Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2009
Contrary to Arendt's claims, totalitarianism is not unique to the modern world. It is found occasionally in past ages and is exemplified in Shaka's rule over the Zulu. It is not clear whether the ideological “logic” of modern dictators differs from the seemingly paranoid behavior of Shaka or of certain ancient despots. Indeed, if Aristotle's account is accurate, certain extreme despots, by definition, treated citizens as slaves or household laborers. They thus projected the private realm into the public, effectively abolishing both; Arendt is wrong to say that modern dictators were the first to do so.
1 Burrows, Robert, “Totalitarianism: The Revised Standard Version,” World Politics 21 (01 1969)Google Scholar. As we shall see, Burrows is not entirely hostile to the concept of totalitarianism.
2 Spiro, Herbert J. and Barber, Benjamin R., “Counter-Ideological Uses of ‘Totalitarianism,’” Politics and Society 1 (11 1970): 3–5.Google Scholar
3 Spiro, Herbert J., “Totalitarianism,” International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, ed. Sills, David, vol. 16 (New York: Macmillan and the Free Press, 1968).Google Scholar
4 See for example, Schapiro, Leonard, Totalitarianism (London: Pall Mall, 1972)Google Scholar; Curtis, C. Michael, Totalitarianism (New Brunswick: Transaction, 1977)Google Scholar; Latey, Maurice, Patterns of Tyranny (New York: Atheneum, 1969)Google Scholar; Friedrich, Carl and Brzezinski, Z. K., Totalitarian Dictatorship and Autocracy (New York: Praeger, 1961).Google Scholar
5 See Kirkpatrick, Jeane J., Dictatorships and Double Standards (New York and Washington: American Enterprise Institute and Simon and Schuster, 1982)Google Scholar and the collection 1984 Revisited, ed. Howe, Irving (New York: Harper and Row, 1983)Google Scholar, especially the essays of Michael Walzer and Leszek Kolakowski. For a radical view see Marcuse, Herbert, One Dimensional Man (Boston: Beacon, 1964).Google Scholar
6 Whitfield, Stephen J., Into the Dark: Hannah Arendt and Totalitarianism (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1980)Google Scholar. Chapter one contains a fine review of the uses of the term totalitarianism.
7 Spiro, and Barber, , “Counter-Ideological Uses of ‘Totalitarianism,’” p. 19 n. 32.Google Scholar
8 Arendt, Hannah, The Origins of Totalitarianism, 2nd ed. (New York: Meridian, 1958), p. 509.Google Scholar
9 The Origins of Totalitarianism, 3rd ed. (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1968), p. xxxviGoogle Scholar. All further references will be to this edition except as noted.
10 Whitfield, , Into the Dark, chap. 1.Google Scholar
11 Ibid., p. 27.
12 Burrows, Robert, “Totalitarianism: The Revised Standard Version,” p. 280.Google Scholar
13 Ibid., pp. 276, 279.
14 Ibid., p. 280.
15 Ibid., pp. 276–77.
16 Ibid., p. 275.
17 Ibid., p. 277 citing The Origins, p. xxxi.Google Scholar
18 Arendt, , The Origins, pp. xxxiii–xxxiv.Google Scholar
19 Aristotle, Politics 1292a17, b8Google Scholar. The translation of SirBarker, Ernest (New York: Oxford University Press, 1958)Google Scholar has been used and consulted. I have sometimes altered the phrasing or compared it with Newman, W. L.'s edition of the text (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1902).Google Scholar
20 Whitfield, , Into the Dark, p. 29.Google Scholar
21 Arendt, , The Origins (London: Unwin, 1967), p. viiff.Google Scholar
22 Arendt, , The Origins, p. viii.Google Scholar
23 Ibid., p. 148 n.45.
24 Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth, Hannah Arendt: For Love of the World (New Haven: Yale, 1982), p. 405Google Scholar, notes that Arendt called herself “a kind of phenomenologist” but not like Husserl or Heidegger. For an excellent analysis of Arendt's debt to Heidegger, see Hinchman, Lewis P. and Hinchman, Sandra K., “In Heidegger's Shadow: Hannah Arendt's Phenomenological Humanism,” The Review of Politics 46 (04 1984)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Cf. p. 188 where the authors stress Arendt's resistance to going “behind the data of consciousness to find their putative causes or psychological origins.”
