Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T21:06:52.917Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Adam Smith on Impartial Patriotism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 May 2021

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Scholars have emphasized Adam Smith's critique of the dangers of patriotism, but have not paid close attention to its potential value. This article recovers from Smith's work an attractive model of patriotism without nationalism. The potential value of patriotism lies in inspiring individuals to realize an ideal of impartial beneficence, which consists in overcoming selfishness and other subpolity partialities and in promoting the greater happiness of all fellow citizens. Smith defends virtuous patriotism against strong cosmopolitanism by arguing that a global division of labor, which directs individuals to benefit their compatriots, more effectively serves the interests of humanity than directly trying to promote global happiness. This article illuminates aspects of Smith's work that contrast with the “invisible hand” argument and favor the conscious pursuit of public interest in some contexts. It contributes to recent discussions of patriotism a distinctive way of understanding its relation to impartiality.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of University of Notre Dame

1. Introduction

The ugly face of patriotism, an emotional attachment to one's country and compatriots, periodically shows itself in expressions of xenophobia and jingoism and in measures to suppress political dissent. Liberal-minded writers have generally responded to the vices of patriotism in one of two ways: by rejecting it outright,Footnote 1 or by arguing that some form of it—moderate, constructive, constitutional, etc.—is consistent with the values of liberal democracy.Footnote 2 If we go down the second path and wish to defend some form of liberal-minded patriotism, eighteenth-century political thought offers fascinating resources for contemporary political theorists. In the eighteenth century, writers on patriotism maintained the classical commitment to shared political institutions without submerging it in the language of nationalism that was to emerge after the French Revolution.Footnote 3 Some eighteenth-century political writers, such as Shaftesbury, Immanuel Kant, Richard Price, and Johann Gottfried Herder, also make a conscious effort to enlighten the classical idea of patriotism, distance it from the Roman legacy of glorifying war and conquest, and persuade lovers of their country that their duty lies in promoting peace, prosperity, and social reform.Footnote 4

This article focuses on the work of the moral philosopher and political economist Adam Smith, and recovers from it a sophisticated and attractive model of patriotism without nationalism.Footnote 5 I will not be arguing for adopting this model and for becoming Smithian patriots. My intention is rather to add Smith's voice to a philosophical conversation on what patriotism should look like for it to be normatively attractive.

The Smithian model draws a helpful distinction between the sentiment of love of country or patriotism, a form of partiality for one's country and compatriots,Footnote 6 and the virtues ideally inspired by it: public spirit, the “preference of public to private interest,”Footnote 7 and beneficence, the performance of actions intended to benefit others on the basis of proper motives.Footnote 8 According to this model, the sentiment of patriotism in itself is neither vicious nor virtuous. It is vicious when it degenerates into prejudice and animosity toward other nations and causes economic and moral harms. It is permissible when one's partiality for country and compatriots remains bound by norms of justice. It is virtuous when it inspires individuals to overcome selfishness and other subpolity partialities and to promote the greater happiness of all members of the polity.

The article makes several contributions to the growing scholarship on Smith's moral and political philosophy. First, some recent work has emphasized his critique of the economic and moral harms of patriotism, and has, at best, mentioned his view on its potential value without paying close attention to it.Footnote 9 This article offers a corrective to this prevailing tendency by reconstructing and analyzing Smith's account of virtuous patriotism (section 2). The analysis fleshes out a hitherto neglected distinction between three models of virtuous patriotism found in Smith's work, described here as heroic, aesthetic, and humane (section 3). While scholars have pointed out the significance of public spirit in Smith's work,Footnote 10 they have not reconstructed the relations between patriotism, public spirit, and beneficence. This article offers a new interpretation of the virtue of patriotism as a combination of public spirit and beneficence. I highlight Smith's depiction of the virtuous patriot as beneficent, which is distinct from Ryan Hanley's depiction of Smith's virtuous patriot as a magnanimous self-lover (section 4).Footnote 11 The article reconstructs Smith's consequentialist defense of patriotism against strong cosmopolitanism,Footnote 12 which has not been properly discussed in the scholarship, introducing what I describe as his “principle of effective beneficence,” and showing how he employs it in defense of partiality toward compatriots (section 5). The article reconstructs three forms of impartiality involved in Smith's account of virtuous patriotism—impartial judgment, impartial justice, and impartial beneficence—and explains why the third constitutes the essence of virtuous patriotism (section 6). Finally, arguing that Smith's account of patriotism idealizes the pursuit of public interest may seem counterintuitive to readers who have in mind primarily his “invisible hand” argument.Footnote 13 I aim to illuminate aspects of Smith's work that contrast with the “invisible hand” argument and to demonstrate that Smith endorses the pursuit of public interest in some contexts (section 7).

A more general aim of the article is to contribute to recent philosophical discussions of patriotism by recovering from Smith's work a distinctive way of thinking about impartial patriotism. Speaking of impartial patriotism may seem paradoxical because patriots, by definition, are partial to their country and compatriots. But as Bernard Gert has argued in an influential account of the relation between impartiality and morality, one is always impartial in some respect with regard to some group.Footnote 14 Recent philosophical work on patriotism has argued that patriots can be impartial in respect of justice with regard to all of humanity. In other words, they can be constrained by impartial, universal norms of justice.Footnote 15 As Igor Primoratz has pointed out, however, such accounts of impartial patriotism have not clearly explained why patriotism may be morally valuable rather than merely permissible.Footnote 16 In Smith's work we find an additional sense of impartiality, which better accounts for the value of patriotism. Smith's virtuous patriots realize an ideal of impartial beneficence, which consists in the overcoming of partial commitments in order to promote the happiness of a greater number of individuals who are of equal moral worth. This ideal of impartial beneficence, when realized with regard to the group of compatriots, is the core value of virtuous patriotism.

2. Two Faces of Patriotism

A growing body of scholarly literature has illuminated the significance of Smith's work beyond economics, especially as a moral and political philosopher addressing the dilemmas of commercial society. Some of this scholarship has explored Smith's idea of patriotism, but as elaborated below, it has mostly focused on his critique of the potential dangers of patriotism. This section lays the foundation for the ensuing discussion by offering a more balanced overview of Smith's treatment of the negative and positive faces of patriotism.Footnote 17

Smith's account of the negative face of patriotism highlights its economic and moral harms when it degenerates into prejudice and animosity toward other commercial nations. Smith highlights the economic harms. In his critique of mercantilism, he singles out “national prejudice and animosity” as one of the two causes—alongside “the monopolizing spirit of merchants and manufacturers”—which lead to the imposition of unreasonable and harmful restraints on free trade.Footnote 18

But there is also an accompanying moral problem: national prejudice can lead individuals to lose their moral compass and to cause injustice to outsiders. The argument, as Smith develops it in the 1790 edition of The Theory of Moral Sentiments (TMS), is an ingenious twist on his well-known doctrine of the impartial spectator. According to the doctrine, proper moral judgment is guided by a sense of praiseworthiness and blameworthiness that aspires to conform to the imagined approbation and disapprobation of an impartial spectator.Footnote 19 But in intergroup conflict, whether international or domestic, citizens are unified by their animosity toward an opposing group, and the consensus among them corrupts their moral judgment and subordinates it to a shared, deceptive moral standard, which Smith describes as the viewpoint of “the indulgent and partial spectator.” Adopting the viewpoint of the partial spectator leads the “ferocious patriot” to disregard and violate the laws of justice in dealings with the “public enemy.”Footnote 20

