Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T14:29:29.403Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Comment on Professor Jeffner's Paper

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Colin Wright
Affiliation:
Lecturer in Philosophy, University of Exeter

Extract

By far the most common term in Professor Jeffner's paper is ‘understanding’, and it is clearly with understanding that he is primarily concerned. However, at the beginning of his paper he talks of understanding and explanation, and at least in the case of his third kind of reality he clearly sees understanding and explanation as intimately related. In this he is surely right. I myself would say that understanding is cognizing a manifold as a single whole in all its internal relationships, and this ties up with what Jeffner has to say about Gestalts on pp. 220–221. And explanation, as I hope to show, depends upon or presupposes the understanding that flows from the possession of a Gestalt. However, Jeffner adopts Hempel and Oppenheim's deductivist account of scientific explanation, and I believe this account to be fundamentally mistaken, and to have serious consequences for his argument. One does not achieve explanation merely by finding a set of empirically true premises from which a proposition expressing the explanandum can be deduced – if that were so one would explain Socrates' mortality by pointing out that everything snub-nosed is mortal, and that Socrates was snub-nosed. It is interesting, in this respect, to compare Hempel's account of explanation with that of Aristotle. There are substantial similarities between the two accounts, but there is one fundamental difference. Hempel insists that there can be no explanation unless events are connected in some way, and so rejects, for example, a mere sequential narrative as constituting an explanation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1981

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 227 note 1 Hempel, C. G., Aspects of Scientific Explanation (New York, The Free Press, and London, Collier-Macmillan), pp. 360362.Google Scholar

page 227 note 2 Ibid. p. 337.

page 228 note 1 Von Lancker, J., Smoking and disease, National Institute on Drug Abuse Research Monograph 17, Rockville, Maryland.Google Scholar

page 228 note 2 Ibid. pp. 258–9.

page 228 note 3 Collins, A. W., ‘Explanation and Causality’, Mind lxxv (1966), 483.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

page 230 note 1 Coulson, C. A., Science and Christian Belief (London, Collins).Google Scholar

page 230 note 2 Foster, M. B., ‘The Christian doctrine of creation and the rise of modern science’, Mind xliii (1934), pp. 446–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar: Christian theology and modern science of nature’, Part I, Mind xlv (1935), pp. 439–66Google Scholar: Part II, Mind xlv (1936), pp. 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

page 231 note 1 Mind xlv (1936), pp. 1013.Google Scholar

page 231 note 2 Ibid. p. 10.

page 232 note 1 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol. ii, No. 2, Chicago, University of Chicago Press).Google Scholar