Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T20:28:39.668Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

DISJUNCTION AND EXISTENCE PROPERTIES IN MODAL ARITHMETIC

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 December 2022

TAISHI KURAHASHI
Affiliation:
GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SYSTEM INFORMATICS KOBE UNIVERSITY 1-1 ROKKODAI, NADA, KOBE 657-8501, JAPAN E-mail: [email protected]
MOTOKI OKUDA
Affiliation:
INDEPENDENT SCHOLAR
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We systematically study several versions of the disjunction and the existence properties in modal arithmetic. First, we newly introduce three classes $\mathrm {B}$, $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$, and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ of formulas of modal arithmetic and study basic properties of them. Then, we prove several implications between the properties. In particular, among other things, we prove that for any consistent recursively enumerable extension T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ with $T \nvdash \Box \bot $, the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$-disjunction property, the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$-existence property, and the $\mathrm {B}$-existence property are pairwise equivalent. Moreover, we introduce the notion of the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$-soundness of theories and prove that for any consistent recursively enumerable extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$, the modal disjunction property is equivalent to the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$-soundness.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

A theory or a logic T is said to have the disjunction property ( $\mathrm {DP}$ ) if for any sentences $\varphi $ and $\psi $ in the language of T, if $T \vdash \varphi \lor \psi $ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ . This is a property that may be considered to represent the constructivity of intuitionistic logic. Gödel [Reference Gödel and Feferman8] noted that the intuitionistic propositional logic has $\mathrm {DP}$ . Gentzen [Reference Gentzen7] and Kleene [Reference Kleene14] proved that the intuitionistic quantified logic and Heyting arithmetic $\mathbf {HA}$ have $\mathrm {DP}$ , respectively. A property in arithmetic that is related to $\mathrm {DP}$ is the (numerical) existence property. We say that a theory T of arithmetic has the existence property ( $\mathrm {EP}$ ) if for any formula $\varphi (x)$ that has no free variables except  $x$ , if $T \vdash \exists x \varphi (x)$ , then $T \vdash \varphi (\overline {n})$ for some natural number $n$ . Here $\overline {n}$ is the numeral for $n$ . Kleene [Reference Kleene14] also proved that $\mathbf {HA}$ has $\mathrm {EP}$ . Moreover, Friedman [Reference Friedman5] proved that for any recursively enumerable (r.e.) extension T of $\mathbf {HA}$ , T has $\mathrm {DP}$ if and only if T has $\mathrm {EP}$ .

A similar situation has been shown to be true for modal arithmetic. Modal arithmetic is a framework of arithmetic equipped with the unary modal operator $\Box $ . Let $\mathcal {L}_A$ and $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ be the languages of arithmetic and modal arithmetic, respectively. A prominent $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory of modal arithmetic is $\mathbf {EA}$ (epistemic arithmetic) which is obtained by adding $\mathbf {S4}$ into Peano arithmetic $\mathbf {PA}$ . The theory $\mathbf {EA}$ was independently introduced by Shapiro [Reference Shapiro21] and Reinhardt [Reference Reinhardt19, Reference Reinhardt20]. In this framework, $\Box $ is intended to represent knowability or informal provability, and the language $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ has the expressive power to make analyses about these concepts. Moreover, it was shown that $\mathbf {HA}$ is faithfully embeddable into $\mathbf {EA}$ via Gödel’s translation (cf. [Reference Flagg and Friedman4, Reference Goodman9, Reference Shapiro21]). This result verifies Shapiro’s suggestion that $\mathbf {EA}$ is a system about both classical and intuitionistic mathematics. From his suggestion, $\mathbf {EA}$ may possess some constructive properties. A theory or a logic T is said to have the modal disjunction property ( $\mathrm {MDP}$ ) if for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentences $\varphi $ and $\psi $ , if $T \vdash \Box \varphi \lor \Box \psi $ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ . Also, T is said to have the modal existence property ( $\mathrm {MEP}$ ) if for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi (x)$ that has no free variables except $x$ , if $T \vdash \exists x \Box \varphi (x)$ , then $T \vdash \varphi (\overline {n})$ for some natural number $n$ . Then, Shapiro [Reference Shapiro21] proved that $\mathbf {EA}$ has both $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\mathrm {MEP}$ . Moreover, Friedman and Sheard [Reference Friedman and Sheard6] proved that for any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory T extending $\mathbf {EA}$ , T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ if and only if T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ .Footnote 1

In the case of classical logic, $\mathrm {DP}$ is related to the completeness of theories. Indeed, it is easy to see that a consistent theory T based on classical logic has $\mathrm {DP}$ if and only if T is complete. Hence, Gödel–Rosser’s first incompleteness theorem is restated as follows: For any consistent r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}$ , T does not have $\mathrm {DP}$ . In this context, Gödel–Rosser’s first incompleteness theorem can be strengthened. For a class $\Gamma $ of formulas, we say that a theory T has the $\Gamma $ -disjunction property ( $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {DP}$ ) if for any $\Gamma $ sentences $\varphi $ and $\psi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi \lor \psi $ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ . Also, T is said to have the $\Gamma $ -existence property ( $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {EP}$ ) if for any $\Gamma $ formula $\varphi (x)$ that has no free variables except  $x$ , if $T \vdash \exists x \varphi (x)$ , then $T \vdash \varphi (\overline {n})$ for some natural number $n$ . Then, it is shown that for any consistent r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}$ , T does not have $\Pi _1$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ (see [Reference Jensen and Ehrenfeucht13]). On the other hand, for extensions of $\mathbf {PA}$ , a similar situation to that of $\mathrm {DP}$ and $\mathrm {EP}$ in intuitionistic logic has been shown to hold. That is, it is known that $\mathbf {PA}$ has both $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . Moreover, Guaspari [Reference Guaspari10] proved that $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ , and the $\Sigma _1$ -soundness are pairwise equivalent for any consistent r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ .

In the usual proof of the incompleteness theorems, a provability predicate $\mathrm {Pr}_T(x)$ , that is, a $\Sigma _1$ formula weakly representing the provability relation of a theory T plays an important role. Besides the context in which $\Box $ is intended as informal provability, a modal logical study of the notion of formalized provability has been developed by interpreting $\Box $ in terms of $\mathrm {Pr}_T(x)$ . One of the important results of this study is Solovay’s arithmetical completeness theorem which states that if T is $\Sigma _1$ -sound, then the propositional modal logic $\mathbf {GL}$ is exactly the logic of all T-verifiable principles [Reference Solovay22]. In this framework, $\mathrm {MDP}$ also makes sense. It is known that $\mathbf {GL}$ enjoys $\mathrm {MDP}$ . Rather than corresponding to some constructive property, this fact corresponds to the fact that if T is $\Sigma _1$ -sound, then $T \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{T}(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner ) \lor \mathrm {Pr}_{T}(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner )$ implies $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ .

Our motivation for the research in the present paper is to provide a unified viewpoint on $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , which have been discussed in different contexts and frameworks. In particular, we would like to unify the arguments on $\Box $ as an informal provability and $\Box $ as a provability predicate. For this purpose, instead of fixing a modal logic such as $\mathbf {S4}$ or $\mathbf {GL}$ , we discuss the theory $\mathbf {PA}(L)$ obtained by adding an arbitrary normal modal logic L to $\mathbf {PA}$ . In particular, $\mathbf {K4}$ is a common sublogic of $\mathbf {S4}$ and $\mathbf {GL}$ , and thus an investigation for extensions of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ would be applicable to both of the two different interpretations of $\Box $ . For example, we prove that for any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory T extending $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ if and only if T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ . This is a strengthening of the above mentioned form of Friedman and Sheard’s result.

We would also like to analyze the possibility of applying existing methods for studying properties such as $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {DP}$ to modal arithmetic. In particular, as suggested by Guaspari’s result, $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\mathrm {MEP}$ may be characterized by soundness with respect to some class of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas. For this reason, in the present paper, we introduce three new classes $\mathrm {B}$ , $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ , and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas. Then, we prove that for any consistent r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory T extending $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ if and only if T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound. We also provide a systematic analysis of the disjunction and the existence properties in modal arithmetic, including investigations of $\mathrm {DP}$ and $\mathrm {EP}$ concerning these new classes of formulas.

Fig. 1 Implications for consistent r.e. extensions T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ with $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ .

The present paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we introduce several theories of modal arithmetic and show that each of them is a conservative extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ . In Section 3, we introduce three new classes $\mathrm {B}$ , $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ , and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas and show some basic properties of these classes. Section 4 is devoted to the study of $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , and related properties. In Section 5, we study $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and related properties. In particular, we prove that for any r.e. extension T of the theory $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ , if $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , then $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ , and $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ are pairwise equivalent. From this result, the equivalence of $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\mathrm {MEP}$ for any consistent r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory extending $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ is obtained. In Section 6, as generalizations of the notions of the soundness and the $\Sigma _1$ -soundness of $\mathcal {L}_A$ -theories, we introduce the notions of the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness and the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theories. We study these notions precisely, and then, we prove that for any consistent r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ if and only T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound. This is a modal arithmetical analogue of Guaspari’s theorem. Figure 1 summarizes our results obtained in Sections 46. We also show some non-implications between the properties: $\Sigma _1$ -soundness does not imply $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ (Proposition 4.28), $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ does not imply $\mathrm {MDP}$ (Proposition 6.65), and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ does not imply $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ (Proposition 6.66). Finally, in the last section, we list several unsolved problems.

2 Theories of modal arithmetic

We work within the framework of modal arithmetic. The language $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ of modal arithmetic consists of logical connectives $\bot , \land , \lor , \to , \neg $ , quantifiers $\forall , \exists $ , elements of the language $\mathcal {L}_A = \{0, S, +, \times , \leq , =\}$ of first-order arithmetic, and modal operator $\Box $ . The formulas $\varphi \leftrightarrow \psi $ and $\Diamond \varphi $ are abbreviations for $(\varphi \to \psi ) \land (\psi \to \varphi )$ and $\neg \Box \neg \varphi $ , respectively. A set of sentences is called a theory. In the present paper, we always assume that the inference rules of every $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory are modus ponens (MP) $\dfrac {\varphi \to \psi \quad \varphi }{\psi }$ , generalization (Gen) $\dfrac {\varphi }{\forall x \varphi }$ , and necessitation (Nec) $\dfrac {\varphi }{\Box \varphi }$ . Since we will study modal arithmetic from a broader perspective than just $\mathbf {EA}$ , we also deal with $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theories obtained by adding normal modal propositional logics other than $\mathbf {S4}$ into $\mathbf {PA}$ . Let $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ be the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding the logical axioms of first-order logic for $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas and the induction axioms for $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas into $\mathbf {PA}$ . Notice that the value of each $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term $t(\vec {x})$ can be effectively computed from the input $\vec {x}$ , and thus universal instantiation $\forall x \varphi (x) \to \varphi (t)$ (where $t$ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term substitutable for $x$ in $\varphi $ ), which is problematic in modal predicate logic, is not a problem in our framework. As in [Reference Došen3, Reference Friedman and Sheard6, Reference Reinhardt19, Reference Shapiro21], we adopt universal instantiation as an axiom scheme of $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ . Of course, this is not the case in general framework (see [Reference Shapiro21, sec. 7]).

For each normal modal propositional logic L, let $\mathbf {PA}(L)$ denote the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding universal closures of formulas corresponding to modal axioms of L into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ . We deal with the following $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theories.

  • $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) = \mathbf {PA}_{\Box } + \{\forall \vec {x}(\Box (\varphi \to \psi ) \to (\Box \varphi \to \Box \psi )) \mid \varphi , \psi $ are $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas $\}$ ;

  • $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) + \{\forall \vec {x}(\Box \varphi \to \Box \Box \varphi ) \mid \varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\}$ ;

  • $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {KT}) = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) + \{\forall \vec {x}(\Box \varphi \to \varphi ) \mid \varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\}$ ;

  • $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4}) = \mathbf {EA} = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {KT}) + \{\forall \vec {x}(\Box \varphi \to \Box \Box \varphi ) \mid \varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\}$ ;

  • $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S5}) = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4}) + \{\forall \vec {x}(\Diamond \varphi \to \Box \Diamond \varphi ) \mid \varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\}$ ;

  • $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) + \{\forall \vec {x}(\Box \varphi \leftrightarrow \varphi ) \mid \varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\}$ ;

  • $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL}) = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) + \{\forall \vec {x}(\Box (\Box \varphi \to \varphi ) \to \Box \varphi ) \mid \varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\}$ ;

  • $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) + \{\Box \bot \}$ .

Interestingly, Došen [Reference Došen3, Lemma 7] proved that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S5})$ and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ are deductively equivalent.

Here we discuss the principle $x = y \to (\varphi (x) \to \varphi (y))$ of identity. Our system has this principle only for atomic formulas $\varphi (x)$ as identity axioms as in the case of classical first-order logic. On the other hand, this principle for all $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas is not generally valid in our framework because our language has the symbol $\Box $ . Shapiro [Reference Shapiro21] states that the following proposition holds for $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ .

Proposition 2.1.

  1. 1. $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash x = y \to \Box x = y$ .

  2. 2. For any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi (x)$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash x = y \to (\varphi (x) \to \varphi (y))$ .

Proof. 1. Let $\varphi (x, y)$ be the formula $x = y \to \Box x = y$ . Firstly, we prove $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \forall y \varphi (0, y)$ . Since $\mathbf {PA} \vdash 0 = 0$ , we have $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \Box 0 = 0$ , and hence $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi (0, 0)$ . Since $\mathbf {PA} \vdash 0 \neq S(y)$ , we also have $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi (0, S(y))$ , and thus $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \forall y(\varphi (0, y) \to \varphi (0, S(y)))$ . By the induction axiom for $\varphi (0, y)$ , we obtain $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \forall y \varphi (0, y)$ .