Smith thus turns out to be an acute analyst and critic of the adverse economic and moral effects of patriotism when it devolves from its “noble” form into “the mean principle of national prejudice.”Footnote 21 As noted above, some recent work on Smith's account of patriotism has focused on his critique of its dangers without looking as closely at its potential value. Fonna Forman has emphasized Smith's critique of national prejudice and isolationism, describing him as arguing that love of country is noble in its foundations, but “frequently whipped into group hatred.” She has said little about Smith's account of love of country beyond that.Footnote 22 Samuel Fleischacker has mentioned Smith's understanding of real love of country as love for laws and institutions that promote peace and well-being, but has focused on the “highly sceptical” aspects of his treatment of national glory and war.Footnote 23 Martha Nussbaum has rightly said that Smith articulates “a positive yet critical notion of patriotism”; yet she, too, has elaborated mainly on its “highly critical” aspects.Footnote 24 Lisa Hill has gone furthest in arguing that “Smith did not much like patriotism”; while he believed that patriotism is natural and sometimes laudable or useful, “on balance, he conceives of patriotism as doing more harm than good.”Footnote 25

Smith never says whether the potential disadvantages of patriotism outweigh its potential advantages. There is, however, ample evidence that he views some manifestations of patriotism as useful and admirable. We can see this early on in his career, in his praise for Jean-Jacques Rousseau's patriotism in the “Letter to the Authors of the Edinburgh Review” (1756). Smith applauds the patriotic spirit of Rousseau's dedication of his Discourse on Inequality (1755) to the Republic of Geneva. He describes the dedication as “an agreeable, animated, and I believe too, a just panegyric,” and adds that it “expresses that ardent and passionate esteem which it becomes a good citizen to entertain for the government of his country and the character of his countrymen.”Footnote 26 This may be a controversial example, because Smith's praise for Rousseau's patriotism has been read as satirical.Footnote 27 But the text provides no clear evidence for such a reading, and the Smith scholarship has mostly read his praise for Rousseau's patriotism as sincere.Footnote 28

Smith's major work of moral philosophy, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, provides ample evidence for his endorsement of virtuous patriotism, especially in parts IV and VI.Footnote 29 For example, when Smith speaks of the “patriot who lays down his life” for society as someone who “excites not only our entire approbation, but our highest wonder and admiration,” he is describing patriotism in favorable terms.Footnote 30 And yet, it is quite challenging to reconstruct out of the textual evidence a coherent philosophical account of virtuous patriotism, because there are some perplexing differences and tensions between Smith's comments. For instance, in part IV of TMS, Smith says that the public spirit of patriots is not commonly motivated by humane sympathy with their compatriots and points out that “love of system” can serve as an alternative source of motivation, whereas in part VI, he criticizes the “man of system,” whose attempt to impose “an ideal plan of government” brings about disorder and misery, idealizing instead the patriotic reformer “whose public spirit is prompted altogether by humanity and benevolence.”Footnote 31 I offer three keys to untangling and clarifying Smith's account of virtuous patriotism: Smith's three models of virtuous patriotism (section 3), the role of beneficence in unifying these models (section 4), and effective beneficence as the principle justifying patriotic partiality against strong cosmopolitanism (section 5).

3. Three Models of Virtuous Patriotism

The differences and tensions between Smith's comments on virtuous patriotism in TMS may reflect a development in his thought over the years. While part IV dates back to the 1759 edition of the work, part VI was added in the 1790 edition. It is possible that Smith changed his mind on some issues and neglected to smooth over all of the inconsistencies.Footnote 32 Much of the apparent confusion is cleared up if we recognize that the 1790 edition contains three different models of virtuous patriotism, distinguished by the predominant motive that prompts the patriot to virtuous action and by the general way of acting associated with it.Footnote 33

The heroic model comes up when Smith wants to illustrate what makes “the greater exertions of public spirit” admirable. True, he argues, public spirit is one of the virtues “most useful to others,” and yet the admiration for “heroic” or magnanimous acts of public spirit arises most immediately from the “great, the noble, and exalted propriety” of such acts rather than from their utility to the public.Footnote 34 The motives that Smith associates with magnanimous self-overcoming are the love of praiseworthiness, which is the desire to do the proper thing regardless of actual praise, and the love of true glory, or the desire of being praised for doing truly praiseworthy things.Footnote 35

Smith offers two striking examples of heroic patriotism: patriotic soldiers sacrificing their lives in war, and the story of Lucius Brutus, founder of the Roman Republic, ordering his two sons, who had conspired against the liberty of the new republic, to be scourged with rods and decapitated before his eyes.Footnote 36 He recognizes that such extreme acts of sacrifice for the public good tend to manifest themselves under “the boisterous and stormy sky of war and faction,”Footnote 37 and he is not calling to cultivate them in commercial society. His tendency is to relegate such acts to the ancient republics or to “savage” and “barbarous” nations—terms that he uses, in his theory of economic and social development, to describe societies of hunters and fishers and societies of shepherds, respectively.Footnote 38 Through these examples, Smith clarifies in a dramatic way what is admirable about virtuous patriotism: the overcoming of private interest for the public good.

Alongside this model of heroic patriotism, we find in part IV of TMS an entirely different story about patriots who are driven to public-spirited reform by what Smith calls “love of system” or “spirit of system.”Footnote 39 Elsewhere Smith describes the passion for creating philosophical systems—constructions of the imagination that connect otherwise discordant phenomena by a few common principles—as a fundamental characteristic of the human imagination, which is distressed by disorder and incoherence.Footnote 40 In part IV of TMS, he explains how this passion for coherence can be utilized to motivate the reform of public institutions and policies in order to promote the happiness of society. “When a patriot exerts himself for the improvement of any part of the public police,” he says, it is not commonly due to “pure sympathy with the happiness of those who are to reap the benefit of it.” In fact, some of the greatest reformers, such as Peter the Great, were “not very sensible to the feelings of humanity.” Smith argues that patriotic reformers are more likely to be drawn to the aesthetic pleasure derived from creating a beautiful and harmonious political system, and the best way to motivate them to public spirit is through systematic studies of politics.Footnote 41

In speaking of “love of system” and “spirit of system,” Smith was entering polemical grounds. On the one hand, system building is central to enlightenment science and to Smith's work itself.Footnote 42 On the other hand, the phrase “spirit of system” was pejoratively employed by sentimentalists and physiocrats in criticizing rationalist and mercantilist attempts to impose their theoretical schemes on nature.Footnote 43 As mentioned above, in part IV of TMS, Smith speaks favorably of love or spirit of system as a motivation to public spirit, but in the 1790 edition of the work, in part VI, he portrays the “spirit of system” as a dangerous motivation for political reform, animating the immoderate “man of system.” This can be read as an outright rejection of aesthetic patriotism, but if we assume, as I do, that parts IV and VI are roughly consistent, then the “man of system” can be seen as representing a perverse manifestation of aesthetic patriotism, which is more likely to show itself in some specific situations. Smith mentions two such situations: “times of public discontent, faction, and disorder,” when public sentiments are enflamed and constitutional reform might become immoderate and harmful; and the reign of arrogant and tyrannical sovereign princes, who turn the spirit of reform against any constitutional limitation of their power.Footnote 44

In contrast to the man of system, Smith introduces a third, humane model of virtuous patriotism. He describes the “real patriot” as the moderate reformer and legislator, whose “more gentle public spirit” is “founded upon the love of humanity.” This humane patriotic leader respects existing privileges and prejudices and establishes only the best political system that can be promoted without violence.Footnote 45

4. The Virtue of Patriotism

What unites these different models of patriotic action—heroic sacrifice, systematic reform, and humane leadership? In this section, I argue that these models are unified by a similar conception of the virtue of patriotism, as a combination of public spirit and beneficence.

