Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2009
To speak of the self is to fix one's attention inward; to speak of social and political things is to direct one's attention outward toward those with whom our life is mysteriously and often involuntarily bound. What do “they,” those fellow citizens, want from us? Shall we approach them openly, guardedly, or perhaps not at all? Shall we look away, turn inward and thus fulfill ourselves? What, precisely, is involved in responding to the others?
1 See Smith, Logan Pearsall, The English Language (New York, 1912), pp. 233–46Google Scholar.
2 Löwith, Karl, From Hegel to Nietzsche, trans. Green, David E. (Garden City, New York, 1967), p. 305Google Scholar.
3 Löwith, , Hegel to Nietzsche, p. 232Google Scholar.
4 Rousseau, Jeanjacques, The Social Contract and Discourses, trans. Cole, G. D. H. (New York, 1950); Second Discourse, p. 211Google Scholar.
5 Ibid., p. 223.
6 This is deeply puzzling, perhaps inexplicable. See Charvet, John, The Social Problem in the Philosophy of Rousseau (Cambridge, 1974)Google Scholar, esp. chap. 2; and also his “Individual Identity and Social Consciousness in Rousseau's Philosophy,” in Hobbes and Rousseau, ed. Cranston, M. and Peters, R. S. (Garden City, New York, 1972), pp. 462–83Google Scholar.
7 Rousseau, , Second Discourse, p. 241Google Scholar.
8 Taylor, Charles, Hegel (Cambridge, 1975), p. 15CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
9 Rousseau, Jean Jacques, Emile, trans. Bloom, A. (New York, 1979), p. 40Google Scholar.
10 Rousseau, , Social Contract, bk. 2, chap. 7, p. 38Google Scholar.
11 Rousseau, , Emile, p. 40Google Scholar.
12 Ibid., p. 252. See, Introduction, ibid., pp. 17–20; and also Charvet, , Philosophy of Rousseau, p. 69Google Scholar.
13 See Rousseau, , Emile, p. 41Google Scholar.
14 See Masters, Roger D., The Political Philosophy of Rousseau (Princeton, 1968), pp. 293–300Google Scholar; and also Boyd, William, The Educational Theory of J. J. Rousseau (New York, 1963), pp. 132–33, 144–45, 155–58Google Scholar.
15 Rousseau, , Social Contract and Discourses (Second Discourse), pp. 190–91.Google Scholar
16 Boyd, , Educational Theory of Rousseau, p. 187Google Scholar.
17 The works to be examined are Schrader, George A., “Responsibility and Existence,” in Existential Phenomenology and Political Theory, ed. Jung, H. Y. (Chicago, 1972), pp. 265–93Google Scholar; and also Pitkin, Hanna F., Wittgenstein and Justice (Berkeley, 1972)Google Scholar. On the self being “situated,” Schrader writes, “the self would not be a self if it did not exist in a world with other selves” (p. 280). And Pitkin, , “In reality, contrary to the assumptions of contract theory, we are born into society as virtual non-persons. We become persons, become who we are only by internalizing (some of) the norms, standards, and patterns of our society” (p. 199)Google Scholar. Cf. also, ibid., p. 334.
18 Schrader, , “Responsibility and Existence,” p. 280.Google Scholar
19 Ibid., p. 271.
20 Ibid., p. 277.
21 Ibid., p. 271.
22 Ibid., pp. 276–77.
23 Cf. Grene, Marjorie, The Knower and the Known (Berkeley, 1974), p. 158Google Scholar.
24 Schrader, , “Responsibility and Existence,” p. 272Google Scholar.
25 Ibid., p. 282.
26 Ibid., p. 283.
27 Idem.
28 Cf. Grene, , Knower and Known, pp. 158–59Google Scholar.
29 Schrader, , “Responsibility and Existence,” p. 285Google Scholar.
30 Ibid., p. 292.
31 Ibid., p. 284 (italics mine). Cf. Schrag, Calvin O., Existence and Freedom (Northwestern University Press, 1961)Google Scholar: “An authentic self-being cannot be fully achieved until resolution sets the other free for the choice of himself (p. 204).
32 Schrader, , “Responsibility and Existence,” p. 284Google Scholar.
33 Ibid., p. 288.
34 Idem.
35 Cf. Zetterbaum, Marvin, “Equality and Human Need,” American Political Science Review, 71 (1977), 993 ffCrossRefGoogle Scholar.
36 Schrader, , “Responsibility and Existence,” p. 291Google Scholar.
37 Ibid., p. 268 (italics mine).
38 Ibid., p. 270.
39 Ibid., p. 268.
40 Ibid., p. 269.
41 Ibid., p. 288.
42 Pitkin, , Wittgenstein, p. 7Google Scholar.
43 Ibid., p. 17.
44 Ibid., p. 272.
45 Ibid., p. 134.
46 Ibid., p. 138. Cf. also pp. 293–94.
47 Ibid., p. 149.
48 Idem.
49 Ibid., p. 272.
50 Ibid., p. 155.
51 Ibid., pp. 153–54.
52 Pitkin refers to Kenneth Minogue “who argues that whereas traditional moral philosophy seems ‘concerned either to discover or to analyze reasons why we ought to do the right thing,’ the real ‘moral significance’ of discourse about action ‘is found in the discoveries we make about ourselves in the course of our deliberations, the kind of temptations we encounter, and the moral character which is implied by the act when it is done’” Ibid., p. 154 fn. 56).
53 Ibid., p. 156.
54 Ibid., pp. 156–57.
55 Ibid., p. 156.
56 Ibid., p. 155.
57 Ibid., p. 237.
58 See ibid., pp. 154–56.
60 Ibid., p. 237.
61 Cf. Schrader, , “Responsibility and Existence,” p. 289Google Scholar.
62 Pitkin, , Wittgenstein, p. 154Google Scholar.
63 Ibid., p. 16.
64 Ibid., p. 17.
65 Idem.
66 Ibid., p. 237 (italics mine). In the penultimate paragraph of her work (p. 339), Pitkin argues that a Wittgensteinian approach requires us to take other cultures seriously, “that we become able to see from the perspective of another.” To the extent to which this can be accomplished, it would appear that individuals would no longer be trapped, each “in his own subjectivity.” I understand Pitkin to mean that this aspiration is desirable but ultimately unattainable.
67 Ibid., p. 326.
68 Ibid., p. 208.
69 Idem.
70 Ibid., p. 321.
71 Ibid., pp. 339–40.
72 Ibid., p. 217.
73 Schrader, , “Responsibility and Existence,” pp. 268–69Google Scholar.
74 See, however, McArdle, Ann, “Rousseau on Rousseau: The Individual and Society,” Review of Politics, 39 (04 1977), 276CrossRefGoogle Scholar “from the time he began to read, [Rousseau] dates the uninterrupted consciousness of himself: his consciousness of himself occurs at the same time as he imagines himself to be another.”
75 Natanson, Maurice, The Journeying Self (Reading, Massachusetts, 1970), p. 108Google Scholar.
76 Gasset, Jose Ortega y, What Is Philosophy? (New York, 1960), pp. 227–28Google Scholar.
77 See Taylor, , Hegel, pp. 537–46Google Scholar.
78 Trilling, Lionel, Sincerity and Authenticity (Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1971), p. 1Google Scholar
79 Taylor, , Hegel, p. 541Google Scholar.
80 Idem.
81 Ortega, , What Is Philosophy?, pp. 149–50Google Scholar.