Secondly, we prove $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \forall y \varphi (x, y) \to \forall y \varphi (S(x), y)$ . Since $\mathbf {PA} \vdash S(x) \neq 0$ , we have $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi (S(x), 0)$ . It follows from $\mathbf {PA} \vdash S(x) = S(y) \to x = y$ that $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi (x, y) \land S(x) = S(y) \to \Box x = y$ . Since $\mathbf {PA} \vdash x = y \to S(x) = S(y)$ , we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \Box x = y \to \Box S(x) = S(y)$ . Thus, we get

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \varphi(x, y) \land S(x) = S(y) \to \Box S(x) = S(y). \end{align*}$$

This means $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi (x, y) \to \varphi (S(x), S(y))$ . By the universal instantiation, we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \forall y \varphi (x, y) \to \varphi (S(x), S(y))$ , and hence

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \forall y\varphi(x, y) \to \forall y(\varphi(S(x), y) \to \varphi(S(x), S(y))). \end{align*}$$

From this with $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi (S(x), 0)$ , we obtain $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \forall y \varphi (x, y) \to \forall y \varphi (S(x), y)$ by the induction axiom for $\varphi (S(x), y)$ .

Finally, by the induction axiom for $\forall y \varphi (x, y)$ , we conclude $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \forall x \forall y \varphi (x, y)$ .

2. This is proved by induction on the construction of $\varphi (x)$ . We only prove the case that $\varphi (x)$ is of the form $\Box \psi (x)$ and the statement holds for $\psi (x)$ . By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash x = y \to (\psi (x) \to \psi (y))$ . Then, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ proves $\Box x = y \to (\Box \psi (x) \to \Box \psi (y))$ . By combining this with Clause 1, we conclude $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash x = y \to (\Box \psi (x) \to \Box \psi (y))$ .

We say that a theory T is a subtheory of a theory U, $U \vdash T$ , if every axiom of T is provable in U. Makinson’s theorem [Reference Makinson17] states that every consistent normal modal propositional logic L is a sublogic of $\mathbf {Triv}$ or $\mathbf {Verum}$ (see also [Reference Hughes and Cresswell12]). Hence, every $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory of the form $\mathbf {PA}(L)$ for some consistent normal propositional modal logic L is a subtheory of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ or $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ . We prove that every such logic is a conservative extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ .

First, we prove that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ is a conservative extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ . In order to prove this, we introduce a translation $\alpha $ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas into $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formulas.

Definition 2.2 ( $\alpha $ -translation)

We define a translation $\alpha $ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas into $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formulas inductively as follows:

  1. 1. If $\varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formula, then $\alpha (\varphi ) : \equiv \varphi $ .

  2. 2. $\alpha $ preserves logical connectives and quantifiers.

  3. 3. $\alpha (\Box \varphi ) : \equiv \alpha (\varphi )$ .

It is obvious that for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \alpha (\varphi )$ . Moreover:

Proposition 2.3. For any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\varphi )$ .

Proof. We prove the proposition by induction on the length of proofs of $\varphi $ in $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is an axiom of $\mathbf {PA}$ , then $\alpha (\varphi ) \equiv \varphi $ and $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is a logical axiom, then so is $\alpha (\varphi )$ , and it is $\mathbf {PA}$ -provable.

  • If $\varphi $ is an induction axiom in the language $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ , then $\alpha (\varphi )$ is also an induction axiom in $\mathcal {L}_A$ , and so $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x}(\Box (\psi \to \sigma ) \to (\Box \psi \to \Box \sigma ))$ , then $\alpha (\varphi )$ is the $\mathbf {PA}$ -provable sentence $\forall \vec {x} \bigl ((\alpha (\psi ) \to \alpha (\sigma )) \to (\alpha (\psi ) \to \alpha (\sigma )) \bigr )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x} (\psi \leftrightarrow \Box \psi )$ , then $\alpha (\varphi )$ is $\forall \vec {x}(\alpha (\psi ) \leftrightarrow \alpha (\psi ))$ . This is provable in $\mathbf {PA}$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is derived from $\psi $ and $\psi \to \varphi $ by MP, then by the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\psi )$ and $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\psi ) \to \alpha (\varphi )$ , and hence $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is derived from $\psi (x)$ by Gen, then $\varphi \equiv \forall x \psi (x)$ . By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\psi (x))$ and hence $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \forall x \alpha (\psi (x))$ . Therefore, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is derived from $\psi $ by Nec, then $\varphi \equiv \Box \psi $ . By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\psi )$ . Since $\alpha (\varphi ) \equiv \alpha (\psi )$ , we have $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\varphi )$ .

Let $\mathbb {N}$ be the standard model of arithmetic in the language $\mathcal {L}_A$ . We say that an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory T is $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sound if for any $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sentence $\varphi $ , $\mathbb {N} \models \varphi $ whenever $T \vdash \varphi $ .

Corollary 2.4. $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ is a conservative extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ . In particular, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ is $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sound.

Proof. Let $\varphi $ be any $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sentence such that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) \vdash \varphi $ . By Proposition 2.3, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\varphi )$ . Since $\alpha (\varphi ) \equiv \varphi $ , $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \varphi $ . Furthermore, by the $\mathcal {L}_A$ -soundness of $\mathbf {PA}$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ is also $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sound.

Next, we prove that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ is a conservative extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ . We also introduce another translation $\beta $ .

Definition 2.5 ( $\beta $ -translation)

We define a translation $\beta $ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas into $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formulas inductively as follows:

  1. 1. If $\varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formula, then $\beta (\varphi ) : \equiv \varphi $ .

  2. 2. $\beta $ preserves logical connectives and quantifiers.

  3. 3. $\beta (\Box \varphi ) : \equiv 0=0$ .

As in the case of $\alpha $ , for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \beta (\varphi )$ . Moreover:

Proposition 2.6. For any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \beta (\varphi )$ .

Proof. As in the proof of Proposition 2.3, this proposition is proved by induction on the length of proofs of $\varphi $ in $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ . We only give proofs of the following three cases:

  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x}(\Box (\psi \to \sigma ) \to (\Box \psi \to \Box \sigma ))$ , then $\beta (\varphi )$ is the $\mathbf {PA}$ -provable sentence $\forall \vec {x} (0=0 \to (0=0 \to 0=0))$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is $\Box \bot $ , then $\beta (\varphi )$ is the $\mathbf {PA}$ -provable sentence $0=0$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is derived from $\psi $ by Nec, then $\varphi \equiv \Box \psi $ . Since $\beta (\varphi ) \equiv 0=0$ , this is $\mathbf {PA}$ -provable.

Corollary 2.7. $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ is a conservative extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ . In particular, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ is $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sound.

We close this section by showing that the notion of $\Sigma _1$ formulas has a high affinity with modal arithmetic. The following theorem is proved by applying a schematic proof of formalized $\Sigma _1$ -completeness theorem (see [Reference Buchholz2, Reference Kurahashi16, Reference Rautenberg18]). This is also implicitly stated in [Reference Friedman and Sheard6].

Theorem 2.8 (Formalized $\Sigma _1$ -completeness theorem)

For any $\Sigma _1$ formula $\varphi $ , we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ .

Proof. Before proving the theorem, we show that for any $\Sigma _1$ formula $\psi $ , there exists a $\Sigma _1$ formula $\psi '$ such that $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \psi \leftrightarrow \psi '$ , $\psi '$ does not contain the connectives $\neg $ and $\to $ , and every atomic formula contained in $\psi '$ is of the form $t_1 = t_2$ for some $\mathcal {L}_A$ -terms $t_1$ and $t_2$ . First, we easily find a $\Sigma _1$ formula $\psi _0$ without the connective $\to $ such that $\psi _0$ is logically equivalent to $\psi $ and every negation symbol $\neg $ in $\psi _0$ is applied to an atomic formula. Then, by replacing every negated atomic formula $\neg (t_1 = t_2)$ or $\neg (t_1 < t_2)$ of $\psi_0$ by $t_1 < t_2 \lor t_2 < t_1$ or $t_1 = t_2 \lor t_2 < t_1$ respectively, we obtain a $\mathbf {PA}$ -equivalent $\Sigma _1$ formula $\psi _1$ without having $\neg $ . Finally, by replacing every atomic formula $t_1 < t_2$ of $\psi _1$ by $\exists y(t_1 + S(y) = t_2)$ , we obtain a required equivalent $\Sigma _1$ formula $\psi '$ . Since $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \Box \psi \leftrightarrow \Box \psi '$ , to prove the theorem, it suffices to show that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ for any $\Sigma _1$ formula $\varphi $ such that it does not contain the connectives $\neg $ and $\to $ , and that every atomic formula contained in $\varphi $ is of the form $t_1 = t_2$ for some $\mathcal {L}_A$ -terms $t_1$ and $t_2$ .

This theorem is proved by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ . If $\varphi $ is $t_1 = t_2$ , then $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash t_1 = t_2 \to \Box t_1 = t_2$ follows from $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash x = y \to \Box x = y$ (Proposition 2.1) by substituting $t_1$ and $t_2$ into $x$ and y, respectively. The cases for $\land $ , $\lor $ , $\forall x < t$ and $\exists $ are proved as in the proof of Theorem 3.13.

3 Classes of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas

In first-order arithmetic, it is important to classify $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formulas according to the arithmetic hierarchy. In this section, we introduce three classes $\mathrm {B}$ , $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ , and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas, and investigate basic properties of formulas in these classes. Our classes $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ are modal arithmetical counterparts of $\Delta _0$ and $\Sigma _1$ , respectively.

Definition 3.9 ( $\mathrm {B}$ , $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ , and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ )

  • Let $\mathrm {B}$ be the class of all $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas of the form $\Box \varphi $ .

  • Let $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ be the smallest class of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas satisfying the following conditions:

    1. 1. $\Delta _0 \cup \mathrm {B} \subseteq \Delta (\mathrm {B})$ .

    2. 2. If $\varphi $ and $\psi $ are in $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ , then so are $\varphi \land \psi $ , $\varphi \lor \psi $ , $\forall x < t\, \varphi $ and $\exists x < t\, \varphi $ , where $t$ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term in which $x$ does not occur.

  • Let $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ be the smallest class of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas satisfying the following conditions:

    1. 1. $\Sigma _1 \cup \mathrm {B} \subseteq \Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ .

    2. 2. If $\varphi $ and $\psi $ are in $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ , then so are $\varphi \land \psi $ , $\varphi \lor \psi $ , $\exists x \varphi $ and $\forall x < t\, \varphi $ , where $t$ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term in which $x$ does not occur.

We emphasize here that in some sense the class $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ is a natural extension of the class $\Sigma _1$ . For each r.e. theory T, let $\mathrm {Pr}_T(x)$ be a fixed $\Sigma _1$ provability predicate of T. In the context of interpreting $\Box $ by $\mathrm {Pr}_T(x)$ , each $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula of the form $\Box \varphi $ is interpreted by a $\Sigma _1$ formula, and hence every $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ formula is also recognized as a $\Sigma _1$ formula. From this perspective, we will attempt to extend the properties possessed by $\Sigma _1$ formulas in first-order arithmetic to $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ formulas in modal arithmetic. Note, however, that $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ , unlike $\Delta _0$ , is not closed under taking negation and implication. For example, it can be shown that there is no $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ such that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \neg \Box \bot \leftrightarrow \varphi $ (see Corollary 3.12).

The following proposition states that the relationship between $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ and $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ is similar to the relationship between $\Sigma _1$ and $\Delta _0$ .

Proposition 3.10. For any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\varphi $ , there exist a variable $v $ and a $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\psi $ such that $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \exists v \psi $ .

Proof. We prove the proposition by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is $\Sigma _1$ , then there exists a $\Delta _0$ formula $\psi $ such that $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \exists v \psi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \varphi _0$ , then $\varphi \in \Delta (\mathrm {B})$ and $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \exists v \varphi $ for a variable $v $ not contained in $\varphi $ .

  • Let $\circ \in \{\land , \lor \}$ . If $\varphi $ is of the form $\varphi _0 \circ \varphi _1$ , then by the induction hypothesis, there exist distinct variables $v_0$ and $v_1$ and $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formulas $\psi _0$ and $\psi _1$ such that $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ proves $\varphi _0 \leftrightarrow \exists v_0 \psi _0$ and $\varphi _1 \leftrightarrow \exists v_1 \psi _1$ . Let $v $ be any variable that does not occur in $\psi _0$ or $\psi _1$ , and is not $v_0$ or $v_1$ . Then, $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ proves the equivalence $\varphi \leftrightarrow \exists v \, \exists v_0 < v \, \exists v_1 < v \, (\psi _0 \circ \psi _1)$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\exists x \varphi _0$ , then by the induction hypothesis, there exist a variable $v_0$ and a $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\psi _0$ such that $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \varphi _0 \leftrightarrow \exists v_0 \psi _0$ . Let $v $ be any variable not contained in $\psi _0$ and is not $v_0$ or $x$ . Then, $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ proves the equivalence $\varphi \leftrightarrow \exists v \, \exists x < v \, \exists v_0 < v \, \psi _0$ .

  • The case that $\varphi $ is of the form $\exists x < t\, \varphi _0$ , where $t$ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term in which $x$ does not occur is proved as in the proof of the case of $\exists $ .

  • Suppose $\varphi $ is of the form $\forall x < t\, \varphi _0$ , where $t$ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term in which $x$ does not occur. By the induction hypothesis, there exists a variable $v_0$ and a $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\psi _0$ such that $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi _0 \leftrightarrow \exists v_0 \psi _0$ . Then, $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \forall x < t\, \exists v_0 \psi _0$ . By the collection principle for $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas derived from the induction axioms for $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas, we obtain

    $$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}_{\Box} \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \exists v\, \forall x < t\, \exists v_0 < v\, \psi_0 \end{align*}$$
    for some appropriate variable $v $ .