Let us start by looking at Ryan Hanley's illuminating account of Smith's virtuous patriot as a “noble self-lover,” who is able to transcend vulgar self-preference and replace it with the magnanimous desire to have a praiseworthy character.Footnote 46 Hanley's account draws our attention to the fact that Smith describes public spirit, the virtue that he commonly associates with patriotism, as involving the spirited, magnanimous overcoming of private interest. “The great and exalted virtue of magnanimity” is identified, in Smith's work, with an exceptional exertion of self-command, which aims at “what is honourable and noble” out of regard for one's own “rank and dignity” in the eyes of real or ideal spectators.Footnote 47 Similarly to Plato, Smith identifies magnanimity with the irascible part of the soul, spirit (thumos), when it is guided by reason to pursue what is honorable and noble.Footnote 48 The rational guidance of spirit is provided, in Smith's account, by the employment of impartial judgment, which steers the agent toward what is truly honorable and noble. Some magnanimous agents are virtuous enough to be content with the imagined approval of the impartial spectator (the love of praiseworthiness), while others require, in addition, actual praise from society (the love of true glory).Footnote 49

But while Hanley's interpretation of Smith's virtuous patriot as a magnanimous self-lover perfectly captures Smith's heroic model, it sits more awkwardly with the other two models. The aesthetic patriot is predominantly motivated by the love of system rather than by the desire for status and recognition associated with magnanimity.Footnote 50 Humane patriotism is even more difficult to reconcile with magnanimity: Smith contrasts the “amiable” virtue of humanity, which is based on sympathy with others, with the “awful and respectable” virtue of magnanimity, which is based on the command of the passions and their subjection to the demands of “our own dignity and honour.”Footnote 51

These difficulties can be resolved by looking more closely at Smith's most elaborate discussion of patriotism, in a chapter found in part VI of TMS.Footnote 52 The title of the chapter, “Of the order in which Societies are by nature recommended to our Beneficence,” suggests that Smith is discussing patriotism as part of his account of the virtue of beneficence. Moreover, the broader section (TMS VI.ii), which includes the chapter on patriotism, discusses “the direction and employment of our very limited powers of beneficence,”Footnote 53 and each one of its chapters is devoted to beneficence in a different sphere of action: private (VI.ii.1), public (VI.ii.2), and universal (VI.ii.3). Smith, then, identifies patriotism with the practice of beneficence in the public sphere, the sphere of one's compatriots.Footnote 54

How exactly does beneficence help us in reconciling Smith's three models of virtuous patriotism? Beneficence is the performance of “actions of a beneficent tendency, which proceed from proper motives.”Footnote 55 The scope of actions covered by beneficence is broad: Smith implies that “proper beneficence” includes all active social duties toward others, including duties of distributive justice.Footnote 56 Arguably, the scope of motives that can prompt agents to beneficent action is also broad, and includes not only benevolent affections, but also motives that proceed from self-love.Footnote 57 Virtuous patriots aim to benefit their compatriots on the basis of various proper motives, including the love of praiseworthiness, the love of true glory, the love of system, and the love of humanity.

Why, then, does Smith speak of patriots as exhibiting “public spirit” rather than “public beneficence?” This may be partly due to contemporary moral and political discourse, which often uses “public spirit” as synonymous with virtuous patriotism.Footnote 58 But it may also indicate that, no matter which predominant motive drives the agent to beneficent actions, virtuous patriotism always involves some measure of magnanimous self-overcoming. Taking into consideration both public spirit and beneficence, I suggest that the virtue of all of Smith's virtuous patriots lies in overcoming private interest in order to benefit one's compatriots on the basis of proper motives.

Finally, Smith may be inviting us to consider the different proper motives that he mentions as complementary. In commercial society, ideal patriots would magnanimously overcome private interest not in order to risk their lives in war, but to promote the happiness of their compatriots, through the pursuit of a systematic idea of the perfection of policy and law, while showing humane respect for the established social order.Footnote 59 Arguably, Smith's ideal patriot would be a magnanimous, visionary, and humane social reformer.

5. Patriotism and Effective Beneficence

If the virtue of patriotism lies in overcoming private interest in order to promote the happiness of society, why restrict ourselves to a national society rather than preferring the interests of humanity? This section reconstructs Smith's consequentialist defense of patriotic partiality, which has not been properly discussed in the scholarship.Footnote 60 I present Smith's model of concentric circles of beneficent affections, explain his general rationale for their weakness or strength (described here as “the principle of effective beneficence”), and show how this rationale is applied in defense of patriotic partiality.

There are good reasons for viewing Smith as committed, in some sense, to cosmopolitanism, the idea that all human beings are citizens in a single world community. Scholars have described as cosmopolitan his commitments to the equal moral status of human beings, to universal norms of justice, and to a global commercial community.Footnote 61 However, he is clearly an anticosmopolitan in his treatment of beneficence in TMS.Footnote 62 Following Cicero, he distinguishes between duties of justice, whose scope is universal, and duties of beneficence, whose scope may be limited.Footnote 63 He describes the natural order of beneficent affections in terms of the Stoic model of concentric circles of affinity (oikeiōsis), starting with care of the self and progressing in concentric circles to family and relatives, friends and acquaintances, strangers distinguished by their wealth or poverty, compatriots, and other inhabitants of the universe.Footnote 64 But as Forman has pointed out, he rejects the radical Stoic prescription to become citizens of the world by eradicating the private and partial affections and cultivating indifference toward the near and dear.Footnote 65 The version of the concentric circles model that he embraces instead is roughly that of Cicero, who argues that the public fellowship with the republic holds priority over more limited and more extensive fellowships.Footnote 66

What is the rationale behind prioritizing love of country? In Cicero's account, gratitude to the republic plays a central role in accounting for civic commitment. Smith justifies patriotism on the basis of its beneficial consequences. To fully appreciate this, let us first look at his general rationale for the strength or weakness of all beneficent affections. The section on beneficence in TMS VI sets out to explain “the foundation of that order which nature seems to have traced out for the distribution of our good offices, or for the direction and employment of our very limited powers of beneficence.” Smith is not arguing that the order of beneficent affections is justified because it is natural. He is rather asking how this natural order can be justified. The answer is that the “unerring wisdom” that regulates nature directs the order of beneficent affections so that “they are always stronger or weaker in proportion as our beneficence is more or less necessary, or can be more or less useful.”Footnote 67 In other words, there is a happy, providentially ordained correspondence between the strength or weakness of beneficent affections and their utility.Footnote 68 Let us call this happy correspondence “the principle of effective beneficence.”

