Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T21:19:35.053Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theistic consubstantialism and omniscience

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 April 2017

ANDREI A. BUCKAREFF*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, Marist College, Poughkeepsie, New York 12601, USA

Abstract

According to theistic consubstantialism, the universe and God are essentially made of the same stuff. If theistic consubstantialism is correct, then God possesses the essential power to have knowledge de se of the contents of the mind of every conscious being internal to God. If theistic consubstantialism is false, then God lacks this essential property. So either God is essentially corporeal and possesses greater essential epistemic powers than God would have otherwise or God is essentially incorporeal and has a diminished range of essential epistemic powers. In light of this dilemma, I argue that theists should accept theistic consubstantialism.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aranyosi, Istvan (2013) God, Mind, and Logical Space: A Revisionary Approach to Divinity (New York: Palgrave Macmillan).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borghini, Andrea & Williams, Neil (2008) ‘A dispositional theory of possibility’, Dialectica, 62, 2141.Google Scholar
Buckareff, Andrei (2016) ‘Theological realism, divine action, and divine location’, in Buckareff, A. & Nagasawa, Y. (eds) Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine (New York: Oxford University Press), 213233.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit (1994) ‘Essence and modality’, Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John (2003) From an Ontological Point of View (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Heil, John (2012) The Universe as We Find It (New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John (2015) ‘Aristotelian supervenience’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 115, 4156.Google Scholar
Hudson, Hud (2009) ‘Omnipresence’, in Rea, M. (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology (New York: Oxford University Press), 199216.Google Scholar
Jacobs, Jonathan (2010) ‘A powers theory of modality: or, how I learned to stop worrying and reject possible worlds’, Philosophical Studies, 151, 227248.Google Scholar
Jantzen, Grace (1984) God's World, God's Body (Philadelphia: Westminster).Google Scholar
Johnston, Mark (2009) Saving God: Religion after Idolatry (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon (2005) Physicalism, Or Something Near Enough (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Leslie, John (2001) Infinite Minds: A Philosophical Cosmology (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Levine, Michael (1994) Pantheism: A Non-Theistic Concept of Deity (New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Mander, William (2007) ‘Theism, pantheism, and petitionary prayer’, Religious Studies, 43, 317331.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. (2007) The Mind in Nature (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Molnar, George (2003) Powers: A Study in Metaphysics (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin (2003) ‘Divine omniscience and knowledge de se’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 53, 7382.Google Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin (2008) God and Phenomenal Consciousness: A Novel Approach to Knowledge Arguments (New York: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin (2016) ‘Modal panentheism’, in Buckareff, A. & Nagasawa, Y. (eds) Alternative Concepts of God: Essays in the Metaphysics of the Divine (New York: Oxford University Press), 91105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakes, Robert (1986) ‘Theistic orthodoxy, theistic consubstantialism, and theistic internalism’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 19, 177189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakes, Robert (1997) ‘The divine infinity: can traditional theists justifiably reject pantheism?’, The Monist, 80, 251265.Google Scholar
Oakes, Robert (2006) ‘Divine omnipresence and maximal immanence: supernaturalism versus pantheism’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 43, 171179.Google Scholar
Oakes, Robert (2012) ‘Strong interiority and (traditional) theism: what's the problem?’, Ratio, 25, 6878.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, John (1979) ‘The problem of the essential indexical’, Nous, 13, 321.Google Scholar
Pfeifer, Karl (2016) ‘Pantheism as panpsychism’, in Buckareff, A. & Nagasawa, Y. (eds) Alternative Concepts of God: Essays in the Metaphysics of the Divine (New York: Oxford University Press), 4149.Google Scholar
Pruss, Alexander (2013) ‘Omnipresence, multilocation, the real presence, and time travel’, Journal of Analytic Theology, 1, 6073.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (1903) The Principles of Mathematics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1993) The Coherence of Theism, rev. edn (New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitehead, A. N. (1929) Process and Reality (New York: Macmillan).Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda (2008) ‘Omnisubjectivity’, Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Religion, 1, 231247.Google Scholar