Proposition 3.11. For any $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ , there exist a natural number $k$ and sentences $\psi _0, \ldots , \psi _{k-1}$ such that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{i < k} \Box \psi _i$ . Here $\bigvee _{i < 0} \Box \psi _i$ denotes $\bot $ .

Proof. We prove the proposition by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is a $\Delta _0$ sentence, then either $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \varphi $ or $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \neg \varphi $ . Thus, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \Box 0=0$ or $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \bot $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ , then the statement is trivial.

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\psi \land \sigma $ , then there exist sentences $\xi _0, \ldots , \xi _{k-1}, \eta _0, \ldots , \eta _{l-1}$ such that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \psi \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{i < k} \Box \xi _i$ and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \sigma \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{j < l} \Box \eta _j$ . Then, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{i < k} \bigvee _{j < l} \Box (\xi _i \land \eta _j)$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\psi \lor \sigma $ , then the statement is obvious by the induction hypothesis.

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\exists y < t\, \psi (y)$ for some $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term $t$ , then $t$ is a closed term because $\varphi $ is a sentence. Let m be the value of $t$ , then $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{i < m} \psi (\overline {i})$ . Then, the statement holds by the induction hypothesis.

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\forall y < t\, \psi (y)$ for some closed $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term $t$ , then for the value m of the term $t$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \bigwedge _{i < m} \psi (\overline {i})$ . We can prove the statement by the induction hypothesis as in the proof of the case $\land $ .

Corollary 3.12. Let T be a theory extending $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ such that $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ and $T \nvdash \neg \Box \bot $ . Then, there is no $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ such that $T \vdash \neg \Box \bot \leftrightarrow \varphi $ .

Proof. Suppose, towards a contradiction, that $\varphi $ is a $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentence such that $T \vdash \neg \Box \bot \leftrightarrow \varphi $ . By Proposition 3.11, there exist $k$ and $\psi _0, \ldots , \psi _{k-1}$ such that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{i < k} \Box \psi _i$ . Then, $T \vdash \neg \Box \bot \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{i < k} \Box \psi _i$ . Since $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , we get $k> 0$ . Then, $T \vdash \Box \psi _0 \to \neg \Box \bot $ . On the other hand, $T \vdash \neg \Box \psi _0 \to \neg \Box \bot $ because T is an extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ . Therefore, we obtain $T \vdash \neg \Box \bot $ . This is a contradiction.

We naturally extend Theorem 2.8 into the framework of modal arithmetic.

Theorem 3.13 (Formalized $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -completeness theorem)

For any $\varphi \in \Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ .

Proof. We prove the theorem by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is a $\Sigma _1$ formula, then $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ by Theorem 2.8.

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ , then $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is $\psi \land \sigma $ , then by the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \psi \land \Box \sigma $ . We have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is $\psi \lor \sigma $ , then by the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ proves $\psi \to \Box (\psi \lor \sigma )$ and $\sigma \to \Box (\psi \lor \sigma )$ . Hence, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ .

  • Suppose that $\varphi $ is $\exists x \psi $ . Since $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \psi \to \exists x \psi $ , we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \Box \psi \to \Box \exists x \psi $ . By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf{K4}) \vdash \psi \to \Box \psi $ . Thus, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf{K4}) \vdash \psi \to \Box \exists x \psi $ . Then, we obtain $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ .

  • Before proving the case that $\varphi $ is of the form $\forall x < t\, \psi (x)$ generally, we prove the restricted case that $t$ is some variable y not occurring in $\psi $ . Suppose that $\varphi (y)$ is of the form $\forall x < y\, \psi (x)$ for some variable y not occurring in $\psi (x)$ . Let $\xi (y)$ be the formula $\varphi (y) \to \Box \varphi (y)$ , and then we prove $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \forall y \xi (y)$ by using the induction axiom.

    For the base step, since trivially $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \forall x < 0\, \psi (x)$ , we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \Box \varphi (0)$ and hence $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \xi (0)$ .

    For the induction step, since

    $$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash [\forall x < S(y)\, \psi(x)] \leftrightarrow [(\forall x < y\, \psi(x)) \land \psi(y)], \end{align*}$$
    we have
    (1) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \varphi(S(y)) \leftrightarrow [\varphi(y) \land \psi(y)]. \end{align} $$
    By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \psi (y) \to \Box \psi (y)$ . By combining this with (1) and the definition of $\xi (y)$ ,
    $$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K4}) \vdash \xi(y) \land \varphi(S(y)) \to \Box \varphi(y) \land \Box \psi(y). \end{align*}$$
    Then, by (1) again,
    $$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K4}) \vdash \xi(y) \land \varphi(S(y)) \to \Box \varphi(S(y)). \end{align*}$$
    Equivalently, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \xi (y) \to \xi (S(y))$ .

    Therefore, by the induction axiom, we conclude $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \forall y \xi (y)$ .

    Finally, suppose that $\varphi $ is of the form $\forall x < t\, \psi $ for some $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term $t$ . We have already proved that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ proves $\forall x < y\, \psi \to \Box \forall x < y\, \psi $ for some variable y not occurring in $\psi $ . By substituting $t$ for y in this formula, we obtain $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box \varphi $ .

Corollary 3.14 ( $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -deduction theorem)

Let T be any extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ and let X be any set of $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentences. Then, for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $T + X \vdash \varphi $ , then there exist $\sigma _0, \ldots , \sigma _{k-1} \in X$ such that $T \vdash \sigma _0 \land \cdots \land \sigma _{k-1} \to \varphi $ .

Proof. This is proved by induction on the length of a proof of $\varphi $ in $T + X$ . We only give a proof of the case that $\varphi $ is derived from $\psi $ by the rule Nec. Then, $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ . By the induction hypothesis, $T \vdash \sigma _0 \land \cdots \land \sigma _{k-1} \to \psi $ for some $\sigma _0, \ldots , \sigma _{k-1} \in X$ . Then, $T \vdash \Box \sigma _0 \land \cdots \land \Box \sigma _{k-1} \to \Box \psi $ . By Theorem 3.13, $T \vdash \sigma _0 \land \cdots \land \sigma _{k-1} \to \Box \psi $ .

4 $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and related properties

We introduce several versions of the partial disjunction property.

Definition 4.15. Let T be a theory and let $\Gamma $ and $\Theta $ be classes of formulas.

  • T is said to have the modal disjunction property ( $\mathrm {MDP}$ ) if for any sentences $\varphi $ and $\psi $ , if $T \vdash \Box \varphi \lor \Box \psi $ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ .

  • T is said to have the modal existence property ( $\mathrm {MEP}$ ) if for any formula $\varphi (x)$ that has no free variables except $x$ , if $T \vdash \exists x \Box \varphi (x)$ , then for some natural number  $n$ , $T \vdash \varphi (\overline {n})$ .

  • T is said to have the $\Gamma $ -disjunction property ( $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {DP}$ ) if for any $\Gamma $ sentences $\varphi $ and $\psi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi \lor \psi $ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ .

  • T is said to have the $\Gamma $ -existence property ( $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {EP}$ ) if for any $\Gamma $ formula $\varphi (x)$ that has no free variables except $x$ , if $T \vdash \exists x \varphi (x)$ , then for some natural number $n$ , $T \vdash \varphi (\overline {n})$ .

  • T is said to have the $(\Gamma , \Theta )$ -disjunction property ( $(\Gamma , \Theta )$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ ) if for any $\Gamma $ sentence $\varphi $ and any $\Theta $ sentence $\psi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi \lor \psi $ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ .

  • For $n \geq 2$ , T is said to have the $n$ -fold $\mathrm {B}$ -disjunction property ( $\mathrm {B}^n$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ ) if for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentences $\varphi _1, \ldots , \varphi _n$ , if $T \vdash \Box \varphi _1 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi _n$ , then $T \vdash \Box \varphi _i$ for some $i \ (1 \leq i \leq n)$ .

  • If T is r.e., then T is said to be $\Gamma $ -disjunctively correct ( $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {DC}$ ) if for any $\Gamma $ sentence $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi \lor \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner )$ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ .

  • We say that T is closed under the box elimination rule if for any sentence $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \Box \varphi $ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ .

Here $\mathrm {Pr}_T(x)$ is a fixed natural $\Sigma _1$ provability predicate of T. We also fix a primitive recursive proof predicate $\mathrm {Prf}_T(x, y)$ of T saying that y encodes a T-proof of $x$ , whose existence is guaranteed by Craig’s trick.

Of course, $(\Gamma , \Gamma )$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and $\mathrm {B}^2$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ are exactly $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , respectively. The notion of $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {DC}$ was introduced in [Reference Kurahashi15]. It is known that for any consistent r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}$ , T is $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ if and only if T is $\Sigma _1$ -sound (cf. [Reference Kurahashi15]).

Proposition 4.16. Let T be any extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ .

  1. 1. For any $n \geq 2$ , if T has $\mathrm {B}^{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , then T also has $\mathrm {B}^n$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

  2. 2. T has $\mathrm {B}^n$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ for all $n \geq 2$ if and only if T has $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proof. 1. Let $\varphi _1, \ldots , \varphi _n$ be any sentences such that $T \vdash \Box \varphi _1 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi _n$ . Then, $T \vdash \Box \varphi _1 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi _n \lor \Box \varphi _n$ . By $\mathrm {B}^{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , for some i ( $1 \leq i \leq n$ ), we have $T \vdash \Box \varphi _i$ .

2. $(\Rightarrow )$ : Let $\varphi $ and $\psi $ be any $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentences such that $T \vdash \varphi \lor \psi $ . By Proposition 3.11, there exist sentences $\varphi _0, \ldots , \varphi _{k-1}$ and $\psi _0, \ldots , \psi _{l-1}$ such that $T \vdash \varphi \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{i < k} \Box \varphi _i$ and ${T \vdash \psi \leftrightarrow \bigvee _{j < l} \Box \psi _j}$ . Then, $T \vdash \bigvee _{i < k} \Box \varphi _i \lor \bigvee _{j < l} \Box \psi _j$ . If $k = 0$ or $l = 0$ , then we easily obtain $T \vdash \varphi $ or ${T \vdash \psi} $ . Thus, we may assume both $k$ and l are larger than  $0$ . Then, $k+l \geq 2$ . By $\mathrm {B}^{k+l}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , there exists $i < k$ or $j < l$ such that $T \vdash \Box \varphi _i$ or ${T \vdash \Box \psi _j}$ . Then, we obtain that $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ .

$(\Leftarrow )$ : We prove this implication by induction on $n \geq 2$ . Since $\mathrm {B} \subseteq \Delta (\mathrm {B})$ , T has $\mathrm {B}^2$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . Suppose that T has $\mathrm {B}^n$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and we would like to prove that T also has $\mathrm {B}^{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . Let $\varphi _1, \ldots , \varphi _n, \varphi _{n+1}$ be any sentences such that $T \vdash \Box \varphi _1 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi _n \lor \Box \varphi _{n+1}$ . Since both $\Box \varphi _1 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi _n$ and $\Box \varphi _{n+1}$ are $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentences, we have $T \vdash \Box \varphi _1 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi _n$ or $T \vdash \Box \varphi _{n+1}$ by $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . In the former case, we obtain $T \vdash \Box \varphi _i$ for some i ( $1 \leq i \leq n$ ) by the induction hypothesis. We have proved that T has $\mathrm {B}^{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

The following proposition is immediate from the definitions.

Proposition 4.17. Let T be any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory.

  1. 1. T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ if and only if T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and is closed under the box elimination rule.

  2. 2. T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ if and only if T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ and is closed under the box elimination rule.

We show that each existence property yields the corresponding disjunction property.

Proposition 4.18. Let T be any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory.

  1. 1. If T is an extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ and T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ (resp. $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ ), then T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ (resp. $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ ).

  2. 2. If T has $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ (resp. $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ ), then T has $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ (resp. $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ ).

Proof. We only give a proof of Clause 1 for $\mathrm {MEP}$ and $\mathrm {MDP}$ . Let $\varphi $ and $\psi $ be any sentences such that $T \vdash \Box \varphi \lor \Box \psi $ . Then, $T \vdash \exists x \Box \bigl ((x = 0 \land \varphi ) \lor (x \neq 0 \land \psi ) \bigr )$ . By $\mathrm {MEP}$ , there exists a natural number $n$ such that $T \vdash (\overline {n} = 0 \land \varphi ) \lor (\overline {n} \neq 0 \land \psi )$ . If $n=0$ , $T \vdash \varphi $ ; if $n \neq 0$ , $T \vdash \psi $ . Therefore, T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ .

In the literature so far, modal disjunction and existence properties in modal arithmetic have been considered only for theories which are closed under the box elimination rule. As shown in Proposition 4.17, if T is closed under the box elimination rule, then $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ are equivalent. Hence, $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ have often been identified in the literature. Since the present paper also deals with theories that are not necessarily closed under the box elimination rule, we distinguish between $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . In fact, as Figure 1 shows, there seems to be a large gap between the strength of these properties.

We explore nontrivial implications between $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $(\Delta (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ , $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , and $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

Lemma 4.19. Let T be any r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ having $\mathrm {B}^{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . Then, for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentences $\varphi _1, \ldots , \varphi _n$ and $\Sigma _1$ sentence $\sigma $ , if $T \vdash \Box \varphi _1 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi _n \lor \sigma $ , then $T \vdash \Box \varphi _i$ for some $i \ (1 \leq i \leq n)$ or $T \vdash \sigma $ .