25 Arendt, , “A Reply” (to Eric Voegelin's review of The Origins) in The Review of Politics 15 (01 1953): 76–84.Google Scholar
26 Kateb, George, Hannah Arendt: Politics, Conscience, Evil (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984), pp. 53–54.Google Scholar
27 Arendt, , The Origins, pp. 368, 385.Google Scholar
28 Kateb, , Hannah Arendt, p. 81.Google Scholar
29 Plato, Republic 579dGoogle Scholar says of the tyrannical soul, “he can never satisfy his desires.”
30 Arendt, , The Origins, pp. 387, 374.Google Scholar
31 Ibid., p. 325.
32 Ibid., p. 373.
33 Ibid., pp. 384, 375n.
34 Ibid., pp. 345–46.
35 Ibid. Thus in distinguishing leaders' personalities from those of followers, Tucker, Robert C. says, “Hitler would in all probability not have had a successful career in the Reichsbank under Hitler.”Google Scholar See “The Dictator and Totalitarianism,” World Politics 17 (07 1965): 577Google Scholar. For another discussion of this point see Aronson, Ronald, The Dialectics of Disaster (London: NLB, 1985), chap. 2, esp. pp. 37–41.Google Scholar
36 Ibid., p. xxxvii.
37 Ibid., pp. xxvi, xxix.
38 For Arendt's view of the uncovering of hypocrisy, see her discussion of Brecht, in The Origins, p. 335Google Scholar, and of Robespierre and the Terror in On Revolution (New York: Viking, 1962), pp. 91–101Google Scholar. Cf. n. 24 above and n. 45.
39 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 468.Google Scholar
40 Ibid., p. 249, citing Delos, , La Nature (Montreal, 1944).Google Scholar
41 Ibid., p. 471.
42 Ibid., p. 458.
43 Ibid., p. 353.
44 Ibid., pp. 457–58. Cf. pp. 453, 412. For a discussion of the relationship between “personal” and “social” logic, see Aronson, , The Dialectics of Disaster, pp. 121–27.Google Scholar
45 See the connection between the concept of ideology and suspicion in Mannheim, Karl's Ideology and Utopia, trans. Wirth, Louis and Shils, Edward (New York: Harcourt, Brace, n.d.), pp. 63–64Google Scholar. I find it difficult to accept in its entirety Robert C. Tucker's separation of ideology from the paranoid personality. Rather, as he himself hints elsewhere, we should look upon the leader as the author of personal delusions expressed and functioning in ideological terms of which he is also partly the author (“The Dictator and Totalitarianism,” p. 571, cf. pp. 580–81).Google Scholar
46 Plato, Republic 576aGoogle Scholar. Cf. 567d; Hiero, , I, 38Google Scholar. Cf. Aristotle who puts into the mouth of the tyrant, “all men want my overthrow, but my friends have the power to effect it; distrust them above all others” (Politics 1313b25).
47 Alliluyeva, Svetlana, Twenty Letters to a Friend (New York: Harper & Row, 1967), p. 78.Google Scholar
48 Ibid., pp. 196–97.
49 Alliluyeva, Svetlana, Only One Year (New York: Harper & Row, 1969), p. 205Google Scholar. The author attributes too much responsibility for the terror to Beria. Roy Medvedev says Stalin was a more traditional tyrant motivated by power and jealousy. Distinguishing between real mental illness and various abnormal states, he denies that Stalin was a fully pathological paranoid schizophrenic and insists that he was fully responsible for his actions. Yet he admits Stalin's “morbid suspiciousness” and “serious psychic derangement,” and he compares Stalin's motives to those of Nero: a jealousy of anyone who could outperform him. Let History Judge: The Origin and Consequences of Stalinism (London: Spokesman, 1976), pp. 306, 313, 316, 351Google Scholar. Alec Nove, on the other hand, speaks of Stalin, 's “pathological suspiciousness” (Was Stalin Really Necessary [London: Unwin, 1964], p. 29).Google Scholar
50 Alliluyeva, , Twenty Letters to a Friend, p. 205.Google Scholar
51 Arendt, , The Origins, pp. 417–18.Google Scholar
52 Politics 1314b1 ffGoogle Scholar. This is the observation of Newman, W. L., The Politics of Aristotle, vol. 4, p. lxiGoogle Scholar. Cf. Politics 1285 a-b. See also Section 5 of the present essay for an elaboration of this point.
53 For a discussion of Lord Shang, see Yu-Ning, Li, ed., Shang Yang's Reforms and State Control in China (White Plains: M. E. Sharpe, 1977)Google Scholar. Cf. Cohn, Norman, The Pursuit of the Millennium (New York: Harper & Row, 1962)Google Scholar; Moore, Barrington Jr., “Totalitarian Elements in Pre-Industrial Societies,” in Political Power and Social Theory (New York: Harper & Row, 1965), pp. 59–73Google Scholar. On Shaka, see particularly Eugene Walter, Victor, Terror and Resistance: A Study of Political Violence (New York: Oxford, 1969)Google Scholar. This is an important work.
