Published online by Cambridge University Press: 11 September 2019
We propose a two-step method for studying the history of political thought roughly in line with the contextualism of the Cambridge School. It reframes the early Cambridge School as a bug-detecting program for the outdated conceptual baggage we unknowingly accommodate with our political terminology. Such accommodation often entails propositions that are inconsistent with even our most cherished political opinions. These bugs can cause political arguments to crash. This reframing takes seriously the importance of theories of meaning in the formative methodological arguments of the Cambridge School and updates the argument in light of new developments. We argue the new orthodoxy of Saul Kripke's causal theory of meaning in the philosophy of language better demonstrates the importance of contextual analysis to modern political theory.
This paper was given at APSA in San Franciso in 2017 we thank the audience for their comments. We also thank Ruth Abbey, Signy Gutnick Allen, Sophie Fehlberg, Jonathan Floyd, Anne Gelling, Ian Hampshire-Monk, Edmund Handby, Christopher Meckstroth, Kari Palonen, Marija Taflaga, John Uhr, Ryan Walter and the four anonymous reviewers.
1 Brett, Annabel, “What Is Intellectual History Now?,” in What Is History Now?, ed. Cannadine, David (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2002), 116–17Google Scholar; Pocock, J. G. A., “Quentin Skinner: The History of Politics and the Politics of History,” Common Knowledge 10, no. 3 (2004): 532–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bevir, Mark, “The Contextual Approach,” in The Oxford Handbook of the History of Political Philosophy, ed. Klosko, George (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011)Google Scholar.
2 Skinner, Quentin, “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas,” History and Theory 8, no. 1 (1969): 27, 44CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Skinner, , Visions of Politics, vol. 1, Regarding Method (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 1–2Google Scholar, 98, 103–27; Skinner, , Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 8Google Scholar.
3 Graham, Keith, “Illocution and Ideology,” in Issues in Marxist Philosophy, ed. Mepham, John and Ruben, D. H. (Brighton: Harvester, 1981), 173Google Scholar; Shapiro, Ian, “Realism in the Study of the History of Ideas,” History of Political Thought 3 (1982): 537Google Scholar; Hollis, Martin, “Say It with Flowers,” in Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and His Critics, ed. Tully, James (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988), 146Google Scholar.
4 See Melzer, Arthur, “Esotericism and the Critique of Historicism,” American Political Science Review 100, no. 2 (2006): 279–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
5 Haslanger, Sally, “What Are We Talking About? The Semantics and Politics of Social Kinds,” in Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
6 Kripke, Saul, Reference and Existence: The John Locke Lectures (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
7 Skinner, “Meaning and Understanding,” 12, 20–22; the target being Strauss, Leo, Persecution and the Art of Writing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952)Google Scholar.
8 Strauss, Leo, Liberalism Ancient and Modern (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968), 5Google Scholar.
9 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001)Google Scholar, 18e.
10 Skinner, “Meaning and Understanding.”
11 Grice, Paul, “Meaning,” Philosophical Review 66, no. 3 (1957): 377–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
12 See Gunnell, J. G., “The Myth of the Tradition,” American Political Science Review 82 (1978): 71–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Condren, Conal, The Status and Appraisal of Classic Texts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
13 See Ball, Terence, Farr, James, and Hanson, Russell L., eds., Political Innovation and Conceptual Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)Google Scholar as well as Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:175–87.
14 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:117.
15 Quentin Skinner, “The State,” in Political Innovation and Conceptual Change, 90–131, and Pettit, Philip, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997)Google Scholar.
16 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London: Kegan Paul, 2010)Google Scholar, 5.6.
17 Pocock, J. G. A., “Verbalizing a Political Act: Toward a Politics of Speech,” Political Theory 1, no. 1 (1973): 27–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
18 Skinner, “Meaning and Understanding,” 46.
19 Ibid., 47.
20 Austin, J. L., How to Do Things with Words, ed. Urmson, J. O. (Oxford: Clarendon, 1962)Google Scholar.
21 Skinner, Quentin, “Some Problems in the Analysis of Political Thought and Action,” Political Theory 2, no. 3 (1974): 283CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
22 Ibid., 280.
23 Stalnaker, Robert, “Critical Notice of Scott Soames's Case against Two-Dimensionalism,” Philosophical Review 116, no. 2 (2007): 251‒66CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Soames, Scott, Philosophy of Language (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2010)Google Scholar.