Proof. Suppose $T \vdash \Box \varphi _1 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi _n \lor \sigma $ and $T \nvdash \sigma $ , and we would like to show $T \vdash \Box \varphi _i$ for some i. We may assume that $\sigma $ is of the form $\exists x \delta (x)$ for some $\Delta _0$ formula $\delta (x)$ . Then, $\mathbb {N} \models \forall x \neg \delta (x)$ because $T \nvdash \sigma $ . By the Fixed Point Lemma, for each i with $1 \leq i \leq n$ , let $\psi _i^0$ and $\psi _i^1$ be $\Sigma _1$ sentences satisfying the following equivalences:

  • $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \psi _i^0 \leftrightarrow \exists x \Bigl ( \bigl (\delta (x) \lor \mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \Box \psi _i^1\urcorner , x) \bigr ) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \Box (\varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0)\urcorner , y) \Bigr )$ ,

  • $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \psi _i^1 \phantom{\quad}\leftrightarrow \exists y \Bigl (\mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \Box (\varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0)\urcorner , y) \land \forall x \leq y \, \bigl (\neg \delta (x) \land \neg \mathrm {Prf}_T (\ulcorner \Box \psi _i^1\urcorner , x) \bigr ) \Bigr )$ .

Then, for each i, we get $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \sigma \to \psi _i^0 \lor \psi _i^1$ . Hence, we have

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA} \vdash \sigma \to \psi_1^0 \lor \cdots \lor \psi_n^0 \lor (\psi_1^1 \land \cdots \land \psi_n^1). \end{align*}$$

By Theorem 2.8,

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \sigma \to \Box \psi_1^0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \psi_n^0 \lor \Box (\psi_1^1 \land \cdots \land \psi_n^1). \end{align*}$$

Hence,

(2) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \sigma \to \Box (\varphi_1 \lor \psi_1^0) \lor \cdots \lor \Box (\varphi_n \lor \psi_n^0) \lor \Box (\psi_1^1 \land \cdots \land \psi_n^1). \end{align} $$

On the other hand, for each i, we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \Box \varphi _i \to \Box (\varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0)$ . From our supposition, we obtain

$$\begin{align*}T \vdash \Box (\varphi_1 \lor \psi_1^0) \lor \cdots \lor \Box (\varphi_n \lor \psi_n^0) \lor \sigma. \end{align*}$$

By combining this with (2),

$$\begin{align*}T \vdash \Box (\varphi_1 \lor \psi_1^0) \lor \cdots \lor \Box (\varphi_n \lor \psi_n^0) \lor \Box (\psi_1^1 \land \cdots \land \psi_n^1). \end{align*}$$

By $\mathrm {B}^{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , we have $T \vdash \Box (\varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0)$ for some i or $T \vdash \Box (\psi _1^1 \land \cdots \land \psi _n^1)$ . If $T \vdash \Box (\psi _1^1 \land \cdots \land \psi _n^1)$ , then $T \vdash \Box \psi _i^1$ for each i.

  • If $T \vdash \Box (\varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0)$ and $T \nvdash \Box \psi _i^1$ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \psi _i^1$ by the choice of $\psi _i^1$ because $\mathbb {N} \models \forall x \neg \delta (x)$ . Thus, $T \vdash \psi _i^1$ by $\Sigma _1$ -completeness, and hence $T \vdash \Box \psi _i^1$ . This is a contradiction.

  • If $T \vdash \Box \psi _i^1$ and $T \nvdash \Box (\varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0)$ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \psi _i^0$ , and hence $T \vdash \psi _i^0$ . Thus, $T \vdash \varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0$ and hence $T \vdash \Box (\varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0)$ , a contradiction.

We have shown that in either case, for some i, both $\Box (\varphi _i \lor \psi _i^0)$ and $\Box \psi _i^1$ are provable in T. Since $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \psi _i^1 \to \neg \psi _i^0$ , we have $T \vdash \Box \neg \psi _i^0$ for such an i. Therefore, we conclude $T \vdash \Box \varphi _i$ .

From Propositions 3.11 and 4.16 and Lemma 4.19, we obtain the following proposition.

Proposition 4.20. Let T be any r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ .

  1. 1. If T has $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , then T has $(\Delta (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

  2. 2. If T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , then T has $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proposition 4.21. Let T be any r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ with $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ . If T has $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , then T is $\Sigma _1$ -sound.

Proof. We prove the contrapositive. Suppose that $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ and T is not $\Sigma _1$ -sound. Then, there exists a $\Delta _0$ formula $\delta (x)$ such that $T \vdash \exists x \delta (x)$ and $\mathbb {N} \models \forall x \neg \delta (x)$ . Let $\sigma _0$ and $\sigma _1$ be $\Sigma _1$ sentences satisfying the following equivalences:

  • $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \sigma _0 \leftrightarrow \exists x \Bigl ( \bigl (\delta (x) \lor \mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \sigma _1\urcorner , x) \bigr ) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \Box \sigma _0\urcorner , y) \Bigr )$ .

  • $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \sigma _1 \leftrightarrow \exists y \Bigl (\mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \Box \sigma _0\urcorner , y) \land \forall x \leq y \, \bigl (\neg \delta (x) \land \neg \mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \sigma _1\urcorner , x) \bigr ) \Bigr )$ .

Since $T \vdash \exists x \delta (x)$ , we have $T \vdash \sigma _0 \lor \sigma _1$ . Therefore, $T \vdash (\Box \sigma _0) \lor \sigma _1$ by Theorem 2.8.

Suppose, towards a contradiction, that $T \vdash \Box \sigma _0$ or $T \vdash \sigma _1$ . Let p be the smallest T-proof of $\Box \sigma _0$ or $\sigma _1$ . If p is a proof of $\Box \sigma _0$ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \sigma _1$ by the choice of $\sigma _1$ . Hence, $T \vdash \sigma _1$ and thus $T \vdash \Box \sigma _1$ . Since $T \vdash \sigma _0 \land \sigma _1 \to \bot $ , we have $T \vdash \Box \bot $ because $T \vdash \Box \sigma _0 \land \Box \sigma _1$ . This is a contradiction. If p is a proof of $\sigma _1$ , then it is shown $T \vdash \sigma _0$ . This contradicts the consistency of T. Thus, we have shown that $T \nvdash \Box \sigma _0$ and $T \nvdash \sigma _1$ . This means that T does not have $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proposition 4.22. Let T be any consistent r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ with $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ and let $\Gamma $ be a class of formulas with $\mathrm {B} \subseteq \Gamma $ . If T has $(\Gamma , \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , then T is $\Gamma $ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

Proof. Suppose that T has $(\Gamma , \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . Let $\varphi $ be any $\Gamma $ sentence such that $T \vdash \varphi \lor \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner )$ . By $(\Gamma , \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner )$ . Since $\mathrm {B} \subseteq \Gamma $ , by Proposition 4.21, T is $\Sigma _1$ -sound. Thus, in either case, we obtain $T \vdash \varphi $ .

The converse implication also holds when $\Gamma $ is $\mathrm {B}$ or $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ . In order to prove this, we generalize the Fixed Point Lemma to modal arithmetic. It is proved by repeating a well-known proof, and so we omit it (see [Reference Boolos1]).

Lemma 4.23 (The Fixed Point Lemma)

For any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas $\varphi _0(x_0, \ldots , x_{k-1})$ , $\ldots $ , $\varphi _{k-1}(x_0, \ldots , x_{k-1})$ with only the free variables $x_0, \ldots , x_{k-1}$ , we can effectively find $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentences $\psi _0, \ldots , \psi _{k-1}$ such that for each $i < k$ ,

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}_{\Box} \vdash \psi_i \leftrightarrow \varphi_i(\ulcorner\psi_0\urcorner, \ldots, \ulcorner\psi_{k-1}\urcorner). \end{align*}$$

Moreover, for each $i < k$ , if $\varphi _i(x_0, \ldots , x_{k-1})$ is a $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ formula, then such a $\psi _i$ can be found as a $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence.

Proposition 4.24. Let T be any r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ .

  1. 1. If T is $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ , then T has $(\Delta (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

  2. 2. If T is $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ , then T has $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proof. We prove only Clause 1. Clause 2 is proved similarly. Suppose that T is $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ . Let $\varphi $ be any $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentence and let $\delta (x)$ be any $\Delta _0$ formula such that $T \vdash \varphi \lor \exists x \delta (x)$ and $T \nvdash \exists x \delta (x)$ . We would like to show $T \vdash \varphi $ . In this case, $\mathbb {N} \models \forall x \neg \delta (x)$ . By Proposition 3.11, we may assume that $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi _0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \psi _{k-1}$ . By the Fixed Point Lemma, let $\xi _0, \ldots , \xi _{k-1}$ be $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentences satisfying the following equivalences for all $i < k$ :

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}_{\Box} \vdash \xi_i \leftrightarrow \Bigl[\psi_i \lor \exists x \bigl(\delta(x) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner, y) \bigr)\Bigr]. \end{align*}$$

Since $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \psi _i \to \xi _i$ , we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \Box \psi _i \to \Box \xi _i$ . Also,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \exists x \delta(x) \land & \neg \mathrm{Pr}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner) \\ & \ \ \ \to \exists x \bigl(\delta(x) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner, y) \bigr), \\ & \ \ \ \to \mathrm{Pr}_T \Bigl(\ulcorner\exists x \bigl(\delta(x) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner, y) \bigr)\urcorner \Bigr), \\ & \ \ \ \to \mathrm{Pr}_T(\ulcorner\xi_i\urcorner). \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \xi _i\urcorner ) \to \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \Box \xi _i\urcorner )$ because $\mathbf {PA}$ can prove that the consequences of T are closed under the rule Nec, we obtain $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \xi _i\urcorner ) \to \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \Box \xi _0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi _{k-1}\urcorner )$ . Thus, we have

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \bigl[\exists x \delta(x) \land \neg \mathrm{Pr}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner) \bigr] \to \mathrm{Pr}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner), \end{align*}$$

and hence

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \exists x \delta(x) \to \mathrm{Pr}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner). \end{align*}$$

Then, by combining this with our assumption that $T \vdash \Box \psi _0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \psi _{k-1} \lor \exists x \delta (x)$ , we obtain

$$\begin{align*}T \vdash \Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1} \lor \mathrm{Pr}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner). \end{align*}$$

By $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ , we have

(3) $$ \begin{align} T \vdash \Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}. \end{align} $$

Since

$$\begin{align*}\mathbb{N} \models \exists y \bigl(\mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner, y) \land \forall x \leq y \, \neg \delta(x) \bigr), \end{align*}$$

this sentence is provable in $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ . Thus,

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}(\mathbf{K}) \vdash \neg \exists x \bigl(\delta(x) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\Box \xi_0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \xi_{k-1}\urcorner, y) \bigr). \end{align*}$$

Then, by the choice of $\xi _i$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \xi _i \to \psi _i$ for each i. From (3), we conclude $T \vdash \Box \psi _0 \lor \cdots \lor \Box \psi _{k-1}$ and hence $T \vdash \varphi $ .

In the statements of Propositions 4.21 and 4.22, the condition “ $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ ” is assumed. On the other hand, for consistent theories T with $T \vdash \Box \bot $ , the situation changes. Indeed, every $\mathrm {B}$ formula is provable in such a theory T. Thus, T does not have $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\mathrm {MEP}$ . Also, every $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formula is T-provably equivalent to some $\Delta _0$ formula. Moreover, every $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ is either provable or refutable in T. Therefore, we obtain the following proposition.

Proposition 4.25. Let T be any extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ . Then, T has $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $(\Delta (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , and $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . Also, T is $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

From Propositions 4.22, 4.24, and 4.25, we have:

Corollary 4.26. Let T be any consistent r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ .

  1. 1. If $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , then T has $(\Delta (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ if and only if T is $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

  2. 2. T has $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ if and only if T is $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

For consistent r.e. extensions of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ , $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ is strictly weaker than $\Sigma _1$ -soundness.

Proposition 4.27. Let T be any consistent r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ . Then, the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. T is $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

  2. 2. $T \nvdash \neg \mathrm {Con}_T$ .

Proof. $(1 \Rightarrow 2)$ : Suppose that T is $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ . Since $T \nvdash \bot $ , we obtain $T \nvdash \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \bot \urcorner ) \lor \bot $ . Hence, $T \nvdash \neg \mathrm {Con}_T$ .

$(2 \Rightarrow 1)$ : Suppose $T \nvdash \neg \mathrm {Con}_T$ . Let $\varphi $ be any $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentence with $T \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner ) \lor \varphi $ . If $T \vdash \neg \varphi $ , then $\varphi $ is T-equivalent to $\bot $ . We have $T \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \bot \urcorner ) \lor \bot $ , and so $T \vdash \neg \mathrm {Con}_T$ . This is a contradiction. Therefore, $T \vdash \varphi $ .

There are $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sound theories that do not have even $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proposition 4.28.

  1. 1. $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ does not have $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

  2. 2. Let T be any r.e. theory such that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) \vdash T \vdash \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ and let $U : = T + \{\mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \Box \bot \urcorner ) \lor \Box \bot \}$ . If $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , then U is $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sound but is not $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

Proof. 1. Let $\varphi $ be a $\Pi _1$ Gödel sentence of $\mathbf {PA}$ . Since $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \varphi \lor \neg \varphi $ , we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) \vdash \Box \varphi \lor \neg \varphi $ . Since $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ is a conservative extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ (Corollary 2.4), $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) \nvdash \varphi $ and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) \nvdash \neg \varphi $ . Then, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) \nvdash \Box \varphi $ and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv}) \nvdash \neg \varphi $ .

2. Since U is a subtheory of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ , U is $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sound by Corollary 2.7. Since $U \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{T}(\ulcorner \Box \bot \urcorner ) \lor \Box \bot $ , we have $U \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_U(\ulcorner \Box \bot \urcorner ) \lor \Box \bot $ . Suppose, towards a contradiction, $U \vdash \Box \bot $ . Since $\mathrm {Pr}_{T}(\ulcorner \Box \bot \urcorner ) \lor \Box \bot $ is a $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence, $T \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{T}(\ulcorner \Box \bot \urcorner ) \lor \Box \bot \to \Box \bot $ by the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -deduction theorem (Corollary 3.14). In particular, $T \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{T}(\ulcorner \Box \bot \urcorner ) \to \Box \bot $ . By Löb’s theorem, $T \vdash \Box \bot $ . This is a contradiction. Therefore, $U \nvdash \Box \bot $ . Hence, U is not $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

5 $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and related properties

First of all, we consider the case that T proves $\Box \bot $ .

Proposition 5.29. Let T be any consistent r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ . Then, the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. T is $\Sigma _1$ -sound.

  2. 2. T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

  3. 3. T has $(\Sigma (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

  4. 4. T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

  5. 5. T has $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

  6. 6. T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

Proof. Since every $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ (resp. $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ ) formula is T-provably equivalent to some $\Sigma _1$ (resp. $\Delta _0$ ) formula, we have $(2 \Leftrightarrow 3)$ . Also by Guaspari’s theorem [Reference Guaspari10] on the equivalence of the $\Sigma _1$ -soundness and $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , the equivalence $(1 \Leftrightarrow 2)$ holds. Moreover, since the implications “ $\Sigma _1$ -sound $\Rightarrow \Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ ,” “ $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {EP} \Rightarrow \Delta _0$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ ,” and “ $\Delta _0$ - $\mathrm {EP} \Rightarrow \Sigma _1$ -sound” are easily verified, we obtain that Clauses 1, 4, and 5 are pairwise equivalent. Finally, since the equivalence of the $\Sigma _1$ -soundness and $\Sigma _1$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ is shown in [Reference Kurahashi15], we get $(1 \Leftrightarrow 6)$ .

Corollary 5.30. $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ but does not have $\mathrm {MDP}$ .

Proof. Since $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ is $\Sigma _1$ -sound by Corollary 2.7, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . On the other hand, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) \vdash \Box \bot $ and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) \nvdash \bot $ , and thus $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ does not have $\mathrm {MDP}$ .

We then discuss theories in which $\Box \bot $ is not necessarily provable. Unlike the cases of $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ and $\mathrm {B}$ (Proposition 4.20), $(\Sigma (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ directly follows from $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ because $\Sigma _1 \subseteq \Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ . Also, as in the cases of $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ and $\mathrm {B}$ (Proposition 4.24), we obtain the following proposition.

Proposition 5.31. Let T be any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory extending $\mathbf {PA}$ . If T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ , then T has $(\Sigma (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proof. Suppose that T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ . Let $\varphi $ be any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence and let $\delta (x)$ be any $\Delta _0$ formula such that $T \vdash \varphi \lor \exists x \delta (x)$ and $T \nvdash \exists x \delta (x)$ . We would like to show $T \vdash \varphi $ . In this case, $\mathbb {N} \models \forall x \neg \delta (x)$ . Let $\sigma $ be a $\Sigma _1$ sentence satisfying

(4) $$ \begin{align} \mathbf{PA} \vdash \sigma \leftrightarrow \exists x \bigl(\delta(x) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\varphi \lor \sigma\urcorner, y) \bigr). \end{align} $$

Since T is an extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ and $\sigma $ is $\Sigma _1$ , we have $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \sigma \to \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \sigma \urcorner )$ , and hence $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \sigma \to \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \lor \sigma \urcorner )$ . By the equivalence (4), we obtain

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA} \vdash \exists x \delta(x) \land \neg \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\varphi \lor \sigma\urcorner) \to \sigma. \end{align*}$$

It follows $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \exists x \delta (x) \land \neg \mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \lor \sigma \urcorner ) \to \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \lor \sigma \urcorner )$ , and hence

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA} \vdash \exists x \delta(x) \to \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\varphi \lor \sigma\urcorner). \end{align*}$$

Since $T \vdash \varphi \lor \exists x \delta (x)$ , we obtain $T \vdash (\varphi \lor \sigma ) \lor \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \lor \sigma \urcorner )$ . Since $\varphi \lor \sigma $ is a $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence, by $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ , we have $T \vdash \varphi \lor \sigma $ . Since $\mathbb {N} \models \forall x \neg \delta (x)$ , $\mathbb {N} \models \exists y \bigl (\mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \lor \sigma \urcorner , y) \land \forall x \leq y \, \neg \delta (x) \bigr )$ and this is provable in T. Then, $T \vdash \neg \sigma $ , and thus $T \vdash \varphi $ .

From Propositions 4.22, 5.29, and 5.31, we obtain the following corollary.

Corollary 5.32. For any r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ , T has $(\Sigma (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ if and only if T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

Before proving our main theorem of this section, we prepare some notations and lemmas.

Definition 5.33. For each $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\varphi $ , we define the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi ^-$ inductively as follows:

  1. 1. If $\varphi $ is $\Sigma _1$ , then $\varphi ^- : \equiv \varphi $ .

  2. 2. If $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ , then $\varphi ^- : \equiv \psi $ .

  3. 3. Otherwise if $\varphi $ is of the form $\psi \land \sigma $ , $\psi \lor \sigma $ , $\exists x \psi $ or $\forall x < t\, \psi $ , then $\varphi ^-$ is respectively $\psi ^- \land \sigma ^-$ , $\psi ^- \lor \sigma ^-$ , $\exists x \psi ^-$ or $\forall x < t\, \psi ^-$ .

The operation $(\cdot )^-$ removes the outermost $\Box $ of nested occurrences of $\Box $ ’s in the formula. For example, $(\Box \Box \varphi \lor \Box \psi )^-$ is $\Box \varphi \lor \psi $ . The following lemma is a strengthening of Theorem 2.8.

Lemma 5.34. For any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\varphi $ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box (\varphi ^-)$ .

Proof. This lemma is proved by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ as in the proof of Theorem 3.13. Notice that if $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ , then $\varphi ^- \equiv \psi $ and thus $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K}) \vdash \varphi \to \Box (\varphi ^-)$ holds.

Definition 5.35. For each $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\varphi (\vec {x})$ , we define the $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\varphi ^*(\vec {x}, \vec {v})$ with zero or more additional free variables $\vec {v}$ which do not occur in $\varphi (\vec {x})$ inductively as follows:

  1. 1. If $\varphi (\vec {x})$ is either $\Delta _0$ or of the form $\Box \psi (\vec {x})$ , then $\varphi ^*(\vec {x}) : \equiv \varphi (\vec {x})$ .

  2. 2. Otherwise if $\varphi (\vec {x})$ is of the form $\psi (\vec {x}) \land \sigma (\vec {x})$ , then $\varphi ^*(\vec {x}, \vec {u}, \vec {v}) : \equiv \psi ^*(\vec {x}, \vec {u}) \land \sigma ^*(\vec {x}, \vec {v})$ where $\vec {u}$ and $\vec {v}$ are pairwise disjoint.

  3. 3. Otherwise if $\varphi (\vec {x})$ is of the form $\psi (\vec {x}) \lor \sigma (\vec {x})$ , then

    $$\begin{align*}\varphi^*(\vec{x}, \vec{u}, \vec{v}, w) : \equiv \Bigl[ \bigl(w = 0 \land \psi^*(\vec{x}, \vec{u}) \bigr) \lor \bigl(w \neq 0 \land \sigma^*(\vec{x}, \vec{v}) \bigr) \Bigr], \end{align*}$$

    where $\vec {u}$ , $\vec {v}$ , and w are pairwise disjoint.

  4. 4. Otherwise if $\varphi (\vec {x})$ is of the form $\forall y < t\, \psi (\vec {x}, y)$ , then $\varphi ^*(\vec {x}, \vec {v}) : \equiv \forall y < t\, \psi ^*(\vec {x}, y, \vec {v})$ .

  5. 5. Otherwise if $\varphi (\vec {x})$ is of the form $\exists y < t\, \psi (\vec {x}, y)$ , then $\varphi ^*(\vec {x}, \vec {v}, w)$ is the formula $\exists y < t\, (y = w \land \psi ^*(\vec {x}, y, \vec {v}))$ .

From the definition, we can easily prove the following lemma by induction on the construction of $\varphi (\vec {x}) \in \Delta (\mathrm {B})$ .

Lemma 5.36. For any $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\varphi (\vec {x})$ , $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi (\vec {x}) \leftrightarrow \exists \vec {v} \varphi ^*(\vec {x}, \vec {v})$ .

The following lemma is an important feature of our two transformations $-$ and $*$ .

Lemma 5.37. Let T be any r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ such that $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ . For any $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ , if there exist numbers $\vec {p}$ such that $T \vdash \Box (\varphi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}})$ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ .

Proof. We prove the lemma by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is a $\Delta _0$ sentence, then $(\varphi ^*)^- \equiv \varphi ^- \equiv \varphi $ . Suppose $T \vdash \Box (\varphi ^*)^-$ , i.e., $T \vdash \Box \varphi $ . If $\mathbb {N} \models \neg \varphi $ , then $T \vdash \neg \varphi $ and $T \vdash \Box \neg \varphi $ . We have $T \vdash \Box \bot $ , a contradiction. Hence, $\mathbb {N} \models \varphi $ . We conclude $T \vdash \varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ , then $(\varphi ^*)^- \equiv (\Box \psi )^- \equiv \psi $ . Suppose $T \vdash \Box (\varphi ^*)^-$ . Then, $T \vdash \varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\psi \land \sigma $ , then $(\varphi ^*)^-(\vec {u}, \vec {v}) \equiv (\psi ^*)^-(\vec {u}) \land (\sigma ^*)^-(\vec {v})$ . Suppose $T \vdash \Box (\varphi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}}, \vec {\overline {q}})$ . Then, $T \vdash \Box (\psi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}})$ and $T \vdash \Box (\sigma ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {q}})$ . By the induction hypothesis, $T \vdash \psi $ and $T \vdash \sigma $ . We conclude $T \vdash \varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\psi \lor \sigma $ , then

    $$\begin{align*}(\varphi^*)^-(\vec{u}, \vec{v}, w) \equiv \Bigl[ \bigl(w = 0 \land (\psi^*)^-(\vec{u}) \bigr) \lor \bigl(w \neq 0 \land (\sigma^*)^-(\vec{v}) \bigr) \Bigr]. \end{align*}$$
    Suppose $T \vdash \Box (\varphi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}}, \vec {\overline {q}}, \overline {r})$ . Then,
    $$\begin{align*}T \vdash \Box \Bigl[ \bigl(\overline{r} = 0 \land (\psi^*)^-(\vec{\overline{p}}) \bigr) \lor \bigl(\overline{r} \neq 0 \land (\sigma^*)^-(\vec{\overline{q}}) \bigr) \Bigr]. \end{align*}$$
    If $r = 0$ , then $T \vdash \Box (\psi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}})$ . By the induction hypothesis, $T \vdash \psi $ . If $r \neq 0$ , then $T \vdash \Box (\sigma ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {q}})$ . By the induction hypothesis, $T \vdash \sigma $ . In either case, $T \vdash \varphi $ .
  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\forall x < t\, \psi (x)$ for some $\mathcal {L}_A$ -term $t$ , then $(\varphi ^*)^-(\vec {v})$ is the formula $\forall x < t\, (\psi ^*)^-(\vec {v}, x)$ . Since $\varphi $ is a sentence, $t$ is a closed term. Let $k$ be the value of the term $t$ and suppose $T \vdash \Box (\varphi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}})$ . Then, for all $n < k$ , $T \vdash \Box (\psi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}}, \overline {n})$ . By the induction hypothesis, $T \vdash \psi (\overline {n})$ . We obtain $T \vdash \varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\exists x < t\, \psi (x)$ for some closed term $t$ , then

    $$\begin{align*}(\varphi^*)^-(\vec{v}, w) \equiv \exists x < t \bigl(x = w \land (\psi^*)^-(\vec{v}, x) \bigr). \end{align*}$$
    Suppose $T \vdash \Box (\varphi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}}, \overline {q})$ . Then, $T \vdash \Box \exists x < t \bigl (x = \overline {q} \land (\psi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}}, x) \bigr )$ . Since $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , the value of $t$ is larger than q. Since $T \vdash \Box (\psi ^*)^-(\vec {\overline {p}}, \overline {q})$ , by the induction hypothesis, $T \vdash \psi (\overline {q})$ . Then, $T \vdash \exists x < t\, \psi (x)$ , that is, $T \vdash \varphi $ .

We are ready to prove our main theorem of this section.

Theorem 5.38. Let T be any r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ such that $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ . Then, the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. T has $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and $(\Sigma (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

  2. 2. T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

  3. 3. T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

  4. 4. T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proof. $(1 \Rightarrow 2)$ : Let $\varphi (x)$ be any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula with no free variables except possibly $x$ , such that $T \vdash \exists x \Box \varphi (x)$ . By the Fixed Point Lemma, let $\psi $ be a $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence satisfying

$$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA}_{\Box} \vdash \psi \leftrightarrow \exists x \bigl(\Box \varphi(x) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\psi\urcorner, y) \bigr). \end{align*}$$

Since $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \exists x \Box \varphi (x) \land \neg \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner ) \to \psi $ , we have $T \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner ) \lor \psi $ . Since T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ by Corollary 5.32, we obtain $T \vdash \psi $ . By the choice of $\psi $ ,

(5) $$ \begin{align} T \vdash \exists x \bigl(\Box \varphi(x) \land \forall y < x \, \neg \mathrm{Prf}_T(\ulcorner\psi\urcorner, y) \bigr). \end{align} $$

Let p be a proof of $\psi $ in T, then $T \vdash \mathrm {Prf}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner , \overline {p})$ and thus $T \vdash \exists x \leq \overline {p} \, \Box \varphi (x)$ by (5). Then, $T \vdash \Box \varphi (\overline {0}) \lor \cdots \lor \Box \varphi (\overline {p})$ . Since T has $\mathrm {B}^{p+1}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ by Proposition 4.16.2, there exists $k \leq p$ such that $T \vdash \Box \varphi (\overline {k})$ . Therefore, T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

$(2 \Rightarrow 3)$ : Let $\varphi (x)$ be any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ formula without having free variables except $x$ such that $T \vdash \exists x \varphi (x)$ . By Proposition 3.10, there exists a $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ formula $\psi (x, y)$ such that $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \varphi (x) \leftrightarrow \exists y \psi (x, y)$ . Also, by Lemma 5.36, $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box } \vdash \psi (x, y) \leftrightarrow \exists \vec {v} \psi ^*(x, y, \vec {v})$ . Then, $T \vdash \exists x \exists y \exists \vec {v} \psi ^*(x, y, \vec {v})$ and

$$\begin{align*}T \vdash \exists w \, \exists x \leq w \, \exists y \leq w \, \exists \vec{v} \leq w\, \bigl( w = \langle x, y, \vec{v} \rangle \land \psi^*(x, y, \vec{v}) \bigr). \end{align*}$$

Here $\langle x, y, \vec {v} \rangle $ is an appropriate iteration of usual $\Delta _0$ representable bijective pairing function $\langle \cdot , \cdot \rangle $ . We may assume that $\mathbf {PA}$ proves $x\, {\leq }\, \langle x, y \rangle $ and $y \, {\leq } \, \langle x, y \rangle $ . By Lemma 5.34,

$$\begin{align*}T \vdash \exists w \, \Box \exists x \leq w \, \exists y \leq w \, \exists \vec{v} \leq w \, \bigl(w = \langle x, y, \vec{v} \rangle \land (\psi^*)^-(x, y, \vec{v}) \bigr). \end{align*}$$

By $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ , there exists a natural number $k$ such that

$$\begin{align*}T \vdash \Box \exists x \leq \overline{k} \, \exists y \leq \overline{k} \, \exists \vec{v} \leq \overline{k} \, \bigl(\overline{k} = \langle x, y, \vec{v} \rangle \land (\psi^*)^-(x, y, \vec{v}) \bigr). \end{align*}$$

For the unique p, q, and $\vec {r}$ such that $k = \langle p, q, \vec {r} \rangle $ ,

$$\begin{align*}T \vdash \Box (\psi^*)^-(\overline{p}, \overline{q}, \vec{\overline{r}}). \end{align*}$$

By Lemma 5.37, we obtain $T \vdash \psi (\overline {p}, \overline {q})$ . Then, $T \vdash \varphi (\overline {p})$ . Therefore, T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

$(3 \Rightarrow 4)$ : By Proposition 4.18.2.

$(4 \Rightarrow 1)$ : This is trivial.

In order to derive the equivalence of $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\mathrm {MEP}$ from Theorem 5.38, we prove a proposition that connects $\mathrm {MDP}$ (resp. $\mathrm {MEP}$ ) and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ (resp. $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ ).

Proposition 5.39. Let T be any r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ .

  1. 1. If T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ , then T also has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

  2. 2. If T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ , then T also has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

Proof. 1. Let $\varphi $ and $\psi $ be any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentences such that $T \vdash \varphi \lor \psi $ . By Theorem 3.13, $T \vdash \Box \varphi \lor \Box \psi $ . By $\mathrm {MDP}$ , we obtain $T \vdash \varphi $ or $T \vdash \psi $ . Therefore, T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Clause 2 is proved similarly.

Corollary 5.40. For any r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ if and only if T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ .

Proof. Since $\mathrm {MEP}$ implies $\mathrm {MDP}$ by Proposition 4.18.1, it suffices to show that $\mathrm {MDP}$ implies $\mathrm {MEP}$ . We may assume that T is consistent. If T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ , then T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ by Proposition 5.39. Also, T is closed under the box elimination rule by Proposition 4.17. Then, $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ by the consistency of T. By Theorem 5.38, T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . By Proposition 4.17 again, we conclude that T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ .

Remark 5.41. In the introduction, we imprecisely mentioned the result of Friedman and Sheard [Reference Friedman and Sheard6]. Firstly, Friedman and Sheard actually proved their theorem in the setting where the use of the rule Nec and the axiom $\forall \vec {x}(\Box (\varphi \to \psi ) \to (\Box \varphi \to \Box \psi ))$ is restricted, that is, in the non-normal setting. In our normal setting, the following result follows from their theorem: For any r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) + \{\forall \vec {x} \Box (\Box \varphi \to \varphi ) \mid \varphi \in \Delta _0\}$ , if T is closed under the box elimination rule, then T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ if and only if T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . Then, in the light of Proposition 4.17, this statement can be rewritten as follows: For any r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) + \{\forall \vec {x} \Box (\Box \varphi \to \varphi ) \mid \varphi \in \Delta _0\}$ , T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ if and only if T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ . Therefore, our Corollary 5.40 shows that the same consequence is obtained without using the axiom scheme $\{\forall \vec {x} \Box (\Box \varphi \to \varphi ) \mid \varphi \in \Delta _0\}$ . Notice that by Theorem 2.8, over $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ , $\{\forall \vec {x} \Box (\Box \varphi \to \varphi ) \mid \varphi \in \Delta _0\}$ is equivalent to a single sentence $\Box \neg \Box \bot $ .

6 Generalizations of the notions of soundness and $\Sigma _1$ -soundness

In this section, we introduce several notions related to the soundness of theories of modal arithmetic with respect to $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentences. This section consists of three subsections. In the first subsection, we introduce the notion of the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness and prove that several $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theories are actually $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound. In the second subsection, we introduce the notions of the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness and the weak $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness. Then, we prove that over appropriate theories, the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness and the weak $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness characterize $\mathrm {MDP}$ and $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , respectively. In the last subsection, we prove two non-implications between the properties as applications of the results we have obtained so far.

6.1 $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness

We formulate the notion of the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness under the interpretation that boxed formulas represent the provability of some formula in the standard model $\mathbb {N}$ of arithmetic. To do so, we once translate each $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentence into an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sentence using a provability predicate, and then consider the truth of the translated sentence in $\mathbb {N}$ . First, we introduce two types of translations $\pi _T$ and $\pi ^{\prime }_T$ .

Definition 6.42 ( $\pi $ -translations)

Let T be any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory. We define a translation $\pi _T$ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas into $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formulas inductively as follows:

  1. 1. If $\varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formula, then $\pi _T(\varphi ) : \equiv \varphi $ .

  2. 2. $\pi _T$ preserves logical connectives and quantifiers.

  3. 3. $\pi _T(\Box \varphi (\vec {x})) : \equiv \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi (\vec {\dot {x}}) \urcorner )$ .

Here $\ulcorner \varphi (\vec {\dot {x}})\urcorner $ is a primitive recursive term corresponding to a primitive recursive function calculating the Gödel number of $\varphi (\vec {\overline {n}})$ from $\vec {n}$ . Note that $\vec {x}$ are free variables in the formula $\mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi (\vec {\dot {x}})\urcorner )$ .

Definition 6.43 ( $\pi '$ -translations)

Let T be any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory. We define a translation $\pi ^{\prime }_T$ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas into $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formulas inductively as follows:

  1. 1. If $\varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formula, then $\pi ^{\prime }_T(\varphi ) : \equiv \varphi $ .

  2. 2. $\pi ^{\prime }_T$ preserves logical connectives and quantifiers.

  3. 3. $\pi ^{\prime }_T(\Box \varphi (\vec {x})) : \equiv \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi (\vec {\dot {x}}) \urcorner ) \land \pi ^{\prime }_T(\varphi (\vec {x}))$ .

The translation $\pi ^{\prime }_T$ is a formalization of Shapiro’s slash interpretation [Reference Shapiro21], introduced in [Reference Halbach and Horsten11] under the name $\sigma _T$ .

Definition 6.44. Let T be any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory.

  • T is said to be $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound if for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentence $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\varphi )$ .

  • T is said to be alternatively $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound if for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentence $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \pi ^{\prime }_T(\varphi )$ .

Actually, these two notions are equivalent.

Proposition 6.45. For any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory T, the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. T is $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

  2. 2. T is alternatively $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

Proof. $(1 \Rightarrow 2)$ : Suppose that T is $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound. We prove by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ that for all $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentences $\varphi $ , $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\varphi ) \leftrightarrow \pi _T'(\varphi )$ . If $\varphi $ is an atomic $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sentence, then $\pi _T(\varphi )$ coincides with $\pi ^{\prime }_T(\varphi )$ . The cases for Boolean connectives are easy.

If $\varphi $ is of the form $\forall x \psi (x)$ , then for any natural number $n$ , $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\psi (\overline {n})) \leftrightarrow \pi ^{\prime }_T(\psi (\overline {n}))$ by the induction hypothesis. Then, $\mathbb {N} \models \forall x \bigl (\pi _T(\psi (x)) \leftrightarrow \pi ^{\prime }_T(\psi (x) \bigr )$ and hence $\mathbb {N} \models \forall x \pi _T(\psi (x)) \leftrightarrow \forall x \pi ^{\prime }_T(\psi (x))$ . This means $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\varphi ) \leftrightarrow \pi ^{\prime }_T(\varphi )$ .

Suppose that $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ . Since $\pi _T(\Box \psi )$ is $\mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner )$ , by the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness of T, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\Box \psi )$ if and only if $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner ) \land \pi _T(\psi )$ . By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner ) \land \pi _T(\psi )$ if and only if $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner ) \land \pi ^{\prime }_T(\psi )$ . Thus, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\Box \psi ) \leftrightarrow \pi ^{\prime }_T(\Box \psi )$ .

$(2 \Rightarrow 1)$ : Suppose that T is alternatively $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound. Similarly, we only prove that for all $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentences $\psi $ , $\mathbb {N} \models \pi ^{\prime }_T(\Box \psi ) \leftrightarrow \pi _T(\Box \psi )$ . $\mathbb {N} \models \pi ^{\prime }_T(\Box \psi )$ is equivalent to $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner ) \land \pi ^{\prime }_T(\psi )$ . Then, by the alternative $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness of T, this is equivalent to $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner )$ . This is exactly $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\Box \psi )$ .

Here we show some propositions that help to prove the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness of each $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory.

Proposition 6.46. Let T be an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ . For any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then for any r.e. extension U of T, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi _U(\varphi )$ .

Proof. Let U be any r.e. extension of T. As in the proof of Proposition 2.3, by induction on the length of proofs of $\varphi $ in T, we prove that for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi _U(\varphi )$ . We only give proofs of the following four cases.

  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x} \bigl (\Box (\psi (\vec {x}) \to \sigma (\vec {x})) \to (\Box \psi (\vec {x}) \to \Box \sigma (\vec {x})) \bigr )$ , then $\pi _U(\varphi )$ is

    $$\begin{align*}\forall \vec{x} \bigl(\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}}) \to \sigma(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \to (\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \to \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\sigma(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner)) \bigr), \end{align*}$$
    and this is provable in $\mathbf {PA}$ .
  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x} \bigl (\Box \psi (\vec {x}) \to \Box \Box \psi (\vec {x}) \bigr )$ , then $\pi _U(\varphi )$ is

    $$\begin{align*}\forall \vec{x} \bigl(\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \to \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \bigr). \end{align*}$$
    Since $\mathbf {PA}$ proves the fact that the consequences of U are closed under the rule Nec, this sentence is provable in $\mathbf {PA}$ .
  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x} \bigl (\Box (\Box \psi (\vec {x}) \to \psi (\vec {x})) \to \Box \psi (\vec {x}) \bigr )$ , then we reason as follows: By invoking Nec,

    $$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA} \vdash \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}}) \to \psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \to \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box(\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}}) \to \psi(\vec{\dot{x}}))\urcorner). \end{align*}$$
    Since U is an extension of T, we have $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_U(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner )$ and hence
    $$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA} \vdash \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box(\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}}) \to \psi(\vec{\dot{x}}))\urcorner) \to \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner). \end{align*}$$
    Then,
    $$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA} \vdash \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}}) \to \psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \to \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner), \end{align*}$$
    and thus
    $$\begin{align*}\mathbf{PA} \vdash \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}}) \to \psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \to \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner). \end{align*}$$
    This means $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi _U(\varphi )$ .
  • If $\varphi (\vec {x})$ is derived from $\psi (\vec {x})$ by Nec, then $\varphi (\vec {x}) \equiv \Box \psi (\vec {x})$ . Since $U \vdash \psi (\vec {x})$ , $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_U(\ulcorner \psi (\vec {\dot {x}})\urcorner )$ . Thus, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi _U(\varphi (\vec {x}))$ .

Proposition 6.47. Let T be an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ , and let U be any r.e. extension of T. If $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\varphi )$ for all $\varphi \in U \setminus T$ , then U is $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

Proof. Suppose that $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\varphi )$ for all $\varphi \in U \setminus T$ . We prove by induction on the length of a proof of $\varphi $ in U that for all $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formulas $\varphi $ , if $U \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\forall \vec {x} \varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is an axiom of T or a logical axiom, then $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi _U(\forall \vec {x} \varphi )$ by Proposition 6.46. Thus, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\forall \vec {x} \varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is in $U \setminus T$ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\varphi )$ by the supposition.

  • If $\varphi $ is derived from $\psi $ and $\psi \to \varphi $ by MP, then by the induction hypothesis, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\forall \vec {x} \psi )$ and $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\forall \vec {x}( \psi \to \varphi ))$ . Then, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\forall \vec {x} \varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is derived from $\psi (y)$ by Gen, then $\varphi \equiv \forall y \psi (y)$ . By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\forall \vec {x} \forall y \psi (y))$ . Hence, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\forall \vec {x} \varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is derived from $\psi $ by Nec, then $\varphi \equiv \Box \psi $ and $U \vdash \psi $ . We have $\mathbb {N} \models \forall \vec {x} \, \mathrm {Pr}_U(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner )$ , and equivalently $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\forall \vec {x} \varphi )$ .