54 Arendt, , Between Past and Future (New York: Viking, 1968), p. 41.Google Scholar
55 Arendt, , The Origins, pp. 218–21.Google Scholar
56 Moore, , Political Power and Social Theory, pp. 78–79; 35–36.Google Scholar
57 Arendt, , The Origins, pp. 191–92Google Scholar, citing James, Selwyn, South of the Congo (London: John Long, 1944)Google Scholar. However, James refers to Shaka as “a black Hitler” and briefly compares him to modern totalitarians. Cf. p. 19.
58 An observer of Shaka, Nathaniel Isaacs, agreed calling Shaka's regime “Zoolucratical (For I do not know of anything resembling it in either ancient or modern history), a form that defies description or detail that can neither be comprehended nor digested” (Isaacs, , Travels and Adventures in East Africa [Cape Town: Van Riebeeck Society, 1936], p. 269; cf. pp. 272, 275).Google Scholar
59 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 470.Google Scholar
60 Ritter, E. A., Shaka Zulu (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978), p. 354Google Scholar. Citing Fynn, Henry Francis, The Diary of Henry Francis Fynn (Pietermaritzburg: Shuter & Shooter, 1950).Google Scholar
61 Isaacs, , Travels, pp. 95–96, 206, 283Google Scholar; Fynn, , Diary, p. 19.Google Scholar
62 Ritter, E. A., Shaka Zulu, p. 180; cf. p. 290.Google Scholar
63 Arendt, , The Origins, pp. 473, 350, 427. Cf. p. 349Google Scholar where Hitler's “prediction” of the annihilation of European Jews is quoted.
64 Walter, , Terror and Resistance, pp. 163–64.Google Scholar
65 Ritter, , Shaka Zulu, p. 174.Google Scholar
66 Walter, , Terror and Resistance, p. 256.Google Scholar
67 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 192.Google Scholar
68 Isaacs, , Travels, p. 62Google Scholar; Fynn, , Diary, p. 139.Google ScholarWalter, , Terror and Resistance, pp. 253–54.Google Scholar Walter calls such views Grundnorms, touchstones of legitimacy (p. 256).Google Scholar
69 Sansom, Basil, “Traditional Rulers and Their Realms,” in Hammond-Tooke, W. D., The Bantu Speaking Peoples of Southern Africa (London: Routledge, 1974), p. 280.Google Scholar Cf. Gluckman, Max, “The Kingdom of the Zulu of South Africa” in African Political Systems, ed. Fortes, M. and Pritchard, E. Evans (London: Oxford University Press, 1940), p. 31.Google Scholar
70 Fynn, , Diary, pp. 147–48; cf. p. 19.Google Scholar
71 Ibid., pp. 139, 144.
72 Ibid., p. 144.
73 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 415.Google Scholar As with modern totalitarians, Shaka “looked forward … with a sort of prophetic spirit for the day to arrive when all his anticipations should be realized…. The success of his operations soon verified his predictions” (Isaacs, , Travels, p. 273).Google Scholar Shaka made wide use of prophecies which he had carefully stage-managed (see Isaacs, , Travels, pp. 276–80).Google Scholar
74 Walter, , Terror and Resistance, p. 258.Google Scholar
75 Ibid., p. 6.
76 Walter, , Terror and Resistance, pp. 134–35.Google Scholar Cf. Fynn, , Diary, pp. 28–29Google Scholar; Isaacs, , Travels, pp. 62, 92, 131–35.Google Scholar
77 Ibid., p. 135.
78 Moore, , Political Power and Social Theory, p. 35.Google Scholar
79 Fynn is strongly of this opinion. Cf. Diary, pp. 139–44.Google Scholar See also Walter, , Terror and Resistance, pp. 279–89.Google Scholar Similar tendencies are found in ancient China: The Confucian, Chu Hsi, complained bitterly of Shang Yang's “reforms” in which the “evils of disturbance and deception unavoidably arose in the giving and the taking of the land” (Yu-Ning, Li, Shang Yang's Reforms, p. xvi).Google Scholar Hsun Tzu complained of the “terror and apprehension” of unalleviated insecurity (Ibid., p. xix); and the literate complained that under Lord Shang's reforms “the people were terrorized, not knowing where to place their feet” (ibid., xxxiii). See The Book of Lord Shang, trans, by Duyvendak, J. J. L. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963).Google Scholar We should remember that Arendt distinguishes between genocide or mass killing that clearly has pretotalitarian origins (as in the massacre of the Armenians by the Turks) and the kind of killing carried out by Shaka which “is no longer a means to frighten people” (Arendt, , The Origins, p. 440).Google Scholar That Shaka did engage in mass murder, there is no doubt. Fynn admits that the number of deaths Shaka occasioned “has been left to conjecture, but exceed a million.” Bird, J., Annals of Natal (Pietermaritzburg: Davis, 1888), p. 67.Google ScholarHattersly, A. F. says that “Natal in 1824 was almost completely depopulated” (The British Settlement of Natal [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1950], p. 13).Google Scholar
