Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T07:14:51.859Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Does the Ontological Argument Beg the Question?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

P. J. McGrath
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University College, Cork, Ireland

Extract

In his paper ‘Has the Ontological Argument Been Refuted?’ (Religious Studies, 29 (1993), 97–110) William F. Vallicella argues that my attempt to show that the Ontological Argument begs the question is unsuccessful.1 I believe he is wrong about this, but before endeavouring to vindicate my position I must first make clear what precisely is the point at issue between us. The Ontological Argument is not a single argument, but a family of arguments. Newly devised formulations of the argument are frequently put forward by philosophers in an effort to avoid difficulties that have been pointed out in previous versions. As a consequence there is no possibility of a conclusive proof that every form of the argument embodies the same fallacy. Nevertheless, one can, I believe, prove that all the standard versions of the argument embody a certain fallacy and that, given the nature of the argument, it is therefore unlikely that the argument can be formulated in such a way as to avoid this difficulty. What I tried to show in my paper is that the six best-known versions of the argument (the non-model versions of Anselm, Descartes and Leibniz and the modal versions of Malcolm, Hartshorne and Plantinga) all beg the question and that they do so at the same point in the argument, namely when it is asserted that it is possible that an absolutely perfect being exists. It is difficult to see how an ontological argument could be formulated without including this claim as one of its premises, since the distinguishing badge of the argument is the inference from the possibility of an absolutely perfect being to its actuality. It must be unlikely then, if my criticism of these six versions is correct, that there is any way of formulating the argument that avoids this fallacy.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See my paper ‘The Refutation of the Ontological Argument’, The Philosophical Quarterly, XL (1990), 195212.Google Scholar

2 It is more convenient because it enables us to avoid such cumbersome expressions as ‘the internal coherence of the concept which a necessary being would exemplify if it were to exist’ and it is more exact because it escapes the difficulty that not everything that would exemplify a coherent concept if it were to exist is consistently describable, since the same thing may exemplify two or more concepts. Thus a foursided triangle is not consistently describable even though it would, if it were to exist, exemplify two internally coherent concepts.