Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T04:06:33.508Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The power to make others worship

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 November 2011

AARON SMUTS
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Rhode Island College, 600 Mount Pleasant Avenue, Providence, RI 02908 e-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

Can any being worthy of worship make others worship it? I think not. By way of an analogy to love, I argue that it is perfectly coherent to think that one could be made to worship. However, forcing someone to worship violates their autonomy, not because worship must be freely given, but because forced worship would be inauthentic – much like love earned through potions. For this reason, I argue that one cannot be made to worship a fitting object; forced worship would be unfitting. My principal claim is that no being worthy of worship could exercise the power to make others worship it, since the act of making another worship would necessarily make one unworthy of worship.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anglin, W. S. (1991) Free Will and the Christian Faith (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Arpaly, Nomy (2006) Merit, Meaning, and Human Bondage: An Essay on Free Will (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Badhwar, Neera Kapur (1989) ‘Friends as ends in themselves’, in , Soble (1989), 165188.Google Scholar
Baier, Annette (1991) Unsafe Loves, in , Solomon and , Higgins (1991), 433450.Google Scholar
Bayne, Tim and Nagasawa, Yujin (2006) ‘The grounds of worship’, Religious Studies, 42, 299313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blaauw, Martin (2005) ‘Worship me! A reply to Brown and Nagasawa’, Ratio, 20, 236240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Campbell and Nagasawa, Yujin (2005) ‘I can't make you worship me’, Ratio, 18, 138144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christman, John (1991) ‘Autonomy and person history’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21(1), 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ekstrom, Laura (2000) Free Will: A Philosophical Study (Boulder: Westview Press).Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry (1998) The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry (1999) ‘Autonomy, necessity, and love’, in Frankfurt, Harry (ed.) Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 129141.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry (2004) The Reasons of Love (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Grau, Christopher (2006) ‘Irreplaceability and unique value’, Philosophical Topics, 32(1&2), 111129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helm, Bennett (2005) ‘Love’, in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Kagan, Shelly (1992) ‘The limits of well-being’, in Paul, E. F., Miller, F. D., and Paul, Jeffrey (eds) The Good Life and the Human Good (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 169189.Google Scholar
Kane, Robert (1998) The Significance of Free Will (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1958) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton (New York: Harper Torch Books).Google Scholar
Kaye, Sharon (2004) ‘Why the liberty of indifference is worth wanting: Buridan's Ass, friendship, and Peter John Olivi’, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 21(1), 2142.Google Scholar
Keller, Simon (2000) ‘How do I love thee? Let me count the properties’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 37(2), 163173.Google Scholar
Keller, Simon (2008) ‘Welfarism’, Philosophy Compass, 3.Google Scholar
Kolodny, Niko (2003) ‘Love as valuing a relationship’, Philosophical Review, 112(2), 135189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The Koran (2003) N. J. Dawood (trans.) (Harmondsworth: Penguin).Google Scholar
Kraut, Robert (1986) ‘Love de re’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10, 413430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liao, S. Matthew (2007) ‘The idea of a duty to love’, The Journal of Value Inquiry, 40(1), 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthews, Gareth (1980) ‘Ritual and the religious feelings’, in Oksenberg Rorty, Amelie, Explaining Emotions (Los Angeles: University of California Press), 339354.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart (2002) Utilitarianism (Indianapolis: Hackett).Google Scholar
Montaigne, Michel de (1991) ‘Of friendship’, in Pakaluk, Michael (ed.) Other Selves: Philosophers on Friendship (Indianapolis: Hackett), 185199.Google Scholar
Morris, Thomas (2000) Our Idea of God (Vancouver: Regent College Publishing).Google Scholar
Murdoch, Iris (2010) The Sovereignty of Good (New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas (1979) ‘Death’, in , Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 110.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books).Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1997) ‘On the Randian Argument’, in , Nozick, Socratic Puzzles (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 249264.Google Scholar
Oakley, Justin (1992) Morality and the Emotions (New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek (1984) ‘What makes someone's life go best’, in , Parfit, Reasons and Persons (New York: Clarendon Press), 493502.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (1997) ‘Determinism al dente’, in Pereboom, Derk (ed.) Free Will (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing), 242272.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (2001) Living without Free Will (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rachels, James (1997) ‘God and moral autonomy’, in , James, Can Ethics Provide Answers (New York: Rowman and Littlefield), 109124.Google Scholar
Roberts, Robert C. (1988) ‘What an emotion is: a sketch’, The Philosophical Review, 97(2), 183209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sankowski, Edward (1978) ‘Love and moral obligation’, The Journal of Value Inquiry, 21(2), 100110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sappho, ‘Deathless Aphrodite of the spangled mind’, trans. Anne Carson, Norton Anthology of Western Literature, I (New York: Norton, 2006), 497.Google Scholar
Soble, Alan (ed.) (1989) Eros, Agape, and Philia: Readings in the Philosophy of Love (St. Paul: Paragon House).Google Scholar
Solomon, Robert (2001) About Love: Reinventing Romance for Our Times (New York: Madison Books).Google Scholar
Solomon, Robert and Kathleen, Higgins (eds) (1991) The Philosophy of (Erotic) Love (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas).Google Scholar
Sommers, Tamler (2007) ‘The objective attitude’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 57, 321341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, Galen (2010) ‘Freedom and belief’ (New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sumner, L. W. (1996) Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1993) The Coherence of Theism (New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Richard (2000) Good and Evil (New York: Prometheus Books).Google Scholar
Thomas, Laurence (1991) ‘Reasons for love’, in , Solomon and , Higgins (1991), 467476.Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory (1989) ‘The individual as an object of love in Plato’, in , Soble (1989), 96135.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan (1993) ‘The importance of free will’, in Fischer, John and Ravizza, M. (eds) Perspectives on Moral Responsibility (Ithaca: Cornell University Press), 101118.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan (1997) ‘Happiness and meaning: two aspects of the good life’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 14, 207225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolterstorff, Nicholas (1988) ‘Suffering love’, in Morris, Thomas (ed.) Philosophy and the Christian Faith (Notre Dame; University of Notre Dame Press), 196240.Google Scholar