The principle of effective beneficence pervades Smith's discussion of the private, public, and universal spheres of action. In his discussion of private beneficence, for instance, human beings are endowed with a strong instinct of self-love because “every man is . . . fitter and abler to take care of himself.” One's love for family members comes next in the order of affections because family members are “the persons upon whose happiness or misery his conduct must have the greatest influence.” Love of relations decreases with distance and separation because one's usefulness to them decreases accordingly. And so on.Footnote 69

The chapter on patriotism employs the same logic in order to justify the motivational pull of love of country. Smith explains that the state or sovereignty is “by nature, most strongly recommended” to individuals because it is “in ordinary cases, the greatest society upon whose happiness or misery, our good or bad conduct can have much influence.”Footnote 70 The normative assumption that underlies this statement is that beneficence calls upon us to promote the good of the greatest possible number of individuals.Footnote 71 Taken on its own, this might lead to strong cosmopolitanism. But Smith counters this expansive commitment with the empirical statement that beneficence is ineffective beyond national borders. While the sentiment of universal benevolence is “noble and generous” and “circumscribed by no boundary,” he says, “our effectual good offices can very seldom be extended to any wider society than that of our own country.”Footnote 72 Smith approves of universal benevolence, but rejects universal beneficence.Footnote 73

Smith's rejection of universal beneficence can be broken down into a negative component and a positive one. Negatively, he argues that universal beneficence is doomed to fail because of the “weakness” of human powers and comprehension. Given this alleged limitation, he thinks that we should focus our energies where they would serve a clear purpose.Footnote 74 Positively, he argues, in a key paragraph, that the natural disposition of individuals to love their country for its own sake and independently of the interest of humanity is, in fact, the best way of promoting the interests of humanity:

We do not love our country merely as a part of the great society of mankind: we love it for its own sake, and independently of any such consideration. That wisdom which contrived the system of human affections, as well as that of every other part of nature, seems to have judged that the interest of the great society of mankind would be best promoted by directing the principal attention of each individual to that particular portion of it, which was most within the sphere both of his abilities and of his understanding. (TMS VI.ii.2.4, 229)

This paragraph describes a global division of beneficent labor, which directs individuals to act within their national sphere. Again, we see a providential wisdom fitting beneficent affections to beneficial ends, and in this case, designing patriotism to serve the interests of humanity.

I take no firm position here on how essential providence is to Smith's defense of patriotism.Footnote 75 Recent liberal defenses of patriotic partiality have made roughly similar arguments about a global division of positive duties without appealing to providence. In particular, Smith's consequentialist defense of patriotism resembles Robert Goodin's “assigned responsibility model.” According to Goodin, special duties toward compatriots can be reconciled with the moral principles of universality and impartiality on the assumption that specialization and division of labor will enable general duties toward people to be more effectively discharged.Footnote 76 What we can learn from Smith to enhance Goodin's account is the integration of the consequentialist argument into virtue ethics and the argument that patriotic partiality becomes justifiable insofar as it serves the exercise of beneficence.

6. Patriotism and Impartiality

Having reconstructed Smith's account of virtuous patriotism, I would like, in this section, to consider its relation to the ideal of impartiality and to ask whether and in what sense Smith's virtuous patriot is an impartial patriot.Footnote 77 I argue that Smith's virtuous patriots are impartial in several ways, and most distinctively, in overcoming private and partial interest and preferring the happiness of a greater number of individuals who are of equal moral worth.

One reason to assume from the outset that Smith thinks of patriots as being impartial is that all the threats to public spirit that he describes are forms of partiality. The villainy of traitors consists in their dramatically partial preference of their “own little interest” to the compounded interests of all of their relations and compatriots.Footnote 78 The moral corruption of religious or political fanatics consists in adopting the deceptive standard of “the indulgent and partial spectator” constructed by their surrounding in-group.Footnote 79 Mercantilist monopolists represent “the clamorous importunity of partial interests” and act against the public interest in free and universal competition.Footnote 80 Prejudiced and belligerent patriots are apt not only to cause injustice to noncompatriots, but also to act against the interest of their own compatriots in peaceful commerce.Footnote 81 Immoderate reformers allow their arrogant partiality for their own intellectual systems to cause violence to their country.Footnote 82 Smith's virtuous patriot must be immune to the seductive powers of partiality in all of these different forms: self-preference, factional fanaticism, the spirit of monopoly, national prejudice, and arrogant spirit of system.

There are three forms of impartiality involved in these dangerous forms of partiality: impartial judgment, impartial justice, and impartial beneficence. I consider them in turn and argue that impartial beneficence constitutes the essence of virtuous patriotism.

Virtuous patriots are guided, at least to some extent, by impartial judgment. The heroic patriot, in particular, “appears to view himself in the light in which the impartial spectator naturally and necessarily views him.”Footnote 83 But this is far from distinctive of patriotism. Impartial judgment is the most general kind of impartiality in Smith's moral philosophy. It guides various forms of virtuous conduct, including partial conduct. The prudent person, for instance, who sacrifices present for future enjoyment, “is always both supported and rewarded by the entire approbation of the impartial spectator.”Footnote 84

The greater drama of impartiality lies in cases in which the moral principles inspired by the imagined viewpoint of the impartial spectator compel agents to overcome their partiality for themselves or for those close to their heart. Both justice and beneficence require such self-overcoming. They differ, however, in the way in which they relate to patriotism. Impartial justice applies to the whole of humanity and operates as a constraint on virtuous patriotism.Footnote 85 Impartial beneficence applies only to the community of compatriots and can be seen as the essence of virtuous patriotism.

Some of the recent philosophical discussions of the morality of patriotism have focused on its potential compatibility with impartial, universal requirements of justice. It has been argued that such compatibility is required for patriotism to be morally permissible.Footnote 86 Smith can be reasonably interpreted as advancing a similar view in his critique of the injustice caused by national prejudice and animosity. In order for patriotism to realize its potential as a “noble” principle, it must overcome the inclination to treat neighboring nations with “little justice,” and treat all fellow human beings with fairness.Footnote 87

Smith condemns the “savage patriotism” of the Roman senator Cato the Elder, who repeatedly called for the destruction of neighboring Carthage. He contrasts it with the plea of the Roman consul Publius Cornelius Scipio Nasica Corculum not to destroy Carthage, which he describes as “the liberal expression of a more enlarged and enlightened mind.”Footnote 88 This has been interpreted as a contrast between the patriotism of Cato the Elder and the “enlarged and enlightened mind” of Scipio Nasica.Footnote 89 But Plutarch, Smith's likely source for this episode, depicts Scipio Nasica as a patriot and a conservative.Footnote 90 It seems more plausible that Smith depicts him as a just and liberal patriot, whose love of country is consistent with the love of mankind.Footnote 91

Hont has interpreted the same paragraph as presenting a “competitor to patriotism”: national emulation, or competition for the economic excellence and superiority of one's nation without envy and animosity.Footnote 92 He overlooks the fact that Smith calls for “national emulation” that involves promoting the excellence of neighboring nations, which is hardly consistent with competition.Footnote 93 He also overlooks Smith's distinction between moral and economic emulation.Footnote 94 Moral emulation is not the desire to outdo others, but the ability to learn from their excellence, or in Smith's words, “the anxious desire that we ourselves should excel” and be “as admirable as those whom we love and admire the most.”Footnote 95 In the comment on national emulation, Smith is arguing that virtuous patriots should promote the excellence of neighboring countries and derive from their excellence, in turn, the desire to improve the excellence of their own country.

Arguing for the compatibility of patriotism with impartial justice only clarifies when patriotism may be permissible, and not why it may be valuable.Footnote 96 The value of patriotism, on Smith's account, can be understood in terms of realizing an ideal of impartial beneficence. To better understand what this means and how this works, let us look more closely at Smith's description of the heroic patriot in the beginning of the chapter on patriotism:

The patriot who lays down his life for the safety, or even the vain-glory of this society, appears to act with the most exact propriety. He appears to view himself in the light in which the impartial spectator naturally and necessarily views him, as but one of the multitude, in the eye of that equitable judge, of no more consequence than any other in it, but bound at all times to sacrifice and devote himself to the safety, to the service, and even to the glory of the greater number. (TMS VI.ii.2.2, 228)

Adopting the viewpoint of the impartial spectator, virtuous patriots view themselves “as but one of the multitude . . . of no more consequence than any other in it.” They recognize that they are morally equal to others.Footnote 97 Subsequently, they prefer the overriding interest of a greater number of individuals who are of equal moral worth.

This type of moral self-overcoming is not unique to patriots. Smith says that individuals see themselves as “but one of the multitude” when they overcome natural self-preference in order to act justly.Footnote 98 But in the case of the virtuous patriot, the ability to prefer the overriding interest of a greater number of individuals who are of equal moral worth is employed not in abstaining from harming others, but in positively acting to promote their happiness. The distinctive virtue of patriots can be described as consisting in impartial beneficence, or the overcoming of selfishness and other subpolity partialities and the promotion of the greater happiness of all members of the polity.

7. Conclusion

In reconstructing and analyzing Smith's account of patriotism, I have aimed, among other things, to contribute to a body of scholarship that has questioned the image of Smith as a champion of selfishness and greed.Footnote 99 More controversially, I have sought to show that, notwithstanding his endorsement of self-preference in some economic contexts, Smith endorses the conscious pursuit of public interest as an ideal of moral excellence and as a practical principle of conduct in some social contexts.

Arguably, the virtue of public spirit, the preference of public to private interest, is the republican ideal of good citizenship. At least, this is how Montesquieu describes the republican ideal of political virtue: the preference of public interest over one's own.Footnote 100 I have refrained from using the word “republicanism,” because it brings in a host of additional problems. Whether and in what sense Adam Smith was a republican has long been a matter of contention, complicated by his enigmatic politics and by the elasticity of the concept of republicanism in the eighteenth century and in recent scholarly work. There is a strong case to be made for seeing Smith's account of patriotism as one of several ways in which he is indebted to republicanism, as he himself understood the concept, in terms borrowed from Montesquieu and from Hume. I leave the development of this argument to future work.Footnote 101

I have aimed to offer a charitable reconstruction of Smith's account of patriotism. I would be remiss not to mention some of its shortcomings. First, the argument that humanity benefits from a global division of beneficent labor, which directs individuals to act within their national sphere, is based on empirical assumptions about the epistemological and practical limitations of human beings, but Smith does not justify these. Even in his own time, effective attempts to benefit others often extended beyond national borders, for instance, in transatlantic cooperation between members of the same religious denominations in Britain and the American colonies.

Second, Smith is never clear on whether and how the ideal of seeing oneself as one of the multitude and preferring the happiness of the greater number works hand in hand with the economic and social inequality that he believes to be useful and necessary in commercial society.Footnote 102 While I cannot develop this issue here, Smith could be interpreted as embracing a division of political labor according to one's economic and social position in society, with the “middle and inferior stations of life” serving society by working, producing, obeying the law, and fulfilling their duties when called upon, and the “superior stations of life” entrusted with the more substantive expressions of public spirit.Footnote 103

Third, in his 1790 comments on constitutional reform in times of public discontent, Smith eloquently describes the tension between two patriotic principles, respect for the established constitution and the desire to promote the welfare of the whole society of one's fellow citizens;Footnote 104 but rather than laying out the theoretical dilemma and allowing for its various resolutions in different circumstances, he comes down on the side of protecting the old system against dangerous innovation. Compared to the argument that the British radical Richard Price makes around the same time, that the duty of patriots is “to liberalize and enlighten” their country, Smith's argument is uninspired and uninspiring.Footnote 105

Having said all that, political philosophers interested in patriotism have much to learn from Smith. First, his distinction between patriotism as a sentiment and the virtues associated with it, public spirit and beneficence, is insightful and helpful. Following Martha Nussbaum, I have been speaking of patriotism as a Janus-faced emotion, which has negative and positive faces,Footnote 106 but in Smithian terms, it would be more precise to say that patriotism is a morally neutral sentiment, an empirical fact, and its normative significance lies in its ability to motivate vice (national prejudice and animosity) or virtue (public spirit and beneficence). Moreover, Smith's work is helpful in thinking about different motivations for patriotic conduct (the love of praiseworthiness, the love of true glory, the love of system, the love of humanity), as well as in thinking about the role of such motivations in shaping different expressions of patriotism (heroic conduct, systematic reform, humane leadership).

Second, looking closely at Smith's account throws light on the different senses in which patriots can be impartial. In particular, it provides insight into the eighteenth-century way of thinking about the impartiality of patriots as their ability to overcome all subpolity partialities and to prefer the happiness of all of their fellow citizens. This way of understanding the possible value of patriotism, which takes as its premise the equal moral worth of individuals rather than drawing on communitarian accounts of morality, may be of particular interest to moral universalists interested in explaining what patriotism might look like at its conceptual and normative best.Footnote 107 In the midst of neoliberalism's reinvention of modern individuals as entrepreneurs of their own satisfaction,Footnote 108 and the concurrent rise of populist nationalism,Footnote 109 Smith's account of impartial patriotism offers a surprising alternative.

Footnotes

I am grateful to Sam Fleischacker, Ryan Hanley, Geneviève Rousselière, Rania Salem, Michelle Schwarze, and the editor and anonymous referees at the Review of Politics for their helpful comments on drafts of the paper. Research was supported by grant 1970/16 from the Israel Science Foundation.

References

1 Gomberg, Paul, “Patriotism Is Like Racism,” Ethics 101, no. 1 (1990): 144–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kateb, George, “Is Patriotism a Mistake?,” Social Research 67, no. 4 (2000): 901–24Google Scholar; Leo Tolstoy, “On Patriotism,” in Writings on Civil Disobedience and Nonviolence (Philadelphia: New Society, 1987), 51–123; Keller, Simon, “Patriotism as Bad Faith,” Ethics 115, no. 3 (2005): 563–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar; McCabe, David, “Patriotic Gore, Again,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 35, no. 2 (1997): 203–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Nathanson, Stephen, “In Defense of ‘Moderate Patriotism,’Ethics 99, no. 3 (1989): 535–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Schatz, Robert T., Staub, Ervin, and Lavine, Howard, “On the Varieties of National Attachment: Blind versus Constructive Patriotism,” Political Psychology 20, no. 1 (1999): 151–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Jürgen Habermas, “Citizenship and National Identity,” in Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), 491–515; Jan-Werner Müller, Constitutional Patriotism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007).

3 Mary Dietz, “Patriotism,” in Political Innovation and Conceptual Change, ed. Terence Ball, James Farr, and Russell L. Hanson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Pre,ss, 1989), 177–93; Viroli, Maurizio, For Love of Country: An Essay on Patriotism and Nationalism (Oxford: Clarendon, 1995)Google Scholar.

4 Shaftesbury, , Characteristicks of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times, ed. den Uyl, Douglas (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2001), 3:88–95Google Scholar; Immanuel Kant, “On the Common Saying: ‘This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice,’” in Political Writings, ed. H. B. Nisbet and H. S. Reiss, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 74; Richard Price, “A Discourse on the Love of Our Country,” in Political Writings, ed. D. O. Thomas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 176–96; Johann Gottfried Herder, “Do We Still Have the Fatherland of the Ancients?,” in Another Philosophy of History and Selected Political Writings, trans. Ioannis D. Evrigenis and Daniel Pellerin (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2004).

5 I have used the following abbreviations for Smith's works, using the Glasgow edition's citation system and adding page numbers.

TMS: The Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. D. D. Raphael and A. L. Macfie (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1982).

WN: An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, ed. R. H. Campbell, A. S. Skinner, and W. B. Todd (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1981).

EPS: Essays on Philosophical Subjects, ed. W. P. D. Wightman and J. C. Bryce (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1982).

LJA and LJB: “Report of 1762–3” and “Report dated 1766,” respectively, in Lectures on Jurisprudence, ed. R. L. Meek, D. D. Raphael, and P. G. Stein (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1982).

LRBL: Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres, ed. J. C. Bryce (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1985).

CAS: The Correspondence of Adam Smith, ed. E. C. Mossner and I. S. Ross (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1987).

LER: “A Letter to the Authors of the Edinburgh Review,” in EPS.

HA: “The Principles Which Lead and Direct Philosophical Enquiries; Illustrated by the History of Astronomy,” in EPS.

6 On love of country as the sentiment of the patriot, see TMS VI.ii.2.2–4, 227–29. Love of country is, for Smith, love of the “society” or “nation” of one's country, or in other words, love of one's compatriots. Smith does not explicitly discuss the potential implications of the size of the territory or the community on the sentiment of patriotism.

7 TMS VII.ii.4.8, 309. For the association between love of country and public spirit, see TMS III.6.1, 171; IV.i.11, 185–87; VI.ii.2, 227–34.

8 TMS II.ii.1.1, 78.

9 See, in particular, Forman-Barzilai, Fonna, Adam Smith and the Circles of Sympathy: Cosmopolitanism and Moral Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 23, 204–11CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fleischacker, Samuel, On Adam Smith's “Wealth of Nations”: A Philosophical Companion (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004), 250–57Google Scholar; Hill, Lisa, “Adam Smith's Cosmopolitanism: The Expanding Circles or Commercial Strangership,” History of Political Thought 31, no. 3 (2010): 449–73Google Scholar; Martha C. Nussbaum, The Cosmopolitan Tradition: A Noble but Flawed Ideal (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2019), 13–14, 172–75. A notable exception is Ryan Hanley's interpretation of Smith's virtuous patriotism in terms of magnanimity, which is discussed below. See his Adam Smith and the Character of Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 155–62.

10 Knud Haakonssen, The Science of a Legislator: The Natural Jurisprudence of David Hume and Adam Smith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), chap. 4; Douglas Long, “Adam Smith's Politics,” in The Cambridge Companion to Adam Smith, ed. Knud Haakonssen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 288–318; Eric Schliesser, Adam Smith: Systematic Philosopher and Public Thinker (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017); Donald Winch, Riches and Poverty: An Intellectual History of Political Economy in Britain, 1750–1834 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), chap. 4; Jeffrey T. Young, Economics as a Moral Science: The Political Economy of Adam Smith (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 1997), chap. 8.

11 Hanley, Character of Virtue, 157–58.

12 David Miller has defined strong cosmopolitanism as requiring “that as agents we should acknowledge equal duties or equal responsibilities to everyone in the world without exception.” See his “Cosmopolitanism: A Critique,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 5, no. 3 (2002): 84.

13 WN IV.ii.9, 456; TMS IV.i.10, 184–85.

14 Gert, Bernard, “Moral Impartiality,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 20, no. 1 (1995): 102–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 Marcia Baron, “Patriotism and ‘Liberal’ Morality,” in Patriotism, ed. Igor Primoratz (Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, 2002), 59–86; Marcia Baron and Taylor Rogers, “Patriotism and Impartiality,” in Handbook of Patriotism, ed. Mitja Sardoc (Cham: Springer, 2020), 409–27; Nathanson, “In Defense of ‘Moderate Patriotism.’”

16 Primoratz, Igor, “Patriotism and Morality: Mapping the Terrain,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 5, no. 2 (2008): 214–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 I am drawing on Martha Nussbaum's account of patriotism as a Janus-faced emotion. See Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2013), 204–56.

18 WN IV.iii.a.1–3, 474–75; IV.iii.c.9–13, 493–96. See also LJA vi.159–65, 389–92; LJB 262–65, 512–13. Smith is following in the footsteps of David Hume, who describes the boundless jealousy and hatred of the English for France as the cause of two groundless and harmful jealousies of trade: the fear that the supply of money will be drained by free trade and the fear that domestic industry will be hurt by the prosperity of a neighboring country. David Hume, “The Balance of Trade,” in Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1987), 308–26; Hume, “The Jealousy of Trade,” in Essays, 327–31.

19 TMS III.2–4, 113–61, esp. III.3.32, 130–31, III.3.26, 146–47; VI, 212–64, esp. VI.i.11, 215. On the doctrine of the impartial spectator, see D. D. Raphael, The Impartial Spectator: Adam Smith's Moral Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). My interpretation of moral judgment is informed by the different reading offered in Douglas J. Den Uyl, “Impartial Spectating and the Price Analogy,” Econ Journal Watch 13, no. 2 (2016): 264–72.

20 TMS III.3.41–42, 154–55.

21 TMS VI.ii.2.3, 228–29.

22 Forman-Barzilai, Circles of Sympathy, 23, 204–11.

23 Fleischacker, On Smith's “Wealth of Nations, 250–57.

24 Nussbaum, Cosmopolitan Tradition, 13–14, 172–75.

25 Hill, “Smith's Cosmopolitanism,” 455, 460–61.

26 LER 16, 254. For Rousseau's dedication, see his Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality among Men, in The Discourses and Other Political Writings, ed. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 114–23.

27 Daniel B. Klein, “Adam Smith's Response to Rousseau,” Adam Smith Review 7 (2014): 325–26.

28 Charles L. Griswold, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Adam Smith: A Philosophical Encounter (London: Routledge, 2018), 35–36; Jeffrey Lomonaco, “Adam Smith's ‘Letter to the Authors of the Edinburgh Review,’” Journal of the History of Ideas 63, no. 4 (Oct. 2002): 676; Peter Minowitz, Profits, Priests, and Princes: Adam Smithʾs Emancipation of Economics from Politics and Religion (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1993), 30; John Rae, Life of Adam Smith (London: Macmillan, 1895), 124; Dennis C. Rasmussen, The Problems and Promise of Commercial Society: Adam Smith's Response to Rousseau (University Park, PA: Penn State University Press, 2008), 66–68.

29 TMS IV.1.11, 185–87; IV.2.9–11, 190–92; VI.ii.2, 227–34.

30 TMS VI.ii.2.2, 228. See also TMS IV.2.10–11, 190–92.

31 TMS IV.1.11, 185–87; VI.ii.2.15–18, 232–34.

32 Fleischacker makes a similar argument regarding TMS VI.i.10 in his On Smith's “Wealth of Nations, chap. 6.

33 In speaking of motive and general way of acting, I am drawing on Smith's account of virtue in TMS I.i.3.5–7, 18; VII.iv.1–35, 327–40.

34 TMS IV.2.9–11, 190–92; VI.ii.2.2, 228.

35 TMS VII.ii.4, 306–14. See also TMS III.2, 113–34.

36 TMS IV.2.9–11, 190–92; VI.ii.2.2, 228. On Lucius Brutus and his sons, see Livy, History of Rome, trans. B. O. Foster, vol. 1 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1919), 233; Plutarch, Plutarch's Lives, trans. Bernadotte Perrin, vol. 1 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1914), 515–17.

37 TMS III.3.37, 153; VI.ii.2.13, 232.

38 TMS V.2.8–10, 204–8; VI.ii.2.3, 228–29. Like some other French and Scottish writers in that period, Smith assumes that societies undergo successive stages of economic and social development distinguished primarily by their mode of subsistence. See Ronald L. Meek, Social Science and the Ignoble Savage (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976).

39 TMS IV.i.11, 185–87.

40 HA II.12, 45–46; IV.19, 66–67; IV.76, 105; LRBL ii.132–34, 145–46; WN V.i.f.25, 768–69.

41 TMS IV.i.11, 185–87.

42 On Smith's own “love of system,” see Dugald Stewart, “Account of the Life and Writings of Adam Smith,” in EPS III.15, 306; Schliesser, Smith: Systematic Philosopher.

43 The dialectic of system in the Enlightenment is beautifully described in Jessica Riskin, “The ‘Spirit of System’ and the Fortunes of Physiocracy,” History of Political Economy 35, no. 5 (2003): 42–73.

44 TMS VI.ii.2.12–18, 231–34. See also F. P. Lock, “Adam Smith and the ‘Man of System’: Interpreting The Theory of Moral Sentiments, VI.ii.2.12–18,” Adam Smith Review, no. 3 (2007): 38–46.

45 TMS VI.ii.2.15–16, 232–33.

46 Hanley, Character of Virtue, 156–62, quote at 157–58.

47 TMS I.i.5.6, 25; I.ii.3.8, 38; I.iii.1.15, 49; II.iii.3.6, 108; IV.2.11, 191; VII.ii.1.4–7, 267–68; VII.ii.1.13, 271; VII.ii.4.2, 306; VII.ii.4.9, 310–11.

48 TMS VII.ii.1.4–7, 267–68. See also Hanley, Character of Virtue, 152–55.

49 TMS VII.ii.4.8–10, 309–11.

50 I am following Hill's account of the concept of spirit in Smith's work as “the desire for status, social recognition and approval.” See her “Adam Smith on Thumos and Irrational Economic ‘Man,’” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 19, no. 1 (2012): 2.

51 TMS I.i.5, 23–26, esp. I.i.5.6, 25.

52 TMS VI.ii.2, 227–34. My interpretation of this chapter as concerned with patriotism and beneficence differs from other readings of it—for instance, as a conflicted appropriation of the Stoic model of concentric circles of affinity (Forman); as an account of the ennoblement of self-love (Hanley); as a critique of physiocracy and an endorsement of international competition for economic excellence (Hont); and as a warning against immoderate reform in Europe and Britain (Lock). See Forman-Barzilai, Circles of Sympathy, 120–34; Hanley, Character of Virtue, 155–62; István Hont, The Jealousy of Trade: International Competition and the Nation-State in Historical Perspective (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2005), 111–25; István Hont, Politics in Commercial Society: Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Adam Smith, ed. Béla Kapossy and Michael Sonenscher (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2015), 123–31; Lock, “Smith and the ‘Man of System.’”

53 TMS VI.ii.intro.2, 218.

54 Hanley argues that section VI.ii is “not immediately recognizable as a treatment of a specific virtue,” in contrast to the immediately preceding and following sections, whose headings declare their concern with the virtues of prudence and self-command. He reads section VI.ii as a “crucial preparative for the treatment of magnanimity in VI.iii.” See his Character of Virtue, 155. Indeed, the heading of section VI.ii is general: “Of the Character of the Individual, so far as it can affect the Happiness of other People.” But the introduction to the section straightforwardly recognizes it as a treatment of beneficence, after having set aside the other virtue concerned with the happiness of others, justice (TMS VI.ii.intro.2, 218).

55 TMS II.ii.1.1, 78.

56 TMS VII.ii.1.10, 269–70. See also Charles L. Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 252; Leonidas Montes, Adam Smith in Context: A Critical Reassessment of Some Central Components of His Thought (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004), 93–94.

57 I believe this to be implied in Smith's discussion of the motives of “generous and public-spirited actions” in TMS VII.ii.4.8, 309, and reinforced by his description of the love of the superiority of one's own character as a virtuous motive of action that affects the happiness of others in TMS III.3.4, 137.

58 See, for example: “TRUE PATRIOTISM, then, considered as a principle, is the same thing with public spirit, or a generous love to our country,—a regard for the happiness of our fellow-creatures, especially a tender concern for the welfare of our fellow-subjects.” Noah Welles, Patriotism Described and Recommended (New London: Timothy Green, 1764), 8.

59 TMS VI.ii.2.7–18, 230–34.

60 James Otteson and Forman have emphasized the logic of “familiarity” or “proximity” that guides Smith's concentric circles model, while Hanley has described the model as part of his account of the ennoblement of self-love. But these are reflections on Smith's discussion rather than a reconstruction of his consequentialist argument. See James R. Otteson, Adam Smith's Marketplace of Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002); Fonna Forman-Barzilai, “Sympathy in Space(s): Adam Smith on Proximity,” Political Theory 33, no. 2 (2005): 189–217; Hanley, Character of Virtue, 155–62.

61 Forman-Barzilai, Circles of Sympathy, chaps. 6–7; Hill, “Smith's Cosmopolitanism”; Nussbaum, Cosmopolitan Tradition, chap. 5.

62 Nussbaum has argued that in WN, Smith shows greater sensitivity to problems of material aid or beneficence; see Cosmopolitan Tradition, chap. 5.

63 On justice and beneficence, see TMS II.i–ii, 78–91. On the scope of beneficence, see TMS VI.ii, 218–37. For Cicero's account, see Marcus Tullius Cicero, On Duties, ed. M. T. Griffin and E. M. Atkins (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 1.20–60, 9–25. On the Ciceronian distinction between justice and beneficence, see Martha C. Nussbaum, “Duties of Justice, Duties of Material Aid: Cicero's Problematic Legacy,” Journal of Political Philosophy 8, no. 2 (2000): 176–206.

64 On Smith and oikeiōsis, see Vivienne Brown, Adam Smith's Discourse: Canonicity, Commerce, and Conscience (London: Routledge, 1994), chaps. 4–5; Forman-Barzilai, Circles of Sympathy.

65 Forman-Barzilai, Circles of Sympathy, 120–34; Forman-Barzilai, “Smith's Anti-Cosmopolitanism,” Adam Smith Review, no. 5 (2010): 145–60. See TMS III.3.11–16, 140–43; VII.ii.1.43–47, 292–92.

66 Cicero, On Duties, 1.42–60, 19–25.

67 TMS VI.ii.intro.2–3, 218; see also VI.ii.2.1, 227.

68 That the unerring wisdom is God's is made explicit in TMS VI.ii.3, 235–37.

69 TMS VI.ii.1, 219–27.

70 TMS VI.ii.2.1–2, 227.

71 In this, Smith agrees with his teacher Francis Hutcheson, who believed, he says, those actions “aimed at the happiness of a great communuity” to be “proportionally the more virtuous,” and whose system, he adds, adequately explains “the peculiar excellency of the supreme virtue of beneficence.” He disagrees with Hutcheson's refusal to acknowledge self-love as a motive of virtuous actions (TMS VII.ii.3.10–15, 303–4, quoted text at VII.ii.3.10, 303 and VII.ii.3.15, 304).

72 TMS VI.ii.3.1–2, 235.

73 In Part III of TMS, Smith says that “extreme sympathy” with the misfortunes of those “who are placed altogether out of the sphere of our activity” and “whom we can neither serve nor hurt” is both unnatural and “perfectly useless.” But there he is concerned specifically with refuting the doctrine of the “whining and melancholy moralists, who are perpetually reproaching us with our happiness, while so many of our brethren are in misery.” The fault of their doctrine lies in aiming to “damp the pleasures of the fortunate, and render a certain melancholy dejection habitual to all men” to no apparent use (TMS III.3.9, 139–40). In TMS VI.ii.3, Smith describes moderate sympathy with the fortune and misery of others as natural and virtuous, and what concerns him is its translation into active universal beneficence.

74 TMS VI.ii.3.6, 237.

75 There is a scholarly debate on the role of providence in Smith. A good starting point would be the discussion in Michelle A. Schwarze and John T. Scott, “Spontaneous Disorder in Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments: Resentment, Injustice, and the Appeal to Providence,” Journal of Politics 77, no. 2 (2015): 463–76.

76 Robert E. Goodin, “What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?,” Ethics 98, no. 4 (July 1988): 678–86.

77 Smith never explicitly describes patriots as impartial, but in the political discourse of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, patriotism and impartiality are often related in some way or other, as argued in Christine Gerrard, “The Language of Impartiality and Party-Political Discourse in England, 1680–1745,” in The Emergence of Impartiality, ed. Kathryn Murphy and Traninger Anita (Leiden: Brill, 2014), 211–22. David Hume uses the phrase “an impartial patriot” in describing an imaginary member of the British Parliament who is deliberating whether to support the house of Stuart or that of Hanover and attempts to “form a just judgment” by “weighing, with impartiality, the advantages and disadvantages on each side” amid contrasting partisan views. See Hume, “Of the Protestant Succession,” in Political Essays, ed. Knud Haakonssen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 216, 219.

78 TMS VI.ii.2.2, 228.

79 TMS III.3.41, 43, 154–55.

80 WN I.xi.b.5, 163–64; IV.ii, 452–72.

81 TMS VI.ii.2.3, 228–29; WN IV.iii.c, 488–98.

82 TMS VI.ii.2.16–18, 233–34.

83 TMS VI.ii.2.3, 228; see also IV.2.9–10, 190–92.

84 TMS VI.i.11, 215.

85 On justice and self-overcoming, see TMS II.ii.2.1–3, 83–85; III.3.4, 136–37. The universal scope of justice is nicely demonstrated by Smith's discussion of the dilemma between the loss of one's finger and the loss of the empire of China in TMS III.3.4.

86 Baron, “Patriotism and ‘Liberal’ Morality”; Baron and Rogers, “Patriotism and Impartiality”; Nathanson, “In Defense of ‘Moderate Patriotism’”; Nathanson, Patriotism, Morality, and Peace.

87 TMS VI.ii.2.3, 228.

88 TMS VI.ii.2.3, 228–29.

89 Hill, “Smith's Cosmopolitanism,” 466.

90 Plutarch explains that Scipio Nasica called to spare Carthage because he “saw, probably, that the Roman people, in its wantoneness, was already guilty of many excesses, and in the pride of its prosperity, spurned the control of the Senate,” and “wished, therefore, that the fear of Carthage should abide, to curb the boldness of the multitude like a bridle, believing her not strong enough to conquer Rome, nor yet weak enough to be despised.” Plutarch, Plutarch's Lives, trans. Bernadotte Perrin, vol. 2 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1914), 383.

91 See also Fleischacker's argument that Smith's true love of country is consistent with the love of mankind (On Smith's “Wealth of Nations, 251).

92 Hont, The Jealousy of Trade, 111–25; Hont, Politics in Commercial Society, 123–31, quote at 131.

93 TMS VI.ii.2.3, 228.

94 TMS I.iii.3.2, 62.

95 TMS III.2.2.3, 114. For the economic model of emulation as competition for excellence, see WN I.viii.44, 100; IV.v.a.39, 523; V.i.b.21, 720; V.i.f.12–13, 763; V.i.f.4, 759–60; V.i.f.45, 780.

96 Primoratz, “Patriotism and Morality,” 214–15.

97 Fleischacker and Stephen Darwall have adduced this phrase as evidence of Smith's moral egalitarianism. Fleischacker, On Smith's “Wealth of Nations, chap. 4; Stephen Darwall, “Equal Dignity in Adam Smith,” Adam Smith Review, no. 1 (2004): 129–34.

98 TMS II.ii.2.2, 82–3; III.3.4, 136–37.

99 See, for example, Fleischacker, On Smith's “Wealth of Nations”; Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment; Hanley, Character of Virtue; McLean, Iain, Adam Smith, Radical and Egalitarian: An Interpretation for the Twenty-First Century (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2006)Google Scholar; Muller, Jerry Z., Adam Smith in His Time and Ours: Designing the Decent Society (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995)Google Scholar; Rothschild, Emma, Economic Sentiments: Adam Smith, Condorcet, and the Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002)Google Scholar.

100 Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, ed. Anne M. Cohler, Basia C. Miller, and Harold S. Stone (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 35–36.

101 For some discussions of the question of Smith's republicanism, see Dennis C. Rasmussen, “Smith, Rousseau and the True Spirit of a Republican,” in Adam Smith and Rousseau: Ethics, Politics, Economics, ed. Maria Pia Paganelli, Dennis C. Rasmussen, and Craig Smith (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2018), 241–59; Shannon C. Stimson, “Republicanism and the Recovery of the Political in Adam Smith,” in Critical Issues in Social Thought, ed. Murray Milgate and Cheryl B. Welch (London: Academic Press, 1989), 91–112; Winch, Donald, “Commercial Realities, Republican Principles,” in Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage, vol. 2, The Values of Republicanism in Early Modern Europe, ed. van, Martin Gelderen and Quentin Skinner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 293310CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

102 Rasmussen, Dennis C., “Adam Smith on What Is Wrong with Economic Inequality,” American Political Science Review 110, no. 2 (2016): 343–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

103 See TMS I.iii.3, 61–66; VI.i.7–15, 213–16.

104 TMS VI.ii.2.11–12, 231–32.

105 Price, “Discourse,” 184. However, on the points of alignment between Smith's and Price's accounts of patriotism, see Hont, Jealousy of Trade, 122n226; Emma Rothschild, Economic Sentiments: Adam Smith, Condorcet, and the Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), 278n106. There is much more to be said about the ideological context and import of Smith's treatment of patriotism in the 1790 edition of TMS. On this topic, see Stewart, “Life and Writings of Adam Smith,” in EPS IV.18–20, 317–319; Hont, Jealousy of Trade, chap. 5; Lock, “Smith and the ‘Man of System.’”

106 Nussbaum, Political Emotions, 204–56.

107 For communitarian accounts of the value of patriotism, see Alasdair MacIntyre, “Is Patriotism a Virtue?,” in Primoratz, Patriotism, 43–58; Oldenquist, Andrew, “Loyalties,” Journal of Philosophy 79, no. 4 (April 1982): 173–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

108 Michel Foucault, The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978–79, ed. Michel Senellart, trans. Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), 226.

109 Hafner-Burton, Emilie M., Narang, Neil, and Rathbun, Brian C., “Introduction: What Is Populist Nationalism and Why Does It Matter?,” Journal of Politics 81, no. 2 (April 2019): 707–11CrossRefGoogle Scholar.