scholar
Jeremy, Butterfield, 1986 (ed.), Language, Mind and Logic (Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Christopher, Cherniak, 1986. Minimal Rationality (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press).Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1980. Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel 1981. ‘Three Types of Intentional Psychology’ in Healey.Google Scholar
Hartry, Field, 1978. ‘Mental Representation’, Erkenntnis, 13, 961.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry 1980. ‘Methodological Solipsism considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology’, Brain and Behavioral Science, 3, 63109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Healey, Richard 1981. (ed.), Reduction, Time and Reality (Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
LePore, Ernest and McLaughlin, Brian 1985. (eds), Actions and Events (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
LePore, Ernest 1986. (ed.), Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Loar, Brian 1981. Mind and Meaning (Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
McDowell, John 1985. ‘Functionalism and Anomalous Monism’, in LePore and McLaughlin)Google Scholar
McGinn, Colin 1982. ‘The Structure of Content’, in Woodfield.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hiliary 1975. Mind, Language and Reality (Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hiliary 1988. Representation and Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press).Google Scholar
Schiffer, Stephen 1987. Remnants of Meaning (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press).Google Scholar
Woodfield, Andrew 1982. (ed.), Thought and Object (Oxford University Press).Google Scholar