Corollary 6.48. The theories $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ are $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

Here, we give some more examples of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound theories. Let $x \in W_y$ be a $\Sigma _1$ formula saying that $x$ is in the y-th r.e. set. Reinhardt’s Weak Mechanistic Thesis (WMT) is the following schema:

  • $\exists y \forall x \bigl (\Box \varphi (x) \leftrightarrow x \in W_y \bigr )$ , where $\varphi (x)$ is an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula having lone free variable $x$ .

When $\Box $ is interpreted as knowledge, WMT can be thought as a formalization of “Knowledge is mechanical.” Concerning WMT, we obtain the following corollary to Proposition 6.47.

Corollary 6.49. Let T be an r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ . Then, the theory $U : = T + \mathrm {WMT}$ is $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

Proof. Since $\mathrm {Pr}_U(\ulcorner \varphi (\dot {x})\urcorner )$ is a $\Sigma _1$ formula, there exists a natural number e such that

$$\begin{align*}\mathbb{N} \models \forall x \bigl(\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\varphi(\dot{x})\urcorner) \leftrightarrow x \in W_{\overline{e}} \bigr). \end{align*}$$

Then, we have $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U \Bigl (\exists y \forall x \bigl (\Box \varphi (x) \leftrightarrow x \in W_y \bigr ) \Bigr )$ . By Proposition 6.47, the theory U is $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

We prove an analogue of Proposition 6.46 with respect to $\pi '$ -translations.

Proposition 6.50. Let T be an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ . For any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then for any r.e. extension U of T, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi ^{\prime }_U(\varphi )$ .

Proof. Let U be any r.e. extension of T. As in the proof of Proposition 2.3, we prove by induction on the length of proofs of $\varphi $ in T that for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi ^{\prime }_U(\varphi )$ . We only give proofs of the following four cases.

  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x} \bigl (\Box (\psi (\vec {x}) \to \sigma (\vec {x})) \to (\Box \psi (\vec {x}) \to \Box \sigma (\vec {x})) \bigr )$ , then $\pi ^{\prime }_U(\varphi )$ is

    $$ \begin{align*} & \forall \vec{x} \Bigl(\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}}) \to \sigma(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \land \pi^{\prime}_U(\psi(\vec{x}) \to \sigma(\vec{x}))\\ & \ \ \ \ \ \to \bigl(\bigl[\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \land \pi^{\prime}_U(\psi(\vec{x})) \bigr] \to \bigl[\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\sigma(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \land \pi^{\prime}_U(\sigma(\vec{x})) \bigr] \bigr) \Bigr). \end{align*} $$
    This sentence is provable in $\mathbf {PA}$ .
  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x}(\Box \psi (\vec {x}) \to \psi (\vec {x}))$ , then $\pi ^{\prime }_U(\varphi )$ is

    $$\begin{align*}\forall \vec{x} \bigl(\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \land \pi^{\prime}_U(\psi(\vec{x})) \to \pi^{\prime}_U(\psi(\vec{x})) \bigr), \end{align*}$$
    and this is obviously provable in $\mathbf {PA}$ .
  • If $\varphi $ is $\forall \vec {x}(\Box \psi (\vec {x}) \to \Box \Box \psi (\vec {x}))$ , then $\pi _U(\varphi )$ is

    $$\begin{align*}&\forall \vec{x} \Bigl(\bigl[\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \land \pi^{\prime}_U(\psi(\vec{x})) \bigr] \\&\quad\to \bigl[\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \land \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\psi(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \land \pi^{\prime}_U(\psi(\vec{x})) \bigr] \Bigr), \end{align*}$$
    and this is provable in $\mathbf {PA}$ .
  • If $\varphi (\vec {x})$ is derived from $\psi (\vec {x})$ by Nec, then $\varphi (\vec {x}) \equiv \Box \psi (\vec {x})$ . Since $T \vdash \psi (\vec {x})$ , by the induction hypothesis, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi ^{\prime }_U(\psi (\vec {x}))$ . Also, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_U(\ulcorner \psi (\vec {\dot {x}})\urcorner )$ because U is an extension of T. Thus, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \pi ^{\prime }_U(\varphi (\vec {x}))$ .

As in the proof of Proposition 6.47, we can prove the following proposition from Propositions 6.45 and 6.50.

Proposition 6.51 (Cf. [Reference Shapiro21, TB])

Let T be an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ , and let U be any r.e. extension of T. If $\mathbb {N} \models \pi ^{\prime }_U(\varphi )$ for all $\varphi \in U \setminus T$ , then U is $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

Corollary 6.52. The theories $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {KT})$ and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ are $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

The alternative $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ is already proved by Shapiro [Reference Shapiro21, TB’].

Corollary 6.53. Let T be an r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4}) + \{\Box \Diamond \varphi \to \varphi \mid \varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sentence $\}$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ . Then, T is $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound.

Proof. By Proposition 6.51, it suffices to show that for any $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sentence $\varphi $ , if $\Box \Diamond \varphi \to \varphi \in T$ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \pi ^{\prime }_T(\Box \Diamond \varphi \to \varphi )$ . Suppose that $\Box \Diamond \varphi \to \varphi \in T$ and $\mathbb {N} \models \pi ^{\prime }_T(\Box \Diamond \varphi )$ . Then, $T \vdash \Diamond \varphi $ , and $T \vdash \Box \Diamond \varphi $ . Since $T \vdash \Box \Diamond \varphi \to \varphi $ , we have $T \vdash \varphi $ . Since T is a subtheory of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ , T is an conservative extension of $\mathbf {PA}$ by Corollary 2.4. Then, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \varphi $ because $\varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -sentence. By the $\mathcal {L}_A$ -soundness of $\mathbf {PA}$ , we have $\mathbb {N} \models \varphi $ and hence $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T'(\varphi )$ . We have proved $\mathbb {N} \models \pi ^{\prime }_U(\Box \Diamond \varphi \to \varphi )$ .

In contrast to Corollary 6.53, we have the following proposition which is a refinement of Proposition 4.28.1.

Proposition 6.54. Let T be a consistent r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory extending the theory $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {KT}) + \{\Box \Diamond \varphi \to \varphi \mid \varphi \text { is a } \Sigma (\mathrm {B})\text {-sentence}\}$ . Then, T does not have $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proof. Let $\varphi $ be a $\Sigma _1$ sentence such that $T \nvdash \varphi $ and $T \nvdash \neg \varphi $ . Then, $T \nvdash \Box \neg \varphi $ because $T \vdash \Box \neg \varphi \to \neg \varphi $ . Since $T \vdash \Box \Diamond \varphi \to \Diamond \varphi $ , we have $T \vdash \Diamond \Box \neg \varphi \lor \Diamond \varphi $ . Then, $T \vdash \Diamond (\Box \neg \varphi \lor \varphi )$ and hence $T \vdash \Box \Diamond (\Box \neg \varphi \lor \varphi )$ . Since $\Box \neg \varphi \lor \varphi $ is a $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence, we obtain $T \vdash \Box \neg \varphi \lor \varphi $ because $\Box \Diamond (\Box \neg \varphi \lor \varphi ) \to (\Box \neg \varphi \lor \varphi )$ is an axiom of T. We have shown that $T \nvdash \Box \neg \varphi $ , $T \nvdash \varphi $ , and $T \vdash \Box \neg \varphi \lor \varphi $ . This means that T does not have $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

6.2 $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness and weak $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness

We then export the notion of the $\Sigma _1$ -soundness to modal arithmetic. This is easy to do since we have already introduced the class $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ corresponding to $\Sigma _1$ in modal arithmetic. Here we further introduce another type of translation $\rho _T$ , which is different from $\pi _T$ .

Definition 6.55 ( $\rho $ -translations)

Let T be any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory. We define a translation $\rho _T$ of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formulas into $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formulas inductively as follows:

  1. 1. If $\varphi $ is an $\mathcal {L}_A$ -formula, then $\rho _T(\varphi ) : \equiv \varphi $ .

  2. 2. $\rho _T$ preserves logical connectives and quantifiers.

  3. 3. $\rho _T(\Box \varphi (\vec {x})) : \equiv \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \Box \varphi (\vec {\dot {x}}) \urcorner )$ .

With respect to $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentences, there is the following relationship between the translations $\pi _T$ and $\rho _T$ .

Proposition 6.56. Let T be any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory.

  1. 1. For any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sentence $\varphi $ , $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\varphi ) \to \rho _T(\varphi )$ .

  2. 2. If T is closed under the box elimination rule, then for any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sentence $\varphi $ , $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi ) \to \pi _T(\varphi )$ .

Proof. These statements are proved by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ . We only prove the case of $\varphi \equiv \Box \psi $ .

1. If $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\Box \psi )$ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner )$ . Then, $T \vdash \psi $ . By the rule Nec, $T \vdash \Box \psi $ . Then, $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \Box \psi \urcorner )$ , and hence $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\Box \psi )$ .

2. If $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\Box \psi )$ , then $T \vdash \Box \psi $ . By the box elimination rule, $T \vdash \psi $ . Hence, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\Box \psi )$ .

We strengthen the usual $\Sigma _1$ -completeness theorem of $\mathbf {PA}$ as follows.

Theorem 6.57 ( $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -completeness theorem)

Let T be any r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ . Then, for any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ , if $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi )$ , then $T \vdash \varphi $ .

Proof. We prove the theorem by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is a $\Sigma _1$ sentence, then the statement immediately follows from the usual $\Sigma _1$ -completeness of $\mathbf {PA}$ because $\rho _T(\varphi )$ is exactly $\varphi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\Box \psi )$ means $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \Box \psi \urcorner )$ , and hence $T \vdash \Box \psi $ .

  • If $\varphi $ is one of the forms $\psi \land \sigma $ , $\psi \lor \sigma $ , $\exists x \psi $ , and $\forall x < t \ \psi $ , then the proof is straightforward by the induction hypothesis.

In the light of Proposition 6.56 and Theorem 6.57, we introduce the following two different types of the notion of $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness.

Definition 6.58. Let T be any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory.

  • T is said to be $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound if for any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\varphi )$ .

  • T is said to be weakly $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound if for any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi )$ .

Lemma 6.59. For any r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory T, the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound.

  2. 2. T is weakly $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound and T is closed under the box elimination rule.

Proof. By Proposition 6.56, it suffices to show that $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness implies the box elimination rule. Suppose that T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound. Let $\varphi $ be any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sentence such that $T \vdash \Box \varphi $ . By the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness of T, $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _T(\Box \varphi )$ and hence $\mathbb {N} \models \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner )$ . We obtain $T \vdash \varphi $ .

We are ready to prove an analogue of Guaspari’s theorem.

Theorem 6.60. Let T be an r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ .

  1. 1. If T contains $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ , $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , and T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , then T is weakly $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound.

  2. 2. If T is weakly $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound, then T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

Proof. 1. We prove by induction on the construction of $\varphi $ that for any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is a $\Sigma _1$ sentence, then $\rho _T(\varphi ) \equiv \varphi $ . Suppose $T \vdash \varphi $ . Since $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ implies $(\mathrm {B}, \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , T is $\Sigma _1$ -sound by Proposition 4.21. Therefore, $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ , then $\rho _T(\varphi ) \equiv \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \Box \psi \urcorner )$ . Suppose $T \vdash \Box \psi $ . Then, obviously $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is of the form $\psi \land \sigma $ or $\forall x < t\, \psi $ , then the proof is straightforward from the induction hypothesis.

  • If $\varphi $ is $\psi \lor \sigma $ , then $\rho _T(\varphi ) \equiv \rho _T(\psi ) \lor \rho _T(\sigma )$ . Suppose $T \vdash \psi \lor \sigma $ . Then, by $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , $T \vdash \psi $ or $T \vdash \sigma $ . By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\psi )$ or $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\sigma )$ . Hence, $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi )$ .

  • If $\varphi $ is $\exists x \psi (x)$ , then $\rho _T(\varphi ) \equiv \exists x \rho _T(\psi (x))$ . Suppose $T \vdash \exists x \psi (x)$ . Since $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , by Theorem 5.38, T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . Then, there exists a natural number $n$ such that $T \vdash \psi (\overline {n})$ . By the induction hypothesis, $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\psi (\overline {n}))$ . Therefore, $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi )$ .

2. Let $\varphi (x)$ be any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ formula having no free variables except $x$ such that $T \vdash \exists x \varphi (x)$ . By the weak $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness of T, $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\exists x \varphi (x))$ . Then, for some natural number $n$ , $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _T(\varphi (\overline {n}))$ . By Theorem 6.57, $T \vdash \varphi (\overline {n})$ .

Corollary 6.61. Let T be an r.e. extension of $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ .

  1. 1. If T contains $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , T is consistent, and T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ , then T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound.

  2. 2. If T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound, then T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ .

Proof. 1. Since T contains $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ and T has $\mathrm {MDP}$ , by Proposition 5.39, T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . Also, T is closed under the box elimination rule by Proposition 4.17. Then, $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ by the consistency of T. By Theorem 6.60.1, T is weakly $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound. By Lemma 6.59, T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound.

2. By Lemma 6.59, T is weakly $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound and is closed under the box elimination rule. By Theorem 6.60.2, T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . Therefore, by Proposition 4.17, T has $\mathrm {MEP}$ .

Since the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness implies the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -soundness, we obtain the following corollary from Propositions 6.47 and 6.51.

Corollary 6.62.

  1. 1. Let T be an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ , and let U be any r.e. extension of T. If $\mathbb {N} \models \pi _U(\varphi )$ for all $\varphi \in U \setminus T$ , then U has $\mathrm {MEP}$ .

