Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T20:04:28.902Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

IDENTITY AND DISCERNIBILITY IN PHILOSOPHY AND LOGIC

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 November 2011

JAMES LADYMAN*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Bristol
ØYSTEIN LINNEBO*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Birkbeck College, University of London
RICHARD PETTIGREW*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Bristol
*
*DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF BRISTOL 9 WOODLAND ROAD, BRISTOL BS8 1TB, UK E-mail: [email protected]
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BIRKBECK COLLEGE, MALET STREET, LONDON WC1E 7HX, UK E-mail: [email protected]
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF BRISTOL 9 WOODLAND ROAD, BRISTOL BS8 1TB, UK E-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

Questions about the relation between identity and discernibility are important both in philosophy and in model theory. We show how a philosophical question about identity and discernibility can be ‘factorized’ into a philosophical question about the adequacy of a formal language to the description of the world, and a mathematical question about discernibility in this language. We provide formal definitions of various notions of discernibility and offer a complete classification of their logical relations. Some new and surprising facts are proved; for instance, that weak discernibility corresponds to discernibility in a language with constants for every object, and that weak discernibility is the most discerning nontrivial discernibility relation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Armstrong, D. (1980). Universals and Scientific Realism, Vol. 1. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, A. (2003). Quantitative parsimony and explanatory power. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54(2), 245259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigaj, T., & Ladyman, J. (2010). The principle of the identity of indiscernibles and quantum mechanics. Philosophy of Science, 77, 117136.Google Scholar
Black, M. (1952). The identity of indiscernibles. Mind, 61, 153164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, J. P. (1999). Review of Stewart Shapiro, Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 40(2), 283291.Google Scholar
Caulton, A., & Butterfield, J. (To appear). On kinds of indiscernibility in logic and metaphysics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axr007.Google Scholar
Hawley, K. (2009). Identity and indiscernibility. Mind, 118, 101119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, J., & Sider, T. (2006). Locations. In Hawthorne, J., editor. Metaphysical Essays. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilbert, D., & Bernays, P. (1934). Grundlagen der Mathematik. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Hodges, W. (1997). A Shorter Model Theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Keränen, J. (2001). The identity problem for realist structuralism. Philosophia Mathematica, 9(3), 308330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ketland, J. (2006). Structuralism and the identity of indiscernibles. Analysis, 66(4), 303315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ketland, J. (2011). Identity and indiscernibility. Review of Symbolic Logic, 4(2), 171185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, J. (2005). Mathematical structuralism and the identity of indiscernibles. Analysis, 65(287), 218221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, J. (2007). Scientific structuralism: On the identity and diversity of objects in a structure. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 81(1), 2343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leitgeb, H., & Ladyman, J. (2008). Criteria of identity and structuralist ontology. Philosophia Mathematica, 16(3), 388396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. (2003). Individuation. In Loux, M., and Zimmerman, D., editors. Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, pp. 7595.Google Scholar
MacBride, F. (2006). What constitutes the numerical diversity of mathematical objects? Analysis, 66, 6369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muller, F. A., & Saunders, S. (2008). Discerning fermions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59(3), 499548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muller, F. A., & Seevinck, M. P. (2009). Discerning elementary particles. Philosophy of Science, 76, 179200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1976). Grades of discriminability. Journal of Philosophy, 73(5), 113116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. (1911). On the relation of particulars and universals. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 12, 124. Reprinted in his Logic and Knowledge, ed. R. C. Marsh, London: George Allen & Unwin, 1956.Google Scholar
Saunders, S. (2003). Physics and Leibniz’s principles. In Brading, K., and Castellani, E., editors. Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections. Oxford, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Saunders, S. (2006). Are quantum particles objects? Analysis, 66, 5263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, S. (2006). Structure and identity. In MacBride, F., editor. Identity and Modality. Oxford, UK: Clarendon, pp. 109145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar