Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T06:19:41.486Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Empathy and divine union in Kierkegaard: solving the faith/history problem in Philosophical Fragments

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 May 2015

JOSHUA COCKAYNE*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of York, York, YO10 5DD, UK e-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

Søren Kierkegaard's account of faith in Philosophical Fragments claims that the historical Incarnation is necessary for faith, but that historical evidence for the Incarnation is neither necessary nor sufficient for faith. It has been argued that the defence of these two claims gives rise to a faith/history problem for Kierkegaard and that it is incoherent to defend an account of faith which affirms both the necessity of the historical Incarnation and rejects the necessity and sufficiency of the historical evidence for the Incarnation. I argue that this problem can be solved by applying Eleonore Stump's (2013) account of divine–human union. I argue that the Incarnation is necessary because it allows us to enjoy a kind of mutual empathy with Christ which is the basis of divine–human union and that the historical evidence is neither necessary nor sufficient since faith is grounded in a second-person experience of Christ. I claim that this solves the faith/history problem and offers a way of defending Kierkegaard's account of faith as coherent.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bogdashina, Olga (2013) Autism and Spirituality: Psyche, Self and Spirit in People on the Autism Spectrum (London: Jessica Kingsley Publishers).Google Scholar
Borg, Emma (2013) ‘More questions for mirror neurons’, Consciousness and Cognition, 22, 11221131.Google Scholar
Buber, Martin (1937) I and Thou, Gregor Smith, Ronald (tr.) (Edinburgh: T&T Clark).Google Scholar
Davies, Martin & Stone, Tony (eds) (1995) Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Descartes, René (1649/1989) Passions of the Soul, Voss, Stephen H. (tr.) (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co, Inc.).Google Scholar
Doherty, Trent (2014) The Problem of Animal Pain: A Theodicy for All Creatures Great and Small (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan).Google Scholar
Elian, Naomi, Hoerl, Christoph, Mccormack, Teresa & Roessler, Joahnnes (eds) (2005) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds, Issues in Philosophy and Psychology (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Evans, C. Stephen (1990) ‘The relevance of historical evidence for Christian faith: a critique of a Kierkegaardian view’, Faith and Philosophy, 7, 470485.Google Scholar
Evans, C. Stephen (1996) The Historical Christ and The Jesus of Faith (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Evans, C. Stephen (2006) Kierkegaard on Faith and the Self: Collected Essays (Waco TX: Baylor University Press).Google Scholar
Ferreira, M. J. (1987) ‘The faith/history problem, and Kierkegaard's a priori “proof” ’, Religious Studies, 23, 337345.Google Scholar
Galese, Vittorio (2001) ‘The “shared manifold” hypothesis: from mirror neurons to empathy’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 3350.Google Scholar
Galese, Vittorio (2003) ‘The roots of empathy: the shared manifold hypothesis and the neural basis of intersubjectivity’, Psychopathology, 36, 171180.Google Scholar
Galese, Vittorio (2005) ‘“Being like me”: self-other identity, mirror neurons, and empathy’, in Hurley, Susan & Chater, Nick (eds) Perspectives on Imitation, I: From Neuroscience to Social Science – Mechanisms of Imitation and Imitation in Animals (Cambridge MA: MIT Press), 101118.Google Scholar
Goldie, Peter & Coplan, Amy (2011) ‘Introduction’, in Coplan, Amy & Goldie, Peter (eds) Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press), ixxlviii.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin (2006) Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin (2011) ‘Two routes to empathy: insights from cognitive neuroscience’, in Coplan, Amy & Goldie, Peter (eds) Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 3144.Google Scholar
Hartshorne, Charles (1941) Man's Vision of God and the Logic of Theism (Chicago: Willett, Clark, & Co.).Google Scholar
Hickok, Gregory (2014) The Myth of Mirror Neurons: The Real Neuroscience of Communication and Cognition (New York: W. W. Norton & Company).Google Scholar
Hudson, Hud (2014) The Fall and Hypertime (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
James, William (1884) ‘What is an emotion?’, Mind, 9, 188205.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, Søren (1844/1985) Philosophical Fragments, Hong, Howard V. & Hong, Edna H. (trs), Kierkegaard's Writings, VII (Princeton: Princeton University Press), 1111.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, Søren (1850/1991) Practice in Christianity, Hong, Howard V. & Hong, Edna H. (trs), Kierkegaard's Writings, XX (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, Søren (1846/1992) Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments, Hong, Howard V. & Hong, Edna H. (trs), Kierkegaard's Writings, XII.1 (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Levine, Michael P. (1982) ‘Why the Incarnation is a superfluous detail for Kierkegaard’, Religious Studies, 18, 171175.Google Scholar
McNeill, William (2012a) ‘Embodiment and the perceptual hypothesis’, Philosophical Quarterly, 62, 569591.Google Scholar
McNeill, William (2012b) ‘On seeing that someone is angry’, European Journal of Philosophy, 20, 575597.Google Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1945/2002) Phenomenology of Perception, Smith, Colin (tr.) (New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1944) ‘Russell's theory of description’, in Schilpp, P. A. (ed.) The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell (La Salle IL: Open Court), 175225.Google Scholar
Moser, Paul K. (2008) The Elusive God: Reorientating Religious Epistemology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Moser, Paul K. & McCreary, Mark L. (2010) ‘Kierkegaard's conception of God’, Philosophy Compass, 5, 127135.Google Scholar
Oxley, Julinna (2006) ‘ Empathy and contractual theories of ethics ’, PhD dissertation, Tulane University.Google Scholar
Patios, Georgios (2014) Kierkegaard on the Philosophy of History (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan).Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin (1981) ‘On taking belief in God as basic’, Noûs, 15, 4151.Google Scholar
Pojman, Louis P. (1982) ‘Kierkegaard on faith and history’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 13, 5768.Google Scholar
Prinz, Jesse J. (2004) Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Rizzolatti, Giacomo & Craighero, Laila (2004) ‘The mirror-neuron system’, Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169192.Google Scholar
Stueber, Karsten (2000) ‘Understanding other minds and the problem of rationality’, in Kögler, H. & Stueber, K. (eds) Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences (Boulder CO: Westview Press), 144162.Google Scholar
Stueber, Karsten (2006) Rediscovering Empathy: Agency, Folk Psychology, and the Human Sciences (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (2003) Aquinas (London & New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (2010) Wandering in Darkness (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (2013) ‘Omnipresence, indwelling and the second-personal’, European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 5, 6387.Google Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1977) The Coherence of Theism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Taliaferro, Charles (1994) Consciousness and the Mind of God (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Taliaferro, Charles (1997) ‘Incorporeality’, in Quinn, Philip L. & Taliaferro, Charles (ed.) A Companion to the Philosophy of Religion (Oxford: Blackwell), 271278.Google Scholar
Westphal, Merold (2014) Kierkegaard's Concept of Faith, Kierkegaard as a Christian Thinker (Grand Rapids MA & Cambridge UK: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company).Google Scholar
Wierenga, Edward (1988) ‘Anselm on omnipresence’, New Scholasticism, 52, 3041.Google Scholar
Wierenga, Edward (1997) ‘Omnipresence’, in Quinn, Philip L. & Taliaferro, Charles (eds) A Companion to the Philosophy of Religion (Oxford: Blackwell), 286290.Google Scholar
Wierenga, Edward (2002) ‘Timelessness out of Mind: on the alleged incoherence of divine timelessness’, in Ganssle, Gregory E. & Woodruff, David M. (eds) God and Time: Essays on the Divine Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 153164.Google Scholar
Yeo, Ray S. (2014) ‘Towards a model of indwelling: a conversation with Jonathan Edwards and William Alston’, Journal of Analytic Theology, 2, 210237.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda (2008) ‘Omnisubjectivity’, in Kvanvig, Jonathan L. (ed.) Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, I (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 231249.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda (2013) Omnisubjectivity: A Defence of a Divine Attribute, The Aquinas Lecture, 2013 (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press).Google Scholar