80 Arendt, , The Origins, pp. 365, 369.Google Scholar
81 Walter, , Terror and Resistance, pp. 166, 173.Google Scholar
82 Ibid., p. 191.
83 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 365 n. 62.Google Scholar She notes that Himmler disdained defining the word “Jew” lest it could not be changed.
84 Arendt, , Between Past and Future, p. 164.Google Scholar
85 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 78.Google Scholar
86 Ibid., pp. 374 n. and 325.
87 Walter, , Terror and Resistance, p. 164.Google Scholar Cf. Isaacs, , Travels, p. 133.Google Scholar
88 Suetonius, , The Twelve Caesars (Baltimore: Penguin 1969), pp. 165–66.Google Scholar
89 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 372 n. 82.Google Scholar
90 Ibid., p. 322.
91 Walter, , Terror and Resistance, pp. 153–55.Google Scholar
92 Moore, , Political Power and Social Theory, p. 71.Google Scholar
93 Aristotle Politics 1313b1.
94 Walter, , Terror and Resistance, p. 154.Google Scholar
95 Aristotle Politics 1313b5.
96 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 440.Google Scholar
97 Ibid., pp. 438, 453, 455, 457.
98 Ibid., p. 467.
99 Ibid., p. 465.
100 Ibid., p. 466. In this respect, Arendt's view is the opposite of Joseph Gabel's which argues, in Bergsonian terms, that space, not motion, is the source of ideological thought and false consciousness. For Gabel, the “morbid rationalism” or the various neuroses including dissociation and depersonalization arise from reification, “the preponderance of static, anti-dialectical spatial experience” (Gabel, , False Consciousness: An Essay in Reification, trans. Margaret, and Thompson, Kenneth [New York: Harper, 1978], p. 22).Google Scholar
101 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 474.Google Scholar
102 Ibid., p. 475.
103 Ibid.
104 Ibid., p. 477.
105 Ibid., p. 477, citing Luther, , “Warum die Einsamkeit fliehen,” in Erbauliche Schriften.Google Scholar
106 Aristotle, PoliticsGoogle Scholar 1314a14.
107 Politics 1311b36.
108 Politics 1302b20.
109 Politics 1313b1.
110 Politics 1313bl. See page 196 above.
111 Arendt, , The Origins, p. 475.Google Scholar Italics added.
112 Ibid., pp. 438, 453, 457.
113 Aristotle, Politics 1260b5, 1254b24, 16, 3.Google Scholar Cf. Plato, Phaedo 80a.Google Scholar As Newman puts it, “how any form of moral virtue can subsist without the deliberative faculty Aristotle does not explain” (The Politics of Aristotle, vol. 1, p. 149).Google Scholar
114 Arendt, , Between Past and Future, p. 105.Google Scholar
115 Aristotle Politics 1313b5.
116 Aristotle Politics 1295a16. Cf. 1279b16, where tyranny is defined as “single-person government of the city on the lines of despots” (despotikē). W. L. Newman concludes that in the Politics “the name, tyranny, may be given to any office exercising despotic authority” (The Politics of Aristotle, vol. 4, p. lxi).Google Scholar
117 Politics 1279b7.
118 Politics 1334a1–2. Cf. Plato, Laws 697.Google Scholar
119 Politics 1279a21. Cf. 1292a17 and b8.
120 Politics 1295a21.
121 Politics 1285b2. Cf. 1295a15.
122 Newman, W. L., ed., The Politics of Aristotle, vol. 4, p. lxi.Google Scholar Cf. the discussion of the benign despot at 1314b1 ff. and especially at 1315b 1.
123 Politics 1285b1; 1295a16.
124 Politics 1315b1–5, a5.
125 Politics 1260b2–8.
126 Politics 1252b6.
127 Politics 1260b7, 1314a14, and 1325a25, where it is said that there is “nothing noble in having the use of a slave insofar as he is a slave; or in issuing commands about necessary things.”
128 Politics 1252b7.
129 Politics 1313b34–36.
130 Politics 1313b40; 1325a29.
131 Arendt, , Between Past and Future, p. 106.Google Scholar