  2. 2. Let T be an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ , and let U be any r.e. extension of T. If $\mathbb {N} \models \pi ^{\prime }_U(\varphi )$ for all $\varphi \in U \setminus T$ , then U has $\mathrm {MEP}$ .

In particular, $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {KT})$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ , and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ have $\mathrm {MEP}$ .

By Lemma 6.59, each $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound theory is also weakly $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound. Therefore, $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {KT})$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ , and $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ also have $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . Recall that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ also has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ (Corollary 5.30).

Here we give another sufficient condition for a theory to have $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . First, we prove an analogue of Proposition 6.46 with respect to $\rho $ -translations.

Proposition 6.63. Let T be any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of the form $\forall \vec {x}(\Box \psi _0 \land \cdots \land \Box \psi _{k-1} \to \Box \psi _k)$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ . Then, for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then for any r.e. extension U of T, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \rho _U(\varphi )$ .

Proof. Let U be any r.e. extension of T. As in the proof of Proposition 2.3, we prove by induction on the length of proofs of $\varphi $ in T that for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\varphi $ , if $T \vdash \varphi $ , then $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \rho _U(\varphi )$ . We only give proofs of the following two cases.

  • The case $\varphi \equiv \forall \vec {x} \bigl (\Box \psi _0(\vec {x}) \land \cdots \land \Box \psi _{k-1}(\vec {x}) \to \Box \psi _k(\vec {x}) \bigr )$ : Since U is an extension of T, we have $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \forall \vec {x} \, \mathrm {Pr}_U(\ulcorner \Box \psi _0(\vec {\dot {x}}) \land \cdots \land \Box \psi _{k-1}(\vec {\dot {x}}) \to \Box \psi _k(\vec {\dot {x}})\urcorner )$ , and hence $\mathbf {PA}$ proves

    $$\begin{align*}\forall \vec{x} \bigl(\mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi_0(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \land \cdots \land \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi_{k-1}(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \to \mathrm{Pr}_U(\ulcorner\Box \psi_k(\vec{\dot{x}})\urcorner) \bigr). \end{align*}$$
    This sentence is exactly $\rho _U(\varphi )$ .
  • If $\varphi (\vec {x})$ is derived from $\psi (\vec {x})$ by Nec, then $\varphi (\vec {x}) \equiv \Box \psi (\vec {x})$ . Since $T \vdash \Box \psi (\vec {x})$ , $U \vdash \Box \psi (\vec {x})$ , and hence $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_U(\ulcorner \Box \psi (\vec {\dot {x}})\urcorner )$ . Thus, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \rho _U(\varphi (\vec {x}))$ .

Corollary 6.64. Let T be any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory obtained by adding some axioms of the form $\forall \vec {x}(\Box \psi _0 \land \cdots \land \Box \psi _{k-1} \to \Box \psi _k)$ into $\mathbf {PA}_{\Box }$ , and let U be any r.e. extension of T. If $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _U(\varphi )$ for all $\varphi \in U \setminus T$ , then U has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

Proof. Suppose that $\mathbb {N} \models \rho _U(\varphi )$ for all $\varphi \in U \setminus T$ . As in the proof of Proposition 6.47, it follows from Proposition 6.63 that U is weakly $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound. Then, by Theorem 6.60, U has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ .

6.3 Applications

In this subsection, as applications of our results we have obtained so far, we show two non-implications between the properties. Corollary 5.30 shows that in general, $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ does not imply $\mathrm {MDP}$ . The first application shows that this is also true for theories that do not contain $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ .

Proposition 6.65.

  1. 1. There exists an r.e. theory T such that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4}) \vdash T \vdash \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ , and T does not have $\mathrm {MDP}$ ;

  2. 2. There exists an r.e. theory T such that $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) \vdash T \vdash \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ , $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ , and T does not have $\mathrm {MDP}$ .

Proof. 1. Let T be the theory $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) + \{\Box \neg \Box \bot \}$ . Since T is a subtheory of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ , we have $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ . By Corollary 6.64, T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . Suppose, towards a contradiction, that $T \vdash \neg \Box \bot $ . Then, by the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -deduction theorem (Corollary 3.14), $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \Box \neg \Box \bot \to \neg \Box \bot $ . Then, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) \vdash \Box \neg \Box \bot \to \neg \Box \bot $ . Since $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum}) \vdash \Box \neg \Box \bot \land \Box \bot $ , this contradicts the consistency of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ . Therefore, $T \nvdash \neg \Box \bot $ . Since $T \vdash \Box \neg \Box \bot $ , T does not have $\mathrm {MDP}$ .

2. Let $T: = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL}) + \{\Box \Box \bot \}$ . By Corollary 6.64, T has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ . Suppose, towards a contradiction, that T proves $\Box \bot $ . By the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -deduction theorem, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL}) \vdash \Box \Box \bot \to \Box \bot $ . Then, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL}) \vdash \Box (\Box \Box \bot \to \Box \bot )$ and hence $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL}) \vdash \Box \Box \bot $ . By $\mathrm {MDP}$ of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ (Corollary 6.62 and Proposition 4.18.1), $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL}) \vdash \bot $ . This is a contradiction. Therefore, $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ . Since $T \vdash \Box \Box \bot $ , T does not have $\mathrm {MDP}$ .

Unlike the notion of the soundness of $\mathcal {L}_A$ -theories, Proposition 6.65.1 shows that the $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -soundness is not preserved by taking a subtheory because $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ is $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -sound but T is not $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -sound.

The second application shows that $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ does not imply $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ in general.

Proposition 6.66. There exists a consistent r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ satisfying the following two conditions:

  1. 1. T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

  2. 2. T does not have $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

Proof. Let $\varphi $ be a Gödel sentence of $\mathbf {PA}$ . Let $T : = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) + \{\Box \varphi \lor \Box \neg \varphi \}$ , $T_0 : = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) + \{\Box \varphi \}$ , and $T_1 : = \mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) + \{\Box \neg \varphi \}$ . By the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -deduction theorem, it is shown that for any $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -formula $\psi $ ,

(6) $$ \begin{align} T \vdash \psi\ \text{if and only if both}\ T_0 \vdash \psi\ \text{and}\ T_1 \vdash \psi. \end{align} $$

Suppose, towards a contradiction, $T_0 \vdash \Box \bot $ . By the $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ -deduction theorem, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ proves $\Box \varphi \to \Box \bot $ . Since this is also provable in $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Triv})$ , by Proposition 2.3, we have $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \alpha (\Box \varphi ) \to \alpha (\Box \bot )$ . Then, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \neg \varphi $ , a contradiction. Similarly, we can prove $T_1 \nvdash \Box \bot $ .

1. Let $\psi $ be any $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ sentence such that $T \vdash \psi \lor \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner )$ . Then, for $i \in \{0, 1\}$ , $T_i \vdash \psi \lor \mathrm {Pr}_T(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner )$ by (6). By Corollary 6.64, $T_i$ has $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {EP}$ , and hence has $(\Sigma (\mathrm {B}), \Sigma _1)$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . By Corollary 5.32, $T_i$ is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ . Therefore, $T_i \vdash \psi $ . By (6), we obtain $T \vdash \psi $ . Thus, T is also $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ .

2. If $T \vdash \Box \neg \varphi $ or $T \vdash \Box \varphi $ , then $T_0 \vdash \Box \bot $ or $T_1 \vdash \Box \bot $ by (6). This is a contradiction. Therefore, $T \nvdash \Box \neg \varphi $ and $T \nvdash \Box \varphi $ . On the other hand, $T \vdash \Box \varphi \lor \Box \neg \varphi $ . Thus, T does not have $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ .

7 Problems

In the present paper, several properties related to the modal disjunction property in modal arithmetic are introduced, and the relationships between them are studied. However, some of the properties have not yet been separated in some particular situation. In this section, we list several unsolved problems for further study.

In Section 4, we introduced $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ and $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . For theories which are closed under the box elimination rule, these properties are equivalent. However, we have not yet been successful in clarifying whether they are equivalent or not in general. We propose the following problem.

Problem 7.67.

  1. 1. Does there exist an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory which has $\Delta (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ but does not have $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ ?

  2. 2. For each $n \geq 2$ , does there exist an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory which has $\mathrm {B}^n$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ but does not have $\mathrm {B}^{n+1}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ ?

For any $\Sigma _1$ -unsound r.e. extension T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {Verum})$ , T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ but does not have $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ (see Propositions 4.25 and 5.29). On the other hand, for consistent r.e. extensions of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ , $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ implies $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ by Propositions 4.17 and 5.39 and Corollary 5.32. We have not yet been sure whether $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ yields $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ in general when $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ .

Problem 7.68. Does there exist an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory T such that $T \nvdash \Box \bot $ , T has $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ , and T is not $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ ?

In the statement of Proposition 5.39, it is assumed that T is an extension of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ . It is not settled yet whether $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ can be replaced by $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ in the statement.

Problem 7.69. In the statements of Proposition 5.39 and Corollaries 5.40 and 6.61.1, can $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ be replaced by $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K})$ ?

Proposition 6.65.1 shows that there exists an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -unsound subtheory T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {S4})$ . Related to this fact, we propose the following problem.

Problem 7.70. Does there exist an $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -unsound r.e. subtheory of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {GL})$ ?

Proposition 6.66 shows that $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ does not imply $\mathrm {B}$ - $\mathrm {DP}$ . We are not successful in determining whether the theory T in the proof of Proposition 6.66 is closed in the box elimination rule. We then propose the following problem.

Problem 7.71. Does there exist a consistent r.e. $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theory T such that T is closed under the box elimination rule, T is $\Sigma (\mathrm {B})$ - $\mathrm {DC}$ , and T does not have $\mathrm {MDP}$ ?

Remark 7.72. Notice that if we define T to be the theory $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) + \{\Box \varphi \lor \Box \neg \varphi \}$ for a $\Pi _1$ Gödel sentence $\varphi $ of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ , then T is not closed under the box elimination rule. This is because $T \vdash \Box (\Box \varphi \lor \neg \varphi )$ and $T \nvdash \Box \varphi \lor \neg \varphi $ . For, if $T \vdash \Box \varphi \lor \neg \varphi $ , then $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \Box \neg \varphi \to (\Box \varphi \lor \neg \varphi )$ . By Proposition 6.46, $\mathbf {PA} \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})}(\ulcorner \neg \varphi \urcorner ) \to (\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})}(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner ) \lor \neg \varphi )$ . Since $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})}(\ulcorner \varphi \urcorner )$ is $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ -equivalent to $\neg \varphi $ , we have $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})}(\ulcorner \neg \varphi \urcorner ) \to \neg \varphi $ . By Löb’s theorem, $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4}) \vdash \neg \varphi $ . This contradicts the $\Sigma _1$ -soundness of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ .

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank the anonymous referees for their valuable comments and suggestions on earlier versions of this paper. This work was partly supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grant Number JP19K14586.

Footnotes

1 Actually, Friedman and Sheard proved this theorem for a wider class of $\mathcal {L}_A(\Box )$ -theories. This will be discussed in Remark 5.41.

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Boolos, G. (1993). The Logic of Provability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Buchholz, W. (1993). Mathematische Logik II. Available from: http://www.mathematik.uni-muenchen.de/buchholz/articles/LogikII.ps.Google Scholar
Došen, K. (1990). Modal translations of Heyting and Peano arithmetic. Publications de l’Institut Mathématique. Nouvelle Série, 47, 1323.Google Scholar
Flagg, R. C. & Friedman, H. (1986). Epistemic and intuitionistic formal systems. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 32, 5360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, H. (1975). The disjunction property implies the numerical existence property. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 72, 28772878.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Friedman, H. & Sheard, M. (1989). The equivalence of the disjunction and existence properties for modal arithmetic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 54(4), 14561459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gentzen, G. (1934–1935). Untersuchungen über das logische Schliessen. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 39(2–3), 176210, 405–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gödel, K. (1933). An interpretation of the intuitionistic propositional calculus. In Feferman, S., editor. Collected Works, Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 301303.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. D. (1984). Epistemic arithmetic is a conservative extension of intuitionistic arithmetic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 49, 192203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guaspari, D. (1979). Partially conservative extensions of arithmetic. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 254, 4768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halbach, V. & Horsten, L. (2000). Two proof-theoretic remarks on EA + ECT. Mathematical Logic Quarterly, 46(4), 461466.3.0.CO;2-I>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, G. E. & Cresswell, M. J. (1996). A New Introduction to Modal Logic. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, D. C. & Ehrenfeucht, A. (1976). Some problem in elementary arithmetics. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 92, 223245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleene, S. C. (1945). On the interpretation of intuitionistic number theory. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 10, 109124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurahashi, T. (2018). On partial disjunction properties of theories containing Peano arithmetic. Archive for Mathematical Logic 57(7–8), 953980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurahashi, T. (2020). A note on derivability conditions. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 85(3), 12241253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Makinson, D. (1971). Some embedding theorems for modal logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 12, 252254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rautenberg, W. (2010). A Concise Introduction to Mathematical Logic (third revised and enlarged edition). London: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinhardt, W. N. (1985). Absolute versions of incompleteness theorems. Nôus, 19(3), 317346.Google Scholar
Reinhardt, W. N. (1986). Epistemic theories and the interpretation of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 15, 427474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, S. (1985). Epistemic and intuitionistic arithmetic. In Intensional Mathematics (Stewart Shapiro (ed.)). North-Holland: Amsterdam. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Vol. 113, pp. 1146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solovay, R. M. (1976). Provability interpretations of modal logic. Israel Journal of Mathematics, 25, 287304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1 Implications for consistent r.e. extensions T of $\mathbf {PA}(\mathbf {K4})$ with $T \nvdash \Box \bot $.