24 Jackson, Frank, “Only Connect,” in Philosophy's Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress, ed. Blackford, Russell and Broderick, Damien (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley, 2017)Google Scholar.
25 Kripke, Saul, Naming and Necessity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980), 91Google Scholar.
26 Kripke, Reference and Existence, 13.
27 Putnam, Hilary, “Meaning and Reference,” Journal of Philosophy 70, no. 4 (1973): 704CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
28 Saxonhouse, Arlene, “Texts and Canons: The Status of Great Books in Political Theory,” in Political Science: The State of the Discipline, ed. Finifter, Ada (Washington, DC: American Political Science Association, 1983), 13Google Scholar.
29 Zerilli, Linda, “Machiavelli's Sisters: Women and ‘the Conversation’ of Political Theory,” Political Theory 19, no. 2 (1991): 257CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
30 Also see Kaplan, David, “Demonstratives,” in Themes from Kaplan, ed. Almog, J., Perry, John, and Wettstein, H. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989)Google Scholar.
31 Jenco, Leigh, “‘What Does Heaven Ever Say?’: A Methods-Centered Approach to Cross-Cultural Engagement,” American Political Science Review 101, no. 4 (2007): 741–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
32 Saxonhouse, “Texts and Canons,” 12.
33 Skinner, “The State,” 90–131.
34 Skinner, Quentin, “Hobbes and the Purely Artificial Person of the State,” in Visions of Politics, vol. 3, Hobbes and Civil Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002)Google Scholar.
35 Kripke, Naming and Necessity, 163.
36 Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. Macpherson, C. B. (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1968), 220Google Scholar.
37 Ibid., 81, 602.
38 See Pocock, J. G. A., Politics, Language, and Time (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989)Google Scholar.
39 Orwell, George, The Orwell Reader: Fiction, Essays, and Reportage (New York: Harcourt, 1984), 357Google Scholar.
40 See Ball, Farr, and Hanson, Political Innovation and Conceptual Change.
41 Soames, Scott, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, vol. 2, The Age of Meaning (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Philosophy of Language (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2010), pace Dummett, Michael, Frege: Philosophy of Language (New York: Harper & Row, 1973), 197Google Scholar.
42 Soames, Philosophical Analysis, 2:433.
43 We have dropped the Kripkean terminology of rigidity here as it has been shown to underdetermine terms that trip the causal theory and constitute necessary a posteriori identities (Soames, Philosophical Analysis). As it happens, however, appraisive terms are rigid in the sense that they are indexed in every possibility to their referent in the historically fixed ideal possible world.
44 Dworkin, Ronald, Justice in Robes (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2007)Google Scholar, 153, 155.
45 Gallie, W. B., “Essentially Contested Concepts,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56, no. 2 (1956): 167–98Google Scholar, esp. 175.
46 Dunn, John, The Political Thought of John Locke: An Historical Account of the “Two Treatises of Government” (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 263CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
47 Ibid., 219.
48 Pace Dunn (ibid., 7).
49 Ibid., 87.
50 Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1974)Google Scholar.
51 See Kripke, Reference and Existence, 41.
52 See Kaplan, “Demonstratives,” for a further elaboration on the distinction.
53 Kripke, Reference and Existence, 29.
54 Plato, The Republic, ed. G. R. F. Ferrari, trans. Tom Griffith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 120.
55 Ibid., 126.
56 Ibid., 174.
57 Collingwood, R. G., Human Nature and Human History (Brooklyn, NY: Haskell House, 1936), 29Google Scholar.
58 Of course, some Christians deny that the Garden of Eden is a nonactual metaphor.
59 William Bosworth, “An Interpretation of Political Argument,” European Journal of Political Theory, published online September 7, 2016, doi:10.1177/1474885116659842.
60 See Melzer, “Esotericism and the Critique of Historicism.”
61 J. Heilbrunn, “Donald Trump's Brains,” New York Review of Books, Dec. 21, 2017.