Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-v2bm5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-07T09:26:25.589Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Lucifer’s disordered love and the first-person perspective: an Augustinian account of primal sin

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2025

Bradley N. Seeman*
Affiliation:
Philosophy Program, Taylor University, Upland, IN, USA

Abstract

Augustinian accounts of ‘primal sin’ face a dilemma: either ‘Lucifer’s’ fall is arbitrary, or it results from God creating a flawed creature. Augustine and others hold that an omnipotent God faces unavoidable limits in creating creatures. In particular, creatures cannot enjoy God’s own first-person awareness of God’s goods, but must experience them second-personally. The resulting qualitative phenomenological difference between (1) the first-person awareness Lucifer had of the goods of his own being, and (2) his second-person awareness of the goods of God means that self-regarding goods would ‘light up’ for Lucifer very differently than other-regarding goods. This opens a psychologically resonant and metaphysically potent account of how the pre-Fall Lucifer could have faced a genuine value conflict – a conflict for which God is not culpable – in which Lucifer might come to love the goods presented first-personally (his own) over the goods presented second-personally (God’s).

Type
Original Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anselm ([c. 1080–1086] 2002) On the fall of the devil. In Williams, T (ed), Anselm, Three Philosophical Dialogues (pp. 52–100). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Augustine ([390] 2005) True religion. In Hill, E (ed), Augustine, On Christian Religion (pp. 29–106). New York: New City Press.Google Scholar
Augustine ([400] 1991) Confessions. World’s Classics, Chadwick, O (translated by). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Augustine ([416] 2002) The literal meaning of Genesis. In Augustine, On Genesis, the Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the 21st Century, Part 1 – Books, Vol. 13, Hill, E (ed) (pp. 155–506). Hyde Park, NY: New City Press.Google Scholar
Augustine ([420] 1991) The Trinity. In The Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the 21st Century, Part 1 – Books, Vol. 5, 2nd ed. Hill, E (ed) (pp. 61–470). Hyde Park, NY: New City Press.Google Scholar
Augustine ([427] 1952) City of God, the Fathers of the Church, Vol. 14, Walsh, GG and Monahan, G (translated by). New York: The Fathers of the Church.Google Scholar
Babcock, W (1988) Augustine on sin and moral agency. The Journal of Religious Ethics 16, 2855.Google Scholar
Barnwell, M (2017) The ‘harder problem’ of the devil’s fall is still a problem: a reply to Wood. Religious Studies 53, 521543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barth, K ([1950] 2004) Church Dogmatics, Volume 3: The Doctrine of Creation, Part 3, Bromiley, G (edited and translated by). Edinburgh: T&T Clark.Google Scholar
The Bible (1978) New International Version. Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan.Google Scholar
Blumenberg, H ([1957] 1993) Light as a metaphor for truth: At the preliminary stage of concept formation. In Levin, DM (ed), Modernity and the Hegemony of Vision. Berkeley: University of California Press, 3062.Google Scholar
Brown, R (1978) The first evil will must be incomprehensible: A critique of Augustine. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 46, 315329.Google Scholar
Buber, M (1958) I and Thou 2d ed, Smith, R (trans). New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.Google Scholar
Cawdron, H (2022) The primigenius felix culpa. Heythrop Journal 63, 10711088.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chappell, T (1994) Explaining the inexplicable: Augustine on the fall. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 62, 869884.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chappell, T (2013) Knowledge of persons. European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 5, 328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cockayne, J (2020) Contemporary with Christ: Kierkegaard and Second-Personal Spirituality. Waco, TX: Baylor University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S (2006) The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Horton, M (2011) The Christian Faith: A Systematic Theology for Pilgrims on the Way. Grand Rapids: Zondervan.Google Scholar
Hume, D [1739–1740] (1975) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jenson, M (2006) The Gravity of Sin: Augustine, Luther and Barth on ‘Homo Incurvatus in Se.’ Edinburgh: T&T Clark.Google Scholar
King, P (2012) Augustine and Anselm on angelic sin. In Hoffman, T (ed), A Companion to Angels in Medieval Philosophy (pp. 261–281). Boston: Brill.Google Scholar
Klein, E (2018) Augustine’s Theology of Angels. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinas, E ([1961] 1969) Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, Lingis, A (translated by). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.Google Scholar
Levinas, E ([1982] 1985) Ethics and Infinity, Cohen, RA (trans). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.Google Scholar
MacDonald, S (1999) Primal sin. In Matthews, G (ed), The Augustinian Tradition. Berkeley: University of California Press, 110139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marcel, G ([1949] 1965) Being and Having: An Existentialist Diary, Farrer, K (trans). New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Marcel, G (1995) The Philosophy of Existentialism, Harari, M (trans). New York: Citadel.Google Scholar
Moser, P (2008) The Elusive God: Reorienting Religious Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T (1974) What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83, 435450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Connor, T (ed) (1995) Agents, Causes, and Events: Essays on Indeterminism and Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T (2000) Persons and Causes: The Metaphysics of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T (2002) Free Will. In Stanford Encyclopedia of PhilosophyGoogle Scholar
Patmore, H (2012) Adam, Satan, and the King of Tyre: The Interpretation of Ezekiel 28:11–19 in Late Antiquity. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Peirce, CS (1958) Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. 8, Burks, AW (ed). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Pini, G (2013) What Lucifer wanted: Anselm, Aquinas, and Scotus on the object of the first evil choice. In Pasnau, R (ed), Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 1. New York: Oxford University Press, 6182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A ([1974] 1989) God, Freedom, and Evil. New York: Harper and Row repr. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A ([2004] 2017) Supralapsarianism, or ‘O Felix Culpa. In Van Inwagen, P (ed), Christian Faith and the Problem of Evil. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 125 In Peterson, ML (ed), The Problem of Evil: Selected Readings, 2nd ed. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 363–389.Google Scholar
Rogers, K (2008) Anselm on Freedom. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seeman, B (2000) Peirce, Habermas, and moral absolutes. Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies 12, 4568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, E (1986) Dante’s Hell, Aquinas’s moral theory, and the love of God. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16, 181198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, E (2010) Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, E (2013) Omnipresence, indwelling, and the second-personal. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 5, 2953.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talbert, B (2015) Knowing other people: A second-person framework. Ratio 28, 190206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teanor, B and Sweetman, B (2021) Gabriel Marcel. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Timpe, K (2013) The arbitrariness of primal sin. In Kvanwig, J (ed), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion. New York: Oxford University Press, 234257.Google Scholar
Vanhoozer, K (2005) The Drama of Doctrine: A Canonical Linguistic Approach to Christian Theology. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press.Google Scholar
Webster, J (2003) Holiness. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Willows, A (2014) Augustine, the origin of evil, and the mystery of free will. Religious Studies 50, 255269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, W (2016) Anselm of Canterbury on the fall of the devil: The hard problem, the harder problem, and a new model of the first sin. Religious Studies 52, 233245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worsley, D (2016) Could there be suffering in paradise? The primal sin, the beatific vision, and suffering in paradise. Journal of Analytic Theology 4, 87105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L (2021) The Two Greatest Ideas: How Our Grasp of the Universe and Our Minds Changed Everything. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar